Jump to content

Vitalism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Dematt (talk | contribs)
m link circular reasoning
 
(928 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Belief about living organisms}}
:''This article is about the non-[[mechanism (philosophy)|mechanist]] philosophy. For other uses, see [[vital]]''
{{About|the non-mechanist philosophy|the Jain philosophical concept|Vitalism (Jainism)|other uses|Vital (disambiguation)}}
'''Vitalism''', as defined by the Merriam-Webster dictionary, [http://www.m-w.com/dictionary/vitalism] is
{{Alternative medicine sidebar |fringe}}


'''Vitalism''' is a belief that starts from the premise that "living organisms are fundamentally different from non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or are governed by different principles than are inanimate things."<ref name=Bechtel>{{cite encyclopedia |url= http://mechanism.ucsd.edu/teaching/philbio/vitalism.htm |author=Bechtel, William; Williamson, Robert C. |year=1998 |title=Vitalism |editor=E. Craig |encyclopedia=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge}}</ref>{{efn|[[Stéphane Leduc]] and [[D'Arcy Thompson]] (''[[On Growth and Form]]'') published a series of works that in Evelyn Fox Keller's view took on the task of uprooting the remaining vestiges of vitalism, essentially by showing that the principles of physics and chemistry were enough, by themselves, to account for the growth and development of biological form.<ref>Evelyn Fox Keller, ''Making Sense of Life Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines''. Harvard University Press, 2002.</ref> On the other hand, [[Michael Ruse]] notes that D'Arcy Thompson's avoidance of [[natural selection]] had an "odor of spirit forces" about it.<ref name=Ruse>{{cite book |author1=Ruse, Michael |editor1-last=Henning |editor1-first=Brian G. |editor2-last=Scarfe |editor2-first=Adam |title=Beyond Mechanism: Putting Life Back Into Biology |date=2013 |publisher=Lexington Books |page=419 |chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=3VtosxAtq-EC|chapter=17. From Organicism to Mechanism-and Halfway Back?|isbn=9780739174371 }}</ref>}} Where vitalism explicitly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy", "''[[élan vital]]''" (coined by vitalist [[Henri Bergson]]), "vital force", or "'''''vis vitalis'''''", which some equate with the [[soul (spirit)|soul]]. In the 18th and 19th centuries, vitalism was [[Alternatives to evolution by natural selection|discussed among biologists]], between those who felt that the known mechanics of physics would eventually explain the difference between life and non-life and vitalists who argued that the processes of life could not be reduced to a mechanistic process. Vitalist biologists such as [[Johannes Reinke]] proposed [[testable]] [[hypotheses]] meant to show inadequacies with mechanistic explanations, but their experiments failed to provide support for vitalism. Biologists now consider vitalism in this sense to have been refuted by [[Scientific evidence|empirical evidence]], and hence regard it either as a [[Superseded scientific theories|superseded scientific theory]],<ref name="Williams2003">{{cite book |last=Williams |first=Elizabeth Ann |title=A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier |url= https://books.google.com/books?id=AvqYl4sdwaYC&pg=PA4 |year=2003 |publisher=Ashgate |isbn=978-0-7546-0881-3 |page=4}}</ref> or, since the mid-20th century, as a [[pseudoscience]].<ref name="DevBio"/><ref name="ps"/>
:1 : a doctrine that the functions of a living organism are due to a vital principle distinct from physicochemical forces
:2 : a doctrine that the processes of life are not explicable by the laws of physics and chemistry alone and that life is in some part self-determining''


Vitalism has a long history in [[medical]] philosophies: many [[traditional medicine|traditional healing]] practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces.
Where vitalism explictly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy" or "[[élan vital]]", which some equate with the "[[soul]]".


== History ==
Vitalism has a long history in [[medical]] philosophies: most [[traditional medicine|traditional healing]] practices posited that disease was the result of some imbalance in the vital energies which distinguish living from non-living matter. In the Western tradition, these vital forces were identified as the [[The four humours|humour]]s; eastern traditions posited similar forces such as [[qi]], [[prana]], etc. More recently, vitalistic thinking has been identified in the naive biological notions of children <ref>Inagaki K, Hatano G (2004) Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology. ''Trends Cogn Sci'' 2004 8:356-62 PMID 15335462 </ref>.


===Ancient times===
==Development of vitalism==
The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back at least to [[ancient Egypt]].<ref>Jidenu, Paulin (1996) ''African Philosophy, 2nd Ed.'' Indiana University Press, {{ISBN|0-253-21096-8}}, p.16.</ref> In [[Greek philosophy]], the [[Milesian school]] proposed natural explanations [[deductive argument|deduced]] from [[materialism]] and [[Mechanism (philosophy)|mechanism]]. However, by the time of [[Lucretius]], this account was supplemented, (for example, by the unpredictable ''[[clinamen]]'' of [[Epicurus]]), and in [[Stoic physics]], the ''[[pneuma]]'' assumed the role of ''[[logos]]''. [[Galen]] believed the lungs draw ''pneuma'' from the air, which the blood communicates throughout the body.<ref>{{harvnb|Birch|Cobb|1985|p=75}}</ref>
[[Image:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|right|[[Plato]] (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of ''[[The School of Athens]]''<!-- this should link to an article about the famous artwork -->, a fresco by [[Raphael]]. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, whilst Plato points up to the heavens showing his belief in the ultimate truth.]]
The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back to at least 384-322 BC. While vitalist ideas have been commonplace in traditional medicine,<ref> e.g. Zarrilli PB. (1989) Three bodies of practice in a traditional South Indian martial art. ''Soc Sci Med'' 28:1289-309. PMID 2660283,
Noll R (1989) What has really been learned about shamanism? ''J Psychoactive Drugs'' 21:47-50 PMID 2656952 and Merchant J. (2006) The developmental/emergent model of archetype, its implications and its application to shamanism. ''J Anal Psychol''51:125-44 PMID 16451325
</ref> attempts to construct workable scientific models date from the 1600s, when it was argued that matter existed in two radically different forms, observable by their behavior with regard to heat. These two forms of matter were termed ''organic'' and ''inorganic''. Inorganic matter could be melted, but could also be restored to its former condition by removing the heat. Organic compounds "cooked" when heated, transforming into new forms that could not be restored to the original. It was argued that the essential difference between the two forms of matter was the "vital force", present only in organic material.


===Medieval===
Aided by the invention of the [[microscope]] in the [[16th century]], the [[germ theory]] of disease challenged the role of vitalism in Western medicine, and the roles of the organs of the human [[anatomy]] in the maintenance of life became better understood, reducing the need to explain things in terms of mystical "vital forces". Nevertheless, vitalist ideas were still thought necessary by many scientists to explain how organisms maintained life.
In Europe, medieval physics was influenced by the idea of ''pneuma'', helping to shape later [[aether theories]].


===Early modern===
The [[phlogiston theory]], developed by [[J. J. Becher]] and [[Georg Stahl]] late in the 17th century held that all flammable materials contain phlogiston, a substance without color, odor, taste, or weight that is liberated in burning. Once burned, the "dephlogisticated" substance was held to be in its "true" form, the calx. This vitalist theory led to the prediction that substances should lose weight after burning; it was tested and falsified by the experimental demonstration that, when combustion took place in a closed, sealed system, no weight was lost or gained.
Vitalists included English anatomist [[Francis Glisson]] (1597–1677) and the Italian doctor [[Marcello Malpighi]] (1628–1694).<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76">{{harvnb|Birch|Cobb|1985|pp=76–78}}</ref> [[Caspar Friedrich Wolff]] (1733–1794) is considered to be the father of [[Epigenesis (biology)|epigenesis]] in [[embryology]], that is, he marks the point when embryonic development began to be described in terms of the proliferation of cells rather than the incarnation of a preformed soul. However, this degree of empirical observation was not matched by a mechanistic philosophy: in his ''[[Theoria Generationis]]'' (1759), he tried to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a ''vis essentialis'' (an organizing, formative force). [[Carl Reichenbach]] (1788–1869) later developed the theory of [[Odic force]], a form of life-energy that permeates living things.


In the 17th century, modern science responded to [[Isaac Newton|Newton]]'s [[action at a distance]] and the mechanism of [[Cartesian dualism]] with vitalist theories: that whereas the chemical transformations undergone by non-living substances are reversible, so-called "organic" matter is permanently altered by chemical transformations (such as cooking).<ref name=Ede/>
In the early 19th century, [[Jöns Jakob Berzelius]], known as one of the "fathers" of modern chemistry, rejected mystical vitalism, but nevertheless argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions. The geologist [[Carl Reichenbach]], considered to be one of the top 1,000 scientists of all time, later developed the theory of [[Odic force]], a form of life-energy that permeated living things; this concept never gained much support despite Reichenbach's prestige.


As worded by [[Charles Birch]] and [[John B. Cobb]], "the claims of the vitalists came to the fore again" in the 18th century:<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/> "[[Georg Ernst Stahl]]'s followers were active as were others, such as the physician genius [[Xavier Bichat|Francis Xavier Bichat]] of the Hotel Dieu."<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/> However, "Bichat moved from the tendency typical of the French vitalistic tradition to progressively free himself from [[metaphysics]] in order to combine with hypotheses and theories which accorded to the scientific criteria of physics and chemistry."<ref>{{harvnb|''History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences''|p=238}}</ref> [[John Hunter (surgeon)|John Hunter]] recognised "a 'living principle' in addition to mechanics."<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/>
==Mesmerism==
A popular vitalist theory of the eighteenth century was "animal magnetism", in the theories of [[Franz Anton Mesmer]] (1734–1815). So popular did Mesmer's ideas become that King [[Louis XVI]] of France appointed two commissions to investigate [[mesmerism]]; one was led by [[Joseph-Ignace Guillotin]], the other, led by [[Benjamin Franklin]], included [[Bailly]] and [[Lavoisier]]. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and trances. In Franklin’s garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid", but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier’s house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid." This was an important example of the power of reason and controlled experiment to falsify theories.
<ref>(Best M, Neuhauser D, Slavin L (2003) Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped. ''Qual Saf Health Care'' 12:232-3 PMID 12792017 [http://qhc.bmjjournals.com/cgi/content/full/12/3/232]</ref> It is sometimes claimed <ref> e.g. Williams Bechtel W. Richardson RC (1998). Vitalism. In Craig E.(Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.</ref> that vitalist ideas are unscientific because they are not testable; here at least is an example of a vitalist theory that was not merely testable but actually falsified.


[[Johann Friedrich Blumenbach]] was influential in establishing epigenesis in the life sciences in 1781 with his publication of ''Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte''. Blumenbach cut up freshwater ''[[Hydra (zoology)|Hydra]]'' and established that the removed parts would regenerate. He inferred the presence of a "formative drive" (''Bildungstrieb'') in living matter. But he pointed out that this name,
==Vitalism in the foundations of chemistry==
{{blockquote|like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification.}}
In the history of chemistry, vitalism played a pivotal role, giving rise to the basic distinction between organic and inorganic subtances, following Aristotle's distinction between the mineral kingdom and the animal and vegetative kingdoms. <ref>see Schummerr J (2003) The notion of nature in chemistry. ''Stud Hist Phil Sci'' 34:705-736 for this account within an extensive review on vitalist notions in the foundations of chemistry [http://www.joachimschummer.net/papers/2003_NatureChemistry_SHPS.pdf]</ref>. The basic premise of these vitalist notions was that organic materials differed from inorganic materials in possessing a "vital force", accordingly, vitalist theory predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components. However, as chemical techniques advanced, [[Friedrich Wöhler]] synthesised [[urea]] from inorganic components in 1828 [http://content.karger.com/ProdukteDB/produkte.asp?Aktion=ShowPDF&ProduktNr=223979&Ausgabe=225203&ArtikelNr=13463&filename=13463.pdf]. Wohler subsequently wrote to Berzelius, saying that he had witnessed "The great tragedy of science, the slaying of a beautiful hypothesis by an ugly fact." The "beautiful hypothesis" was vitalism; the ugly fact was a dish of urea crystals. <ref> cited by Schummerr J, op cit, [http://www.joachimschummer.net/papers/2003_NatureChemistry_SHPS.pdf]</ref>


===19th century===
According to the conventional view of the subsequent progress of chemistry, further discoveries pushed aside the "vital force" explanation, as more and more life processes came to be described in chemical or physical terms. However, contemporary accounts do not support the claim that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. ''The Wöhler Myth'', as it was called by historian of science Peter J. Ramberg , originates from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931 which, "Ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until "one afternoon the miracle happened"." <ref>[http://www.bioethicsjournal.com/past/cheng.html]</ref>
{{further|Alternatives to Darwinism}}
[[File:Sample of Urea.jpg|thumb|right|The synthesis of [[urea]] in the early 19th century from [[inorganic chemistry|inorganic compounds]] was [[counterevidence]] for the vitalist hypothesis that only organisms could make the components of living things.]]


[[Jöns Jakob Berzelius]], one of the early 19th century founders of modern [[chemistry]], argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions.<ref name=Ede>Ede, Andrew. (2007) ''The Rise and Decline of Colloid Science in North America, 1900–1935: The Neglected Dimension'', p. 23</ref> Berzelius contended that compounds could be distinguished by whether they required any organisms in their [[Biosynthesis|synthesis]] ([[organic compounds]]) or whether they did not ([[inorganic compounds]]).<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Wilkinson|first=Ian|date=10 June 2002|title=History of Clinical Chemistry|journal=EJIFCC|volume=13|issue=4|pages=114–118|issn=1650-3414|pmc=6208063}}</ref> Vitalist chemists predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components, but [[Friedrich Wöhler]] synthesised [[urea]] from inorganic components in 1828.<ref>{{Cite journal|url=https://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/13463|title=Vitalism and Synthesis of Urea|first1=E.|last1=Kinne-Saffran|first2=R. K. H.|last2=Kinne|date=August 7, 1999|journal=American Journal of Nephrology|volume=19|issue=2|pages=290–294|via=www.karger.com|doi=10.1159/000013463|pmid=10213830|s2cid=71727190}}</ref> However, contemporary accounts do not support the common belief that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. This ''Wöhler Myth'', as historian Peter Ramberg called it, originated from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931, which, "ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until 'one afternoon the miracle happened'".<ref>{{cite journal|doi=10.1179/amb.2000.47.3.170|pmid=11640223|title=The Death of Vitalism and the Birth of Organic Chemistry: Wohler's Urea Synthesis and the Disciplinary Identity of Organic Chemistry.|journal=Ambix|volume=47|issue=3|pages=170–195|year=2000|last1=Ramberg|first1=Peter J.|s2cid=44613876}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Schummer |first1=Joachim |title=The notion of nature in chemistry |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A |date=December 2003 |volume=34 |issue=4 |pages=705–736 |doi=10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00050-5|bibcode=2003SHPSA..34..705S |url=http://www.joachimschummer.net/papers/2003_NatureChemistry_SHPS.pdf}}</ref>{{efn|In 1845, [[Adolph Kolbe]] succeeded in making acetic acid from inorganic compounds, and in the 1850s, [[Marcellin Berthelot]] repeated this feat for numerous organic compounds. In retrospect, Wöhler's work was the beginning of the end of Berzelius's vitalist hypothesis, but only in retrospect, as Ramberg had shown.}}
[[Image:Tableau Louis Pasteur.jpg|thumb|left|150px|Louis Pasteur in his laboratory, painting by [[Albert Edelfelt|A. Edelfeldt]] in [[1885]].]]
Some of the greatest scientific minds of the time continued to investigate these vital properties. [[Louis Pasteur]], shortly after his famous rebuttal of spontaneous generation, made several experiments that he felt supported the vital concepts of life. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." In 1858, Pasteur showed that fermentation only occurs when living cells are present and, that fermentation only occurs in the absence of oxygen; he was thus led to describe fermentation as ‘life without air’. He found no support for the claims of Berzelius, [[Liebig]], Traube and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, and so he concluded that fermentation was a "vital action" "


Between 1833 and 1844, [[Johannes Peter Müller]] wrote a book on [[physiology]] called ''Handbuch der Physiologie'', which became the leading textbook in the field for much of the nineteenth century. The book showed Müller's commitments to vitalism; he questioned why organic matter differs from inorganic, then proceeded to chemical analyses of the blood and lymph. He describes in detail the circulatory, lymphatic, respiratory, digestive, endocrine, nervous, and sensory systems in a wide variety of animals but explains that the presence of a [[soul]] makes each organism an indivisible whole. He claimed that the behaviour of light and sound waves showed that living organisms possessed a life-energy for which physical laws could never fully account.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Otis |first1=Laura |title=Johannes Peter Müller (1801-1858) |url=https://vlp.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/pdfgen/essays/enc22.pdf |website=Virtual Laboratory: Essays and Resources on the Experimentalization of Life (Max Planck Institute) |date=October 2004}}</ref>
==Vitalism in Psychology==
[[Image:Hall Freud Jung in front of Clark 1909.jpg|thumb|right|Group photo 1909 in front of [[Clark University]]. Front row from left: Sigmund Freud, [[Granville Stanley Hall]], [[Carl Jung]]. Back row from left: [[Abraham A. Brill]], [[Ernest Jones]], [[Sandor Ferenczi]].]]


[[File:Albert Edelfelt - Louis Pasteur - 1885.jpg|thumb|upright|left|[[Louis Pasteur]] argued that only life could catalyse [[fermentation]]. Painting by [[Albert Edelfelt]], 1885]]
Perhaps more than any other area of science, [[psychology]] has been rich in vitalist concepts, particularly through the ideas of [[Sigmund Freud]] and [[Carl Jung]]. Freud was a student of the notable anti-vitalist Herman von Helmhotz, and initially struggled to express his concepts in strictly neurological terms. Abandoning this effort as fruitless, he became famous for his theory that behaviour is determined by an unconscious mind, of which the waking mind is unaware. In 1923, in ''[[The Ego and the Id]]'', he developed the concept of "[[psychic energy]]" as the energy by which the work of the personality is performed.
[[Louis Pasteur]] (1822–1895) after his famous rebuttal of [[spontaneous generation]], performed several experiments that he felt supported vitalism. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." Rejecting the claims of Berzelius, [[Liebig]], [[Moritz Traube|Traube]] and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, Pasteur concluded that fermentation was a "vital action".<ref name=Bechtel/>


===20th century===
Although Freud and Jung remain hugely influential, psychology has made a determined effort to rid itself of the most mystical of these concepts in an attempt to appear more like the "hard" sciences of chemistry and physics<ref> see Warren HC (1918) Mechanism Versus Vitalism, in the Domain of Psychology ''Phil Rev''27:597-615 [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108(191811)27%3A6%3C597%3AMVVITD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-E] and
Elkus SA (1911) Mechanism and Vitalism ''J Phil Psych Sci Meth'' 8: 355-8 [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0160-9335(19110622)8%3A13%3C355%3AMAV%3E2.0.CO%3B2-M] for examples of this debate within psychology </ref>. However, concepts for instance of [[mind]], or of [[intelligence]], and of motivational states such as [[anger]], [[fear]], [[anxiety]] and [[stress]], remain essentially higher level constructs, with observable correlates, but with no adequate low-level description of underlying mechanisms or processes. Whether such low-level descriptions are either possible or desirable is controversial, but some psychologists believe that further change is needed in psychology to eliminate all concepts which have no defined physico-chemical substrates [http://htpprints.yorku.ca/archive/00000011/00/HOE.htm]


[[Hans Driesch]] (1867–1941) interpreted his experiments as showing that life is not run by physicochemical laws.<ref name="DevBio">{{Cite web|url=http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?ch=10&id=110|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20061031180529/http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?ch=10&id=110|url-status=dead|title=Developmental Biology 8e Online: A Selective History of Induction|archivedate=October 31, 2006}}</ref> His main argument was that when one cuts up an embryo after its first division or two, each part grows into a complete adult. Driesch's reputation as an experimental biologist deteriorated as a result of his vitalistic theories, which scientists have seen since his time as pseudoscience.<ref name="DevBio" /><ref name=ps>{{cite book |last=Dyde |first=Sean |editor1-last=Normandin |editor1-first=Sebastian |editor2-last=Wolfe |editor2-first= T. Charles |title=Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightenment Life Science, 1800–2010 |chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=EQVAAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 |year=2013 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-007-2445-7 |page=104 |chapter=Chapter 5: Life and the Mind in Nineteenth-Century Britain |quote=In medicine and biology, vitalism has been seen as a philosophically-charged term, a pseudoscientific gloss that corrupted scientific practice …}}</ref> Vitalism is a superseded scientific hypothesis, and the term is sometimes used as a [[pejorative]] [[epithet]].<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://www.pep-web.org/document.php?id=aop.004.0041a|title=Psychic Energy: A Historical Perspective|first=R. M.|last=Galatzer-Levy|date=August 7, 1976|journal=Ann. Psychoanal.|volume=4|pages=41–61|via=PEP Web}}</ref> [[Ernst Mayr]] (1904–2005) wrote:
==Vitalism in Developmental Biology==
{{quote|It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine... The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Mayr|first1=Ernst|date=2002|url= http://www.biologie.uni-hamburg.de/b-online/e01_2/autonomy.htm |title=BOTANY ONLINE: Ernst MAYR: Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology |access-date=2006-09-24 |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20060926210457/http://www.biologie.uni-hamburg.de/b-online/e01_2/autonomy.htm |archive-date=2006-09-26 }}</ref>}}
[[Caspar Friedrich Wolff]] (1733-1794) is considered to be the father of epigenetic descriptive embryology. In his Theoria Generationis (1759), he tried to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a "vis essentialis", an organizing, formative force, and declared that "All believers in epigenesis are Vitalists." However, even early vitalists were aware that the vital forces that they proposed were to be understood ''metaphorically'', not ''literally''. For example, [[Johann Friedrich Blumenbach]], established [[epigenesis]] as the model of thought in the life sciences in 1781, with his publication of ''Über den Bildungstrieb and das Zeugungsgeschäfte.'' Blumenbach cut up freshwater polyps and established that the removed parts would regenerate; he inferred the presence of a "formative drive". an organic force, which he called "Bildungstrieb". He pointed out that this, "like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification."
{{quote|Vitalism has become so disreputable a belief in the last fifty years that no biologist alive today would want to be classified as a vitalist. Still, the remnants of vitalist thinking can be found in the work of [[Alistair Hardy]], [[Sewall Wright]], and [[Charles Birch]], who seem to believe in some sort of nonmaterial principle in organisms.<ref>Ernst Mayr ''Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist'' 1988, p. 13. {{ISBN|978-0674896666}}.</ref>}}


Other vitalists included [[Johannes Reinke]] and [[Oscar Hertwig]]. Reinke used the word ''neovitalism'' to describe his work, claiming that it would eventually be verified through experimentation, and that it was an improvement over the other vitalistic theories. The work of Reinke influenced [[Carl Jung]].<ref>{{Cite journal|url=https://www.academia.edu/6789277|title=Jung's concept of die Dominanten (the Dominants) (1997)|first=Richard|last=Noll|via=www.academia.edu}}</ref>
Vitalism was also important in the thinking of later [[teleology|teleologists]] such as [[Hans Driesch]] (1867-1941) [http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?ch=10&id=110]
In 1894, Driesch wrote a theoretical essay entitled ''Analytische Theorie der organischen Entwicklung'' where he declared that
:''Development starts with a few ordered manifoldnesses; but the manifoldnesses create, by interactions, new manifoldnesses, and these are able, by acting back on the original ones, to provoke new differences, and so on. With each new response, a new cause is immediately provided, and a new specific reactivity for further specific responses. We derive a complex structure from a simple one given in the egg.''
This insight, which can be seen as anticipating modern developmental biology, came from his experiments on [[sea urchin]] eggs; he observed that if an egg was divided in two, it nevertheless gave rise to a perfect, though small [[embryo]]. Driesch, already a famous biologist, thus became an avowed vitalist, and in so doing saw his retutation as a biologist ruined. He moved to Heidelberg and became a Professor of Natural Philosophy, seeing his vitalism an extension of Immanual [[Kant]]'s notion that the organism develops as if it had a purposeful intelligence.


[[John Scott Haldane]] adopted an anti-mechanist approach to biology and an [[idealist]] philosophy early on in his career. Haldane saw his work as a vindication of his belief that [[teleology]] was an essential concept in biology. His views became widely known with his first book ''Mechanism, life and personality'' in 1913.<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168">Bowler, Peter J. Reconciling science and religion: the debate in early-twentieth-century Britain, 2001, pp. 168–169. {{ISBN|978-0226068589}}.</ref> Haldane borrowed arguments from the vitalists to use against mechanism; however, he was not a vitalist. Haldane treated the organism as fundamental to biology: "we perceive the organism as a self-regulating entity", "every effort to analyze it into components that can be reduced to a mechanical explanation violates this central experience".<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168" /> The work of Haldane was an influence on [[organicism]]. Haldane stated that a purely mechanist interpretation could not account for the characteristics of life. Haldane wrote a number of books in which he attempted to show the invalidity of both vitalism and mechanist approaches to science. Haldane explained:
==Vitalist notions in the foundations of complementary medicine==
Some systems of complementary and [[alternative medicine]], such as as [[acupuncture]] and [[chiropractic]], emphasize a [[holistic]] approach to the cause and treatment of disease (see main articles on these subjects). They retain some concepts that were originally mystical, vitalist concepts, although in some cases they now use these metaphorically rather than as literally implying an animate essence. For example, "[[innate intelligence|Innate Intelligence]]" in [[chiropractic]] was introduced as an overtly religious sense of an internal guiding force; now it is also used to represent the physiological mechanisms of self-repair, including in particular the regulation of the [[immune system]] by the [[nervous system]][http://www.jcca-online.org/client/cca/JCCA.nsf/objects/Commentary+The+meanings+of+Innate/$file/3-Commentary%20Keating.pdf].


{{quote|We must find a different theoretical basis of biology, based on the observation that all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so coordinated that they express what is normal for an adult organism.|<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95" />}}
The founder of [[homeopathy]], Hahnemann, promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." However, as practised today, homeopathy simply rests on the premise of treating sick persons with extremely diluted agents that - in undiluted doses - are deemed to produce similar symptoms in a healthy individual. Thus modern expressions of homeopathy have largely excluded early vitalistic concepts, though whether they have gained any credibility as a result is debatable (see main article [[Homeopathy]])


By 1931, biologists had "almost unanimously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged belief."<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95">{{cite book |title=The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science|editor1-first=Mark A. |editor1-last=Bedau|editor1-link=Mark Bedau |editor2-first=Carol E.|editor2-last=Cleland |editor2-link= Carol Cleland |chapter=The Decline of Vitalism |first=Ernst |last=Mayr |author-link=Ernst Mayr |pages=93–95|quote=Yet considering how dominant vitalism was in biology and for how long a period it prevailed, it is surprising how rapidly and completely it collapsed. The last support of vitalism as a viable concept in biology disappeared about 1930." (p.&nbsp;94) From p.&nbsp;95: "Vitalism survived even longer in the writings of philosophers than it did in the writings of physicists. But so far as I know, there are no vitalists among the philosophers of biology who started publishing after 1965. Nor do I know of a single reputable living biologist who still supports straightforward vitalism. The few late twentieth-century biologists with vitalist leanings (A. Hardy, S. Wright, A. Portmann) are no longer alive. |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L3ycvNfa320C&pg=PA93 |publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] |year=2010 |isbn=9781139488655}}</ref>
==Vitalism in "New Age" mysticism==
Vitalism is also an aspect of many "[[New Age]]" theories. Examples include [[Rupert Sheldrake]]'s concept of "[[morphic resonance]]" - the idea of telepathy-type interconnections between organisms and of collective memories within species[http://www.sheldrake.org/papers/Morphic/morphic_intro.html], and revivals of Reichenbach's Odic force, which is sometimes used to explain [[Aura (paranormal)|colored auras]].<ref> See United States Patent 6016450, "Method and apparatus for stimulating the healing of living tissue using aura therapy" [http://www.freepatentsonline.com/6016450.html]</ref>[[Anthroposophy]], founded by Rudolf [[Steiner]], is a quasi-religious cult whose teachings, in Steiner's words, lead "from the spirit in the human being to the spirit in the universe." <ref>The Anthroposophical Society in America; website [http://www.anthroposophy.org/]</ref> An early form of sustainable agriculture, [[biodynamic agriculture]], was fostered by this movement.


==Emergentism ==
==Modern versions of vitalism in science==
{{main|Emergentism}}
Although scientific understanding of the [[biochemistry | biochemical processes]] which distinguish living from non-living matter has become increasingly sophisticated, so has the realization that these fundamental processes are incredibly complicated; no complete, [[reductionism|reductionist]] theory has yet been proposed which coordinates all of the actions which occur in a single [[cell (biology)|cell]] (let alone a higher organism).


Contemporary science and engineering sometimes describe [[emergence|emergent processes]], in which the properties of a system cannot be fully described in terms of the properties of the constituents.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Schultz |first=S.G. |title=A century of (epithelial) transport physiology: from vitalism to molecular cloning |journal=The American Journal of Physiology |volume=274 |issue=1 Pt 1 |pages=C13–23 |year=1998 |pmid=9458708 |doi=10.1152/ajpcell.1998.274.1.C13 |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gilbert |first1=S.F. |last2=Sarkar |first2=S. |title=Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century |journal=Developmental Dynamics |volume=219 |issue=1 |pages=1–9 |year=2000 |pmid=10974666 |doi=10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A |doi-access=free }}</ref> This may be because the properties of the constituents are not fully understood, or because the interactions between the individual constituents are important for the behavior of the system.
In terms of the [[biology]] of the cell, a type of "vitalism" can be recognized in contemporary molecular biology, for example in the proposal that some "high level features" of organisms, perhaps including even life itself, are examples of [[emergence|emergent process]]es which cannot be accurately described simply by understanding each of the chemical processes which occur in the cell in isolation from all the others <ref> see Berg EL, Kunkel EJ, Hytopoulos E. (2005) Biological complexity and drug discovery: a practical systems biology approach. ''Syst Biol'' 152:201-6 PMID 16986261 and see [http://ajpcell.physiology.org/cgi/reprint/274/1/C13.pdf.] for an explicit discussion of both historical and contemporary "vitalist" concepts in current epithelial cell physiology </ref>; When individual chemical processes form interconnected feedback cycles which produce products perpetuating these cycles rather than unconnected products, they can form systems with properties that the reactions, taken individually, lack <ref>e.g. see Gilbert SF, Sarkar S. (2000) Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century. ''Dev Dyn'' 219:1-9 for explicit discussion of relationship to vitalism. PMID 10974666 </ref>. Such emergent processes have been recognised as, for example, contributing to subcellular morphology <ref>
Tabony J (2006) Microtubules viewed as molecular ant colonies. ''Biol Cell'' 98:603-17 PMID 16968217 </ref>, developmental biology <ref>see e.g. Theise ND, d'Inverno M (2004) Understanding cell lineages as complex adaptive systems. ''Blood Cells Mol Dis'' 32:17-20 PMID 14757407 and Ruiz i Altaba A, Nguyen V, Palma V (2003) The emergent design of the neural tube: prepattern, SHH morphogen and GLI code. ''Curr Opin Genet Dev'' 13:513-21 PMID 14550418</ref>, metabolic networks <ref>Jeong H ''et al.''(2000) The large scale organisation of metabolic networks ''Nature'' 407: 651-4 [http://www.nd.edu/~hjeong/metabolic.pdf]</ref>, [[proteomics]] <ref>e.g. Grindrod P, Kibble M (2004) Review of uses of network and graph theory concepts within proteomics. ''Expert Rev Proteomics'' 1:229-38 PMID 15966817 and
Ye X, Chu J, Zhuang Y, Zhang S (2005) Multi-scale methodology: a key to deciphering systems biology. ''Front Biosci'' 10:961-5 PMID 15569634</ref> and indeed in purely physical systems as well as biological systems <ref> e.g. Cho YS, ''et al.'' (2005) Self-organization of bidisperse colloids in water droplets. ''J Am Chem Soc'' 127:15968-75 PMID 16277541</ref>. At a higher level, emergent processes are a widespread concept in cellular neuroscience <ref> see e.g. Burak Y, Fiete I (2006) Do we understand the emergent dynamics of grid cell activity? ''J Neurosci'' 26:9352-4 PMID 16977716</ref> and in cognitive science <ref> e.g. Courtney SM (2004) Attention and cognitive control as emergent properties of information representation in working memory. ''Cogn Affect Behav Neurosci'' 4:501-16 PMID 15849893 </ref>. At a still higher level, emergent properties are recognised for example in the behaviour of ant colonies and the concept of [[swarm intelligence]] ,<ref>Theraulaz G, ''et al.''. (2002) Spatial patterns in ant colonies. ''Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A.'' 99:9645-9 PMID 12114538</ref>; they have been simulated in artificial systems <ref>Theraulaz G, Bonabeau E (1999)A brief history of stigmergy. ''Artif Life'' 5:97-116 PMID 10633572</ref>, and parallels have been drawn with human societies <ref> Bonabeau E, Meyer C (2001) Swarm intelligence. A whole new way to think about business. ''Harv Bus Rev'' 79:106-14 PMID 11345907</ref>.


Whether [[emergence|emergent system properties]] should be characterized with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy.<ref> see "Emergent Properties" in the ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. online at [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/] for explicit discussion; briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also Emmeche C (2001) Does a robot have an Umwelt? ''Semiotica'' 134: 653-693 [http://www.nbi.dk/~emmeche/cePubl/2001d.robumwelt.pdf]</ref> If vitalism is not used in a strictly literal sense to refer to concepts that explicitly posit a mystical agency, then it is not easy to distinguish objectively between vitalism and contemporary scientific theories of complex systems, as explicitly recognized in a review entitled ''Molecular "vitalism"'' published in ''Cell'', the leading journal of [[molecular biology]]. <ref> Kirschner M, Gerhart J, Mitchison T (2000) Molecular "vitalism" ''Cell'' 100:79-88 PMID 10647933 </ref>
Whether emergence should be grouped with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy.{{efn|See;<ref>{{cite web |last1=O’Connor |first1=Timothy |title=Emergent Properties |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |date=2021}}</ref> briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Emmeche|first=C|title=Does a robot have an Umwelt? Reflections on the qualitative biosemiotics of Jakob von Uexküll |journal=Semiotica |date=16 July 2001 |volume=2001 |issue=134 |pages=653–693 |doi=10.1515/semi.2001.048|url=http://www.nbi.dk/~emmeche/cePubl/2001d.robumwelt.pdf}}</ref>}} According to Emmeche ''et al.'' (1997):


{{quote|On the one hand, many scientists and philosophers regard emergence as having only a pseudo-scientific status. On the other hand, new developments in physics, biology, psychology, and cross-disciplinary fields such as cognitive science, artificial life, and the study of non-linear dynamical systems have focused strongly on the high level 'collective behaviour' of complex systems, which is often said to be truly emergent, and the term is increasingly used to characterize such systems.|<ref name="Emmeche 1997">Emmeche, C. (1997) Explaining Emergence: towards an ontology of levels. ''Journal for General Philosophy of Science'' [http://alf.nbi.dk/~emmeche/coPubl/97e.EKS/emerg.html available online] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20061006171903/http://alf.nbi.dk/~emmeche/coPubl/97e.EKS/emerg.html |date=2006-10-06 }}</ref>}}
==Vitalism; its status in science==
Whether particular vitalistic concepts are "scientific" or not is a subjective judgement, one largely passed by the winners of a debate after the debate has been resolved: many "vitalistic" theories now abandoned were considered as mainstream scientific theories in their time. The replacement of vitalistic theories can thus be seen as having been a progressive refinement of scientific understanding, as the underlying mechanisms of complex phenomena are revealed. However the limits to [[reductionism]] have become apparent in recent years, most strikingly in the Mathematics of [[Chaos Theory]], and from the work of [[Benoit Mandelbrot]]. These ideas are best known in the metaphor of the "[[butterfly effect]]", first recognised by a [[meteorologist]], [[Edward Norton Lorenz]], who noted that his deterministic [[differential equations]] model of climate systems was unexpectedly sensitive to initial conditions. This finding was expressed famously (and variously) as implying that the flap of a butterfly's wings in a jungle in South America was enough to "cause" a hurricane on the other side of the world. This insight, that complex non-linear systems can produce ''inherently'' unpredictable behavior, seemed to set limits on the ability to "explain" complex behavior by ''any'' deterministic description, by setting limits on their "[[predictability]]". Subsequently, the work of [[Stephan Wolfram]], Stuart Kaufmann and others explored how chaos can be "harnessed", by exploring how organised behaviors can arise in a structured way from complex systems, giving rise to the modern concepts of [[emergent behavior]] and [[self-organisation]].


== Mesmerism ==
Thus, historically, "vitalist" concepts often "stood for" things that we do not yet fully understand in reductionist terms; this is particularly true in psychology, where the program for replacing vitalistic concepts has been explicitly aimed at replacing them with lower level descriptions. Limits or qualifications to this ambition are now recognised in the concepts associated with emergent behavior.
{{main|Animal magnetism}}
[[File:Franz Anton Mesmer.jpg|thumb|upright|[[Franz Mesmer]] proposed the vitalist force of ''[[animal magnetism|magnétisme animal]]'' in animals with breath.]]


A popular vitalist theory of the 18th century was "[[animal magnetism]]", in the theories of [[Franz Mesmer]] (1734–1815). However, the use of the (conventional) English term ''animal magnetism'' to translate Mesmer's '''magnétisme animal''' can be misleading for three reasons:
==Opinions of Vitalism==
* Mesmer chose his term to clearly distinguish his variant of ''magnetic'' force from those referred to, at that time, as ''mineral magnetism'', ''cosmic magnetism'' and ''planetary magnetism''.
* Mesmer felt that this particular force/power only resided in the bodies of humans and animals.
* Mesmer chose the word "''animal''," for its root meaning (from Latin ''animus''="breath") specifically to identify his force as a quality that belonged to all creatures with breath; viz., the animate beings: humans '''and''' animals.


Mesmer's ideas became so influential that King [[Louis XVI]] of France appointed two commissions to investigate [[mesmerism]]; one was led by [[Joseph-Ignace Guillotin]], the other, led by [[Benjamin Franklin]], included [[Jean Sylvain Bailly|Bailly]] and [[Lavoisier]]. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and [[trance]]s. In Franklin's garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid," but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier's house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid."<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Best |first1=M. |last2=Neuhauser |first2=D. |last3=Slavin |first3=L. |title=Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped |url= http://qhc.bmjjournals.com/cgi/content/full/12/3/232 |journal=Quality & Safety in Health Care |volume=12 |issue=3 |pages=232–3 |year=2003 |pmid=12792017 |pmc=1743715 |doi=10.1136/qhc.12.3.232}}</ref>
Vitalism is often used as a [[pejorative]] epithet <ref>"Other writers (eg, Peterfreund, 1971) simply use the term vitalism as a pejorative label." in
Galatzer-Levy,RM (1976) Psychic Energy, A Historical Perspective ''Ann Psychoanal'' 4:41-61 [http://www.pep-web.org/document.php?id=aop.004.0041a]</ref>. e.g. Bechtel and Williamson <ref> Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1998). Vitalism. In E. Craig (Ed.), ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. London: Routledge. [http://mechanism.ucsd.edu/~bill/teaching/philbio/vitalism.htm]</ref>, talking of the literal mystical definition of vitalism that "holds that living entities contain some fluid, or a distinctive "spirit", declare their opinion that "vitalism now has no credibility" because it is often viewed as unfalsifiable, and "therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine". However, the same authors also published a book which presents "an approach to explanation that appeals to interactions between simple components, rather than assigning functions to individual components", recognizing the "sometimes false assumption that nature is significantly decomposable and hierarchical" <ref>Bechtel W, Richardson, RC. (1992) ''Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research'' Princeton University Press ISBN: 0-691-08762-8[http://pup.princeton.edu/titles/4971.html]</ref>. Thus any judgement on whether vitalism is credible or not depends on exactly what is meant by vitalism.


== Medical philosophies ==
Most of the proponents of avowedly vitalistic theories described in this article were not "fringe" scientists but mainstream scientists of their time; their theories similarly were mostly mainstream theories; Driesch, Pasteur, Reichenbach, and Berzelius for example are all listed among the "[[Top 1000 Scientists: From the Beginning of Time to 2000 AD|top 1,000 scientists]] of all time". Many of the older theories described here have been refuted or superceded; in the view of philosopher of science [[Karl Popper]], it is the fate of most scientific theories to be refuted or replaced, and this is the hallmark of "good" science. Popper attacked Freud's psychoanalytical theories for their lack of falsifiability, but vitalism ''per se'' is not unscientific in this sense: not only were many vitalistic theories [[falsifiable]], many were in fact falsified, notably Mesmerism and the phlogiston theory (see above). The perverse retention of falsified theories might be considered unscientific; but this is the case whether the perversely retained theories are vitalistic or not.


Vitalism has a long history in [[medical]] philosophies: many [[traditional medicine|traditional healing]] practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces. One example of a similar notion in Africa is the [[Yoruba people|Yoruba]] concept of [[Ase (Yoruba)|ase]]. In the European tradition founded by [[Hippocrates]], these vital forces were associated with the [[four temperaments]] and [[The four humours|humours]]. Multiple Asian traditions posited an imbalance or blocking of [[qi]] or [[prana]]. Amongst unterritorialized traditions such as religions and arts, forms of vitalism continue to exist as philosophical positions or as memorial tenets.{{citation needed|date=April 2017}}
For many scientists, "vitalist" theories are unsatifactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, [[Francis Crick]], the co-discoverer of the structure of [[DNA]], stated “And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only cranks will believe tomorrow” <ref> Crick F (1967) ''Of Molecules and Men''; Great Minds Series
Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed in [http://www.mala.bc.ca/~johnstoi/reviews/crickandkurtz.htm]. Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) Molecular biology vs. organicism: The enduring dispute between mechanism and vitalism ''Synthese'' 20:238-253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings" [http://www.springerlink.com/content/m821384707h6h254/fulltext.pdf]</ref>. By contrast, [[Ernst Mayr]], co-founder of the [[modern evolutionary synthesis]] and a critic of both vitalism and reductionism, writing in 2002 after the mathematical development of theories underlying emergent behavior, stated:


[[Complementary and alternative medicine]] therapies include [[energy therapy|energy therapies]],<ref name="titleComplementary and Alternative Medicine – U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual">{{cite web |url= https://www.nlm.nih.gov/tsd/acquisitions/cdm/subjects24.html |title=Complementary and Alternative Medicine – U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual |access-date=2008-03-31}}</ref> associated with vitalism, especially biofield therapies such as [[therapeutic touch]], [[Reiki]], external [[qi]], [[chakra]] healing and SHEN therapy.<ref name="Rubik">{{cite web|last=Rubik|first=Beverly|title=Bioenergetic Medicines|work=American Medical Student Association Foundation|access-date=8 November 2006|url= http://www.amsa.org/ICAM/C6.doc |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20060214125248/https://www.amsa.org/ICAM/C6.doc |archive-date=2006-02-14 }}</ref> In these therapies, the "[[subtle energy]]" field of a patient is manipulated by a practitioner. The subtle energy is held to exist beyond the electromagnetic energy produced by the heart and brain. Beverly Rubik describes the biofield as a "complex, dynamic, extremely weak EM field within and around the human body...."<ref name="Rubik" />
:''It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine…..The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable. But all their efforts to find a scientific answer to all the so-called vitalistic phenomena were failures.… rejecting the philosophy of reductionism is not an attack on analysis. No complex system can be understood except through careful analysis. However the interactions of the components must be considered as much as the properties of the isolated components.'' <ref>Mayr E (2002) ''The Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology'', adapted for the internet, on [http://www.biologie.uni-hamburg.de/b-online/e01_2/autonomy.htm]</ref>

The founder of [[homeopathy]], [[Samuel Hahnemann]], promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." The view of disease as a dynamic disturbance of the immaterial and dynamic vital force is taught in many homeopathic colleges and constitutes a fundamental principle for many contemporary practising homeopaths.{{citation needed|date=April 2017}}

== Criticism ==
[[File:Pierre Mignard - Portrait de Jean-Baptiste Poquelin dit Molière (1622-1673) - Google Art Project (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright|left|The 17th century French playwright [[Molière]] mocked vitalism in his 1673 play ''[[Le Malade imaginaire]]''.]]

Vitalism has sometimes been criticized as [[begging the question]] by inventing a name. [[Molière]] had famously parodied this fallacy in ''[[Le Malade imaginaire]]'', where a quack "answers" the question of "Why does [[opium]] cause sleep?" with "Because of its '''dormitive virtue''' (i.e., [[soporific]] power)."<ref name="fr.wikisource.org">'' Mihi a docto doctore / Demandatur causam et rationem quare / Opium facit dormire. / A quoi respondeo, / Quia est in eo / Vertus dormitiva, / Cujus est natura / Sensus assoupire.'' [http://fr.wikisource.org/wiki/Le_Malade_imaginaire_-_3%C3%A8me_interm%C3%A8de Le Malade imaginaire, (French Wikisource)]</ref> [[Thomas Henry Huxley]] compared vitalism to stating that water is the way it is because of its "aquosity".<ref name="The Physical Basis of Life">[http://aleph0.clarku.edu/huxley/comm/PMG/PBofL.html The Physical Basis of Life], ''Pall Mall Gazette'', 1869</ref> His grandson [[Julian Huxley]] in 1926 compared "vital force" or ''élan vital'' to explaining a railroad locomotive's operation by its ''élan locomotif'' ("locomotive force").

Another criticism is that vitalists have failed to rule out mechanistic explanations. This is rather obvious in retrospect for [[organic chemistry]] and [[developmental biology]], but the criticism goes back at least a century. In 1912, [[Jacques Loeb]] published ''The Mechanistic Conception of Life'', in which he described experiments on how a sea urchin could have a pin for its father, as [[Bertrand Russell]] put it (''Religion and Science''). He offered this challenge:

: "... we must either succeed in producing living matter artificially, or we must find the reasons why this is impossible." (pp.&nbsp;5–6)

Loeb addressed vitalism more explicitly:

: "It is, therefore, unwarranted to continue the statement that in addition to the acceleration of oxidations the beginning of individual life is determined by the entrance of a metaphysical "life principle" into the egg; and that death is determined, aside from the cessation of oxidations, by the departure of this "principle" from the body. In the case of the evaporation of water we are satisfied with the explanation given by the kinetic theory of gases and do not demand that to repeat a well-known jest of Huxley the disappearance of the "aquosity" be also taken into consideration." (pp.&nbsp;14–15)

Bechtel states that vitalism "is often viewed as [[Falsifiability|unfalsifiable]], and therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine."<ref name=Bechtel/> For many scientists, "vitalist" theories were unsatisfactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, [[Francis Crick]], the co-discoverer of the structure of [[DNA]], stated "And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only [[Crank (person)|cranks]] will believe tomorrow."<ref name="Crick">Crick, Francis (1967) ''Of Molecules and Men''; Great Minds Series Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed [http://www.mala.bc.ca/~johnstoi/reviews/crickandkurtz.htm here]. Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) [https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF00413789 Molecular biology vs. organicism: The enduring dispute between mechanism and vitalism.] ''Synthese'' 20:238–253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings".</ref>

While many vitalistic theories have in fact been falsified, notably Mesmerism, the [[pseudoscience|pseudoscientific]] retention of untested and [[Testability|untestable]] theories continues to this day. [[Alan Sokal]] published an analysis of the wide acceptance among professional nurses of "scientific theories" of spiritual healing. (Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers?).<ref name="Sokal">[http://physics.nyu.edu/faculty/sokal/pseudoscience_rev.pdf Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers? (pdf)]</ref> Use of a technique called [[therapeutic touch]] was especially reviewed by Sokal, who concluded, "nearly all the pseudoscientific systems to be examined in this essay are based philosophically on vitalism" and added that "Mainstream science has rejected vitalism since at least the 1930s, for a plethora of good reasons that have only become stronger with time."<ref name="Sokal" />

Joseph C. Keating, Jr.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.ncmic.com/pages/ce/seminars/speakers/keating.htm|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20060525203939/http://www.ncmic.com/pages/ce/seminars/speakers/keating.htm|url-status=dead|title=Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD: Biographical sketch|archivedate=May 25, 2006}}</ref> discusses vitalism's past and present roles in [[chiropractic]] and calls vitalism "a form of [[bio-theology]]." He further explains that:

: "Vitalism is that rejected tradition in biology which proposes that life is sustained and explained by an unmeasurable, intelligent force or energy. The supposed effects of vitalism are the manifestations of life itself, which in turn are the basis for inferring the concept in the first place. This [[circular reasoning]] offers pseudo-explanation, and may deceive us into believing we have explained some aspect of biology when in fact we have only labeled our ignorance. 'Explaining an unknown (life) with an unknowable (Innate),' suggests chiropractor Joseph Donahue, 'is absurd'."<ref name="keating_innate">{{citation |title=The Meanings of Innate |author=Keating, Joseph C. |volume=46 |issue=1 |pmc=2505097 |journal=The Journal of the Canadian Chiropractic Association |year=2002 |pages=4–10}}</ref>

Keating views vitalism as incompatible with scientific thinking:

: "Chiropractors are not unique in recognizing a tendency and capacity for self-repair and auto-regulation of human physiology. But we surely stick out like a sore thumb among professions which claim to be scientifically based by our unrelenting commitment to vitalism. So long as we propound the 'One cause, one cure' rhetoric of Innate, we should expect to be met by ridicule from the wider health science community. Chiropractors can't have it both ways. Our theories cannot be both dogmatically held vitalistic constructs and be scientific at the same time. The purposiveness, consciousness and rigidity of the Palmers' Innate should be rejected."<ref name="keating_innate" />

Keating also mentions Skinner's viewpoint:

: "Vitalism has many faces and has sprung up in many areas of scientific inquiry. Psychologist [[B.F. Skinner]], for example, pointed out the irrationality of attributing behavior to mental states and traits. Such 'mental way stations,' he argued, amount to excess theoretical baggage which fails to advance cause-and-effect explanations by substituting an unfathomable psychology of 'mind'."<ref name="keating_innate" />

According to Williams, "[t]oday, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force."<ref name="Williams" /> "Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality."<ref name="Williams">{{cite encyclopedia|encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of Pseudoscience: From Alien Abductions to Zone Therapy|editor-first=William F.|editor-last=Williams|year=2013|edition=revised|title=Vitalism|page=367|isbn=9781135955229|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=vH1EAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA395 |quote='''VITALISM''' &ndash; The concept that bodily functions are due to a 'vital principle' or 'life force' that is distinct from the physical forces explainable by the laws of chemistry and physics. Many alternative approaches to modern medicine are rooted in vitalism. ... The exact nature of the vital force was debated by early philosophers, but vitalism in one form or another remained the preferred thinking behind most science and medicine until 1828. That year, German scientist [[Friedrich Wöhler]] (1800&ndash;82) synthesized an organic compound from an inorganic substance, a process that vitalists considered to be impossible. ... Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality. Today, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force.}}</ref>

[[Victor J. Stenger|Victor Stenger]]<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/vstenger/Medicine/Biofield.html|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20160303202347/http://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/vstenger/Medicine/Biofield.html|url-status=dead|title=Victor J. Stenger's site|archivedate=March 3, 2016}}</ref> states that the term "bioenergetics" "is applied in biochemistry to refer to the readily measurable [[Biological thermodynamics|exchanges of energy]] within organisms, and between organisms and the environment, which occur by normal physical and chemical processes. This is not, however, what the new vitalists have in mind. They imagine the [[Energy (esotericism)|bioenergetic]] field as a holistic living force that goes beyond reductionist physics and chemistry."<ref name=Stenger>{{cite journal |last=Stenger |first=Victor J. |title=The Physics of 'Alternative Medicine': Bioenergetic Fields |journal=The Scientific Review of Alternative Medicine |date=Spring–Summer 1999 |volume=3 |issue=1 |url= http://www.sram.org/0301/bioenergetic-fields.html |author-link=Victor J Stenger |access-date=2006-12-03 |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20061218144228/http://www.sram.org/0301/bioenergetic-fields.html |archive-date=2006-12-18 |url-status=dead }}</ref>

Such a field is sometimes explained as electromagnetic, though some advocates also make confused appeals to quantum physics.<ref name="Rubik" /> Joanne Stefanatos states that "The principles of energy medicine originate in quantum physics."<ref name="Stefanatos">Stefanatos, J. 1997, ''Introduction to Bioenergetic Medicine'', Shoen, A.M. and S.G. Wynn, ''Complementary and Alternative Veterinary Medicine: Principles and Practices'', Mosby-Yearbook, Chicago.</ref> Stenger<ref name="Stenger" /> offers several explanations as to why this line of reasoning may be misplaced. He explains that energy exists in discrete packets called quanta. Energy fields are composed of their component parts and so only exist when quanta are present. Therefore, energy fields are not holistic, but are rather a system of discrete parts that must obey the laws of physics. This also means that energy fields are not instantaneous. These facts of quantum physics place limitations on the infinite, continuous field that is used by some theorists to describe so-called "human energy fields".<ref name="Biley">Biley, Francis C. 2005, ''Unitary Health Care: Martha Rogers' Science of Unitary Human Beings'', University of Wales College of Medicine, viewed 30 November 2006, {{cite web |url= http://medweb.uwcm.ac.uk/martha/ |title=RogersHomepage |access-date=2006-12-02 |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20061205024515/http://medweb.uwcm.ac.uk/martha/ |archive-date=2006-12-05 }}</ref> Stenger continues, explaining that the effects of EM forces have been measured by physicists as accurately as one part in a billion and there is yet to be any evidence that living organisms emit a unique field.<ref name="Stenger" />

Vitalistic thinking has been identified in the naive biological theories of children: "Recent experimental results show that a majority of preschoolers tend to choose vitalistic explanations as most plausible. Vitalism, together with other forms of intermediate causality, constitute unique causal devices for naive biology as a core domain of thought."<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2004.06.004 |last1=Inagaki |first1=K. |last2=Hatano |first2=G. |year=2004 |title='Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology.' |journal=Trends Cogn Sci |volume=8 |issue=8|pages=356–62 |pmid=15335462 |s2cid=29256474 }}</ref>


== See also ==
== See also ==
{{div col|colwidth=22em}}
* [[Dualism]]
* [[Egregore]]
* [[Energy (esotericism)]]
* [[Etheric body]]
* [[Georges Canguilhem]]
* [[Henri Bergson]]
* [[Henri Bergson]]
* [[Holism in science]]
* [[Homeopathy]]
* [[Hylozoism]]
* [[Irreducible complexity]]
* ''[[Lebensphilosophie]]''
* [[Mind–body dualism]]
* [[Morphic resonance]]
* [[Odic force]]
* [[Odic force]]
* [[Philosophy of biology]]
* [[Orenda]]
* [[Orgone]]
* [[Orthogenesis]]
* [[Qi]]
* [[Qi]]
* [[Holism in science]]
* [[Ratiovitalism]]
* [[Royal Commission on Animal Magnetism]]
* [[Spirit (animating force)]]
* [[Vis medicatrix naturae]]
* [[Vital materialism]]
* [[Vitality]]
{{div col end}}


==Notes==
{{notelist}}


==External links==
==References==
{{reflist}}
* [http://skepdic.com/vitalism.html Vitalism] - the Skeptic's Dictionary
* [http://www.projectworldview.org/wvtheme5.htm Vitalism vs. Scientific Materialism] -- diametrically opposed worldview themes from Project Worldview


== References ==
==Sources==
* {{cite book|last1=Birch|first1=Charles|last2=Cobb|first2=John B|title=The Liberation of Life: From the Cell to the Community|year=1985|publisher=CUP Archive |isbn=9780521315142|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=h3c6AAAAIAAJ}}
* {{cite book|ref={{harvid|''History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences''}}|title=History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences|volume=29|year=2007|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tUkoAQAAIAAJ}}


==External links==
*Crick, Francis. (1967). Of Molecules and Men. Seattle: University of Washington Press, 24, 99.
{{Wikiversity}}
* {{In Our Time|Vitalism|b00dwhwt|Vitalism}}
* [http://skepdic.com/vitalism.html Vitalism] at the [[Skeptic's Dictionary]]


* For vital force and vitalism in the Spanish context, see Nicolás Fernández-Medina's ''[https://www.academia.edu/37425761/Life_Embodied_The_Promise_of_Vital_Force_in_Spanish_Modernity Life Embodied: The Promise of Vital Force in Spanish Modernity]'' (McGill-Queen's UP, 2018).


{{Evolution}}
<div class="references-small"><references/></div>
{{Philosophy of biology}}
{{philosophy of science}}


[[Category:History of science]]
[[Category:Vitalism| ]]
[[Category:Philosophy of science]]
[[Category:History of biology]]
[[Category:Obsolete scientific theories]]
[[Category:Obsolete scientific theories]]
[[Category:Pseudoscience]]
[[Category:Pseudoscience]]
[[Category:Religious philosophy and doctrine]]

[[cs:Vitalismus]]
[[de:Vitalismus]]
[[es:Vitalismo]]
[[fr:Vitalisme]]
[[fy:Animatisme]]
[[it:Vitalismo]]
[[nl:Vitalisme (filosofie)]]
[[ja:生気論]]
[[no:Vitalisme]]
[[nn:Vitalisme]]
[[pl:Witalizm]]
[[sk:Vitalizmus]]
[[fi:Vitalismi]]
[[sv:Vitalism]]

Latest revision as of 09:23, 2 November 2024

Vitalism is a belief that starts from the premise that "living organisms are fundamentally different from non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or are governed by different principles than are inanimate things."[1][a] Where vitalism explicitly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy", "élan vital" (coined by vitalist Henri Bergson), "vital force", or "vis vitalis", which some equate with the soul. In the 18th and 19th centuries, vitalism was discussed among biologists, between those who felt that the known mechanics of physics would eventually explain the difference between life and non-life and vitalists who argued that the processes of life could not be reduced to a mechanistic process. Vitalist biologists such as Johannes Reinke proposed testable hypotheses meant to show inadequacies with mechanistic explanations, but their experiments failed to provide support for vitalism. Biologists now consider vitalism in this sense to have been refuted by empirical evidence, and hence regard it either as a superseded scientific theory,[4] or, since the mid-20th century, as a pseudoscience.[5][6]

Vitalism has a long history in medical philosophies: many traditional healing practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces.

History

[edit]

Ancient times

[edit]

The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back at least to ancient Egypt.[7] In Greek philosophy, the Milesian school proposed natural explanations deduced from materialism and mechanism. However, by the time of Lucretius, this account was supplemented, (for example, by the unpredictable clinamen of Epicurus), and in Stoic physics, the pneuma assumed the role of logos. Galen believed the lungs draw pneuma from the air, which the blood communicates throughout the body.[8]

Medieval

[edit]

In Europe, medieval physics was influenced by the idea of pneuma, helping to shape later aether theories.

Early modern

[edit]

Vitalists included English anatomist Francis Glisson (1597–1677) and the Italian doctor Marcello Malpighi (1628–1694).[9] Caspar Friedrich Wolff (1733–1794) is considered to be the father of epigenesis in embryology, that is, he marks the point when embryonic development began to be described in terms of the proliferation of cells rather than the incarnation of a preformed soul. However, this degree of empirical observation was not matched by a mechanistic philosophy: in his Theoria Generationis (1759), he tried to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a vis essentialis (an organizing, formative force). Carl Reichenbach (1788–1869) later developed the theory of Odic force, a form of life-energy that permeates living things.

In the 17th century, modern science responded to Newton's action at a distance and the mechanism of Cartesian dualism with vitalist theories: that whereas the chemical transformations undergone by non-living substances are reversible, so-called "organic" matter is permanently altered by chemical transformations (such as cooking).[10]

As worded by Charles Birch and John B. Cobb, "the claims of the vitalists came to the fore again" in the 18th century:[9] "Georg Ernst Stahl's followers were active as were others, such as the physician genius Francis Xavier Bichat of the Hotel Dieu."[9] However, "Bichat moved from the tendency typical of the French vitalistic tradition to progressively free himself from metaphysics in order to combine with hypotheses and theories which accorded to the scientific criteria of physics and chemistry."[11] John Hunter recognised "a 'living principle' in addition to mechanics."[9]

Johann Friedrich Blumenbach was influential in establishing epigenesis in the life sciences in 1781 with his publication of Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte. Blumenbach cut up freshwater Hydra and established that the removed parts would regenerate. He inferred the presence of a "formative drive" (Bildungstrieb) in living matter. But he pointed out that this name,

like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification.

19th century

[edit]
The synthesis of urea in the early 19th century from inorganic compounds was counterevidence for the vitalist hypothesis that only organisms could make the components of living things.

Jöns Jakob Berzelius, one of the early 19th century founders of modern chemistry, argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions.[10] Berzelius contended that compounds could be distinguished by whether they required any organisms in their synthesis (organic compounds) or whether they did not (inorganic compounds).[12] Vitalist chemists predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components, but Friedrich Wöhler synthesised urea from inorganic components in 1828.[13] However, contemporary accounts do not support the common belief that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. This Wöhler Myth, as historian Peter Ramberg called it, originated from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931, which, "ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until 'one afternoon the miracle happened'".[14][15][b]

Between 1833 and 1844, Johannes Peter Müller wrote a book on physiology called Handbuch der Physiologie, which became the leading textbook in the field for much of the nineteenth century. The book showed Müller's commitments to vitalism; he questioned why organic matter differs from inorganic, then proceeded to chemical analyses of the blood and lymph. He describes in detail the circulatory, lymphatic, respiratory, digestive, endocrine, nervous, and sensory systems in a wide variety of animals but explains that the presence of a soul makes each organism an indivisible whole. He claimed that the behaviour of light and sound waves showed that living organisms possessed a life-energy for which physical laws could never fully account.[16]

Louis Pasteur argued that only life could catalyse fermentation. Painting by Albert Edelfelt, 1885

Louis Pasteur (1822–1895) after his famous rebuttal of spontaneous generation, performed several experiments that he felt supported vitalism. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." Rejecting the claims of Berzelius, Liebig, Traube and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, Pasteur concluded that fermentation was a "vital action".[1]

20th century

[edit]

Hans Driesch (1867–1941) interpreted his experiments as showing that life is not run by physicochemical laws.[5] His main argument was that when one cuts up an embryo after its first division or two, each part grows into a complete adult. Driesch's reputation as an experimental biologist deteriorated as a result of his vitalistic theories, which scientists have seen since his time as pseudoscience.[5][6] Vitalism is a superseded scientific hypothesis, and the term is sometimes used as a pejorative epithet.[17] Ernst Mayr (1904–2005) wrote:

It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine... The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable.[18]

Vitalism has become so disreputable a belief in the last fifty years that no biologist alive today would want to be classified as a vitalist. Still, the remnants of vitalist thinking can be found in the work of Alistair Hardy, Sewall Wright, and Charles Birch, who seem to believe in some sort of nonmaterial principle in organisms.[19]

Other vitalists included Johannes Reinke and Oscar Hertwig. Reinke used the word neovitalism to describe his work, claiming that it would eventually be verified through experimentation, and that it was an improvement over the other vitalistic theories. The work of Reinke influenced Carl Jung.[20]

John Scott Haldane adopted an anti-mechanist approach to biology and an idealist philosophy early on in his career. Haldane saw his work as a vindication of his belief that teleology was an essential concept in biology. His views became widely known with his first book Mechanism, life and personality in 1913.[21] Haldane borrowed arguments from the vitalists to use against mechanism; however, he was not a vitalist. Haldane treated the organism as fundamental to biology: "we perceive the organism as a self-regulating entity", "every effort to analyze it into components that can be reduced to a mechanical explanation violates this central experience".[21] The work of Haldane was an influence on organicism. Haldane stated that a purely mechanist interpretation could not account for the characteristics of life. Haldane wrote a number of books in which he attempted to show the invalidity of both vitalism and mechanist approaches to science. Haldane explained:

We must find a different theoretical basis of biology, based on the observation that all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so coordinated that they express what is normal for an adult organism.

— [22]

By 1931, biologists had "almost unanimously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged belief."[22]

Emergentism

[edit]

Contemporary science and engineering sometimes describe emergent processes, in which the properties of a system cannot be fully described in terms of the properties of the constituents.[23][24] This may be because the properties of the constituents are not fully understood, or because the interactions between the individual constituents are important for the behavior of the system.

Whether emergence should be grouped with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy.[c] According to Emmeche et al. (1997):

On the one hand, many scientists and philosophers regard emergence as having only a pseudo-scientific status. On the other hand, new developments in physics, biology, psychology, and cross-disciplinary fields such as cognitive science, artificial life, and the study of non-linear dynamical systems have focused strongly on the high level 'collective behaviour' of complex systems, which is often said to be truly emergent, and the term is increasingly used to characterize such systems.

— [27]

Mesmerism

[edit]
Franz Mesmer proposed the vitalist force of magnétisme animal in animals with breath.

A popular vitalist theory of the 18th century was "animal magnetism", in the theories of Franz Mesmer (1734–1815). However, the use of the (conventional) English term animal magnetism to translate Mesmer's magnétisme animal can be misleading for three reasons:

  • Mesmer chose his term to clearly distinguish his variant of magnetic force from those referred to, at that time, as mineral magnetism, cosmic magnetism and planetary magnetism.
  • Mesmer felt that this particular force/power only resided in the bodies of humans and animals.
  • Mesmer chose the word "animal," for its root meaning (from Latin animus="breath") specifically to identify his force as a quality that belonged to all creatures with breath; viz., the animate beings: humans and animals.

Mesmer's ideas became so influential that King Louis XVI of France appointed two commissions to investigate mesmerism; one was led by Joseph-Ignace Guillotin, the other, led by Benjamin Franklin, included Bailly and Lavoisier. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and trances. In Franklin's garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid," but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier's house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid."[28]

Medical philosophies

[edit]

Vitalism has a long history in medical philosophies: many traditional healing practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces. One example of a similar notion in Africa is the Yoruba concept of ase. In the European tradition founded by Hippocrates, these vital forces were associated with the four temperaments and humours. Multiple Asian traditions posited an imbalance or blocking of qi or prana. Amongst unterritorialized traditions such as religions and arts, forms of vitalism continue to exist as philosophical positions or as memorial tenets.[citation needed]

Complementary and alternative medicine therapies include energy therapies,[29] associated with vitalism, especially biofield therapies such as therapeutic touch, Reiki, external qi, chakra healing and SHEN therapy.[30] In these therapies, the "subtle energy" field of a patient is manipulated by a practitioner. The subtle energy is held to exist beyond the electromagnetic energy produced by the heart and brain. Beverly Rubik describes the biofield as a "complex, dynamic, extremely weak EM field within and around the human body...."[30]

The founder of homeopathy, Samuel Hahnemann, promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." The view of disease as a dynamic disturbance of the immaterial and dynamic vital force is taught in many homeopathic colleges and constitutes a fundamental principle for many contemporary practising homeopaths.[citation needed]

Criticism

[edit]
The 17th century French playwright Molière mocked vitalism in his 1673 play Le Malade imaginaire.

Vitalism has sometimes been criticized as begging the question by inventing a name. Molière had famously parodied this fallacy in Le Malade imaginaire, where a quack "answers" the question of "Why does opium cause sleep?" with "Because of its dormitive virtue (i.e., soporific power)."[31] Thomas Henry Huxley compared vitalism to stating that water is the way it is because of its "aquosity".[32] His grandson Julian Huxley in 1926 compared "vital force" or élan vital to explaining a railroad locomotive's operation by its élan locomotif ("locomotive force").

Another criticism is that vitalists have failed to rule out mechanistic explanations. This is rather obvious in retrospect for organic chemistry and developmental biology, but the criticism goes back at least a century. In 1912, Jacques Loeb published The Mechanistic Conception of Life, in which he described experiments on how a sea urchin could have a pin for its father, as Bertrand Russell put it (Religion and Science). He offered this challenge:

"... we must either succeed in producing living matter artificially, or we must find the reasons why this is impossible." (pp. 5–6)

Loeb addressed vitalism more explicitly:

"It is, therefore, unwarranted to continue the statement that in addition to the acceleration of oxidations the beginning of individual life is determined by the entrance of a metaphysical "life principle" into the egg; and that death is determined, aside from the cessation of oxidations, by the departure of this "principle" from the body. In the case of the evaporation of water we are satisfied with the explanation given by the kinetic theory of gases and do not demand that to repeat a well-known jest of Huxley the disappearance of the "aquosity" be also taken into consideration." (pp. 14–15)

Bechtel states that vitalism "is often viewed as unfalsifiable, and therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine."[1] For many scientists, "vitalist" theories were unsatisfactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, Francis Crick, the co-discoverer of the structure of DNA, stated "And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only cranks will believe tomorrow."[33]

While many vitalistic theories have in fact been falsified, notably Mesmerism, the pseudoscientific retention of untested and untestable theories continues to this day. Alan Sokal published an analysis of the wide acceptance among professional nurses of "scientific theories" of spiritual healing. (Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers?).[34] Use of a technique called therapeutic touch was especially reviewed by Sokal, who concluded, "nearly all the pseudoscientific systems to be examined in this essay are based philosophically on vitalism" and added that "Mainstream science has rejected vitalism since at least the 1930s, for a plethora of good reasons that have only become stronger with time."[34]

Joseph C. Keating, Jr.[35] discusses vitalism's past and present roles in chiropractic and calls vitalism "a form of bio-theology." He further explains that:

"Vitalism is that rejected tradition in biology which proposes that life is sustained and explained by an unmeasurable, intelligent force or energy. The supposed effects of vitalism are the manifestations of life itself, which in turn are the basis for inferring the concept in the first place. This circular reasoning offers pseudo-explanation, and may deceive us into believing we have explained some aspect of biology when in fact we have only labeled our ignorance. 'Explaining an unknown (life) with an unknowable (Innate),' suggests chiropractor Joseph Donahue, 'is absurd'."[36]

Keating views vitalism as incompatible with scientific thinking:

"Chiropractors are not unique in recognizing a tendency and capacity for self-repair and auto-regulation of human physiology. But we surely stick out like a sore thumb among professions which claim to be scientifically based by our unrelenting commitment to vitalism. So long as we propound the 'One cause, one cure' rhetoric of Innate, we should expect to be met by ridicule from the wider health science community. Chiropractors can't have it both ways. Our theories cannot be both dogmatically held vitalistic constructs and be scientific at the same time. The purposiveness, consciousness and rigidity of the Palmers' Innate should be rejected."[36]

Keating also mentions Skinner's viewpoint:

"Vitalism has many faces and has sprung up in many areas of scientific inquiry. Psychologist B.F. Skinner, for example, pointed out the irrationality of attributing behavior to mental states and traits. Such 'mental way stations,' he argued, amount to excess theoretical baggage which fails to advance cause-and-effect explanations by substituting an unfathomable psychology of 'mind'."[36]

According to Williams, "[t]oday, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force."[37] "Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality."[37]

Victor Stenger[38] states that the term "bioenergetics" "is applied in biochemistry to refer to the readily measurable exchanges of energy within organisms, and between organisms and the environment, which occur by normal physical and chemical processes. This is not, however, what the new vitalists have in mind. They imagine the bioenergetic field as a holistic living force that goes beyond reductionist physics and chemistry."[39]

Such a field is sometimes explained as electromagnetic, though some advocates also make confused appeals to quantum physics.[30] Joanne Stefanatos states that "The principles of energy medicine originate in quantum physics."[40] Stenger[39] offers several explanations as to why this line of reasoning may be misplaced. He explains that energy exists in discrete packets called quanta. Energy fields are composed of their component parts and so only exist when quanta are present. Therefore, energy fields are not holistic, but are rather a system of discrete parts that must obey the laws of physics. This also means that energy fields are not instantaneous. These facts of quantum physics place limitations on the infinite, continuous field that is used by some theorists to describe so-called "human energy fields".[41] Stenger continues, explaining that the effects of EM forces have been measured by physicists as accurately as one part in a billion and there is yet to be any evidence that living organisms emit a unique field.[39]

Vitalistic thinking has been identified in the naive biological theories of children: "Recent experimental results show that a majority of preschoolers tend to choose vitalistic explanations as most plausible. Vitalism, together with other forms of intermediate causality, constitute unique causal devices for naive biology as a core domain of thought."[42]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Stéphane Leduc and D'Arcy Thompson (On Growth and Form) published a series of works that in Evelyn Fox Keller's view took on the task of uprooting the remaining vestiges of vitalism, essentially by showing that the principles of physics and chemistry were enough, by themselves, to account for the growth and development of biological form.[2] On the other hand, Michael Ruse notes that D'Arcy Thompson's avoidance of natural selection had an "odor of spirit forces" about it.[3]
  2. ^ In 1845, Adolph Kolbe succeeded in making acetic acid from inorganic compounds, and in the 1850s, Marcellin Berthelot repeated this feat for numerous organic compounds. In retrospect, Wöhler's work was the beginning of the end of Berzelius's vitalist hypothesis, but only in retrospect, as Ramberg had shown.
  3. ^ See;[25] briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also.[26]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c Bechtel, William; Williamson, Robert C. (1998). "Vitalism". In E. Craig (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  2. ^ Evelyn Fox Keller, Making Sense of Life Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines. Harvard University Press, 2002.
  3. ^ Ruse, Michael (2013). "17. From Organicism to Mechanism-and Halfway Back?". In Henning, Brian G.; Scarfe, Adam (eds.). Beyond Mechanism: Putting Life Back Into Biology. Lexington Books. p. 419. ISBN 9780739174371.
  4. ^ Williams, Elizabeth Ann (2003). A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier. Ashgate. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-7546-0881-3.
  5. ^ a b c "Developmental Biology 8e Online: A Selective History of Induction". Archived from the original on October 31, 2006.
  6. ^ a b Dyde, Sean (2013). "Chapter 5: Life and the Mind in Nineteenth-Century Britain". In Normandin, Sebastian; Wolfe, T. Charles (eds.). Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightenment Life Science, 1800–2010. Springer. p. 104. ISBN 978-94-007-2445-7. In medicine and biology, vitalism has been seen as a philosophically-charged term, a pseudoscientific gloss that corrupted scientific practice …
  7. ^ Jidenu, Paulin (1996) African Philosophy, 2nd Ed. Indiana University Press, ISBN 0-253-21096-8, p.16.
  8. ^ Birch & Cobb 1985, p. 75
  9. ^ a b c d Birch & Cobb 1985, pp. 76–78
  10. ^ a b Ede, Andrew. (2007) The Rise and Decline of Colloid Science in North America, 1900–1935: The Neglected Dimension, p. 23
  11. ^ History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, p. 238
  12. ^ Wilkinson, Ian (10 June 2002). "History of Clinical Chemistry". EJIFCC. 13 (4): 114–118. ISSN 1650-3414. PMC 6208063.
  13. ^ Kinne-Saffran, E.; Kinne, R. K. H. (August 7, 1999). "Vitalism and Synthesis of Urea". American Journal of Nephrology. 19 (2): 290–294. doi:10.1159/000013463. PMID 10213830. S2CID 71727190 – via www.karger.com.
  14. ^ Ramberg, Peter J. (2000). "The Death of Vitalism and the Birth of Organic Chemistry: Wohler's Urea Synthesis and the Disciplinary Identity of Organic Chemistry". Ambix. 47 (3): 170–195. doi:10.1179/amb.2000.47.3.170. PMID 11640223. S2CID 44613876.
  15. ^ Schummer, Joachim (December 2003). "The notion of nature in chemistry" (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A. 34 (4): 705–736. Bibcode:2003SHPSA..34..705S. doi:10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00050-5.
  16. ^ Otis, Laura (October 2004). "Johannes Peter Müller (1801-1858)" (PDF). Virtual Laboratory: Essays and Resources on the Experimentalization of Life (Max Planck Institute).
  17. ^ Galatzer-Levy, R. M. (August 7, 1976). "Psychic Energy: A Historical Perspective". Ann. Psychoanal. 4: 41–61 – via PEP Web.
  18. ^ Mayr, Ernst (2002). "BOTANY ONLINE: Ernst MAYR: Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology". Archived from the original on 2006-09-26. Retrieved 2006-09-24.
  19. ^ Ernst Mayr Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist 1988, p. 13. ISBN 978-0674896666.
  20. ^ Noll, Richard. "Jung's concept of die Dominanten (the Dominants) (1997)" – via www.academia.edu. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  21. ^ a b Bowler, Peter J. Reconciling science and religion: the debate in early-twentieth-century Britain, 2001, pp. 168–169. ISBN 978-0226068589.
  22. ^ a b Mayr, Ernst (2010). "The Decline of Vitalism". In Bedau, Mark A.; Cleland, Carol E. (eds.). The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 93–95. ISBN 9781139488655. Yet considering how dominant vitalism was in biology and for how long a period it prevailed, it is surprising how rapidly and completely it collapsed. The last support of vitalism as a viable concept in biology disappeared about 1930." (p. 94) From p. 95: "Vitalism survived even longer in the writings of philosophers than it did in the writings of physicists. But so far as I know, there are no vitalists among the philosophers of biology who started publishing after 1965. Nor do I know of a single reputable living biologist who still supports straightforward vitalism. The few late twentieth-century biologists with vitalist leanings (A. Hardy, S. Wright, A. Portmann) are no longer alive.
  23. ^ Schultz, S.G. (1998). "A century of (epithelial) transport physiology: from vitalism to molecular cloning". The American Journal of Physiology. 274 (1 Pt 1): C13–23. doi:10.1152/ajpcell.1998.274.1.C13. PMID 9458708.
  24. ^ Gilbert, S.F.; Sarkar, S. (2000). "Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century". Developmental Dynamics. 219 (1): 1–9. doi:10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A. PMID 10974666.
  25. ^ O’Connor, Timothy (2021). "Emergent Properties". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  26. ^ Emmeche, C (16 July 2001). "Does a robot have an Umwelt? Reflections on the qualitative biosemiotics of Jakob von Uexküll" (PDF). Semiotica. 2001 (134): 653–693. doi:10.1515/semi.2001.048.
  27. ^ Emmeche, C. (1997) Explaining Emergence: towards an ontology of levels. Journal for General Philosophy of Science available online Archived 2006-10-06 at the Wayback Machine
  28. ^ Best, M.; Neuhauser, D.; Slavin, L. (2003). "Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped". Quality & Safety in Health Care. 12 (3): 232–3. doi:10.1136/qhc.12.3.232. PMC 1743715. PMID 12792017.
  29. ^ "Complementary and Alternative Medicine – U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual". Retrieved 2008-03-31.
  30. ^ a b c Rubik, Beverly. "Bioenergetic Medicines". American Medical Student Association Foundation. Archived from the original on 2006-02-14. Retrieved 8 November 2006.
  31. ^ Mihi a docto doctore / Demandatur causam et rationem quare / Opium facit dormire. / A quoi respondeo, / Quia est in eo / Vertus dormitiva, / Cujus est natura / Sensus assoupire. Le Malade imaginaire, (French Wikisource)
  32. ^ The Physical Basis of Life, Pall Mall Gazette, 1869
  33. ^ Crick, Francis (1967) Of Molecules and Men; Great Minds Series Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed here. Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) Molecular biology vs. organicism: The enduring dispute between mechanism and vitalism. Synthese 20:238–253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings".
  34. ^ a b Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers? (pdf)
  35. ^ "Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD: Biographical sketch". Archived from the original on May 25, 2006.
  36. ^ a b c Keating, Joseph C. (2002), "The Meanings of Innate", The Journal of the Canadian Chiropractic Association, 46 (1): 4–10, PMC 2505097
  37. ^ a b Williams, William F., ed. (2013). "Vitalism". Encyclopedia of Pseudoscience: From Alien Abductions to Zone Therapy (revised ed.). p. 367. ISBN 9781135955229. VITALISM – The concept that bodily functions are due to a 'vital principle' or 'life force' that is distinct from the physical forces explainable by the laws of chemistry and physics. Many alternative approaches to modern medicine are rooted in vitalism. ... The exact nature of the vital force was debated by early philosophers, but vitalism in one form or another remained the preferred thinking behind most science and medicine until 1828. That year, German scientist Friedrich Wöhler (1800–82) synthesized an organic compound from an inorganic substance, a process that vitalists considered to be impossible. ... Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality. Today, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force.
  38. ^ "Victor J. Stenger's site". Archived from the original on March 3, 2016.
  39. ^ a b c Stenger, Victor J. (Spring–Summer 1999). "The Physics of 'Alternative Medicine': Bioenergetic Fields". The Scientific Review of Alternative Medicine. 3 (1). Archived from the original on 2006-12-18. Retrieved 2006-12-03.
  40. ^ Stefanatos, J. 1997, Introduction to Bioenergetic Medicine, Shoen, A.M. and S.G. Wynn, Complementary and Alternative Veterinary Medicine: Principles and Practices, Mosby-Yearbook, Chicago.
  41. ^ Biley, Francis C. 2005, Unitary Health Care: Martha Rogers' Science of Unitary Human Beings, University of Wales College of Medicine, viewed 30 November 2006, "RogersHomepage". Archived from the original on 2006-12-05. Retrieved 2006-12-02.
  42. ^ Inagaki, K.; Hatano, G. (2004). "'Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology.'". Trends Cogn Sci. 8 (8): 356–62. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.06.004. PMID 15335462. S2CID 29256474.

Sources

[edit]
[edit]