Associating social constructionism and extended cognition in information studies

George Adam Holland (Department of Humanities and Social Science, University of Technology, Sydney, Australia)

Journal of Documentation

ISSN: 0022-0418

Article publication date: 1 January 2006

1558

Abstract

Purpose

To develop a unified research framework that synthesizes similarities between cognitive science and information studies, particularly language. This framework is proposed and explored as useful for future information study research.

Design/methodology/approach

Analysis is conducted of two contemporary developments in the distinct disciplines of information studies and cognitive science. The theories of extended cognition and social constructionism are explored, focusing on the issue of context in each of the arguments. The complementarity argument is presented as the strongest argument for extended cognition, while Sanna Talja's work is offered as representative of social constructionism in information studies. The philosophical similarities between extended cognition and social constructionism are then integrated at points of similarity.

Findings

Cognitive science and information studies have a number of unexpected similarities both in broad and specific terms. The opportunity to develop a synchronized research framework is presented as both feasible and mutually beneficial. Additionally, cognitive science is suggested as useful tool in bridging the gap between the frameworks of cognitivism and social constructionism in information studies.

Research limitations/implications

The philosophic discussion borders on technical at times possibly limiting it to those familiar with or interested in the philosophy or meta‐theory within cognitive science and information studies.

Practical implications

The conclusion points to future research between cognitive science and information studies that can be conducted in further research projects. The arguments also move toward continuing discussions of interdisciplinarity in information studies.

Originality/value

Cognitive science is being frequently employed in information studies research and practice. This paper presents an alternative take on how the two can relate and possible benefits, while also exploring very particular movements within each discipline.

Keywords

Citation

Adam Holland, G. (2006), "Associating social constructionism and extended cognition in information studies", Journal of Documentation, Vol. 62 No. 1, pp. 91-100. https://doi.org/10.1108/00220410610642066

Publisher

:

Emerald Group Publishing Limited

Copyright © 2006, Emerald Group Publishing Limited


1. Introduction

This paper seeks to draw together two contemporary developments in the distinct disciplines of information studies and cognitive science. The first development is social constructionist[1] research and theory in information studies, which is growing into an influential paradigm within the discipline. The second development is the extended theory of cognition, often called the extended mind, which has gained momentum within cognitive science since the late 1990s. These two movements have existed independently, yet shared motivation and influences, and I will propose potential links in methodologies and research programmes in the following pages. I begin with an overview of each development, seeking to represent the central issues and arguments of each. Then an argument is made for a synchronized research framework with specific benefits for information studies. While the association of these two research perspectives does not propose a solution to a specific problem within information studies, the integrative methodology implemented attempts to encourage collaboration within information studies. Implications from such collaboration can impact and influence a number of aspects within the discipline, limited only by the avenues pursued by researchers. Finally, the general value and possible implications of such a synchronized framework are evaluated for information studies, with particular relevance given to the work of Birger Hjørland.

2. Central elements of social constructionism and extended cognition

It is both naïve and simplistic to refer to “the” movement of either social constructionism or extended cognitive theory because of the non‐linear and decentralized growth of both theories. A comprehensive account of either is a full paper in itself, so a strict overview is attempted here. The core and central elements of both research perspectives are presented and discussed in the context of the arguments that are made for them in each disciplines' literature, beginning with social constructionism in information studies.

2.1. Social constructionism

Social constructionist theory can be characterized in a variety of ways across many disciplines (Tuominen et al. 2002, p. 3). In the context of information studies a number of useful definitions and explanations are offered, with the work of Tuominen et al. being properly representative of the majority:

Social constructionism focus on talk, interaction and language use in various contexts. In information studies, constructionism provides a dialogic viewpoint to study the assumptions and implicit theories that people draw on when they engage in information practices and produce accounts of them. (Tuominen et al., 2005, p. 1).

Research by Tuominen et al. seeks to capture the socially and linguistically shaped ways of understanding information practices[2].

While I wish to avoid offering an iron clad definition of social constructionism, this paper will employ a relatively concise understanding of the concept. Vakkari (1997) identifies that research perspectives are orientation strategies to the world, and that such orientations can change. Following Touminen et al.'s passage above I want to offer a working definition of social constructionism that seeks to represent the major arguments in information literature while retaining a flexibility to incorporate inevitable future development.

Social constructionism in information studies is taken to mean the focus on dialogue and discourse as the essential elements in people describing and producing their experiences. Dialogue and discourse stress the role of language in the building of social reality, which encompasses information practices as seeking, accessing, creating, using and sharing information. All associated experiences, emotions, identities and social worlds are language based, and thus best researched with a dialogue and discourse focus.

2.1.1. Social constructionism and contextual factors. With the core of social constructionism being language, consideration must be given to social, political and historical contexts which heavily influence or create language. A leading contributor to the social constructionist development in information studies is Sanna Talja who describes information as being concerned with what people do with language and what language does to people (Talja, 1997, p. 70). Information in this understanding is therefore language based which, in turn, is comprised of social, political and historical contributions.

Cognitivism is an influential framework within information studies which presents significant differences to social constructionism. Without going in‐depth into the variety of differences an important issue to consider is the role of context in cognitivism and social constructionism. Cognitivism views information seeking behaviour as time and space dependent, but prioritizes the role of the individual over contextual factors (Tuominen et al., 2002, p. 275). For social constructionist theory the social, political and history context are crucial to understanding information practice. Individuals are not sites of power in information seeking or unique builders of knowledge; rather they are principally influenced by other members of society and society itself. In the most basic of terms cognitivism is an individual‐centred approach to information practice, while social constructionism is a dialogic approach(Tuominen et al., 2002, p. 272)[3]. Dialogue, or language, and contextual factors are the central focus of social constructionism which is in contrast to the cognitivist paradigm. Section 3.2.2 will present the work of Birger Hjørland as similar in motivation to the work of Talja and other social constructionists, and identify possible links with the socio‐cognitive perspective Hjørland presents.

While this is not a comprehensive examination of social constructionist arguments it summarizes major components. The potential change social constructionism offers to information studies is wide ranging and plays out in a variety of ways, with an alternative course proposed in section 3 of this paper. I now present an account of the extended mind argument as developed in cognitive science, before going on to argue for alliances between social constructionism and extended cognitive theory.

2.2. Extended cognition

Many philosophers and cognitive scientists cite Andy Clark and David Chalmer's article “The extended mind” as the seminal text that provided the impetus for theorizing the human mind as outside the confines of biology(Clark and Chalmers, 1998). The history and development of extended cognition reaches much further than Clark and Chalmers article, but they did summarize and promote some central issues in a widely circulated way. In presenting extended cognitive theory I will draw heavily on Andy Clark's work while also incorporating more peripheral contributors such as Ed Hutchins.

2.2.1. The extended mind. Extended mind theorists propose a radical answer to the question: What roles do the external world and human body play in cognitive processes? Andy Clark, a strong proponent of the extended mind couches the central idea of extension as this:

… the project of understanding what is distinctive about human thought and reason may depend on a much broader focus than that to which cognitive science has become most accustomed, one that includes not just body, brain and the natural world, but the props and aids (pens, papers, PCs, institutions) in which our biological brains learn, mature and operate (Clark, 2001a, p. 141).

I will now investigate portions of the external world functioning as a kind of cognitive aid in the extended mind, and specifically complementarity, account.

2.2.2. The complementarity argument. In terms used by cognitive scientists, humans are surrounded by “cognitive tools”, which play integral roles in our cognitive life. The environment, both created and natural, surrounding a cognitive agent provides cognitive tools. The extended mind (EM hereafter) explanation of the ability humans have to exploit and utilize this environment (cognitive tools) bring its unique claims to the fore. The cognitive tools become part of a hybrid that qualifies the combination of external world and brain as a unified cognitive system. The argument for this hybrid comes in two main forms: parity or complementarity.

Some externalists about the mind claim that the external world can serve a cognitive purpose on the basis of parity. The parity criterion requires events and objects in the external world to function in the same way as events and objects in the brain. This view sees parts of the world suited to being involved in cognitive processes because they perform tasks in similar ways to the brain[4]. A part of the world qualifies itself as cognitive if it performs a function, which if it were to occur in the brain, would be called cognitive. Thus, the parity argument extends the mind on the basis of equivalence.

The complementarity claim is similar, but importantly distinct to the parity argument. The complementarity argument (CA henceforth) proposes that it is useful to understand cognitive technologies as affording complementary operations to those that come most naturally to biological brains. This is importantly dissimilar to the parity argument because of its heterogeneity. CA proponents are not looking for “mental” things existing in the world that will move cognition out of the brain. The goal of the CA is to incorporate parts of the world that complement biological cognition precisely because they are different to the functions of the brain. CA argues that parts of the world are useful as cognitive technologies because they perform functions that the biological brain cannot naturally do well.

A crucial attribute of the CA claim is the breaking down of complex cognitive processes into more naturally manageable processes of the biological brain. An example often given in the extended mind literature is that of a large multiplication problem broken down into smaller patterns. Take 329*764, which is broken down into 4*9 then 4*2 and so forth. These more simple patterns can then be joined together to solve the original larger problem. This combination of smaller patterns is an example of how the CA views the breaking down of complex cognitive process via cognitive tools. The pencil and paper used to write the smaller patterns can be seen as a type of extra‐neural memory, but they serve a much more crucial purpose. They provide a cognitive tool that breaks down a large sequential problem into smaller parts that prove more easily processed by the human brain. Cognitive tasks which prove very taxing such as multifarious arrangements of multiple mental tasks are made possible, or more effective through utilizing cognitive tools. Ed Hutchins has done considerable research into human cognitive and environment interaction and summarizes this point in his book Cognition in the Wild:

Such tools permit the users to do the tasks that need to be done while doing the kinds of things people are good at: recognizing patterns, modeling simple dynamics of the world, and manipulating objects in the environment (Hutchins, 1995, p. 155).

Andy Clark, along with others, (Deheane et al., 1999) has forwarded the argument that words and linguistic labels themselves are a fundamental type of cognitive tool (Clark and Thornton, 1997)[5].

CA is a distinctive argument for cognitive extension because it offers a plausible explanation of how human brains repeatedly create and exploit various species of cognitive tools so as to expand and re‐shape the space of human reason (Clark, 2001b, p. 134). Humans employ non‐biological elements in novel ways to complement the basic biological modes of cognition because the external world provides unique means to break down complex cognitive processes into familiar biological cognitive processes. But these unique external technologies are significantly different to the biological means (e.g. pen and paper are quite different to the way theories of cognition propose the biological brain works) of cognitive acts. Consequently, it is not a matter of finding parts of the world which match the biological brain (as the parity argument claims); rather all parts of the external world have the potential to be cognitive tools on the basis of the complementarity criteria. Anything that can aid and/or enhance a cognitive act on the basis of difference qualifies if it complements the biological brain. This heterogeneous mix results in extended cognitive systems whose abilities and explanations of human thought and rationality are quite different to the naked brain.

2.2.3. In summary. While this is not a comprehensive overview of EM, the particular issues presented here will form important contacts with information studies in the sections to come[6]. To better develop both the social constructionist and cognitive science discussions above, potential links between the two will now be explored.

3. Links between social constructionism and EM

I want to briefly explore the most prominent link between social constructionism and EM. The clearest link is the incorporation of context, or environment, into theory. The EM argument proposes environmental objects as crucial to understanding human cognition, while social constructionism promotes context and environment as critical to understanding the construction of meaning and experience. For both cognitive science and information studies this offers emphasis of context. Human cognition does not occur within a vacuum, and neither does information practice. The context in both instances is integral to the processes, according to EM and social constructionism. This is the broadest of similarities between the two, forging a clear alliance of contextual focus.

3.1. The linguistic aspect

A more subtle alliance is more specific and potentially fruitful because of its possible developments. Within the argument for extended cognition there are sub‐arguments for language itself being a cognitive technology, as briefly mentioned in section 2.2.2. This argument is often identified, but rarely fully developed[7]. The central tenant of this linguistic focused argument is that language, both verbal and written, provides tools for humans to alter and enhance their cognitive activities. Within this argument public language constitutes more than inter‐personal communication, which is the most obvious role of language. Language can also reorganize information in a way that compliments the human brain, thus augmenting human cognition in a potentially extended sense. The core of this argument is that language enables us to pursue manipulations and juxtapositions of ideas and information in a way which would not be possible, or would quickly overload, the human brain. Written and spoken words allow us to search, store, order and reorganize information in much more advanced manners than the brain by itself[8].

3.1.1. Scrabble and academic writing. There are a variety of ways to argue for language as cognitive tools for humans. The two examples I want to briefly examine are common to most of us. For Scrabble players, it is common practice to place Scrabble tiles in ways to stimulate thought and present possible word fragments. Such a strategy is a basic example of using the external world of language as part of a cognitive process[9]. Another simple example is the writing of an academic paper. Words presented on the screen are cut and pasted, rearranged and manipulated to stimulate ideas and lines of arguments. Is the language on the screen purely reflecting the inner knowledge of the writer? In as much as the words direct, refine, alter, offload and instigate the writer's thoughts they complement cognition in a categorically similar way to the complementarity argument.

Language still allows communication, which is its most obvious cognitive application. The argument here is that further to communication, an extension of cognition is possible based on the complementarity of language as a cognitive tool. Constraints of space prevent a comprehensive argument for language as a cognitive tool in the complimentary sense. Likewise, addressing possible criticisms of such an argument is also prevented. The possibility of language and mind being part of a hybrid cognitive process is intriguing in its possible implications for information studies and I turn to focus on such possibilities in the following sections.

I conclude with sentences from Andy Clark summarizing the liberal spread of cognition into the world via language:

… language is so ubiquitous it is almost invisible; so intimate, it is not clear whether it is a kind of tool or an added dimension of the user. But whatever the boundaries, we confront a complex coalition in which the basic biological brain is fantastically empowered by some of its strangest and most recent creations: words in the air, symbols on the printed page (Clark, 1998, p. 183).

Because of distinct understandings of language and a meshing of the two theories, unique implications and further questions for information studies can be presented. Three issues will be presented below as potentially interesting avenues of research based on the coalition of extended cognition and social constructionism.

3.2. Implications for research

3.2.1. Implications for physical environments. The first issue is a tangible and physical manifestation of combined theory. Research into the architecture and ergonomics of libraries is gaining importance in current information and knowledge discussions[10]. If dialogue and language are seen as integral aspects of information practice then physical spaces can be designed which seek to enable and facilitate a dialogic focus. In particular, if language is seen as a cognitive tool then spaces can be created which use this to their advantage, both in communication and other cognitive tasks. This is a potentially intriguing avenue of research given the developing focus on physical space in information environments, with fascinating implications for how buildings and communication are coordinated.

3.2.2. Hjørland's socio‐cognitive proposal. Birger Hjørland presents many challenging proposals for information studies, particularly his socio‐cognitive viewpoint. Without any attempt to fully explore Hjørland's research and writing here, some broad issues can be raised as potential links. Specifically Hjørland's work on epistemology and socio‐cognitive views within information studies share conceptual concerns expressed in this paper. Hjørland's socio‐cognitive (or domain activity paradigm) viewpoint also focuses on social factors, cognition within a broader context and the domain of activity as critical issues (Hjørland, 2002). As the following passage from his work demonstrates, he shares a concern with social constructionists for incorporating context into IS (information studies) theory:

… the best way to understand information in IS is to study the knowledge domains as thought or discourse communities (Hjørland and Albrechtesen, 1995, p. 400).

A similar methodological emphasis is put on context and dialogue in Hjørland's research. His suggestion of developing an implicit epistemology within information science is also an important contribution and challenge (Hjørland, 1998). Given the broad compatibilities suggested here, one possibility is basing such an epistemology on extended cognition. It could be argued that the socio‐cognitive viewpoint can be seen to epistemologize cognitive activity for IS by necessarily positioning it within a historical and social context. A full and robust exploration of applying extended cognition to Hjørland's work is potential fruitful, but requiring fuller consideration than possible here[11].

3.3. Cognitivism and social constructionism

The final point takes up where much work is currently being conducted in information studies. The dominance of cognitivism in information studies for a number of years has helped lead to the development of social constructionism as a consistent alternative. Where cognitivism begins with the acts of an individual, social constructionism emphasizes context and public language. This difference bears out a two sided criticism: cognitivism focuses on the individual at the expense of the context and social constructionism focuses on the context at the expense of the individual's acts. I want to propose EM as a supplement to social constructionism that goes towards addressing the criticism of neglecting the individual.

By combining extended cognition and social constructionism a balance of context and individual is achieved. The individual is given focus on the basis of cognition being human based, predominantly in individual brains. At the same time the context which the brain is cognizing in is recognized as absolutely integral to understanding human cognition because of its complementarity to the brain. It is at the expense of a full and balanced understanding that either the individual or the context is neglected. In this way a social constructionist framework supplemented with an extended cognition perspective goes towards addressing the criticism that the individual is neglected. To investigate information practice, an understanding of cognitive acts that incorporates both the individual and the context is crucial.

4. Conclusion

I have maintained the integration of social constructionism and extended cognition is useful for a number of reasons. The strongest contribution is made through examining two theories which prioritize language and context in diverse manners. EM adds a fundamentally distinct argument for incorporating context and environment, such as technology and physical spaces, into an understanding of the individual, and thus adds a dimension for information studies to investigate.

This added dimension is useful, I have argued, because it opens up possibilities for understanding social constructionism in new ways. Specifically the role of language in human cognition allows for a clear link between extended cognition and social constructionism. The topic of enabling and encouraging information access through the designing of spaces is a topic of growing interest. The addition of extended cognition to this discussion could prove intriguing by breaking down hard demarcations between the user and the space. Likewise, potential links with Hjørland's work justify further investigation. Ultimately, in terms of contribution to the discipline of information studies, the association of extended cognition and social constructionism provides the most exciting and potentially fruitful arguments and implications through a response to cognitivist criticisms of social constructionism. There are many ways social constructionism can address the criticism of neglecting the individual, but EM mediates in a way that retains the central tenants of social constructionism while also gesturing towards the strengths of cognitivism. It is this specific area, with possible links to Hjørland's theories, which I would flag as the most deserving of future research.

Notes

The terms “social constructionism” and “social constructivism” are often used interchangeably in information studies and for convenience the term “social constructionism” will be consistently used in this paper. The terms are taken to be essentially synonymous, further discussion see (Raskin, 2002).

Other information studies researchers offer similar arguments, but in the pursuit of efficiency and conciseness I will focus on Talja, Tuominen and Savolainen. For others see Julien (1999) and Olsson (2004).

Talja and Tuominen are not the first, or only, to emphasize the need for contextual consideration in information studies. The work of Talja and other social constructionists can be seen as the continuation of arguments for more context in information studies. Discussion can be found in Capurro (1992) and broadly, including historical developments in Järvelin and Ingwersen (2004).

The prime example of this is the Tetris case in Clark and Chalmers (1998, pp. 10,11).

For specific discussion see Clark and Thornton (1997, pp. 57‐67).

I have not touched on criticisms of EM for reasons of space. For a wider analysis of EM including criticisms see Haugeland (1998); Jackendoff (1996); Eliasmith (1996); Van Gelder (1995); Clark (2001a, pp. 120‐139).

Andy Clark offers the core of this argument in Clark (1997, p. 207).

For a full discussion of Scrabble strategies in this theme see Kirsh (1995).

Of similar worthwhile consideration is the work of Bonnie Nardi developing applications of the socio‐cognitive viewpoint through diverse information ecologies(Nardi and O'Day, 2000). The heterogeneous mixture of materials, people and practice has strong possible links with the argument presented in this paper.

Corresponding author

George Adam Holland can be contacted at: [email protected]

References

Bechtel, W. (1996), “What knowledge must be in the head in order to acquire language”, in Velichkovsky, B. and Rumbaugh, D. (Eds), Communicating Meaning: The Evolution and Development of Language, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ.

Boone, M. (2002), “Library design – the architects view. A discussion with Tom Findley”, Lib High Tech, Vol. 20 No. 3, pp. 38892.

Bradley, S. and Woodling, G. (2000), “Accommodating future business intelligence: new work‐space and work‐time challenges for management and design”, Library Review, Vol. 18 No. 3, pp. 1627.

Brand, J. (2003), “The architecture of change”, Journal of Property Management, June, No. 68.

Capurro, R. (1992), “What is information science for? A philosophical reflection”, in Vakkari, P. and Cronin, B. (Eds), Conceptions of Library and Information Science: Historical, Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives, Taylor Graham, London, pp. 8298.

Carruthers, P. (1996), Language, Thought, and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Clark, A. (1997), Being There, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Clark, A. (1998), “Magic words: how language augments human computation”, in Carruthers, P. and Boucher, J. (Eds), Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 16283.

Clark, A. (2001a), Mindware, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Clark, A. (2001b), “Reasons, robots and extended mind”, Mind & Language, No. 16.

Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. (1998), “The extended mind”, Analysis, Vol. 58, pp. 1023.

Clark, A. and Thornton, C. (1997), “Trading spaces: connectionism and the limits of uninformed learning”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Vol. 20, pp. 5767.

Davenport, E. and Bruce, I. (2002), “Innovation, knowledge management and the use of space: questioning assumptions about non‐traditional office work”, Journal of Information Science, Vol. 28 No. 3, pp. 22530.

Deheane, S., Sperke, E., Pinel, P., Strenescu, R. and Tviskin, S. (1999), “Sources of mathematic thinking: behavioral and brain imaging evidence”, Science, Vol. 284, pp. 9704.

Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained, Little and Brown, New York, NY.

Dennett, D. (1994), “Labeling and learning”, Mind & Language, Vol. 8, pp. 5408.

Eliasmith, C. (1996), “The third contender: a critical examination of the dynamicist theory of cognition”, Philosophical Psychology, Vol. 9 No. 4.

Haugeland, J. (1998), “Mind embodied and embedded”, in Haugeland, J. (Ed.), Having Thought, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

Hjørland, B. (1998), “Theory and metatheory of information science: a new interpretation”, Journal of Documentation, Vol. 54, pp. 60621.

Hjørland, B. (2002), “Epistemology and the socio‐cognitive perspective in information science”, Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, Vol. 53 No. 4, pp. 25770.

Hjørland, B. and Albrechtesen, H. (1995), “Toward a new horizon in information science: domain analysis”, Journal of the American Society for Information Science, Vol. 46, pp. 40025.

Huang, J. (2001), “Future space: a new blueprint for business architecture”, Harvard Business Review, April.

Hutchins, E. (1995), Cognition in the Wild, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Jackendoff, R. (1996), “How language helps us think”, Pragmatics and Cognition, Vol. 4 No. 1, pp. 134.

Järvelin, K. and Ingwersen, P. (2004), “Information seeking research needs extension towards tasks and technology”, Information Research, Vol. 10 No. 1, available at: http://InformationR.net/ir/10‐1/paper212.html.

Julien, H. (1999), “Constructing ‘users’ in library and information science”, Aslib Proceedings, Vol. 51 No. 6, pp. 2069.

Kirsh, D. (1995), “The intelligent use of space”, Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 72, pp. 152.

Nardi, B. and O'Day, V. (2000), Information Ecologies: Using Technology with Heart, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

Olsson, M. (2004), “Understanding users: context, communication and construction”, paper presented at ALIA 2004: Challenging Ideas, Gold Coast, 21‐24 September.

Raskin, J.D. (2002), “Constructivism in psychology: personal construct psychology, radical constructivism, and social constructionism”, in Raskin, J.D. and Bridges, S.K. (Eds), Studies in Meaning: Exploring Constructivist Psychology, Pace University Press, New York, NY, pp. 125.

Talja, S. (1997), “Constituting ‘information’ and ‘user’ as research objects: a theory of knowledge formations as an alternative to the information‐man theory”, in Vakkari, P., Savolainen, R. and Dervin, B. (Eds), Information Seeking in Context, Taylor Graham, London, pp. 8196.

Tuominen, K., Talja, S. and Savolainen, R. (2002), “Discourse, cognition and reality: towards a social constructionist metatheory for library and information science”, in Fidel, R., Bruce, H., Ingwersen, P. and Vakkari, P. (Eds), Emerging Frameworks and Methods: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Conceptions of Library and Information Science (CoLIS4), Libraries Unlimited, Seattle, WA, pp. 27183.

Tuominen, K., Talja, S. and Savolainen, R. (2005), “The social constructionist viewpoint on information practices”, in McKechnie, L. (Ed.), Theories of Information Behaviour, Information Today, Medford, NJ.

Vakkari, P. (1997), “Information seeking in context: a challenging metatheory”, in Vakkari, P., Savolainen, R. and Dervin, B. (Eds), Information Seeking in Context, Taylor Graham, London and Los Angeles, CA.

Van Gelder, T. (1995), “What could cognition be, if not computational?”, Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 91.

Related articles