Pragmatism and French Voluntarism: with Especial Reference to the Notion of Truth in the Development of French Philosophy from Maine de Biran to Professor Bergson
()
About this ebook
Related to Pragmatism and French Voluntarism
Related ebooks
Philosophy and the Physicists Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Why We Need Ordinary Language Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSongs For Winter Rain Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSaintly Influence: Edith Wyschogrod and the Possibilities of Philosophy of Religion Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIndexical Elegies Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Gale Researcher Guide for: Heidegger on Death, Finitude, and Care Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBergson And His Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Yves R. Simon Reader: The Philosopher's Calling Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Wittgensteins Remarks on Colour: A Commentary and Interpretation Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHusserl's Missing Technologies Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5Lysis (SparkNotes Philosophy Guide) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Machines of Evolution and the Scope of Meaning Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsClarissa Harlowe; or the history of a young lady — Volume 1 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLudwig Wittgenstein's Tractatus Odyssey: The Great War and the Writing of the Tractatus-Logico-Philosophicus Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsNietzsche Was Probably Right Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSpeaking Hermeneutically: Understanding in the Conduct of a Life Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEdmund Burke for Our Time: Moral Imagination, Meaning, and Politics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCulture of Enlightening: Abbé Claude Yvon and the Entangled Emergence of the Enlightenment Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPersuasion, Reflection, Judgment: Ancillae Vitae Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTransplanting the Metaphysical Organ: German Romanticism between Leibniz and Marx Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsComments on Massimo Leone’s Article (2019) "Semiotics of Religion: A Map" Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMaking and Breaking Mathematical Sense: Histories and Philosophies of Mathematical Practice Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHorace Bushnell: Minister to a Changing America Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPhilosophical Methodology in Classical Chinese and German Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEnds of Enlightenment Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA New Philosophy: Henri Bergson Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHegel: The Philosopher of Freedom Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Sources of Religious Insight (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn Learning: A general theory of objects and object-relations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Philosophy For You
The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Courage to Be Happy: Discover the Power of Positive Psychology and Choose Happiness Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tao Te Ching: A New English Version Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Little Book of Hygge: Danish Secrets to Happy Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Be Here Now Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/512 Rules for Life: An Antidote to Chaos Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Laws of Connection: The Scientific Secrets of Building a Strong Social Network Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsExperiencing God (2021 Edition): Knowing and Doing the Will of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Republic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Inward Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Antidote: Happiness for People Who Can't Stand Positive Thinking Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The City of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE EMERALD TABLETS OF THOTH THE ATLANTEAN Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar...: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Pray: Reflections and Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for Pragmatism and French Voluntarism
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Pragmatism and French Voluntarism - L. Susan Stebbing
Foreword from the Editor
Pragmatism and French Voluntarism, published in January 1914, was the doctoral thesis of Susan Stebbing, who was the first woman to hold a philosophy chair in the United Kingdom. Later Stebbing wrote a complete and successful synthesis of ancient and modern logic (A Modern Introduction to Logic), and in the dark years of the second world war she was dear to many readers through some books that invited to return to rational thinking with respect to the contemporary political events: Thinking to Some Purpose and Ideals and Illusions, published respectively in 1939 and 1941, works which were defined manuals of first-aid to clear thinking
.
Pragmatism and French Voluntarism is an account of the epistemological ideas that were widespread and widely discussed in the early twentieth century: it introduces us methodically into the world of American pragmatism and of the many French currents of thought that we usually group together in a generic way under the title of anti-intellectualism, and which culminated in Bergson’s philosophy. Why read it today? First of all because inside this book we find a clear and intelligent account, much more valuable and expressive than an encyclopedia entry, of the philosophical currents it deals with. Despite its age, this book is still a useful guide to orient oneself in the contexts of pragmatism and anti-intellectualism of the early twentieth century.
But this is the least of the reasons; the best reason to read this book is that, although it is a work written by the author in her young age and encyclopedic in nature, the personality of the author strongly acts in it. Stebbing was throughout her life an intransigent critic, who never accepted compromise, of each fall into irrational thinking of twentieth century culture. So this book is permeated with awareness of the deeply irrational and inconsistent statements which can be found in the epistemological currents in vogue at the time, and this awareness corresponds to a moral discomfort, clearly and strongly expressed, although still rudimentary and not articulated, because the times were not ripe to study the prevailing irrationalism in the culture of that era. Nor are they still ripe today: so the works of Stebbing are destined to be instruments for the historiography of the times to come, in precisely determining the falls in irrationality and the genesis of specific mythologies that we can recognize in the most unexpected places of twentieth century culture, and particularly in the science of nature.
Biographic data and basic information about Stebbing are available on the site plato.stanford.edu. See Beaney, Michael and Chapman, Siobhan, Susan Stebbing
, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
URL =
Note to the 2018 electronic edition
This e-book has been composed on the basis of the original printed edition. The scanned text was carefully controlled, in order to make available to the public a good quality electronic version of Stebbing’s work.
The page numbers of the original edition have been preserved in [square brackets].
To facilitate the reading of this electronic edition, the footnotes containing remarks that add something to the main discourse have been marked with an asterisk ‘*’. Therefore the remaining notes should be consulted only by those who have an interest in identifying the author’s sources.
Original Title Page
Girton College Studies
Edited by Lilian Knowles, Litt.D., Reader in Economic History in the University of London
No. 6
Pragmatism And French Voluntarism
Thesis approved for the degree of Master of Arts in the University of London, 1912
PRAGMATISM AND FRENCH VOLUNTARISM
with Especial Reference to the Notion of Truth in the Development of French Philosophy from Maine de Biran to Professor Bergson
by
L. Susan Stebbing, M.A.
Tutor and Lecturer King’s College for Women
Visiting Lecturer Girton College
Cambridge, at the University Press 1914
Printed by John Clay, M.A. at the University Press
PREFACE
[v] The keen and widespread interest of all classes of readers in the philosophy of Bergson—an interest that was increased by his visits to the Universities of Oxford, Birmingham and London—shows no sign of diminishing. The enthusiasm with which the ‘New Philosophy’ was at first welcomed seems, however, to be setting in the opposite direction, and the excessive praise and indiscriminating acceptance of his doctrines have now given place to a criticism no less indiscriminating and, perhaps, equally unjustifiable.
In the present state of public opinion, therefore, I venture to offer this essay which, although written from a so-called ‘intellectualistic’ standpoint diametrically opposed to M. Bergson’s, is nevertheless not blind to the interest and importance of his work.
It is the fashion among present day philosophers to depreciate reason, and in the forefront of these are the French Voluntarists—especially the Bergsonian Intuitionists—and the Pragmatists. But in their methods and conclusions they are obviously opposed and an attempt is made to show that in no sense can the French Voluntarists be classed as Pragmatists. In their treatment of the problem of truth this divergence becomes marked. Both, however, fail to give a satisfactory account of truth, the Pragmatist because he identifies truth with one of its consequences, the Bergsonian Intuitionist because he [vi] identifies truth with reality. Hence both resort to non-intellectual methods of determining truth and of solving metaphysical problems. But only, it is urged, by the admission of the non-existential character of truth and by the complete working out of the demands of intellect can we obtain knowledge that is at once complete and rational, hence truly knowledge.
In the original form this essay, written during the course of 1911 and completed in the early days of 1912, was submitted to the University of London and gained for its author the degree of Master of Arts. Only a few verbal alterations have been made in the essay itself, quotations have for the most part been translated, and the bibliography has been enlarged and brought up to date. In a paper, entitled The Notion of Truth in Bergson’s Theory of Knowledge,
read by the author before the Aristotelian Society in May 1913 some part of this essay was reproduced and has since appeared in the Proceedings of the Society.
In conclusion, I wish to thank the Rev. Professor Caldecott for his valuable help and kind encouragement during the writing of this essay and its preparation for the press, and also Miss E. E. C. Jones, Mistress of Girton College, and the Council whose grant made the publication of it possible.
L. S. S.
London, January 14th, 1914.
ABBREVIATIONS USED
I. INTRODUCTION
[1] The philosophy of the present age, no less than its politics, is characterised by the prevailing spirit of democracy, hence by a hatred of authority, a passion for equality and, finally, by a tendency to bring all questions in the last resort to the arbitrament of force.
The basis of democracy is the recognition of the worth of man as man, irrespective of social status, work or capacity. A government
is worthy of obedience and respect only if it embody the choice of the people
; there are none so low nor ignorant that they should be denied a voice in the government of their country. The will of the majority must be made to prevail, by force if necessary. In other words, the struggle for existence must be admitted in so far as all who survive
are to be accounted equally fit,
but is to be condemned in so far as it involves the elimination of the unfit. This contradiction which lies at the heart of democracy is curiously repeated and illustrated in pragmatic philosophy which, partially derived from the anti-democratic philosophy of Nietzsche, is yet a striking outcome of the democratic demand for a purely human
philosophy of life—a Humanism
based upon the actual interests and emotions of mankind.
[2] The latter part of the nineteenth century has consequently witnessed the reaction of this ideal upon philosophy which has been gradually permeated with the democratic spirit. No longer must philosophy remain within the closet
; it must be brought down to the plain man
whose appeal has lately been so eloquently uttered. It is, indeed, instructive to compare the sentiment expressed by Prof. Jacks in The Bitter Cry of the Plain Man[1], with the intellectual aloofness of Mr Bradley’s standpoint. Philosophy, says Mr Bradley, must always remain an affair of the intellect; it will always be hard[2].
In revolt against such a view the plain man
as represented by Prof. Jacks, appalled by the supremely forbidding
character of the Hegelian dialectic, protests that if the truths most important to men explain themselves in this manner, then our lot in this world is dismal in the extreme[3]
and he makes his appeal to philosophers,—Is it beneath you gentlemen, to attend to these by-products of your work, to study the effect of your potions not only on some isolated nerve of the intellect, but as affecting the vital pulse of the human heart?
The protest that philosophy has been made too hard for the plain man does not confine itself to condemnation of technicalities of language and the uncouthness of German philosophical terminology, but becomes a plea for the recognition of other attitudes towards the Universe than that of regarding it as a problem-to-be-solved.
Life, it is urged, is more than intellect, hence a rational explanation of the Universe could not suffice to satisfy the [3] philosopher as a man; his whole emotional reaction must be taken into account.
Over the philosophers themselves is passing a wave which leads them to bring philosophy into contact with life, to invest it with the charm of personality, and to breathe life into the dead bones of metaphysics.
The natural outlet of this wave is some form of Voluntarism
which shall lay stress on the active, volitional side of man by denying that intellect is the sole guide to, and judge of truth, or even the dominant factor in its construction. Intellect must not only be dethroned from its proud position as sovereign in philosophy; it must henceforth assume its rightful place as a mere instrument for the furtherance of human activity.
There is a further force at work to revolutionize the philosopher’s attitude. The too complete success of the mechanical sciences in the early part of the nineteenth century, coupled with the recognition of the reign of natural law in the animal kingdom brought about mainly by Darwin’s Origin of Species, has led to a revolt against that mechanical conception of the Universe that reduces it to the dead level of matter in motion and looks for the progress of science in "the extension of the province of what we call matter and causation, and the concomitant gradual banishment from all regions of human thought of what we call spirit and spontaneity[4]."
This nightmare
conception—to use Huxley’s own expression—has provoked a reaction against science as the construction of intellect on the one hand, and on the other—most markedly in France—has led to the admission of contingency into the realm of physical science itself.
[4] This reaction from a rigid, all-pervading determinism to radical contingency we shall find to be characteristic of French Voluntarism; it is, indeed, in France that the philosophy of contingency
first attained clear and complete expression.
We find, then, in contemporary philosophy two tendencies: on the one hand a tendency to bring philosophy into closer touch with life and to put contingency everywhere so as to ensure our finding freedom in man; on the other hand a tendency to disparage intellect as the faculty of conceptual knowledge and to turn to some higher form of perception
as giving a direct contact with reality.
In Pragmatism—whether it be regarded as epistemological utilitarianism of the worst sort,
or merely as a theory of the manipulation of data for the purposes of science—these two tendencies are closely connected. Disparagement of intellect is here an outcome of the desire to bring philosophy down into the arena of "the drudgery and commonplace that are our daily portion[5]," by laying stress on the emotional rather than on the intellectual aspects of life, regarding intellect only as a means to the satisfaction of other needs of man. The end is doing, not knowing. Knowledge is subservient to action and what is useful in the way of conduct becomes the supreme criterion of its trustworthiness. In French Voluntarism, however, the condemnation of intellect is based upon the alleged inability of the intellect to resolve the Kantian antinomies and Zenonian paradoxes that result from the conception of time as a [5] continuum, while the assertion of universal contingency appears to be the outcome of a radically anti-intellectualistic temporalism.
Pragmatism, which frequently claims to be only an epistemological method compatible with the most varied metaphysics, originated in a rule first formulated in the interests of clear thinking by the American mathematician, Mr C. S. Peirce. In his posthumous work James sums it up thus: The pragmatic rule is that the meaning of a concept may always be found, if not in some sensible particular which it directly designates, then in some particular difference in the course of human experience which its being true will make.
According to James’ earlier statements the doctrine may be summed up: the practical bearings of a concept constitute its whole meaning and value. This later substitution of particular
for practical
is significant. The word practical
is of course ambiguous and is susceptible of different interpretations. But it at once lends itself to the construction that what is ‘practical’
is what affects our conduct in daily life,
in the sense in which we distinguish a practical man
or man of affairs
from a dreamer
or scholar.
In considering "practical[6]*" consequences on this view, purposes and [6] needs, i.e. practical interests will be brought to the front, and volition and emotion will have a large share in determining the value of a concept.
Such is the theory explicitly maintained in the Will to Believe
; the passional nature is raised to the level of the intellectual nature as a determinant of truth.
For purposes of criticism it will be of use to consider just how this conclusion is reached. The problem may be stated: Required—A theory that will satisfy the emotional nature and ensure the satisfaction of its longings and aspirations. Solution: Raise the value of the emotional element, i.e. recognise the right of emotion to enter as a determining factor into the construction of truth. But a difficulty arises. When we believe, we think we believe independently of our emotions and will. However eloquently the rights
of the passional nature may be stated, however certainly it may be proved that