Aristotle - The Poetics
Aristotle - The Poetics
Aristotle - The Poetics
I
I propose to treat of Poetry in itself and of its various kinds, noting
the essential quality of each; to inquire into the structure of the
plot as requisite to a good poem; into the number and nature of
the parts of which a poem is composed; and similarly into
whatever else falls within the same inquiry. Following, then, the
order of nature, let us begin with the principles which come first.
Thus in the music of the flute and of the lyre, 'harmony' and
rhythm alone are employed; also in other arts, such as that of the
shepherd's pipe, which are essentially similar to these. In
dancing, rhythm alone is used without 'harmony'; for even dancing
imitates character, emotion, and action, by rhythmical movement.
There are, again, some arts which employ all the means above
mentioned, namely, rhythm, tune, and metre. Such are
Dithyrambic and Nomic poetry, and also Tragedy and Comedy;
but between them the difference is, that in the first two cases
these means are all employed in combination, in the latter, now
one means is employed, now another.
Such, then, are the differences of the arts with respect to the
medium of imitation.
II
Since the objects of imitation are men in action, and these men
must be either of a higher or a lower type (for moral character
mainly answers to these divisions, goodness and badness being
the distinguishing marks of moral differences), it follows that we
must represent men either as better than in real life, or as worse,
or as they are. It is the same in painting. Polygnotus depicted men
as nobler than they are, Pauson as less noble, Dionysius drew
them true to life.
III
There is still a third difference--the manner in which each of these
objects may be imitated. For the medium being the same, and the
objects the same, the poet may imitate by narration--in which
case he can either take another personality as Homer does, or
speak in his own person, unchanged--or he may present all his
characters as living and moving before us.
IV
Poetry in general seems to have sprung from two causes, each of
them lying deep in our nature. First, the instinct of imitation is
implanted in man from childhood, one difference between him and
other animals being that he is the most imitative of living
creatures, and through imitation learns his earliest lessons; and
no less universal is the pleasure felt in things imitated. We have
evidence of this in the facts of experience. Objects which in
themselves we view with pain, we delight to contemplate when
reproduced with minute fidelity: such as the forms of the most
ignoble animals and of dead bodies. The cause of this again is,
that to learn gives the liveliest pleasure, not only to philosophers
but to men in general; whose capacity, however, of learning is
more limited. Thus the reason why men enjoy seeing a likeness
is, that in contemplating it they find themselves learning or
inferring, and saying perhaps, 'Ah, that is he.' For if you happen
not to have seen the original, the pleasure will be due not to the
imitation as such, but to the execution, the colouring, or some
such other cause.
Whether Tragedy has as yet perfected its proper types or not; and
whether it is to be judged in itself, or in relation also to the
audience,--this raises another question. Be that as it may,
Tragedy--as also Comedy --- was at first mere improvisation. The
one originated with the authors of the Dithyramb, the other with
those of the phallic songs, which are still in use in many of our
cities. Tragedy advanced by slow degrees; each new element that
showed itself was in turn developed. Having passed through
many changes, it found its natural form, and there it stopped.
V
Comedy is, as we have said, an imitation of characters of a lower
type, not, however, in the full sense of the word bad, the
Ludicrous being merely a subdivision of the ugly. It consists in
some defect or ugliness which is not painful or destructive. To
take an obvious example, the comic mask is ugly and distorted,
but does not imply pain.
VI
Of the poetry which imitates in hexameter verse, and of Comedy,
we will speak hereafter. Let us now discuss Tragedy, resuming its
formal definition, as resulting from what has been already said.
The Plot, then, is the first principle, and, as it were, the soul of a
tragedy: Character holds the second place. A similar fact is seen
in painting. The most beautiful colours, laid on confusedly, will not
give as much pleasure as the chalk outline of a portrait. Thus
Tragedy is the imitation of an action, and of the agents mainly
with a view to the action.
Of the remaining elements Song holds the chief place among the
embellishments.
VII
These principles being established, let us now discuss the proper
structure of the Plot, since this is the first and most important thing
in Tragedy.
VIII
Unity of plot does not, as some persons think, consist in the Unity
of the hero. For infinitely various are the incidents in one man's
life which cannot be reduced to unity; and so, too, there are many
actions of one man out of which we cannot make one action.
Hence, the error, as it appears, of all poets who have composed a
Heracleid, a Theseid, or other poems of the kind. They imagine
that as Heracles was one man, the story of Heracles must also be
a unity. But Homer, as in all else he is of surpassing merit, here
too--whether from art or natural genius--seems to have happily
discerned the truth. In composing the Odyssey he did not include
all the adventures of Odysseus--such as his wound on
Parnassus, or his feigned madness at the mustering of the
host--incidents between which there was no necessary or
probable connection: but he made the Odyssey, and likewise the
Iliad, to centre round an action that in our sense of the word is
one. As therefore, in the other imitative arts, the imitation is one
when the object imitated is one, so the plot, being an imitation of
an action, must imitate one action and that a whole, the structural
union of the parts being such that, if any one of them is displaced
or removed, the whole will be disjointed and disturbed. For a thing
whose presence or absence makes no visible difference, is not an
organic part of the whole.
IX
It is, moreover, evident from what has been said, that it is not the
function of the poet to relate what has happened, but what may
happen,-- what is possible according to the law of probability or
necessity. The poet and the historian differ not by writing in verse
or in prose. The work of Herodotus might be put into verse, and it
would still be a species of history, with metre no less than without
it. The true difference is that one relates what has happened, the
other what may happen. Poetry, therefore, is a more philosophical
and a higher thing than history: for poetry tends to express the
universal, history the particular. By the universal, I mean how a
person of a certain type will on occasion speak or act, according
to the law of probability or necessity; and it is this universality at
which poetry aims in the names she attaches to the personages.
The particular is--for example--what Alcibiades did or suffered. In
Comedy this is already apparent: for here the poet first constructs
the plot on the lines of probability, and then inserts characteristic
names;--unlike the lampooners who write about particular
individuals. But tragedians still keep to real names, the reason
being that what is possible is credible: what has not happened we
do not at once feel sure to be possible: but what has happened is
manifestly possible: otherwise it would not have happened. Still
there are even some tragedies in which there are only one or two
well known names, the rest being fictitious. In others, none are
well known, as in Agathon's Antheus, where incidents and names
alike are fictitious, and yet they give none the less pleasure. We
must not, therefore, at all costs keep to the received legends,
which are the usual subjects of Tragedy. Indeed, it would be
absurd to attempt it; for even subjects that are known are known
only to a few, and yet give pleasure to all. It clearly follows that
the poet or 'maker' should be the maker of plots rather than of
verses; since he is a poet because he imitates, and what he
imitates are actions. And even if he chances to take an historical
subject, he is none the less a poet; for there is no reason why
some events that have actually happened should not conform to
the law of the probable and possible, and in virtue of that quality
in them he is their poet or maker.
Of all plots and actions the epeisodic are the worst. I call a plot
'epeisodic' in which the episodes or acts succeed one another
without probable or necessary sequence. Bad poets compose
such pieces by their own fault, good poets, to please the players;
for, as they write show pieces for competition, they stretch the plot
beyond its capacity, and are often forced to break the natural
continuity.
XI
Reversal of the Situation is a change by which the action veers
round to its opposite, subject always to our rule of probability or
necessity. Thus in the Oedipus, the messenger comes to cheer
Oedipus and free him from his alarms about his mother, but by
revealing who he is, he produces the opposite effect. Again in the
Lynceus, Lynceus is being led away to his death, and Danaus
goes with him, meaning, to slay him; but the outcome of the
preceding incidents is that Danaus is killed and Lynceus saved.
Recognition, as the name indicates, is a change from ignorance
to knowledge, producing love or hate between the persons
destined by the poet for good or bad fortune. The best form of
recognition is coincident with a Reversal of the Situation, as in the
Oedipus. There are indeed other forms. Even inanimate things of
the most trivial kind may in a sense be objects of recognition.
Again, we may recognise or discover whether a person has done
a thing or not. But the recognition which is most intimately
connected with the plot and action is, as we have said, the
recognition of persons. This recognition, combined, with Reversal,
will produce either pity or fear; and actions producing these
effects are those which, by our definition, Tragedy represents.
Moreover, it is upon such situations that the issues of good or bad
fortune will depend. Recognition, then, being between persons, it
may happen that one person only is recognised by the
other-when the latter is already known--or it may be necessary
that the recognition should be on both sides. Thus Iphigenia is
revealed to Orestes by the sending of the letter; but another act of
recognition is required to make Orestes known to Iphigenia.
XII
[The parts of Tragedy which must be treated as elements of the
whole have been already mentioned. We now come to the
quantitative parts, and the separate parts into which Tragedy is
divided, namely, Prologue, Episode, Exode, Choric song; this last
being divided into Parode and Stasimon. These are common to all
plays: peculiar to some are the songs of actors from the stage
and the Commoi.
In the second rank comes the kind of tragedy which some place
first. Like the Odyssey, it has a double thread of plot, and also an
opposite catastrophe for the good and for the bad. It is accounted
the best because of the weakness of the spectators; for the poet
is guided in what he writes by the wishes of his audience. The
pleasure, however, thence derived is not the true tragic pleasure.
It is proper rather to Comedy, where those who, in the piece, are
the deadliest enemies---like Orestes and Aegisthus--quit the
stage as friends at the close, and no one slays or is slain.
XIV
Fear and pity may be aroused by spectacular means; but they
may also result from the inner structure of the piece, which is the
better way, and indicates a superior poet. For the plot ought to be
so constructed that, even without the aid of the eye, he who hears
the tale told will thrill with horror and melt to pity at what takes
place. This is the impression we should receive from hearing the
story of the Oedipus. But to produce this effect by the mere
spectacle is a less artistic method, and dependent on extraneous
aids. Those who employ spectacular means to create a sense not
of the terrible but only of the monstrous, are strangers to the
purpose of Tragedy; for we must not demand of Tragedy any and
every kind of pleasure, but only that which is proper to it. And
since the pleasure which the poet should afford is that which
comes from pity and fear through imitation, it is evident that this
quality must be impressed upon the incidents.
XV
In respect of Character there are four things to be aimed at. First,
and most important, it must be good. Now any speech or action
that manifests moral purpose of any kind will be expressive of
character: the character will be good if the purpose is good. This
rule is relative to each class. Even a woman may be good, and
also a slave; though the woman may be said to be an inferior
being, and the slave quite worthless. The second thing to aim at is
propriety. There is a type of manly valour; but valour in a woman,
or unscrupulous cleverness, is inappropriate. Thirdly, character
must be true to life: for this is a distinct thing from goodness and
propriety, as here described. The fourth point is consistency: for
though the subject of the imitation, who suggested the type, be
inconsistent, still he must be consistently inconsistent. As an
example of motiveless degradation of character, we have
Menelaus in the Orestes: of character indecorous and
inappropriate, the lament of Odysseus in the Scylla, and the
speech of Melanippe: of inconsistency, the Iphigenia at Aulis,--for
Iphigenia the suppliant in no way resembles her later self.
XVI
What Recognition is has been already explained. We will now
enumerate its kinds.
First, the least artistic form, which, from poverty of wit, is most
commonly employed recognition by signs. Of these some are
congenital,-- such as 'the spear which the earth-born race bear on
their bodies,' or the stars introduced by Carcinus in his Thyestes.
Others are acquired after birth; and of these some are bodily
marks, as scars; some external tokens, as necklaces, or the little
ark in the Tyro by which the discovery is effected. Even these
admit of more or less skilful treatment. Thus in the recognition of
Odysseus by his scar, the discovery is made in one way by the
nurse, in another by the swineherds. The use of tokens for the
express purpose of proof --and, indeed, any formal proof with or
without tokens --is a less artistic mode of recognition. A better
kind is that which comes about by a turn of incident, as in the
Bath Scene in the Odyssey.
But, of all recognitions, the best is that which arises from the
incidents themselves, where the startling discovery is made by
natural means. Such is that in the Oedipus of Sophocles, and in
the Iphigenia; for it was natural that Iphigenia should wish to
dispatch a letter. These recognitions alone dispense with the
artificial aid of tokens or amulets. Next come the recognitions by
process of reasoning.
XVII
In constructing the plot and working it out with the proper diction,
the poet should place the scene, as far as possible, before his
eyes. In this way, seeing everything with the utmost vividness, as
if he were a spectator of the action, he will discover what is in
keeping with it, and be most unlikely to overlook inconsistencies.
The need of such a rule is shown by the fault found in Carcinus.
Amphiaraus was on his way from the temple. This fact escaped
the observation of one who did not see the situation. On the
stage, however, the piece failed, the audience being offended at
the oversight.
Again, the poet should work out his play, to the best of his power,
with appropriate gestures; for those who feel emotion are most
convincing through natural sympathy with the characters they
represent; and one who is agitated storms, one who is angry
rages, with the most life-like reality. Hence poetry implies either a
happy gift of nature or a strain of madness. In the one case a man
can take the mould of any character; in the other, he is lifted out
of his proper self.
After this, the names being once given, it remains to fill in the
episodes. We must see that they are relevant to the action. In the
case of Orestes, for example, there is the madness which led to
his capture, and his deliverance by means of the purificatory rite.
In the drama, the episodes are short, but it is these that give
extension to Epic poetry. Thus the story of the Odyssey can be
stated briefly. A certain man is absent from home for many years;
he is jealously watched by Poseidon, and left desolate.
Meanwhile his home is in a wretched plight---suitors are wasting
his substance and plotting against his son. At length, tempest-
tost, he himself arrives; he makes certain persons acquainted with
him; he attacks the suitors with his own hand, and is himself
preserved while he destroys them. This is the essence of the plot;
the rest is episode.
XVIII
Every tragedy falls into two parts,--Complication and Unravelling
or Denouement. Incidents extraneous to the action are frequently
combined with a portion of the action proper, to form the
Complication; the rest is the Unravelling. By the Complication I
mean all that extends from the beginning of the action to the part
which marks the turning-point to good or bad fortune. The
Unravelling is that which extends from the beginning of the
change to the end. Thus, in the Lynceus of Theodectes, the
Complication consists of the incidents presupposed in the drama,
the seizure of the child, and then again The Unravelling extends
from the accusation of murder to the end.
Again, the poet should remember what has been often said, and
not make an Epic structure into a Tragedy--by an Epic structure I
mean one with a multiplicity of plots--as if, for instance, you were
to make a tragedy out of the entire story of the Iliad. In the Epic
poem, owing to its length, each part assumes its proper
magnitude. In the drama the result is far from answering to the
poet's expectation. The proof is that the poets who have
dramatised the whole story of the Fall of Troy, instead of selecting
portions, like Euripides; or who have taken the whole tale of
Niobe, and not a part of her story, like Aeschylus, either fail utterly
or meet with poor success on the stage. Even Agathon has been
known to fail from this one defect. In his Reversals of the
Situation, however, he shows a marvellous skill in the effort to hit
the popular taste,--to produce a tragic effect that satisfies the
moral sense. This effect is produced when the clever rogue, like
Sisyphus, is outwitted, or the brave villain defeated. Such an
event is probable in Agathon's sense of the word: 'it is probable,'
he says, 'that many things should happen contrary to probability.'
XIX
It remains to speak of Diction and Thought, the other parts of
Tragedy having been already discussed. Concerning Thought, we
may assume what is said in the Rhetoric, to which inquiry the
subject more strictly belongs. Under Thought is included every
effect which has to be produced by speech, the subdivisions
being,-- proof and refutation; the excitation of the feelings, such
as pity, fear, anger, and the like; the suggestion of importance or
its opposite. Now, it is evident that the dramatic incidents must be
treated from the same points of view as the dramatic speeches,
when the object is to evoke the sense of pity, fear, importance, or
probability. The only difference is, that the incidents should speak
for themselves without verbal exposition; while the effects aimed
at in speech should be produced by the speaker, and as a result
of the speech. For what were the business of a speaker, if the
Thought were revealed quite apart from what he says?
XX
[Language in general includes the following parts:- Letter,
Syllable, Connecting word, Noun, Verb, Inflexion or Case,
Sentence or Phrase.
A Letter is an indivisible sound, yet not every such sound, but only
one which can form part of a group of sounds. For even brutes
utter indivisible sounds, none of which I call a letter. The sound I
mean may be either a vowel, a semi-vowel, or a mute. A vowel is
that which without impact of tongue or lip has an audible sound. A
semi-vowel, that which with such impact has an audible sound, as
S and R. A mute, that which with such impact has by itself no
sound, but joined to a vowel sound becomes audible, as G and D.
These are distinguished according to the form assumed by the
mouth and the place where they are produced; according as they
are aspirated or smooth, long or short; as they are acute, grave,
or of an intermediate tone; which inquiry belongs in detail to the
writers on metre.
Inflexion belongs both to the noun and verb, and expresses either
the relation 'of,' 'to,' or the like; or that of number, whether one or
many, as 'man' or 'men '; or the modes or tones in actual delivery,
e.g. a question or a command. 'Did he go?' and 'go' are verbal
inflexions of this kind.
XXI
Words are of two kinds, simple and double. By simple I mean
those composed of non-significant elements, such as . By double
or compound, those composed either of a significant and
non-significant element (though within the whole word no element
is significant), or of elements that are both significant. A word may
likewise be triple, quadruple, or multiple in form, like so many
Massilian expressions, e.g. 'Hermo-caico-xanthus who prayed to
Father Zeus.'
Every word is either current, or strange, or metaphorical, or
ornamental, or newly-coined, or lengthened, or contracted, or
altered.
XXII
The perfection of style is to be clear without being mean. The
clearest style is that which uses only current or proper words; at
the same time it is mean:--witness the poetry of Cleophon and of
Sthenelus. That diction, on the other hand, is lofty and raised
above the commonplace which employs unusual words. By
unusual, I mean strange (or rare) words, metaphorical,
lengthened,--anything, in short, that differs from the normal idiom.
Yet a style wholly composed of such words is either a riddle or a
jargon; a riddle, if it consists of metaphors; a jargon, if it consists
of strange (or rare) words. For the essence of a riddle is to
express true facts under impossible combinations. Now this
cannot be done by any arrangement of ordinary words, but by the
use of metaphor it can. Such is the riddle:--'A man I saw who on
another man had glued the bronze by aid of fire,' and others of
the same kind. A diction that is made up of strange (or rare) terms
is a jargon. A certain infusion, therefore, of these elements is
necessary to style; for the strange (or rare) word, the
metaphorical, the ornamental, and the other kinds above
mentioned, will raise it above the commonplace and mean, while
the use of proper words will make it perspicuous. But nothing
contributes more to produce a clearness of diction that is remote
from commonness than the lengthening, contraction, and
alteration of words. For by deviating in exceptional cases from the
normal idiom, the language will gain distinction; while, at the same
time, the partial conformity with usage will give perspicuity. The
critics, therefore, are in error who censure these licenses of
speech, and hold the author up to ridicule. Thus Eucleides, the
elder, declared that it would be an easy matter to be a poet if you
might lengthen syllables at will. He caricatured the practice in the
very form of his diction, as in the verse: ' , or,
. To employ such license at all obtrusively is, no doubt, grotesque;
but in any mode of poetic diction there must be moderation. Even
metaphors, strange (or rare) words, or any similar forms of
speech, would produce the like effect if used without propriety and
with the express purpose of being ludicrous. How great a
difference is made by the appropriate use of lengthening, may be
seen in Epic poetry by the insertion of ordinary forms in the verse.
So, again, if we take a strange (or rare) word, a metaphor, or any
similar mode of expression, and replace it by the current or proper
term, the truth of our observation will be manifest. For example
Aeschylus and Euripides each composed the same iambic line.
But the alteration of a single word by Euripides, who employed
the rarer term instead of the ordinary one, makes one verse
appear beautiful and the other trivial. Aeschylus in his Philoctetes
says: .
Euripides substitutes 'feasts on' for 'feeds on.' Again, in the line,
, the difference will be felt if we substitute the common words,
. Or, if for the line, , We read, .
Or, for ,
XXIII
As to that poetic imitation which is narrative in form and employs
a single metre, the plot manifestly ought, as in a tragedy, to be
constructed on dramatic principles. It should have for its subject a
single action, whole and complete, with a beginning, a middle,
and an end. It will thus resemble a living organism in all its unity,
and produce the pleasure proper to it. It will differ in structure from
historical compositions, which of necessity present not a single
action, but a single period, and all that happened within that
period to one person or to many, little connected together as the
events may be. For as the sea-fight at Salamis and the battle with
the Carthaginians in Sicily took place at the same time, but did not
tend to any one result, so in the sequence of events, one thing
sometimes follows another, and yet no single result is thereby
produced. Such is the practice, we may say, of most poets. Here
again, then, as has been already observed, the transcendent
excellence of Homer is manifest. He never attempts to make the
whole war of Troy the subject of his poem, though that war had a
beginning and an end. It would have been too vast a theme, and
not easily embraced in a single view. If, again, he had kept it
within moderate limits, it must have been over-complicated by the
variety of the incidents. As it is, he detaches a single portion, and
admits as episodes many events from the general story of the
war--such as the Catalogue of the ships and others--thus
diversifying the poem. All other poets take a single hero, a single
period, or an action single indeed, but with a multiplicity of parts.
Thus did the author of the Cypria and of the Little Iliad. For this
reason the Iliad and the Odyssey each furnish the subject of one
tragedy, or, at most, of two; while the Cypria supplies materials for
many, and the Little Iliad for eight--the Award of the Arms, the
Philoctetes, the Neoptolemus, the Eurypylus, the Mendicant
Odysseus, the Laconian Women, the Fall of Ilium, the Departure
of the Fleet.
XXIV
Again, Epic poetry must have as many kinds as Tragedy: it must
be simple, or complex, or 'ethical,' or 'pathetic.' The parts also,
with the exception of song and spectacle, are the same; for it
requires Reversals of the Situation, Recognitions, and Scenes of
Suffering. Moreover, the thoughts and the diction must be artistic.
In all these respects Homer is our earliest and sufficient model.
Indeed each of his poems has a twofold character. The Iliad is at
once simple and 'pathetic,' and the Odyssey complex (for
Recognition scenes run through it), and at the same time 'ethical.'
Moreover, in diction and thought they are supreme.
As for the metre, the heroic measure has proved its fitness by the
test of experience. If a narrative poem in any other metre or in
many metres were now composed, it would be found
incongruous. For of all measures the heroic is the stateliest and
the most massive; and hence it most readily admits rare words
and metaphors, which is another point in which the narrative form
of imitation stands alone. On the other hand, the iambic and the
trochaic tetrameter are stirring measures, the latter being akin to
dancing, the former expressive of action. Still more absurd would
it be to mix together different metres, as was done by
Chaeremon. Hence no one has ever composed a poem on a
great scale in any other than heroic verse. Nature herself, as we
have said, teaches the choice of the proper measure.
XXV
With respect to critical difficulties and their solutions, the number
and nature of the sources from which they may be drawn may be
thus exhibited.
The poet being an imitator, like a painter or any other artist, must
of necessity imitate one of three objects,--things as they were or
are, things as they are said or thought to be, or things as they
ought to be. The vehicle of expression is language,--either current
terms or, it may be, rare words or metaphors. There are also
many modifications of language, which we concede to the poets.
Add to this, that the standard of correctness is not the same in
poetry and politics, any more than in poetry and any other art.
Within the art of poetry itself there are two kinds of faults, those
which touch its essence, and those which are accidental. If a poet
has chosen to imitate something, but has imitated it incorrectly
through want of capacity, the error is inherent in the poetry. But if
the failure is due to a wrong choice if he has represented a horse
as throwing out both his off legs at once, or introduced technical
inaccuracies in medicine, for example, or in any other art the error
is not essential to the poetry. These are the points of view from
which we should consider and answer the objections raised by
the critics.
Again, does the error touch the essentials of the poetic art, or
some accident of it? For example,--not to know that a hind has no
horns is a less serious matter than to paint it inartistically.
Further, if it be objected that the description is not true to fact, the
poet may perhaps reply,--'But the objects are as they ought to be':
just as Sophocles said that he drew men as they ought to be;
Euripides, as they are. In this way the objection may be met. If,
however, the representation be of neither kind, the poet may
answer,--This is how men say the thing is.' This applies to tales
about the gods. It may well be that these stories are not higher
than fact nor yet true to fact: they are, very possibly, what
Xenophanes says of them. But anyhow, 'this is what is said.'
Again, a description may be no better than the fact: 'still, it was
the fact'; as in the passage about the arms: 'Upright upon their
butt-ends stood the spears.' This was the custom then, as it now
is among the Illyrians.
Thus, there are five sources from which critical objections are
drawn. Things are censured either as impossible, or irrational, or
morally hurtful, or contradictory, or contrary to artistic correctness.
The answers should be sought under the twelve heads above
mentioned.
XXVI
The question may be raised whether the Epic or Tragic mode of
imitation is the higher. If the more refined art is the higher, and the
more refined in every case is that which appeals to the better sort
of audience, the art which imitates anything and everything is
manifestly most unrefined. The audience is supposed to be too
dull to comprehend unless something of their own is thrown in by
the performers, who therefore indulge in restless movements. Bad
flute-players twist and twirl, if they have to represent 'the
quoit-throw,' or hustle the coryphaeus when they perform the
'Scylla.' Tragedy, it is said, has this same defect. We may
compare the opinion that the older actors entertained of their
successors. Mynniscus used to call Callippides 'ape' on account
of the extravagance of his action, and the same view was held of
Pindarus. Tragic art, then, as a whole, stands to Epic in the same
relation as the younger to the elder actors. So we are told that
Epic poetry is addressed to a cultivated audience, who do not
need gesture; Tragedy, to an inferior public. Being then unrefined,
it is evidently the lower of the two.
Now, in the first place, this censure attaches not to the poetic but
to the histrionic art; for gesticulation may be equally overdone in
epic recitation, as by Sosi-stratus, or in lyrical competition, as by
Mnasitheus the Opuntian. Next, all action is not to be condemned
any more than all dancing--but only that of bad performers. Such
was the fault found in Callippides, as also in others of our own
day, who are censured for representing degraded women. Again,
Tragedy like Epic poetry produces its effect even without action; it
reveals its power by mere reading. If, then, in all other respects it
is superior, this fault, we say, is not inherent in it.
And superior it is, because it has all the epic elements--it may
even use the epic metre--with the music and spectacular effects
as important accessories; and these produce the most vivid of
pleasures. Further, it has vividness of impression in reading as
well as in representation. Moreover, the art attains its end within
narrower limits; for the concentrated effect is more pleasurable
than one which is spread over a long time and so diluted. What,
for example, would be the effect of the Oedipus of Sophocles, if it
were cast into a form as long as the Iliad? Once more, the Epic
imitation has less unity; as is shown by this, that any Epic poem
will furnish subjects for several tragedies. Thus if the story
adopted by the poet has a strict unity, it must either be concisely
told and appear truncated; or, if it conform to the Epic canon of
length, it must seem weak and watery. Such length implies some
loss of unity, if, I mean, the poem is constructed out of several
actions, like the Iliad and the Odyssey, which have many such
parts, each with a certain magnitude of its own. Yet these poems
are as perfect as possible in structure; each is, in the highest
degree attainable, an imitation of a single action.