Jump to content

Tarski's axiomatization of the reals

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 96.63.208.31 (talk) at 17:45, 12 May 2022 (How these axioms imply a field:). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In 1936, Alfred Tarski set out an axiomatization of the real numbers and their arithmetic, consisting of only the 8 axioms shown below and a mere four primitive notions:[1] the set of reals denoted R, a binary total order over R, denoted by infix <, a binary operation of addition over R, denoted by infix +, and the constant 1.

The literature occasionally mentions this axiomatization but never goes into detail, notwithstanding its economy and elegant metamathematical properties. This axiomatization appears little known, possibly because of its second-order nature. Tarski's axiomatization can be seen as a version of the more usual definition of real numbers as the unique Dedekind-complete ordered field; it is however made much more concise by using unorthodox variants of standard algebraic axioms and other subtle tricks (see e.g. axioms 4 and 5, which combine the usual four axioms of abelian groups).

The term "Tarski's axiomatization of real numbers" also refers to the theory of real closed fields, which Tarski showed completely axiomatizes the first-order theory of the structure 〈R, +, ·, <〉.

The axioms

Axioms of order (primitives: R, <):

Axiom 1
If x < y, then not y < x. That is, "<" is an asymmetric relation. This implies that "<" is not a reflexive relationship, i.e. for all x, x < x is false.
Axiom 2
If x < z, there exists a y such that x < y and y < z. In other words, "<" is dense in R.
Axiom 3
"<" is Dedekind-complete. More formally, for all XY ⊆ R, if for all x ∈ X and y ∈ Y, x < y, then there exists a z such that for all x ∈ X and y ∈ Y, if z ≠ x and z ≠ y, then x < z and z < y.

To clarify the above statement somewhat, let X ⊆ R and Y ⊆ R. We now define two common English verbs in a particular way that suits our purpose:

X precedes Y if and only if for every x ∈ X and every y ∈ Y, x < y.
The real number z separates X and Y if and only if for every x ∈ X with x ≠ z and every y ∈ Y with y ≠ z, x < z and z < y.

Axiom 3 can then be stated as:

"If a set of reals precedes another set of reals, then there exists at least one real number separating the two sets."

The three axioms imply that R is a linear continuum.

Axioms of addition (primitives: R, <, +):

Axiom 4
x + (y + z) = (x + z) + y.
Axiom 5
For all x, y, there exists a z such that x + z = y.
Axiom 6
If x + y < z + w, then x < z or y < w.

Axioms for one (primitives: R, <, +, 1):

Axiom 7
1 ∈ R.
Axiom 8
1 < 1 + 1.

This axiomatization does not give rise to a first-order theory, because the formal statement of axiom 3 includes two universal quantifiers over all possible subsets of R. Tarski proved that these 8 axioms and 4 primitive notions are independent.

How these axioms imply a field:

Theorem —  is a Archimedean ordered abelian group.

Proof

Tarski's axioms imply that is a totally ordered[2] abelian group under addition with distinguished element . Since is Dedekind-complete and a totally ordered abelian group, is Archimedean, because the Dedekind-completion of any totally ordered abelian group with infinite elements or infinitesimals is not an abelian group, and the Dedekind-completion of any Archimedean ordered abelian group is still Archimedean.

Theorem —  embeds in .

Proof

Tarski's axioms imply that is a totally ordered abelian group under addition with distinguished element . As a result, there exist maximum and minimum binary functions and , with the absolute value function defined as . Since is an abelian group, it is a -module, and since is totally ordered, it is a flat module and thus a torsion-free abelian group, which means that the integers embed in , with injective group homomorphism where and . As a result, for every integer and the affine functions are well defined in .

Since is Dedekind-complete, Archimedean and a totally ordered abelian group, is a metric space with respec to teh absolute value and thus a Hausdorff space, and every Cauchy net in converges to a unique element of , and thus the absolute value is a complete metric on . Furthermore, any closed interval on is compact and conencted. As a result, the intermediate value theorem is satisfied for every function from a closed interval to . Because are monotonic for , and for the function is just the negation of a monotonic function, have a root for . Thus is a divisible group and a -vector space, with an injective group homomorphism where and .

Theorem —  is a field

Proof

Otto Hölder showed that every Archimedean group is isomorphic (as an ordered group) to a subgroup of the Dedekind-complete Archimedean group with distinguished element , .[3][4][5][6] Because is an Archimedean ordered field, let us define as the Dedekind completion of . The Dedekind completion of any Archimedean ordered field is terminal in the concrete category of Dedekind complete Archimedean ordered fields,[7] Because is a Dedekind-complete Archimedean ordered field, every Archimedean group embeds into as well. As a result, the two sets and are isomorphic to each other, which means that is a field.

Tarski stated, without proof, that these axioms gave a total ordering. The missing component was supplied in 2008 by Stefanie Ucsnay.[2]

References

  1. ^ Tarski, Alfred (24 March 1994). Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences (4 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-504472-0.
  2. ^ a b Ucsnay, Stefanie (Jan 2008). "A Note on Tarski's Note". The American Mathematical Monthly. 115 (1): 66–68. JSTOR 27642393.
  3. ^ Fuchs, László; Salce, Luigi (2001), Modules over non-Noetherian domains, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol. 84, Providence, R.I.: American Mathematical Society, p. 61, ISBN 978-0-8218-1963-0, MR 1794715
  4. ^ Fuchs, László (2011) [1963]. Partially ordered algebraic systems. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications. pp. 45–46. ISBN 978-0-486-48387-0.
  5. ^ Kopytov, V. M.; Medvedev, N. Ya. (1996), Right-Ordered Groups, Siberian School of Algebra and Logic, Springer, pp. 33–34, ISBN 9780306110603.
  6. ^ For a proof for abelian groups, see Ribenboim, Paulo (1999), The Theory of Classical Valuations, Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, p. 60, ISBN 9780387985251.
  7. ^ Univalent Foundations Program (2013). Homotopy Type Theory: Univalent Foundations of Mathematics. Institute for Advanced Study.