Determined: A Science of Life without Free Will
4/5
()
About this ebook
“Excellent…Outstanding for its breadth of research, the liveliness of the writing, and the depth of humanity it conveys.” – Wall Street Journal
One of our great behavioral scientists, the bestselling author of Behave, plumbs the depths of the science and philosophy of decision-making to mount a devastating case against free will, an argument with profound consequences
Robert Sapolsky’s Behave, his now classic account of why humans do good and why they do bad, pointed toward an unsettling conclusion: We may not grasp the precise marriage of nature and nurture that creates the physics and chemistry at the base of human behavior, but that doesn’t mean it doesn’t exist. Now, in Determined, Sapolsky takes his argument all the way, mounting a brilliant (and in his inimitable way, delightful) full-frontal assault on the pleasant fantasy that there is some separate self telling our biology what to do.
Determined offers a marvelous synthesis of what we know about how consciousness works—the tight weave between reason and emotion and between stimulus and response in the moment and over a life. One by one, Sapolsky tackles all the major arguments for free will and takes them out, cutting a path through the thickets of chaos and complexity science and quantum physics, as well as touching ground on some of the wilder shores of philosophy. He shows us that the history of medicine is in no small part the history of learning that fewer and fewer things are somebody’s “fault”; for example, for centuries we thought seizures were a sign of demonic possession.
Yet, as he acknowledges, it’s very hard, and at times impossible, to uncouple from our zeal to judge others and to judge ourselves. Sapolsky applies the new understanding of life beyond free will to some of our most essential questions around punishment, morality, and living well together. By the end, Sapolsky argues that while living our daily lives recognizing that we have no free will is going to be monumentally difficult, doing so is not going to result in anarchy, pointlessness, and existential malaise. Instead, it will make for a much more humane world.
Robert M. Sapolsky
Robert M. Sapolsky is the author of several works of nonfiction, including A Primate’s Memoir, The Trouble with Testosterone, and Why Zebras Don’t Get Ulcers. His most recent book, Behave, was a New York Times bestseller and named a best book of the year by The Washington Post and The Wall Street Journal. He is a professor of biology and neurology at Stanford University and the recipient of a MacArthur Foundation “Genius Grant.” He and his wife live in San Francisco.
Read more from Robert M. Sapolsky
Behave: The Biology of Humans at Our Best and Worst Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Primate's Memoir: A Neuroscientist's Unconventional Life Among the Baboons Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Monkeyluv: And Other Essays on Our Lives as Animals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Trouble With Testosterone: And Other Essays On The Biology Of The Human Predi Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related to Determined
Related ebooks
This is Improbable: Cheese String Theory, Magnetic Chickens and Other WTF Research Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5What The Princess Discovered Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHumanity, a Failed Experiment Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Quantum Akashic Field: A Guide to Out-of-Body Experiences for the Astral Traveler Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Psych: The Story of the Human Mind Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMind Over Matter: Conversations with the Cosmos Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Human: The Science Behind What Makes Your Brain Unique Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Field Updated Ed: The Quest for the Secret Force of the Universe Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Enigma of Evolution and the Challenge of Chance Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Theory of Everything Else: A Voyage Into the World of the Weird Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Grey Aliens and Artificial Intelligence: The Battle between Natural and Synthetic Beings for the Human Soul Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOur Universe: A Journey Into Mystery Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn Purpose Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Elephants on Acid: And Other Bizarre Experiments Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How We Should Think: The Intersections of Philosophical Thought Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Myth of the Great Ending: Why We've Been Longing for the End of Days Since the Beginning of Time Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGorgeous Evasions Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Edge of Knowledge: Unsolved Mysteries of the Cosmos Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWoman Aware: Could Eliminating Religious Creeds Emancipate Women? Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Teachings of 431QK Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUnderstanding the Psychic Powers of Man (Revised Edition) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Walk On The Wild Side: One Man's Experiences With Psychic Phenomena Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHaunted New Haven Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMullins Collection of Best New Fiction Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Crack in the Cosmic Egg: New Constructs of Mind and Reality Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Digital Consciousness: A Transformative Vision: A Transformative Vision Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Effect Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBorn This Way: Becoming, Being, and Understanding Scientists Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Biology For You
The Sixth Extinction: An Unnatural History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Peptide Protocols: Volume One Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Laws of Connection: The Scientific Secrets of Building a Strong Social Network Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Soul of an Octopus: A Surprising Exploration into the Wonder of Consciousness Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Lifespan: Why We Age—and Why We Don't Have To Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5"Cause Unknown": The Epidemic of Sudden Deaths in 2021 & 2022 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep Origins of Consciousness Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Gut: The Inside Story of Our Body's Most Underrated Organ (Revised Edition) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Why We Sleep: Unlocking the Power of Sleep and Dreams Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Dopamine Detox: Biohacking Your Way To Better Focus, Greater Happiness, and Peak Performance Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Crack In Creation: Gene Editing and the Unthinkable Power to Control Evolution Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Woman: An Intimate Geography Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Obesity Code: the bestselling guide to unlocking the secrets of weight loss Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Thinking Clearly Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Winner Effect: The Neuroscience of Success and Failure Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Grieving Brain: The Surprising Science of How We Learn from Love and Loss Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Suicidal: Why We Kill Ourselves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Emotional Blackmail: When the People in Your Life Use Fear, Obligation, and Guilt to Manipulate You Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Anatomy 101: From Muscles and Bones to Organs and Systems, Your Guide to How the Human Body Works Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Our Kind of People: Inside America's Black Upper Class Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Deepest Well: Healing the Long-Term Effects of Childhood Trauma and Adversity Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mothers Who Can't Love: A Healing Guide for Daughters Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Letter to Liberals: Censorship and COVID: An Attack on Science and American Ideals Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Ultralearning: Master Hard Skills, Outsmart the Competition, and Accelerate Your Career Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Homo Deus: A Brief History of Tomorrow Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for Determined
37 ratings3 reviews
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5I don't think I've read anything by the author before. I heard him on Sam Harris' podcast. There doesn't seem to be anything philosophically new here (I wrote the same thing in an Anthropology blue book in 1972 and the TA gave me a D and wrote a vulgar comment.); macroscopic determinism excludes free will. But what I enjoyed so much was the author's careful development of his argument and the huge number of small neuroscientific, behavioral, psychological, and evolutionary facts that he uses. I liked his use of epilepsy, schizophrenia, autism, and obesity as examples of the progression of our understanding of these conditions (and I was reminded that tuberculosis was considered a disease of artists, wayward women, and Jews before the discovery of Mycobacteria, and that gastric ulcers were considered a stress-related illness common in white bankers before the re-discovery of Helicobacter pylori).
The second part of the book is Sapolsky's look at the consequences of living in a world in which the absence of free will was accepted. Although he shows that some changes might be possible, especially in his review of the Norwegian penal system, changing the view of other aspects of our life, e.g. Are we really ready to say that all of our personal achievements are due to chance?, are enormously challenging. To say nothing of the effect on Hollywood if revenge movies were seen as ridiculous. - Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5This is an amazing book; I don't think I have ever learned as much from one book as I did from this one. As a non-scientist, it was not an easy read, despite an eminently readable (and frequently very funny) prose style. It was well worth the effort, however. So much for the matter of the book, what about the conclusion? That is very challenging, as the author acknowledges. I find myself in the odd position of intellectually accepting his arguments, but emotionally ignoring them. I think the idea of no free will may take quite a while to move from my head to my heart, if it ever does.
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Thought provoking and mind expanding.
I am reminded on the statement I have heard attributed to Schopenhauer:” you may do as you will but you can’t will as you will. I wonder of rather than full determinism we should compare this to Feynman’s particles that follow a course set by probability. To some extent the author speaks to that idea. Still off one ours fortunate enough to have opportunities perhaps believing in free will incentivizes trying to be one’s best or as the marines say: be all you can be. “
Book preview
Determined - Robert M. Sapolsky
Praise for Determined
Sapolsky’s decades of experience studying the effects of the interplay of genes and the environment on behavior shine brightly…. He provides compelling examples that bad luck compounds…convincingly argues against claims that chaos theory, emergent phenomena, or the indeterminism offered by quantum mechanics provide the gap required for free will to exist.
—Science
"The behavioural scientist engagingly lays out the reasons why our every action is predetermined—and why we shouldn’t despair about it…. Determined is a bravura performance, well worth reading for the pleasure of Sapolsky’s deeply informed company…. Absorbing and compassionate."
—The Guardian
Few people understand the human brain as well as renowned neuroscientist Robert Sapolsky.
—San Francisco Chronicle
"Witty and engaging, Determined is also a goldmine of fascinating information (most of it accessible even to those of us who aren’t scientifically literate) about neuroscience; philosophy; chaos theory; emergent complexity; quantum indeterminacy; evolving knowledge of the causes of epilepsy, schizophrenia, and autism; and, of course, the impact of nature and nurture on decision-making."
—Psychology Today
"Determined is a sustained attempt at demonstrating that the decisions we make every day are products of complex factors of which we’re not in charge…. This is an amiable, surprisingly accessible, and at times a persuasive book—a paean to empathy and tolerance that yearns for a world in which societies eventually realize that retribution is futile and wrong…. [Sapolsky] can be pleased with the knowledge that what he’s written is stimulating to read, even for those who doubt his conclusions."
—San Francisco Chronicle
Sapolsky presents in his inimitable style a cogent argument explaining that free will is an illusion…. Sapolsky tackles many complicated facets of this demanding subject with aplomb, making difficult material accessible. His engaging style and silly humor make learning fun…. The debate is essential.
—Booklist
A neuroscientific takedown of the notion that free will guides us…[Sapolsky] is fearless in taking on a matter that is fraught with a long history of debate and division, and he covers a wide variety of disciplines, from philosophy to ethics and law, with admirable clarity…. Sure to stir controversy, which, to judge by this long but lucid exposition, the author is perfectly willing to court.
—Kirkus Reviews (starred review)
Penguin Books
Determined
Robert M. Sapolsky is the author of several works of nonfiction, including A Primate’s Memoir, The Trouble with Testosterone, and Why Zebras Don’t Get Ulcers. His most recent books Determined and Behave were New York Times bestsellers. He is the John A. and Cynthia Fry Gunn Professor and professor of biology, of neurology and neurological sciences, and of neurosurgery at Stanford University and the recipient of a MacArthur Foundation Genius Grant.
He and his wife live in San Francisco.
Also by Robert M. Sapolsky
Behave: The Biology of Humans at Our Best and Worst
Monkeyluv: And Other Essays on Our Lives as Animals
A Primate’s Memoir
The Trouble with Testosterone and Other Essays on the Biology of the Human Predicament
Why Zebras Don’t Get Ulcers: A Guide to Stress, Stress-Related Diseases, and Coping
Stress, the Aging Brain, and the Mechanisms of Neuron Death
Book Title, Determined: A Science of Life without Free Will, Author, Robert M. Sapolsky, Imprint, Penguin PressPENGUIN BOOKS
An imprint of Penguin Random House LLC
First published in the United States of America by Penguin Press, an imprint of Penguin Random House LLC, 2023
Published in Penguin Books 2024
Copyright © 2023 by Robert M. Sapolsky
Penguin Random House supports copyright. Copyright fuels creativity, encourages diverse voices, promotes free speech, and creates a vibrant culture. Thank you for buying an authorized edition of this book and for complying with copyright laws by not reproducing, scanning, or distributing any part of it in any form without permission. You are supporting writers and allowing Penguin Random House to continue to publish books for every reader.
The English translation by Daniel Kahn, of the Yiddish poem Mayn Rue Platz
by Morris Rosenfeld, on this page is used by permission.
This page constitutes an extension of this copyright page.
Ebook ISBN 9780525560982
Paperback ISBN 9780525560999
the library of congress has cataloged the hardcover edition as follows:
Names: Sapolsky, Robert M., author.
Title: Determined : a science of life without free will / Robert M. Sapolsky.
Description: New York : Penguin Press, 2023. | Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2023023790 (print) | LCCN 2023023791 (ebook) | ISBN 9780525560975 (hardcover) | ISBN 9780525560982 (ebook)
Subjects: LCSH: Free will and determinism.
Classification: LCC BJ1461 .S325 2023 (print) | LCC BJ1461 (ebook) | DDC 123/.5—dc23/eng/20230705
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2023023790
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2023023791
Cover design: Pete Garceau
Designed by Alexis Farabaugh, adapted for ebook by Cora Wigen
pid_prh_7.0_148814534_c0_r0
Contents
Dedication
1. Turtles All the Way Down
2. The Final Three Minutes of a Movie
3. Where Does Intent Come From?
4. Willing Willpower: The Myth of Grit
5. A Primer on Chaos
6. Is Your Free Will Chaotic?
7. A Primer on Emergent Complexity
8. Does Your Free Will Just Emerge?
9. A Primer on Quantum Indeterminacy
10. Is Your Free Will Random?
10.5. Interlude
11. Will We Run Amok?
12. The Ancient Gears within Us: How Does Change Happen?
13. We Really Have Done This Before
14. The Joy of Punishment
15. If You Die Poor
Epilogue: Things I Wish I’d Written in the Hardcover Edition
Acknowledgments
Appendix: Neuroscience 101
Notes
Illustration Credits
Index
_148814534_
To L, and to B & R,
Who make it all seem worth it.
Who make it worth it.
my brain: click them
me: why?
my brain: you gotta
Serving kitchen tongs isolated on a white background with clipping path1
Turtles All the Way Down
When I was in college, my friends and I had an anecdote that we retold frequently; it went like this (and our retelling was so ritualistic that I suspect this is close to verbatim, forty-five years later):
So, it seems that William James was giving a lecture about the nature of life and the universe. Afterward, an old woman came up and said, Professor James, you have it all wrong.
To which James asked, How so, madam?
Things aren’t at all like you said,
she replied. The world is on the back of a gigantic turtle.
Hmm.
said James, bemused. That may be so, but where does that turtle stand?
On the back of another turtle,
she answered.
But madam,
said James indulgently, where does that turtle stand?
To which the old woman responded triumphantly: It’s no use, Professor James. It’s turtles all the way down!
[*1]
Oh, how we loved that story, always told it with the same intonation. We thought it made us seem droll and pithy and attractive.
We used the anecdote as mockery, a pejorative critique of someone clinging unshakably to illogic. We’d be in the dinner hall, and someone had said something nonsensical, where their response to being challenged had made things worse. Inevitably, one of us would smugly say, It’s no use, Professor James!
to which the person, who had heard our stupid anecdote repeatedly, would inevitably respond, Screw you, just listen. This actually makes sense.
Here is the point of this book: While it may seem ridiculous and nonsensical to explain something by resorting to an infinity of turtles all the way down, it actually is much more ridiculous and nonsensical to believe that somewhere down there, there’s a turtle floating in the air. The science of human behavior shows that turtles can’t float; instead, it is indeed turtles all the way down.
Someone behaves in a particular way. Maybe it’s wonderful and inspiring, maybe it’s appalling, maybe it’s in the eye of the beholder, or maybe just trivial. And we frequently ask the same basic question: Why did that behavior occur?
If you believe that turtles can float in the air, the answer is that it just happened, that there was no cause besides that person having simply decided to create that behavior. Science has recently provided a much more accurate answer, and when I say recently,
I mean in the last few centuries. The answer is that the behavior happened because something that preceded it caused it to happen. And why did that prior circumstance occur? Because something that preceded it caused it to happen. It’s antecedent causes all the way down, not a floating turtle or causeless cause to be found. Or as Maria sings in The Sound of Music, Nothing comes from nothing, nothing ever could.
[*2]
To reiterate, when you behave in a particular way, which is to say when your brain has generated a particular behavior, it is because of the determinism that came just before, which was caused by the determinism just before that, and before that, all the way down. The approach of this book is to show how that determinism works, to explore how the biology over which you had no control, interacting with environment over which you had no control, made you you. And when people claim that there are causeless causes of your behavior that they call free will,
they have (a) failed to recognize or not learned about the determinism lurking beneath the surface and/or (b) erroneously concluded that the rarefied aspects of the universe that do work indeterministically can explain your character, morals, and behavior.
Once you work with the notion that every aspect of behavior has deterministic, prior causes, you observe a behavior and can answer why it occurred: as just noted, because of the action of neurons in this or that part of your brain in the preceding second.[*3] And in the seconds to minutes before, those neurons were activated by a thought, a memory, an emotion, or sensory stimuli. And in the hours to days before that behavior occurred, the hormones in your circulation shaped those thoughts, memories, and emotions and altered how sensitive your brain was to particular environmental stimuli. And in the preceding months to years, experience and environment changed how those neurons function, causing some to sprout new connections and become more excitable, and causing the opposite in others.
And from there, we hurtle back decades in identifying antecedent causes. Explaining why that behavior occurred requires recognizing how during your adolescence a key brain region was still being constructed, shaped by socialization and acculturation. Further back, there’s childhood experience shaping the construction of your brain, with the same then applying to your fetal environment. Moving further back, we have to factor in the genes you inherited and their effects on behavior.
But we’re not done yet. That’s because everything in your childhood, starting with how you were mothered within minutes of birth, was influenced by culture, which means as well by the centuries of ecological factors that influenced what kind of culture your ancestors invented, and by the evolutionary pressures that molded the species you belong to. Why did that behavior occur? Because of biological and environmental interactions, all the way down.[*4]
As a central point of this book, those are all variables that you had little or no control over. You cannot decide all the sensory stimuli in your environment, your hormone levels this morning, whether something traumatic happened to you in the past, the socioeconomic status of your parents, your fetal environment, your genes, whether your ancestors were farmers or herders. Let me state this most broadly, probably at this point too broadly for most readers: we are nothing more or less than the cumulative biological and environmental luck, over which we had no control, that has brought us to any moment. You’re going to be able to recite this sentence in your irritated sleep by the time we’re done.
There are all sorts of aspects about behavior that, while true, are not relevant to where we’re heading. For example, the fact that some criminal behavior can be due to psychiatric or neurological problems. That some kids have learning differences
because of the way their brains work. That some people have trouble with self-restraint, because they grew up without any decent role models or because they’re still a teenager with a teenager’s brain. That someone has said something hurtful merely because they’re tired and stressed, or even because of a medication they’re taking.
All of these are circumstances where we recognize that sometimes, biology can impinge on our behavior. This is essentially a nice humane agenda that endorses society’s general views about agency and personal responsibility but reminds you to make exceptions for edge cases: judges should consider mitigating factors in criminals’ upbringing during sentencing; juvenile murderers shouldn’t be executed; the teacher handing out gold stars to the kids who are soaring in learning to read should do something special too for that kid with dyslexia; college admissions officers should consider more than just SAT cutoffs for applicants who have overcome unique challenges.
These are good, sensible ideas that should be instituted if you decide that some people have much less self-control and capacity to freely choose their actions than average, and that at times, we all have much less than we imagine.
We can all agree on that; however, we’re heading into very different terrain, one that I suspect most readers will not agree with, which is deciding that we have no free will at all. Here would be some of the logical implications of that being the case: That there can be no such thing as blame, and that punishment as retribution is indefensible—sure, keep dangerous people from damaging others, but do so as straightforwardly and nonjudgmentally as keeping a car with faulty brakes off the road. That it can be okay to praise someone or express gratitude toward them as an instrumental intervention, to make it likely that they will repeat that behavior in the future, or as an inspiration to others, but never because they deserve it. And that this applies to you when you’ve been smart or self-disciplined or kind. Oh, as long as we’re at it, that you recognize that the experience of love is made of the same building blocks that constitute wildebeests or asteroids. That no one has earned or is entitled to being treated better or worse than anyone else. And that it makes as little sense to hate someone as to hate a tornado because it supposedly decided to level your house, or to love a lilac because it supposedly decided to make a wonderful fragrance.
That’s what it means to conclude that there is no free will. This is what I’ve concluded, for a long, long time. And even I think that taking that seriously sounds absolutely nutty.
Moreover, most people agree that it sounds that way. People’s beliefs and values, their behavior, their answers to survey questions, their actions as study subjects in the nascent field of experimental philosophy,
show that people believe in free will when it matters—philosophers (about 90 percent), lawyers, judges, jurors, educators, parents, and candlestick makers. As well as scientists, even biologists, even many neurobiologists, when push comes to shove. Work by psychologists Alison Gopnik at UC Berkeley and Tamar Kushnir at Cornell shows that preschool kids already have a robust belief in a recognizable version of free will. And such a belief is widespread (but not universal) among a wide variety of cultures. We are not machines in most people’s view; as a clear demonstration, when a driver or an automated car makes the same mistake, the former is blamed more.[1] And we are not alone in our faith in free will—research that we’ll look at in a later chapter suggests that other primates even believe that there is free will.[2]
This book has two goals. The first is to convince you that there is no free will,[*5] or at least that there is much less free will than generally assumed when it really matters. To accomplish that, we’ll look at the way smart, nuanced thinkers argue for free will, from the perspectives of philosophy, legal thought, psychology, and neuroscience. I’ll be trying to present their views to the best of my ability, and to then explain why I think they are all mistaken. Some of these mistakes arise from the myopia (used in a descriptive rather than judgmental sense) of focusing solely on just one sliver of the biology of behavior. Sometimes this is because of faulty logic, such as concluding that if it’s not possible to ever tell what caused X, maybe nothing caused it. Sometimes the mistakes reflect unawareness or misinterpretation of the science underlying behavior. Most interestingly, I sense that mistakes arise for emotional reasons that reflect that there being no free will is pretty damn unsettling; we’ll consider this at the end of the book. So one of my two goals is to explain why I think all these folks are wrong, and how life would improve if people stopped thinking like them.[3]
Right around here, one might ask of me, Where do you get off? As will be seen, free-will debates often revolve around narrow issues—Does a particular hormone actually cause a behavior or just make it more likely?
or Is there a difference between wanting to do something and wanting to want something?
—that are usually debated by specialized authorities. My intellectual makeup happens to be that of a generalist. I’m a neurobiologist
with a lab that does things like manipulate genes in a rat’s brain to change behavior. At the same time, I spent part of each year for more than three decades studying the social behavior and physiology of wild baboons in a national park in Kenya. Some of my research turned out to be relevant to understanding how adult brains are influenced by the stress of childhood poverty, and as a result, I’ve wound up spending time around the likes of sociologists; another facet of my work has been relevant to mood disorders, leading me to hang with psychiatrists. And for the last decade, I’ve had a hobby of working with public defender offices on murder trials, teaching juries about the brain. As a result, I’ve been carpetbagging in a number of different fields related to behavior. Which I think has made me particularly prone toward deciding that free will doesn’t exist.
Why? Crucially, if you focus on any single field like these—neuroscience, endocrinology, behavioral economics, genetics, criminology, ecology, child development, or evolutionary biology—you are left with plenty of wiggle room for deciding that biology and free will can coexist. In the words of UC San Diego philosopher Manuel Vargas, Claiming that some scientific result shows the falsity of ‘free will’…is either bad scholarship or academic hucksterism.
[4] He is right, if in-your-face. As we will see in the next chapter, most experimental neurobiology research about free will is narrowly anchored by the result of one study that examined events that happen in the brain a few seconds before a behavior occurs. And Vargas would correctly conclude that this scientific result
(plus the spin-offs it has generated in the subsequent forty years) doesn’t prove there’s no free will. Similarly, you can’t disprove free will with a scientific result
from genetics—genes in general are not about inevitability but, rather, about vulnerability and potential, and no single gene, gene variant, or gene mutation has ever been identified that falsifies free will;[*6] you can’t even do it when considering all our genes at once. And you can’t disprove free will from a developmental/sociological perspective by emphasizing the scientific result that a childhood filled with abuse, deprivation, neglect, and trauma astronomically increases the odds of producing a deeply damaged and damaging adult—because there are exceptions. Yeah, no single result or scientific discipline can do that. But—and this is the incredibly important point—put all the scientific results together, from all the relevant scientific disciplines, and there’s no room for free will.[*7]
Why is that? Something deeper than the idea that if you examine enough different disciplines, one -ology after another, you’re bound to eventually find one that provides a slam dunk, falsifying free will all by itself. It is also deeper than the idea that even though each discipline has a hole that precludes it from falsifying free will, at least one of the other disciplines compensates for it.
Crucially, all these disciplines collectively negate free will because they are all interlinked, constituting the same ultimate body of knowledge. If you talk about the effects of neurotransmitters on behavior, you are also implicitly talking about the genes that specify the construction of those chemical messengers, and the evolution of those genes—the fields of neurochemistry,
genetics,
and evolutionary biology
can’t be separated. If you examine how events in fetal life influence adult behavior, you are also automatically considering things like lifelong changes in patterns of hormone secretion or in gene regulation. If you discuss the effects of mothering style on a kid’s eventual adult behavior, by definition you are also automatically discussing the nature of the culture that the mother passes on through her actions. There’s not a single crack of daylight to shoehorn in free will.
As such, the first half of the book’s point is to rely on this biological framework in rejecting free will. Which brings us to the second half of the book. As noted, I haven’t believed in free will since adolescence, and it’s been a moral imperative for me to view humans without judgment or the belief that anyone deserves anything special, to live without a capacity for hatred or entitlement. And I just can’t do it. Sure, sometimes I can sort of get there, but it is rare that my immediate response to events aligns with what I think is the only acceptable way to understand human behavior; instead, I usually fail dismally.
As I said, even I think it’s crazy to take seriously all the implications of there being no free will. And despite that, the goal of the second half of the book is to do precisely that, both individually and societally. Some chapters consider scientific insights about how we might go about dispensing with free-will belief. Others examine how some of the implications of rejecting free will are not disastrous, despite initially seeming that way. Some review historical circumstances that demonstrate something crucial about the radical changes we’d need to make in our thinking and feeling: we’ve done it before.
The book’s intentionally ambiguous title reflects these two halves—it is both about the science of why there is no free will and the science of how we might best live once we accept that.
Styles of Views: Whom I Will Be Disagreeing With
I’m going to be discussing some of the common attitudes held by people writing about free will. These come in four basic flavors:[*8]
The world is deterministic and there’s no free will. In this view, if the former is the case, the latter has to be as well; determinism and free will are not compatible. I am coming from this perspective of hard incompatibilism.
[*9]
The world is deterministic and there is free will. These folks are emphatic that the world is made of stuff like atoms, and life, in the elegant words of psychologist Roy Baumeister (currently at the University of Queensland in Australia), is based on the immutability and relentlessness of the laws of nature.
[5] No magic or fairy dust involved, no substance dualism, the view where brain and mind are separate entities.[*10] Instead, this deterministic world is viewed as compatible with free will. This is roughly 90 percent of philosophers and legal scholars, and the book will most often be taking on these compatibilists.
The world is not deterministic; there’s no free will. This is an oddball view that everything important in the world runs on randomness, a supposed basis of free will. We’ll get to this in chapters 9 and 10.
The world is not deterministic; there is free will. These are folks who believe, like I do, that a deterministic world is not compatible with free will—however, no problem, the world isn’t deterministic in their view, opening a door for free-will belief. These libertarian incompatibilists
are a rarity, and I’ll only occasionally touch on their views.
There’s a related quartet of views concerning the relationship between free will and moral responsibility. The last word obviously carries a lot of baggage with it, and the sense in which it is used by people debating free will typically calls forth the concept of basic desert, where someone can deserve to be treated in a particular way, where the world is a morally acceptable place in its recognition that one person can deserve a particular reward, another a particular punishment. As such, these views are:
There’s no free will, and thus holding people morally responsible for their actions is wrong. Where I sit. (And as will be covered in chapter 14, this is completely separate from forward-looking issues of punishment for deterrent value.)
There’s no free will, but it is okay to hold people morally responsible for their actions. This is another type of compatibilism—an absence of free will and moral responsibility coexist without invoking the supernatural.
There’s free will, and people should be held morally responsible. This is probably the most common stance out there.
There’s free will, but moral responsibility isn’t justified. This is a minority view; typically, when you look closely, the supposed free will exists in a very narrow sense and is certainly not worth executing people about.
Obviously, imposing these classifications on determinism, free will, and moral responsibility is wildly simplified. A key simplification is pretending that most people have clean yes
or no
answers as to whether these states exist; the absence of clear dichotomies leads to frothy philosophical concepts like partial free will, situational free will, free will in only a subset of us, free will only when it matters or only when it doesn’t. This raises the question of whether the edifice of free-will belief is crumbled by one flagrant, highly consequential exception and, conversely, whether free-will skepticism collapses when the opposite occurs. Focusing on gradations between yes and no is important, since interesting things in the biology of behavior are often on continua. As such, my fairly absolutist stance on these issues puts me way out in left field. Again, my goal isn’t to convince you that there’s no free will; it will suffice if you merely conclude that there’s so much less free will than you thought that you have to change your thinking about some truly important things.
Despite starting by separating determinism / free will and free will / moral responsibility, I follow the frequent convention of merging them into one. Thus, my stance is that because the world is deterministic, there can’t be free will, and thus holding people morally responsible for their actions is not okay (a conclusion described as deplorable
by one leading philosopher whose thinking we’re going to dissect big time). This incompatibilism will be most frequently contrasted with the compatibilist view that while the world is deterministic, there is still free will, and thus holding people morally responsible for their actions is just.
This version of compatibilism has produced numerous papers by philosophers and legal scholars concerning the relevance of neuroscience to free will. After reading lots of them, I’ve concluded that they usually boil down to three sentences:
Wow, there’ve been all these cool advances in neuroscience, all reinforcing the conclusion that ours is a deterministic world.
Some of those neuroscience findings challenge our notions of agency, moral responsibility, and deservedness so deeply that one must conclude that there is no free will.
Nah, it still exists.
Naturally, a lot of time will be spent examining the nah
part. In doing so, I’ll consider only a subset of such compatibilists. Here’s a thought experiment for identifying them: In 1848 at a construction site in Vermont, an accident with dynamite hurled a metal rod at high speed into the brain of a worker, Phineas Gage, and out the other side. This destroyed much of Gage’s frontal cortex, an area central to executive function, long-term planning, and impulse control. In the aftermath, Gage was no longer Gage,
as stated by one friend. Formerly sober, reliable, and the foreman of his work crew, Gage was now fitful, irreverent, indulging at times in the grossest profanity (which was not previously his custom)…obstinate, yet capricious and vacillating,
as described by his doctor. Phineas Gage is the textbook case that we are the end products of our material brains. Now, 170 years later, we understand how the unique function of your frontal cortex is the result of your genes, prenatal environment, childhood, and so on (wait for chapter 4).
Now the thought experiment: Raise a compatibilist philosopher from birth in a sealed room where they never learn anything about the brain. Then tell them about Phineas Gage and summarize our current knowledge about the frontal cortex. If their immediate response is Whatever, there’s still free will,
I’m not interested in their views. The compatibilist I have in mind is one who then wonders, OMG, what if I’m completely wrong about free will?,
ponders hard for hours or decades, and concludes that there’s still free will, here’s why, and it’s okay for society to hold people morally responsible for their actions. If a compatibilist has not wrestled through being challenged by knowledge of the biology of who we are, it’s not worth the time trying to counter their free-will belief.
Ground Rules and Definitions
What is free will? Groan, we have to start with that, so here comes something totally predictable along the lines of Different things to different types of thinkers, which gets confusing.
Totally uninviting. Nevertheless, we have to start there, followed by What is determinism?
I’ll do my best to mitigate the drag of this.
What Do I Mean by Free Will?
People define free will differently. Many focus on agency, whether a person can control their actions, act with intent. Other definitions concern whether, when a behavior occurs, the person knows that there are alternatives available. Others are less concerned with what you do than with vetoing what you don’t want to do. Here’s my take.
Suppose that a man pulls the trigger of a gun. Mechanistically, the muscles in his index finger contracted because they were stimulated by a neuron having an action potential (i.e., being in a particularly excited state). That neuron in turn had its action potential because it was stimulated by the neuron just upstream. Which had its own action potential because of the next neuron upstream. And so on.
Here’s the challenge to a free willer: Find me the neuron that started this process in this man’s brain, the neuron that had an action potential for no reason, where no neuron spoke to it just before. Then show me that this neuron’s actions were not influenced by whether the man was tired, hungry, stressed, or in pain at the time. That nothing about this neuron’s function was altered by the sights, sounds, smells, and so on, experienced by the man in the previous minutes, nor by the levels of any hormones marinating his brain in the previous hours to days, nor whether he had experienced a life-changing event in recent months or years. And show me that this neuron’s supposedly freely willed functioning wasn’t affected by the man’s genes, or by the lifelong changes in regulation of those genes caused by experiences during his childhood. Nor by levels of hormones he was exposed to as a fetus, when that brain was being constructed. Nor by the centuries of history and ecology that shaped the invention of the culture in which he was raised. Show me a neuron being a causeless cause in this total sense. The prominent compatibilist philosopher Alfred Mele of Florida State University emphatically feels that requiring something like that of free will is setting the bar absurdly high.
[6] But this bar is neither absurd nor too high. Show me a neuron (or a group of neurons, or an entire brain) whose generation of a behavior is independent of the sum of its biological past, and for the purposes of this book, you’ve demonstrated free will. The point of the first half of this book is to establish that this can’t be shown.
What Do I Mean by Determinism?
It’s virtually required to start this topic with the dead White male Pierre Simon Laplace, the eighteenth-/nineteenth-century French polymath (it’s also required to call him a polymath, as he contributed to mathematics, physics, astronomy, and philosophy). Laplace provided the canonical claim of determinism: If a superhuman knew the location of every particle in the universe at this moment, they could accurately predict every moment in the future. Moreover, if this superhuman (eventually termed Laplace’s demon
) re-created the exact location of every particle at any point in the past, it would lead to a present identical to our current one. The past and future of the universe are already determined.
Science since Laplace’s time shows that he wasn’t completely right, particularly about the future (proving that Laplace was not a Laplacian demon), but the spirit of his demon lives on. Contemporary views of determinism incorporate the fact that certain types of predictability turn out to be impossible (the subject of chapters 5 and 6) and certain aspects of the universe are actually nondeterministic (chapters 9 and 10).
Moreover, contemporary models of determinism must also accommodate the role played by meta-level consciousness. What do I mean by this? Consider a classic psychology demonstration of people having less freedom in their choices than they assumed.[7] Ask someone to name their favorite detergent, and if you have unconsciously cued them earlier with the word ocean, they become more likely to answer, Tide.
As an important measure of where meta-level consciousness comes in, suppose the person realizes what the researcher is up to and, wanting to show that they can’t be manipulated, decides that they won’t say Tide,
even if it is their favorite. Their freedom has been just as constrained, a point in many of the coming chapters. Similarly, wind up as an adult exactly like your parents or the exact opposite of them, and you are equally unfree—in the latter case, the pull toward adopting their behavior, the ability to consciously recognize that tendency to do that, the mindset to recoil from that with horror and thus do the opposite, are all manifestations of the ways that you became you outside your control.
Finally, any contemporary view of determinism must accommodate a profoundly important point, one that dominates the second half of the book—despite the world being deterministic, things can change. Brains change, behaviors change. We change. And that doesn’t counter this being a deterministic world without free will. In fact, the science of change strengthens the conclusion; this will come in chapter 12.
With those issues in mind, time to see the version of determinism that this book builds on.
Imagine a university graduation ceremony. Almost always moving, despite the platitudes, the boilerplate, the kitsch. The happiness, the pride. The families whose sacrifices now all seem worth it. The graduates who were the first in their family to finish high school. The ones whose immigrant parents sit there glowing, their saris, dashikis, barongs broadcasting that their pride in the present isn’t at the cost of pride in their past.
And then you notice someone. Amid the family clusters postceremony, the new graduates posing for pictures with Grandma in her wheelchair, the bursts of hugs and laughter, you see the person way in the back, the person who is part of the grounds crew, collecting the garbage from the cans on the perimeter of the event.
Randomly pick any of the graduates. Do some magic so that this garbage collector started life with the graduate’s genes. Likewise for getting the womb in which nine months were spent and the lifelong epigenetic consequences of that. Get the graduate’s childhood as well—one filled with, say, piano lessons and family game nights, instead of, say, threats of going to bed hungry, becoming homeless, or being deported for lack of papers. Let’s go all the way so that, in addition to the garbage collector having gotten all that of the graduate’s past, the graduate would have gotten the garbage collector’s past. Trade every factor over which they had no control, and you will switch who would be in the graduation robe and who would be hauling garbage cans. This is what I mean by determinism.
And Why Does This Matter?
Because we all know that the graduate and the garbage collector would switch places. And because, nevertheless, we rarely reflect on that sort of fact; we congratulate the graduate on all she’s accomplished and move out of the way of the garbage guy without glancing at him.
Skip Notes
*1 The turtles all the way down
story has versions featuring other celebrated thinkers as the fall guy, rather than William James. We told our version because we liked James’s beard, and there was a building on campus named for him. The turtles all the way down
punch line has been referenced in numerous cultural contexts, including a great book with that title by John Green (Dutton Books, 2017). All the versions of the story have a male Philosopher King Whoever being challenged by an absurd old woman, which now seems kind of sexist and ageist. That didn’t particularly register with us then, we adolescent males of our time and place.
*2 My wife is a musical theater director, and I’m her rusty rehearsal pianist/generalized gofer; as a result, this book is riddled with allusions to musicals. If my college self, being ostensibly cool by referring to William James, had been told that my future included my family and me debating who was the greatest Elphaba of all time, (Idina Menzel. Obviously.) I would have been astonished—Musicals? Broadway MUSICALS?! What about atonalism?
It’s not what I asked for; sometimes life just slips in through a back door.
*3 The appendix is an introduction to neuroscience, for readers without a background in this area. Also, anyone who has read an agonizingly long book that I wrote (Behave: The Biology of Humans at Our Best and Worst, Penguin Press, 2017) will recognize the book summarized in the next few paragraphs: Why did that behavior occur? Because of events one second before, one minute…one century…one hundred million years before.
*4 Interactions
implies that those biological influences are meaningless outside the context of social environment (as well as the reverse). They’re inseparable. My orientation happens to be biological, and analyzing the inseparability from that angle is clearest in my mind. But at times, framing the inseparability from a biological rather than a social science perspective makes things clunky; I’ve tried to avoid that to the best of my biologist abilities.
*5 Some of the most extreme there’s NO free will
fellow travelers include philosophers such as Gregg Caruso, Derk Pereboom, Neil Levy, and Galen Strawson; I’ll often be discussing their thinking in the pages to come; as an important point, while all reject free will in the everyday sense we understand it when justifying punishment and reward, their rejection is not particularly along biological grounds. In terms of rejecting free will almost entirely on biological grounds, my views are closest to those of Sam Harris, who, appropriately, is not only a philosopher, but a neuroscientist as well.
*6 That said, there are a few rare diseases that are guaranteed to alter behavior because of a mutation in a single gene (e.g., Tay-Sachs, Huntington’s, and Gaucher diseases). Nonetheless, this isn’t remotely related to issues of our everyday sense of free will, as these diseases cause massive damage in the brain.
*7 I’d like to note something in preparation for my spending the first half of the book repeatedly saying, They’re all wrong,
about a lot of scholars thinking about this subject. I can be intensely emotional about ideas, with some evoking the closest I can ever feel to religious awe and others seeming so appallingly wrong that I can be bristly, acerbic, arrogantly judgmental, hostile, and unfair in how I critique them. But despite that, I am majorly averse to interpersonal conflict. In other words, with a few exceptions that will be clear, none of my criticisms are meant to be personal. And as a some of my best friends
cliché, I like being around people with a particular type of belief in free will, because they’re generally nicer people than those on my side
and because I hope some of their peace will rub off on me. What I’m trying to say is that I hope I won’t be sounding like a jerk at times, because I very much don’t want to.
*8 Note: I won’t be considering any theologically based Judeo-Christian views about these subjects beyond this broad summary here. As far as I can tell, most of the theological discussions center around omniscience—if God’s all-knowingness includes knowing the future, how can we ever freely, willingly choose between two options (let alone be judged for our choice)? Amid the numerous takes on this, one answer is that God is outside of time, such that past, present, and future are meaningless concepts (implying, among other things, that God could never relax by going to a movie and being pleasantly surprised by a plot turn—He always knows that the butler didn’t do it). Another answer is one of the limited God, something explored by Aquinas—God cannot sin, cannot make a boulder too heavy for Him to lift, cannot make a square circle (or, as another example that I’ve seen offered by a surprising number of male but not female theologians, even God cannot make a married bachelor). In other words, God cannot do everything, He can just do whatever is possible, and foreseeing whether someone will choose good or evil is not knowable, even for Him. Related to this all, Sam Harris mordantly notes that even if we each have a soul, we sure didn’t get to pick it.
*9 Which I’m viewing as synonymous with hard determinism
; all sorts of philosophers, however, make fine distinctions between the two.
*10 Compatibilists make that clear. For example, one paper in the field is entitled Free Will and Substance Dualism: The Real Scientific Threat to Free Will?
For the author, there’s actually no threat to free will; there’s a threat, though, of irksome scientists thinking they’ve scored points against compatibilists by labeling them as substance dualists. Because, to paraphrase a number of compatibilist philosophers, saying that free will doesn’t exist because substance dualism is mythical is like saying that love doesn’t exist because Cupid is mythical.
2
The Final Three Minutes of a Movie
Two men stand by a hangar in a small airfield at night. One is in a police officer’s uniform, the other dressed as a civilian. They talk tensely while, in the background, a small plane is taxiing to the runway. Suddenly, a vehicle pulls up and a man in a military uniform gets out. He and the police officer talk tensely; the military man begins to make a phone call; the civilian shoots him, killing him. A vehicle full of police pulls up abruptly, the police emerging rapidly. The police officer speaks to them as they retrieve the body. They depart as abruptly, with the body but not the shooter. The police officer and the civilian watch the plane take off and then walk off together.
What’s going on? A criminal act obviously occurred—from the care with which the civilian aimed, he clearly intended to shoot the man. A terrible act, compounded further by the man’s remorseless air—this was cold-blooded murder, depraved indifference. It is puzzling, though, that the police officer made no attempt to apprehend him. Possibilities come to mind, none good. Perhaps the officer has been blackmailed by the civilian to look the other way. Maybe all the police who appeared on the scene are corrupt, in the pocket of some drug cartel. Or perhaps the police officer is actually an impostor. One can’t be certain, but it’s clear that this was a scene of intent-filled corruption and lawless violence, the police officer and the civilian exemplars of humans at their worst. That’s for sure.
Intent features heavily in issues about moral responsibility: Did the person intend to act as she did? When exactly was the intent formed? Did she know that she could have done otherwise? Did she feel a sense of ownership of her intent? These are pivotal issues to philosophers, legal scholars, psychologists, and neurobiologists. In fact, a huge percentage of the research done concerning the free-will debate revolves around intent, often microscopically examining the role of intent in the seconds before a behavior happens. Entire conferences, edited volumes, careers, have been spent on those few seconds, and in many ways, this focus is at the heart of arguments supporting compatibilism; this is because all the careful, nuanced, clever experiments done on the subject collectively fail to falsify free will. After reviewing these findings, the purpose of this chapter is to show how, nevertheless, all this is ultimately irrelevant to deciding that there’s no free will. This is because this approach misses 99 percent of the story by not asking the key question: And where did that intent come from in the first place? This is so important because, as we will see, while it sure may seem at times that we are free do as we intend, we are never free to intend what we intend. Maintaining belief in free will by failing to ask that question can be heartless and immoral and is as myopic as believing that all you need to know to assess a movie is to watch its final three minutes. Without that larger perspective, understanding the features and consequences of intent doesn’t amount to a hill of beans.
Three Hundred Milliseconds
Let’s start off with William Henry Harrison, ninth president of the United States, remembered only for idiotically insisting on giving a record-long two-hour inauguration speech in the freezing cold in January 1841, without coat or hat; he caught pneumonia and died a month later, the first president to die in office and the shortest presidential term.[*1],[1]
With that in place, think about William Henry Harrison. But first, we’re going to stick electrodes all over your scalp for an electroencephalogram (EEG), to observe the waves of neuronal excitation generated by your cortex when you’re thinking of Bill.
B8B50N William Henry Harrison President of the US 1841. Hand-colored engravingNow don’t think of Harrison—think about anything else—as we continue recording your EEG. Good, well done. Now don’t think about Harrison, but plan to think about him whenever you want a little while later, and push this button the instant you do. Oh, also, keep an eye on the second hand on this clock and note when you chose to think about Harrison. We’re also going to wire up your hand with recording electrodes to detect precisely when you start the pushing; meanwhile, the EEG will detect when neurons that command those muscles to push the button start to activate. And this is what we find out: those neurons had already activated before you thought you were first freely choosing to start pushing the button.
But the experimental design of this study isn’t perfect, because of its nonspecificity—we may have just learned what’s happening in your brain when it is generically doing something, as opposed to doing this particular something. Let’s switch instead to your choosing between doing A and doing B. William Henry Harrison sits down to some typhoid-riddled burgers and fries, and he asks for ketchup. If you decide he would have pronounced it ketch-up,
immediately push this button with your left hand; if it was cats-up,
push this other button with your right. Don’t think about his pronunciation of ketchup right now; just look at the clock and tell us the instant you chose which button to push. And you get the same answer—the neurons responsible for whichever hand pushes the button activate before you consciously formed your choice.
Let’s do something fancier now than looking at brain waves, since EEG reflects the activity of hundreds of millions of neurons at a time, making it hard to know what’s happening in particular brain regions. Thanks to a grant from the WHH Foundation, we’ve bought a neuroimaging system and will do functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) of your brain while you do the task—this will tell us about activity in each individual brain region at the same time. The results show clearly, once again, that particular regions have decided
which button to push before you believe you consciously and freely chose. Up to ten seconds before, in fact.
Eh, forget about fMRI and the images it produces, where a single pixel’s signal reflects the activity of about half a million neurons. Instead, we’re going to drill holes in your head and then stick electrodes into your brain to monitor the activity of individual neurons; using this approach, once again, we can tell if you’ll go for ketch-up
or cats-up
from the activity of neurons before you believe you decided.
These are the basic approaches and findings in a monumental series of studies that have produced a monumental shitstorm as to whether they demonstrate that free will is a myth. These are the core findings in virtually every debate about what neuroscience can tell us on the subject. And I think that at the end of the day, these studies are irrelevant.
It began with Benjamin Libet, a neuroscientist at the University of California at San Francisco, in a 1983 study so provocative that at least one philosopher refers to it as infamous,
there are conferences held about it, and scientists are described as doing Libet-style studies.
[*2],[2]
We know the experimental setup. Here’s a button. Push it whenever you want. Don’t think about it beforehand; look at this fancy clock that makes it easy to detect fractions of a second and tell us when you decided to push the button, that moment of conscious awareness when you freely made your decision.[*3] Meanwhile, we’ll be collecting EEG data from you and monitoring exactly when your finger starts moving.
Out of this came the basic findings: people reported that they decided to push the button about two hundred milliseconds—two tenths of a second—before their finger started moving. There was also a distinctive EEG pattern, called a readiness potential, when people prepared to move; this emanated from a part of the brain called the SMA (supplementary motor area), which sends projections down the spine, stimulating muscle movement. But here’s the crazy thing: the readiness potential, the evidence that the brain had committed to pushing the button, occurred about three hundred milliseconds before people believed they had decided to push the button. That sense of freely choosing is just a post hoc illusion, a false sense of agency.
This is the observation that started it all. Read technical papers on biology and free will, and in 99.9 percent of them, Libet will appear, usually by the second paragraph. Ditto for articles in the lay press—Scientist Proves There Is No Free Will; Your Brain Decides Before You Think You Did.
[*4] It inspired scads of follow-up research and theorizing; people are still doing studies directly inspired by Libet nearly forty years after his 1983 publication. For example, there’s a 2020 paper entitled Libet’s Intention Reports Are Invalid.
[3] Having your work be important enough that decades later, people are still trash-talking it is immortality for a scientist.
The basic Libet finding that you’re kidding yourself if you think you made a decision when it feels like you did has been replicated. Neuroscientist Patrick Haggard of University College London had subjects choose between two buttons—choosing to do A versus B, rather than choosing to do something versus not. This suggested the same conclusion that the brain has seemingly decided before you think you did.[4]
These findings ushered in Libet 2.0, the work of John-Dylan Haynes and colleagues at Humboldt University in Germany. It was twenty-five years later, with fMRIs available; everything else was the same. Once again, people’s sense of conscious choice came about two hundred milliseconds before the muscles started moving. Most important, the study replicated the conclusion from Libet, fleshing it out further.[*5] With fMRI, Haynes was able to spot the which-button decision even farther up in the brain’s chain of command, in the prefrontal cortex (PFC). This made sense, as the PFC is where executive decisions are made. (When the PFC, along with the rest of the frontal cortex, is destroyed, à la Gage, one makes terrible, disinhibited decisions.) To simplify a bit, once having decided, the PFC passes the decision on to the rest of the frontal cortex, which passes it to the premotor cortex, then to the SMA and, a few steps later, on to your muscles.[*6] Supporting the view of Haynes having spotted decision-making farther upstream, the PFC was making its decision up to ten seconds before subjects felt they were consciously deciding.[*7],[5]
Then Libet 3.0 explored free-will-is-an-illusion down to monitoring the activity of individual neurons. Neuroscientist Itzhak Fried of UCLA worked with patients with intractable epilepsy, unresponsive to antiseizure medications. As a last-ditch effort, neurosurgeons remove the part of the brain where these seizures initiate; with Fried’s patients, it was the frontal cortex. One obviously wants to minimize the amount of tissue removed, and in preparation for that, electrodes are implanted in the targeted area prior to the surgery, allowing for monitoring activity there. This provides a fine-grained map of function, telling you what subparts you should avoid removing, if there’s any leeway.
So Fried would have the subjects do a Libet-style task while electrodes in their frontal cortex detected when particular neurons there activated. Same punch line: some neurons activated in preparation for a particular movement decision seconds before subjects claimed they had consciously decided. In fascinating related studies, he has shown that neurons in the hippocampus that code for a specific episodic memory activate one to two seconds before the person becomes aware of freely recalling that memory.[6]
Thus, three different techniques, monitoring the activity of hundreds of millions of neurons down to single neurons, all show that at the moment when we believe that we are consciously and freely choosing to do something, the neurobiological die has already been cast. That sense of conscious intent is an irrelevant afterthought.
This conclusion is reinforced by studies showing how malleable the sense of intent and agency is. Back to the basic Libet paradigm; this time, pushing a button caused a bell to ring, and the researchers would vary how long of a fraction-of-a-second time delay there’d be between the pushing and the ringing. When the bell ringing was delayed, subjects reported their intent to push the button coming a bit later than usual—without the readiness potential or actual movement changing. Another study showed that if you feel happy, you perceive that conscious sense of choice sooner than if you’re unhappy, showing how our conscious sense of choosing can be fickle and subjective.[7]
Other studies of people undergoing neurosurgery for intractable epilepsy, meanwhile, showed that the sense of intentional movement and actual movement can be separated. Stimulate an additional brain region relevant to decision-making,[*8] and people would claim they had just moved voluntarily—without so much as having tensed a muscle. Stimulate the pre-SMA instead, and people would move their finger while claiming that they hadn’t.[8]
One neurological disorder reinforces these findings. Stroke damage to part of the SMA produces anarchic hand syndrome,
where the hand controlled by that side of the SMA[*9] acts against the person’s will (e.g., grabbing food from someone else’s plate); sufferers even restrain their anarchic hand with their other one.[*10] This suggests that the SMA keeps volition on task, binding intention to action,
all before the person believes they’ve formed that intention.[9]
Psychology studies also show how the sense of agency can be illusory. In one study, pushing a button would be followed immediately by a light going on…some of the time. The percentage of time the light would go on was varied; subjects were then asked how much control they felt they had over the light. People consistently overestimate how reliably the light occurs, feeling that they control it.[*11] In another study, subjects believed they were voluntarily choosing which hand to use in pushing a button. Unbeknownst to them, hand choice was being controlled by transcranial magnetic stimulation[*12] of their motor cortex; nonetheless, subjects perceived themselves as controlling their decisions. Meanwhile, other studies used manipulations straight out of the playbook of magicians and mentalists, with subjects claiming agency over events that were actually foregone and out of their control.[10]
If you do X and this is followed by Y, what increases the odds of your feeling like you caused Y? Psychologist Daniel Wegner of Harvard, a key contributor in this area, identified three logical variables. One is priority—the shorter the delay between X and Y, the more readily we have an illusory sense of will. There are also consistency and exclusivity—how consistently Y happens after you’ve done X, and how often Y happens in the absence of X. The more of the former and the less of the latter, the stronger the illusion.[11]
Collectively, what does this Libetian literature, starting with Libet, show? That we can have an illusory sense of agency, where our sense of freely, consciously choosing to act can be disconnected from reality;[*13] we can be manipulated as to when we first feel a sense of conscious control; most of all, this sense of agency