Jump to content

Pasquale Galluppi: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Bluemoose (talk | contribs)
catholic/1911 import
 
No edit summary
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit Advanced mobile edit
 
(44 intermediate revisions by 35 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Italian philosopher (1770-1846)}}
'''Pasquale Galluppi''' ([[2 April]] [[1770]], [[Tropea], [[Calabria]] - [[13 December]], [[1846]] [[Naples]]) was an [[Italy|Italian]] philosopher, from 1831 he was a professor at the [[University of Naples]]. His philosophy is a mixture of assent to and dissent from [[Descartes]], the French and English sensists, [[Kant]], and the Scottish school of Reid. [[Cartesianism]] tempered by the modifications introduced into it by Leibniz, Wolf, and Genovesi, was the system in which Galluppi's mind was trained. The problem of human knowledge was his chief preoccupation. He maintained the objective reality of our knowledge, which he based on the testimony of consciousness, making us aware not only of our internal experience, but also of the external causes to which it is due. This theory was aimed at Kant, though Galluppi agreed with him that space and time are [[a priori]] forms in the mind. Against the sensists, he denied that the mind was merely passive or receptive, and held that like a builder it arranged and ordered the materials supplied it, deducing therefrom new truths which sensation alone could never reach. He threw no light, however, on the difference between sensory and intellectual knowledge. This was the great weakness of his argument against the Scottish school, that the soul perceives not only its own affections or the qualities of bodies, but also its own substance and that of things outside itself. It was also natural that Galluppi should be foremost in attacking the theories of Rosemini concerning the idea of God as the first object of our knowledge: and it was this polemic (quiet enough in itself) which drew public attention to the Roveretan philosopher.
{{Infobox philosopher
| honorific_prefix =
| name = <!-- include middle initial, if not specified in birth_name -->
| native_name = <!-- add name in the philosopher's language or script if different from the English name -->
| honorific_suffix =
| image = Statue of Pasquale Galluppi - Tropea - Italy 2015 (2).JPG
| image_size =
| alt =
| caption = Pasquale Galluppi
| other_names =
| birth_name = <!-- only use if different from name -->
| birth_date = {{birth date|1770|4|2}}
| birth_place = [[Tropea]], [[Kingdom of Sicily]]
| death_date = {{death date and age|1846|12|13|1770|4|2}}
| death_place = [[Naples]], [[Kingdom of the Two Sicilies]]
| death_cause =
| nationality = [[Italy|Italian]]
| parents = Vincenzo Galluppi and Lucrezia Galluppi
| spouse = {{marriage|Barbara d'Aquino|1794}}
| children = 14
| family =
| relatives =
| education =
| alma_mater = [[University of Naples Federico II]]
| occupation = Philosopher
| notable_works = <!-- use "notable_works" in place of "books" parameter (deprecated) -->
| awards =
| signature =
| signature_type =
| signature_size =
| signature_alt =
| era =
| region = {{tree list}}
* [[Western philosophy]]
** [[Italian philosophy]]{{tree list/end}}
| school_tradition =
| institutions = [[University of Naples Federico II]]
| thesis_title = <!--(or | thesis1_title = and | thesis2_title = )-->
| thesis_url = <!--(or | thesis1_url = and | thesis2_url = )-->
| thesis_year = <!--(or | thesis1_year = and | thesis2_year = )-->
| doctoral_advisor = <!--(or | doctoral_advisors = )-->
| academic_advisors =
| doctoral_students =
| notable_students =
| language =
| main_interests =
| notable_ideas =
| website = <!-- {{URL|example.com}} -->
}}
'''Pasquale Galluppi''' (2 April 1770 – 13 December 1846) was an Italian [[philosopher]].


==Biography and philosophy==
The morality of our actions, according to Galluppi, depends on the notion of duty which springs from the very nature of man. He never made use of the phrase "categoric imperative", but everything goes to show that on that point he did not completely escape Kant's influence: and although he asserted as the two great moral commandments "Be just" and "Be beneficent", he none the less approved of Kant's moral principle. Hence we do not find in him any hint as to the connection between the moral law and God, beyond the statement that God must reward virtue and punish vice. Against the Scottish school, on the other hand, he denied that morality depends on the feelings. His theodicy is well within the limits of that of Leibniz, and therefore admits not only the possibility of revelation, but also the divinity of Christianity. The care and clearness of his style made his works very popular; but when the Hegelianism of the Neapolitan school became the fashion in non-Catholic circles of thought, and Scholasticism regained its hold among Catholics, Galluppi's philosophy quickly lost ground. He always kept aloof from political questions; and his works were planned and written in his own home, amidst the noise and bustle of a large and happy family.
Galluppi was born at [[Tropea]], [[Calabria]], into the patrician [[Galluppi|Galluppi family]]. From 1831 he was a professor at the [[University of Naples]], where he died in 1846.


His philosophy is a mixture of assent to and dissent from [[Descartes]], the French and English [[sensist]]s, [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], and the Scottish school of [[Thomas Reid]]. [[Cartesianism]] tempered by the modifications introduced into it by [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Wolff]], and [[Genovesi]], was the system in which Galluppi's mind was trained.
His principal works are;

* ''Saggio filosofico sulla critica della conoscenza umana'', 4 vols;
The problem of human knowledge was Galuppi's chief preoccupation. He maintained the [[objective reality]] of knowledge, which he based on the testimony of [[consciousness]], making humans aware not only of their internal experience, but also of the external causes to which it is due. This theory was aimed at Kant, though Galluppi agreed with him that space and time are ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' forms in the mind. Against the sensists, he denied that the mind was merely passive or receptive, and held that like a builder it arranged and ordered the materials supplied it, deducing therefrom new truths which sensation alone could never reach. He threw no light, however, on the difference between [[Empirical evidence|sensory]] and intellectual knowledge. This was the great weakness of his argument against the Scottish school, that the soul perceives not only its own affections or the qualities of bodies, but also its own substance and that of things outside itself. It was also natural that Galluppi should be foremost in attacking the theories of [[Antonio Rosmini-Serbati|Rosmini]] concerning the idea of [[God]] as the first object of human knowledge: and it was this [[polemic]] (quiet enough in itself) which drew public attention to the Roveretan philosopher.
* ''Lettere sulle vicende della filosofia da Cartesio a Kant'';

* ''Elementi di Filosofica''; ''Lezioni di Logica e Metafisica'';
The morality of actions, according to Galluppi, depends on the notion of duty which springs from human nature. He never made use of the phrase "categoric imperative", but everything goes to show that on that point he did not completely escape Kant's influence: and although he asserted as the two great moral commandments "Be just" and "Be beneficent", he nonetheless approved of Kant's moral principle. Therefore, he does not draw any connection between the moral law and God, beyond the statement that God must reward [[virtue]] and punish [[vice]]. Against the Scottish school, on the other hand, he denied that morality depends on the feelings. His [[theodicy]] is well within the limits of that of Leibniz, and therefore admits not only the possibility of revelation, but also the divinity of [[Christianity]].
* ''Filosofia della volontà'';

* ''Considerazioni filosofiche sull' idealismo trascendentale''.
The care and clearness of Galluppi's style made his works very popular; but when the [[Hegel]]ianism of the Neapolitan school became the fashion in non-Catholic circles of thought, and [[Scholasticism]] regained its hold among [[Catholics]], Galluppi's philosophy quickly lost ground. He always kept aloof from political questions; and his works were planned and written in his own home, amidst the noise and bustle of a large and happy family.
* ''Storia della Filisofia'' only the first volume completed.

==Selected works==
* {{lang|it|Saggio filosofico sulla critica della conoscenza umana}}, 4 vols
* {{lang|it|Lettere sulle vicende della filosofia da Cartesio a Kant}}
* {{lang|it|Elementi di Filosofica}}
* {{lang|it|Lezioni di Logica e Metafisica}}
* {{lang|it|Filosofia della volontà}}
* {{lang|it|Considerazioni filosofiche sull' idealismo trascendentale}}
* {{lang|it|Storia della Filisofia}} (only the first volume completed)


==References==
==References==
Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1909). Galluppi, Pasquale, Philosopher. ''Catholic Encyclopedia''. Vol 6. New York: The Encyclopaedia Press. p. 370.
{{Catholic}}
*{{CE1913|wstitle=Pasquale Galluppi}}

{{Authority control}}


[[Category:Italian philosophers|Galluppi, Pasquale]]
{{DEFAULTSORT:Galluppi, Pasquale}}
[[Category:1770 births|Galluppi, Pasquale]]
[[Category:1770 births]]
[[Category:1846 deaths|Galluppi, Pasquale]]
[[Category:1846 deaths]]
[[Category:People from the Province of Vibo Valentia]]
[[Category:People from the Kingdom of Naples]]
[[Category:Kingdom of the Two Sicilies people]]
[[Category:18th-century Italian philosophers]]
[[Category:19th-century Italian philosophers]]

Latest revision as of 10:38, 21 June 2024

Pasquale Galluppi
Pasquale Galluppi
Born(1770-04-02)April 2, 1770
DiedDecember 13, 1846(1846-12-13) (aged 76)
NationalityItalian
Alma materUniversity of Naples Federico II
OccupationPhilosopher
Spouse
Barbara d'Aquino
(m. 1794)
Children14
Parent(s)Vincenzo Galluppi and Lucrezia Galluppi
Region
InstitutionsUniversity of Naples Federico II

Pasquale Galluppi (2 April 1770 – 13 December 1846) was an Italian philosopher.

Biography and philosophy

[edit]

Galluppi was born at Tropea, Calabria, into the patrician Galluppi family. From 1831 he was a professor at the University of Naples, where he died in 1846.

His philosophy is a mixture of assent to and dissent from Descartes, the French and English sensists, Kant, and the Scottish school of Thomas Reid. Cartesianism tempered by the modifications introduced into it by Leibniz, Wolff, and Genovesi, was the system in which Galluppi's mind was trained.

The problem of human knowledge was Galuppi's chief preoccupation. He maintained the objective reality of knowledge, which he based on the testimony of consciousness, making humans aware not only of their internal experience, but also of the external causes to which it is due. This theory was aimed at Kant, though Galluppi agreed with him that space and time are a priori forms in the mind. Against the sensists, he denied that the mind was merely passive or receptive, and held that like a builder it arranged and ordered the materials supplied it, deducing therefrom new truths which sensation alone could never reach. He threw no light, however, on the difference between sensory and intellectual knowledge. This was the great weakness of his argument against the Scottish school, that the soul perceives not only its own affections or the qualities of bodies, but also its own substance and that of things outside itself. It was also natural that Galluppi should be foremost in attacking the theories of Rosmini concerning the idea of God as the first object of human knowledge: and it was this polemic (quiet enough in itself) which drew public attention to the Roveretan philosopher.

The morality of actions, according to Galluppi, depends on the notion of duty which springs from human nature. He never made use of the phrase "categoric imperative", but everything goes to show that on that point he did not completely escape Kant's influence: and although he asserted as the two great moral commandments "Be just" and "Be beneficent", he nonetheless approved of Kant's moral principle. Therefore, he does not draw any connection between the moral law and God, beyond the statement that God must reward virtue and punish vice. Against the Scottish school, on the other hand, he denied that morality depends on the feelings. His theodicy is well within the limits of that of Leibniz, and therefore admits not only the possibility of revelation, but also the divinity of Christianity.

The care and clearness of Galluppi's style made his works very popular; but when the Hegelianism of the Neapolitan school became the fashion in non-Catholic circles of thought, and Scholasticism regained its hold among Catholics, Galluppi's philosophy quickly lost ground. He always kept aloof from political questions; and his works were planned and written in his own home, amidst the noise and bustle of a large and happy family.

Selected works

[edit]
  • Saggio filosofico sulla critica della conoscenza umana, 4 vols
  • Lettere sulle vicende della filosofia da Cartesio a Kant
  • Elementi di Filosofica
  • Lezioni di Logica e Metafisica
  • Filosofia della volontà
  • Considerazioni filosofiche sull' idealismo trascendentale
  • Storia della Filisofia (only the first volume completed)

References

[edit]

Herbermann, Charles, ed. (1909). Galluppi, Pasquale, Philosopher. Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol 6. New York: The Encyclopaedia Press. p. 370.

  •  This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainHerbermann, Charles, ed. (1913). "Pasquale Galluppi". Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.