(Colin Farrelly) An Introduction To Contemporary P
(Colin Farrelly) An Introduction To Contemporary P
(Colin Farrelly) An Introduction To Contemporary P
QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page i
Introduction to
Contemporary Political Theory
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page ii
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page iii
Introduction to
Contemporary Political
Theory
Colin Farrelly
SAGE Publications
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page iv
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page v
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page vi
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page vii
Contents
Preface
ix
3
3
7
10
15
17
21
23
26
33
33
35
39
41
46
49
53
53
54
57
63
67
4 Dworkin on Equality
4.1 Introduction
4.2 Dworkin on equality of resources
4.3 Welfare reform and the basic income proposal
4.4 Political equality and democracy
4.5 Against luck egalitarianism
73
73
75
80
85
89
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page viii
viii
Contents
95
5 Communitarianism
5.1 Introduction
5.2 Deontological liberalism and the unencumbered self
5.3 State neutrality
5.4 Walzer and complex equality
5.5 Miller on nationalism
5.6 Conclusion
97
97
99
102
106
110
115
6 Multiculturalism
6.1 Introduction: the politics of recognition
6.2 Kymlicka and the rights of national minorities
6.3 Polyethnic rights
6.4 Barry against multiculturalism
119
119
122
127
131
7 Deliberative Democracy
7.1 Introduction: the importance of democracy
7.2 Moving beyond the aggregative model of democracy
7.3 How substantive are the principles of democracy?
7.4 Retaining the critical edge of deliberative democracy
7.5 Critically assessing the ideal of deliberative democracy
137
137
139
144
148
150
8 Feminism
8.1 Introduction
8.2 Liberal feminism
8.3 The public/private dichotomy
8.4 The politics of difference
8.5 Conclusion
157
157
159
164
169
174
Bibliography
177
Index
183
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page ix
Preface
What is political theory?
I suppose the obvious place to begin a textbook entitled An Introduction to
Contemporary Political Theory is to stipulate what I take to count as contemporary and, more importantly, what counts as political theory. This is not
as easy as it sounds. Let me begin with the second and more difficult of these
two questions that of defining what political theory is. I am hesitant to stipulate a concise, all-encompassing definition; any such definition is bound to
alienate someone and thus result in the charge that my definition is not
inclusive. There is no consensus among political theorists as to what, exactly,
constitutes the discipline. When one surveys the journals in political theory
and the books written by those who call themselves political theorists one
sees a variety of topics being addressed. These range from the history of
political thought to analyses of political concepts like freedom, equality and
democracy. Topics from such diverse traditions as feminism, socialism, anarchism and liberalism all fall under the general rubric of political theory. The
fact that political theory is thriving as a discipline makes it all the more difficult to provide an inclusive definition of the discipline. The areas of
enquiry that political theorists explore are constantly changing, and with
this, our understanding of what qualifies as political theory.
However, having said that, I think it is accurate to say that what unites
these diverse traditions under the rubric of political theory is their concern
for how we ought, collectively, to live together. More than forty years ago
John Plamenatz described political theory as the systematic thinking about
the purposes of government (Plamenatz, 1960: 37) and I think this definition
is just as apt today as it was then. I doubt a more inclusive definition could
be constructed that would cover the vast array of concerns which contemporary political theorists have.
Political theory is thus a normative discipline, it is primarily concerned
with how things ought to be as opposed to how things actually are. Of
course this does not mean that theorists should not take seriously the realities of the current social and political arrangements. This is essential as one
cannot determine what we should be aspiring towards if one does not know
where we currently are and thus what the pros and cons of the current
arrangement are. But political theorists do not engage in the descriptive or
explanatory project that the political scientist engages in. The political scientist tackles questions like How is the American political system different
from that of other countries?, or Who actually wields political power in
America? Whereas the political theorist will ask Who should wield political
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page x
Preface
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
Preface
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page xi
xi
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
xii
Page xii
Preface
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
Preface
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page xiii
xiii
3119-PRELIMS.QXD
11/5/03 2:30 PM
Page xiv
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 1
Part One:
Contemporary Liberal
Theory
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 2
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 3
Summary Contents
1.1
1.2
1.3
1.4
1.5
1.6
1.7
1.8
Introduction
The original position
Equal opportunity
Cohen on incentives
The principles that apply to individuals
Who are the least advantaged?
Beitz on global Justice
A political conception of justice
3
7
10
15
17
21
23
26
1.1 Introduction
John Rawls is arguably the most important political philosopher of the
twentieth century. In his two most important books, A Theory of Justice
(1971)1 and Political Liberalism (1993), he defends his theory entitled justice
as fairness. Justice as fairness is primarily concerned with the way in which
major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooperation (Rawls, 1999: 6). As
such, justice as fairness is a theory designed to apply to what Rawls calls the
basic structure the political, social and economic institutions of society. It
provides a normative ideal by which we are to judge the political constitution of society and the principal economic and social arrangements. The just
society, according to justice as fairness, is one governed by the two principles
of justice. These principles are:
Each person has the same indefensible claim to a fully adequate scheme
of equal basic liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same
scheme of liberties for all (equal basic liberties principle).
Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions. First, they
are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of
fair equality of opportunity (fair equality of opportunity principle); and
second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged
members of society (difference principle).
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 4
The principles are presented in lexical order. This means that they are listed
in order of priority. The equal basic liberties principle must be satisfied
before the second principle is invoked and the fair equality of opportunity
principle must be satisfied before the difference principle can be invoked.
In this chapter we shall consider the main components of Rawlss liberal
theory and some of the objections raised against it. Many of the theorists we
shall examine in later chapters will also raise objections to Rawlss liberal
theory of justice. In constructing his theory of justice as fairness Rawls
appeals to the idea of the social contract. His theory is inspired by contractarians like John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Immanuel Kant. The
main rival of the contractarian tradition is utilitarianism and Rawls offers his
theory as an alternative to utilitarianism, which had been the dominant tradition
prior to the publication of A Theory of Justice. It is perhaps best to begin then
with a brief discussion of utilitarianism and Rawlss objections to it.
In Contemporary Ethics: Taking Account of Utilitarianism William Shaw
claims that two fundamental ideas underlie utilitarianism: first, that the
results of our actions are the key to their moral evaluation, and second, that
one should assess and compare those results in terms of the happiness they
cause (or more broadly, in terms of their impact on peoples well-being)
(Shaw, 1999: 2). When stated like this, it is easy to see why utilitarianism has
enjoyed an eminent list of devotees, which include David Hume, Adam
Smith, Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. It captures some of our most
basic moral intuitions concerning the importance of, for example, impartiality and human welfare. Utilitarians have put forth diverse accounts of what
qualifies as human happiness, or utility, but they share the belief that the
best outcome is the one that maximizes overall happiness or utility.
It is important to note that utilitarianism can be utilized as both an ethical
theory designed to answer the question what should I do? and as a political theory that applies to the conduct of political affairs the decisions we
make regarding how we are, collectively, to live together. It is this appeal to
utilitarianism as a public philosophy that Rawls criticizes and thus I shall
focus only on its viability as a normative political theory.
In A Theory of Justice Rawls invokes two main concepts of ethics the right
and the good in order to illustrate how his contractarian theory differs
from utilitarianism. The structure of an ethical theory is, then, largely determined by how it defines and connects these two basic notions (Rawls, 1999:
21). Rawls distinguishes between the following two ways of relating the
right and the good. The first way is to define the good independently from
the right, and then the right as that which maximizes the good. Suppose, for
example, one defines the good as material prosperity. If we accept this definition of the good then we can determine which laws and policies are the
right ones by simply choosing the institutional arrangement that will bring
about the greatest level of material prosperity. Institutions and acts are right
if, of the available alternatives, they produce the most good. Rawls calls this
type of theory a teleological theory. It is contrasted with a deontological theory.
Deontological theories can be defined as a theory that either does not specify
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 5
the good independently from the right, or does not interpret the right as
maximising the good (Rawls, 1999: 26). Rawls wants to defend a theory that
is deontological in this second sense, that is, it gives a priority to the right
over the good.
The appeal of the deontological position can be brought out by considering the example noted above. A teleological theory instructs us to maximize
the good. If we define the good as material prosperity, for example, the institutions of our society will be designed to maximize overall material prosperity. But such a goal may be pursued by measures we think are unjust.
Maximizing overall material prosperity might justify restricting the number
of children people can have or denying the terminally ill expensive health
care provisions. By asserting a priority of the right over the good Rawls
seeks to avoid the injustices that may be made in the name of maximizing
utility. As Rawls puts it, each person possesses an inviolability founded on
justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override (Rawls,
1999: 3).
The main target of Rawlss critique is the classical utilitarian doctrine
espoused by Jeremy Bentham and Henry Sidgwick. This version maintains
that society is rightly ordered, and therefore just, when its major institutions
are arranged so as to achieve the greatest net balance of satisfaction summed
over all the individuals belonging to it (Rawls, 1999: 20). Such an approach
extends what is a commonsensical approach to the principle of choice for
one person to the principle of choice for an association of people. Rawls
explains how, as a principle of choice for one person, the utilitarian ethic
seems like a rational ethic:
Each man in realizing his own interests is certainly free to balance his own
losses against his own gains. We may impose a sacrifice on ourselves now
for the sake of a greater advantage later. A person quite properly acts, at
least when others are not affected, to achieve his own greatest good, to
advance his rational ends as far as possible. (Rawls, 1999: 21)
But the reasoning that is appropriate for the choice of one person should
not, argues Rawls, be extended to the choice for an association of people.
This is what utilitarianism does. In doing so it does not take seriously the
distinction between persons. There are some things we should not do to
people, even if doing it achieves the greatest net balance of satisfaction for
all. In particular, Rawls argues that in a just society the basic liberties are
taken for granted and the rights secured by justice are not subject to political
bargaining or to the calculus of social interests (Rawls, 1999: 25).
Utilitarianism treats questions of distributive justice as questions of efficient administration. The nature of the decision made by the ideal legislator
is not, therefore, materially different from that of an entrepreneur deciding
how to maximize his profit by producing this or that commodity, or that of
a consumer deciding how to maximize his satisfaction by the purchase of
this or that collection of goods (Rawls, 1999: 24). But justice, claims Rawls,
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 6
must trump the virtue of efficiency. The right is prior to the good. Justice
denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good
shared by others.
Rawlss method
The task of determining which principles should govern the main institutions of our society is a monumental one and Rawls believes that we must
begin this task with some criteria for assessing the viability of the principles
on offer. Rawls claims that there is a definite if limited class of facts against
which conjectured principles can be checked . . .(Rawls, 1999: 44). This class
of facts comprises the considered judgements we have concerning what constitutes a just society. Our moral sensibilities tell us that acts of murder, slavery and discrimination, for example, are acts that our institutions should
seek to prevent and, in cases where they do occur, the perpetrators should be
appropriately punished. Any theory of justice that conflicts with these judgements will fail to be compelling. For example, a theory that permits denying
ethnic minorities the right to vote will fail to secure our approval. One of our
most firmly entrenched beliefs concerning justice is that all citizens should
be entitled to the right to vote, regardless of their race, religion or gender. A
theory that fails to accommodate such a widely shared belief fails to be a
viable account of the demands of justice.
This appeal to a shared understanding of what justice demands is an
important aspect of Rawlss theory. When constructing a theory we must
start somewhere, and Rawls wants to start with general and widely accepted
premises, premises that reflect the considered judgements citizens of a
democratic society have. These judgements serve as the moral data from
which we are to construct and test a theory of justice. A theory that blatantly
violates one of these convictions will fail to be a viable theory. While Rawls
endorses appealing to some shared beliefs in the initial stages of his theory,
he is quick to point out that he does not appeal to values that violate what he
calls the fact of reasonable pluralism. This is the fact of profound and irreconcilable differences in citizens reasonable comprehensive religious and philosophical conceptions of the world, and in their views of the moral and
aesthetic values to be sought in human life (Rawls, 2001: 3). Citizens affirm
diverse and often competing conceptions of what is of value in life. An appeal
to contentious claims concerning, for example, what the Bible says concerning the sexual relations between a man and a woman, goes well beyond the
shared judgements citizens of a free and democratic society have.
Rawls does not provide an exhaustive list of what these initial shared
assumptions are. Nor does he claim that our initial convictions are exempt
from scrutiny. On the contrary, once we begin to consider the complexities of
issues raised by different conceptions of justice, we will find that we revise
or perhaps even abandon some of the initial convictions we began with.
What we seek is a fit between the principles of justice and our considered
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 7
judgements. This is what Rawls calls reflective equilibrium. We will not find a
perfect fit between these two things, but by striving for such a fit we can rule
out various contending principles of justice as well as clarify what our
considered judgements are regarding the demands of justice.
While Rawls does not provide an exhaustive list of what these initial
assumptions are, he does invoke certain fundamental ideas he believes are
embedded in the public political culture of a democratic society. These
include the following:
1 The idea of society as a fair system of social cooperation over time from one
generation to the next.
2 The idea of citizens as free and equal persons. As such, they are taken to possess two moral powers. Firstly, the capacity for a sense of justice. That is,
the capacity to understand, to apply, and to act from (and not merely in
accordance with) the principles of political justice that specify the fair
terms of social cooperation. Secondly, persons have a capacity for a conception of the good. That is, the capacity to have, revise, and rationally
to pursue a conception of the good. (Rawls, 2001: 1819)
These fundamental ideas are, claims Rawls, viewed as being familiar from
the public political culture of a democratic society.
Even though such ideas are not often expressly formulated, nor their meaning clearly marked out, they may play a fundamental role in societys political thought and in how its institutions are interpreted, for example, by
courts and in historical or other texts regarded as being of enduring significance. That a democratic society is often viewed as a system of social cooperation is suggested by the fact that from a political point of view, and in
the context of the public discussion of basic questions of political rights, its
citizens do not regard their social order as a fixed natural order, or as an
institutional structure justified by religious doctrines or hierarchical principles pressing aristocratic values. (Rawls, 2001: 6)
If we begin with these fundamental organizing ideas, how are we to determine what the specific requirements of fair terms of cooperation actually
are? To answer this question Rawls introduces the original position.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 8
individuals. They are also given a limited list of principles from which to
choose. This list includes Rawlss two principles of justice and their priority
rules, utilitarianism and perfectionism.2
Rawls describes the original position as the appropriate initial status quo. It
is one in which all people are treated as equals. In order to be so, certain conditions must hold. In everyday life a number of unfair factors influence
agreements that we want to rule out in the original position. For example,
unfair bargaining advantages, threats of force and coercion, and deception
and fraud. In order to ensure that the choice of principles of justice is impartial and fair Rawls invokes the following two constraints:
1 The principles must fulfil what he calls the formal constraints of the right.
2 They must be chosen behind a veil of ignorance.
The formal constraints of the right impose five restrictions on the choice of
principles. The principles must be general in form and universal in application, they are to be publicly recognized as a final court of appeal for ordering the
conflicting claims of moral persons. Rawls provides an explanation for each of
the five constraints of the right.3 But none of the formal constraints of the
right rule out the traditional conceptions of justice. What they do rule out are
certain variants of egoism. The generality requirement, for example, rules
out first-person dictatorships.
Further constraints are imposed on the choice situation by the veil of ignorance. By placing the parties behind a veil of ignorance Rawls believes that
the choice situation will nullify the effects of specific contingencies that put
men at odds and tempt them to exploit social and natural circumstances to
their own advantage (Rawls, 1999: 118). From behind the veil of ignorance
the parties are denied certain information which will ensure that they evaluate principles solely on the basis of general considerations. The parties do
not know the following information:
The only facts the parties do know are general facts about society (for example,
principles of economic theory and laws of human psychology) and that their
society is subject to the circumstances of justice.4
Having clarified the task facing the parties in the original position and the
constraints placed on their choice by the formal constraints of the right and
the veil of ignorance, Rawls turns to the issue of the rationality of the parties.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 9
If the parties do not know what their conception of the good is, how are they
to decide which principles to choose? Rawls claims that the parties have
some rational plan of life, they just do not know what the details of this plan
are. In order to ensure that individuals have the opportunity to pursue their
conception of the good in the real world, once the veil is lifted, the parties in
the original position seek to secure the largest share they can of what Rawls
calls the social primary goods. These goods are rights and liberties, powers and
opportunities, income and wealth and self-respect.
Now of course Rawls is not suggesting that real people should live their
daily lives in accordance with the maximin principle. He argues that it is the
appropriate strategy to invoke in the special case of the original position. But
Harsanyi rejects even this claim. By evaluating institutional arrangements in
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 10
10
terms of the interests of the least advantaged Harsanyi argues that the
difference principle has some unacceptable moral implications.
Consider a society consisting of one doctor and two patients, both of them
critically ill with pneumonia. Their only chance to recover is to be treated
by an antibiotic, but the amount available suffices only to treat one of the
two patients. Of these two patients, individual A is a basically healthy
person, apart from his present attack of pneumonia. On the other hand,
individual B is a terminal cancer victim but, even so, the antibiotic could
prolong his life by several months. Which patient should be given the
antibiotic? According to the difference principle, it should be given to the
cancer victim, who is obviously the less fortunate of the two patients.
(Harsanyi, 1975: 596)
Harsaynis interpretation of what the difference principle requires is questionable. As we shall see, a lot depends on how one defines the least advantaged. Rawls does not adopt the position Harsayni implies in this example.
That is, that the least advantaged are those with the most serious illness. But
Harsaynis critique of the maximin principle has led many to question the
viability of Rawlss assumption that it is rational for the parties in the original position to adopt a conservative attitude.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 11
11
Formal equality of opportunity does not capture the intuitive appeal of the
ideal of equal opportunity. The elimination of arbitrary barriers (for example,
policies of racial or gender discrimination) to advancement is a necessary
but not sufficient measure for securing equal opportunity for all. The system
of natural liberty permits morally arbitrary factors to greatly influence ones
distributive share. Brian Barry (1989) refers to these factors as the result of
three lotteries:
There is the natural lottery, which distributes genetic endowments; there is
the social lottery, which distributes more or less favorable home and school
environments; and there is what Hobbes called the secret working of God,
which men call Good Luck the lottery that distributes illnesses, accidents,
and the chance of being in the right place at the right time. (Barry, 1989: 226)
These three lotteries greatly influence ones life prospects. Those who fare
well in these lotteries will have a much greater chance of succeeding in a
system of natural liberty. But those who fare poorly in, for example, the
natural and social lotteries of life, will not stand nearly as good a chance of
succeeding. This is unfair: people do not deserve the genetic endowments
they are born with nor the social position they are born into. Justice requires
us to mitigate the influence of these morally arbitrary factors. We can do so
through the basic structure of our society. But the system of natural liberty
fails to do this. It is thus an inadequate interpretation of equal opportunity.
A second, more viable interpretation of equal opportunity is what Rawls
calls liberal equality. Like formal equality of opportunity it maintains that arbitrary barriers to advancement must be eliminated. But it goes further than
invoking the slogan careers open to talents by adding the further condition
of the principle of fair equality of opportunity. Fair equality of opportunity
seeks to eliminate, or at least minimize as much as possible, the influence
social contingencies (such as social class) have on peoples opportunities.
More specifically, assuming that there is a distribution of natural assets,
those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have the same willingness to use them, should have the same prospects of success regardless
of their initial place in the social system. In all sectors of society there should
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
12
Page 12
In order to ensure that the influence of the social lottery is mitigated our
institutions have to preserve the social conditions for fair equality of opportunity. The system of natural liberty, with its free market economy, failed to
do this. Liberal equality requires that excessive accumulations of property
and wealth be prevented and that equal opportunities of education for all be
maintained. Educational barriers such as parents inability to pay for their
childs education should be eliminated.
Liberal equality is more appealing than the system of natural liberty. It
does a better of job of cohering to the intuitions that underlie our commitment to the ideal of equal opportunity. But, argues Rawls, it still does not go
far enough. While it is fair that persons with identical talents should have
similar life prospects, what about persons who have less talents? The natural
lottery of life is just as morally arbitrary as the social lottery of life. If justice
requires our institutions to mitigate the influence of factors such as social
class then it should also mitigate factors such as our natural endowments.
The abilities and talents we have are influenced by morally arbitrary factors
such as our genetic endowment. Social factors and class attitudes also influence the extent to which our natural capacities develop and these cannot be
mitigated by the principle of fair equality of opportunity. The principle of
fair equality of opportunity can be only imperfectly carried out, claims
Rawls, at least as long as some form of the family exists. Rawls claims:
Even the willingness to make an effort, to try, and so to be deserving in the
ordinary sense is itself dependent upon happy family and social circumstances. It is impossible in practice to secure equal chances of achievement
and culture for those similarly endowed, and therefore we may want to
adopt a principle which recognizes this fact and also mitigates the arbitrary
effects of the natural lottery itself. That the liberal conception fails to do this
encourages one to look for another interpretation of the two principles of
justice. (Rawls, 1999: 64)
The systems of natural liberty and liberal equality are inadequate interpretations of equal opportunity because they do not go far enough in requiring society to mitigate the influences of the social and natural lotteries of life.
Rawls puts forward a third and final interpretation which he feels succeeds
in achieving this. This third interpretation is democratic equality. It is arrived
at by combining the principle of fair equality of opportunity with the difference principle (Rawls, 1999: 65). Rawlss analysis of equal opportunity
has, so far, pushed us in the direction of objecting to any inequalities in social
primary goods because such inequalities will reflect morally arbitrary
factors. Formal equality of opportunity and liberal equality fail to provide us
with compelling reasons why all citizens, especially the least advantaged,
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 13
13
Efficiency
In order to understand how a move away from equality to inequality can
satisfy the requirements of the difference principle one must consider the
issue of efficiency. This aspect of Rawlss theory gets rather technical and I do
not intend to consider all of these issues in detail. By making justice the first
virtue of institutions Rawls seeks to ensure that other virtues, such as efficiency, do not trump considerations of fairness. But that does not mean Rawls
wants to rule out all concerns relating to efficiency. It is important for a
theory of distributive justice to consider this issue and Rawls attempts to do
this by opting for the difference principle instead of strict equality of goods.
The importance of efficiency can be illustrated with the following example.
Imagine that there are 100 units of goods that are to be distributed between
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 14
14
Bob and Mary. There are many possible efficient distributions of these goods.
The following distributive outcomes are all efficient ones:
Bob:
0 units
Bob: 100 units
Bob: 99 units
Bob: 50 units
Each of these distributive outcomes are Pareto optimal. That is, the outcome
is such that it is not possible to move away from it in a way that makes one
party better off without making another worse off. The fact that a distributive outcome is efficient does not guarantee that it is fair. For example, if
we give Bob all 100 units and give Mary nothing we have an efficient distribution but an unfair one. Our egalitarian intuitions tell us that the closer the
distribution comes to an equal one the better. But there are many possible
equal distributions that are not efficient. Consider the following equal but
inefficient distributive outcomes:
Bob:
Bob:
Bob:
Bob:
2
10
25
49
units
units
units
units
Mary:
Mary:
Mary:
Mary:
2
10
25
49
units
units
units
units
Each of these distributive outcomes are inefficient, that is, they are not
Pareto optimal. In each case we could give extra goods to someone without
reducing the amount of goods of the other person. This is so because we
have a total of 100 units to distribute. Any distributive arrangement that
does not total 100 units will be inefficient. A theory of justice should be
guided not only by concerns of fairness and equality, but also by concerns of
efficiency.
The real world does not have a fixed stock of commodities and thus we
should not approach the issue of justice as if it were as simple as the twoperson example noted above. The amount of goods to be distributed will be
influenced by a number of factors. One important factor is that of incentives.
The rewards we offer people, especially the most talented, will influence the
level of our societys prosperity. This point can be illustrated by returning to
the example of Bob and Mary. Instead of beginning with a fixed number of
commodities let us assume that the amount of goods to be distributed will
be determined by how well Bob and Mary can produce. Let us assume that
if we tell Bob and Mary that they will get an equal share of whatever they
produce then the total amount of goods they produce is 100 units. They thus
each get 50 units. But suppose that it turns out that Mary is very talented and
that she could produce a lot more if given the right incentives. For example,
if we allot her 175 units her extra effort will raise the total amount of goods
from 100 units to 300 units. This means that Bob can actually increase his initial 50 units of goods to 125 units if he permits the inequality-generating
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 15
15
incentives that Mary requires in order to be more productive. This is the kind
of scenario the difference principle envisions when it claims that inequalities
are to be arranged so that they are to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged. This argument has been referred to as the Pareto argument for inequality.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 16
16
rich and poor but if such a tax cut benefits the worst off then it is consistent
with Rawlsian justice.
Cohen rejects the conclusion that such tax cuts, even if they benefit the
worst off, should be labelled just. He asks us to consider why the talented
require the extra income the tax cut will give them before they will be more
productive. Once we do this we see that the motives of such individuals are
themselves unjust. Cohen distinguishes between incentives that are physically and/or psychologically necessary and those that are necessary only in
an intention-relative sense. That is, incentives the talented choose not to work
as productively without. While Cohen does not deny that there are genuine
cases where incentives might be physically and/or psychologically necessary
in order for people to perform certain tasks, these are not the kinds of
incentives that high earners are appealing to when they demand their
income tax be reduced from 60 to 40 per cent. It is the second category of
incentives, those the talented choose not to work as productively without,
that are at play in this instance and it is this category of incentives that Cohen
wants to claim is morally suspect.
Within the category of incentives that are necessary only in an intentionrelative sense further distinctions can be made. Cohen distinguishes between
cases where people are motivated by self-interest to some reasonable extent
and those where people are simply being selfish. Cohen does not wish to
rule out a modest right of self-interest, but such a right could not justify the
extremes of wealth and poverty that actually obtain in real capitalist societies. One major reason such extremes of wealth and poverty exist is that
policies like Thatchers tax cut appease the selfish choices of higher earners.
The attitudes of such individuals, Cohen claims, are unjust. If these individuals truly cared about the least advantaged they would not need special
incentives before they would be more productive. These individuals are not
committed to the spirit of the difference principle. But this, for Rawls, is perfectly just. It is only institutions that must fulfil the requirements of the difference principle. As such, Cohen claims that Rawlss conception of justice is
too narrow. The principles of justice must apply to both the legally coercive
structure and the choices that people make within that structure.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 17
17
best benefit society. But isnt this thick ethos simply too demanding? Does
justice require us to be saints?
Consider the case of Thatchers tax cut in 1988. If such a tax cut actually
benefited everyone, including the least advantaged, do you think such a tax
cut should be called just? Reflect on your own attitudes toward taxation. Do
you think you pay too much tax or not enough tax?
David Estlund (1998) argues that there are a number of distinct reasonable
motives which can cause inequality. For example, the pursuit of the interests
of ones family, loved ones and friends. The talented may require extra pay
so they can send their children to college, or can afford in-home care for an
ageing parent. Which prerogatives do you think should be permitted and why?
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
18
Page 18
All of the obligations that apply to persons, claims Rawls, can be derived
from the principle of fairness. The principle of fairness imposes on us an
obligation to do ones fair share in a system we benefit from. Free-riders are
the obvious example of people who fail to fulfil this obligation. By accepting
the benefits of cooperation but failing to fulfil the burdens of cooperation,
free-riders lack a sense of fair play.
Rawls claims that the notion of obligations, as distinct from natural duties,
helps us with the case of political officers. Members of political office, for
example, must fulfil a number of moral requirements beyond those expected
of the average citizen. Judges, members of parliament, etc. have voluntarily
taken on their roles and thus are bound even more tightly to the scheme of
just institutions.
Natural duties differ from obligations in that they do not have the three
characteristics noted above. Natural duties apply to individuals without
regard to our voluntary acts. Their content is not, in general, defined by the
rules of these arrangements. And natural duties hold between all as equal
moral persons, irrespective of their institutional relationships. Natural
duties include both positive and negative duties. The former include the
duty to uphold justice, the duty of mutual aid, and the duty of mutual
respect. The negative duties include the duty not to injure and the duty not
to harm the innocent. These are, claims Rawls, the principles (for individuals) that would be chosen in the original position.
The duty to uphold justice has two parts. First, we are to support and to
comply with just institutions that exist and apply to us. And second, we are
to assist in the establishment of just arrangements when they do not exist, at
least when this can be done with little cost to ourselves. The duty of mutual
respect requires us to show a person the respect which is due to him as a
moral being, that is, as a being with a sense of justice and a conception of the
good (Rawls, 1999: 297). This mutual respect for others can be expressed in
different ways. For example, when we are willing to see the situation of
others from their point of view. Or when we are prepared to give reasons for
our actions whenever the interests of others are materially affected. The parties in the original position would choose this duty because it is essential for
the most important primary good self-respect.
Now the reason why this duty would be acknowledged is that although the
parties in the original position take no interest in each others interests, they
know that in society they need to be assured by the esteem of their associates. Their self-respect and their confidence in the value of their own system
of ends cannot withstand the indifference much less the contempt of others.
Everyone benefits then from living in a society where the duty of mutual
respect is honored. The cost to self-interest is minor in comparison with the
support for the sense of ones own worth. (Rawls, 1999: 297)
The duty of mutual aid imposes on citizens a duty of helping another when
he is in need or jeopardy, provided that one can do so without excessive risk or
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 19
19
loss to oneself (Rawls, 1999: 98). There are many distinct arguments for including this duty in an account of justice. Kant, for example, argues that the ground
for proposing this duty is that situations may arise in which we will need the
help of others.6 But this is not, for Rawls, the most important reason for adopting the duty of mutual aid. The most important reason for adopting this duty
is its pervasive effect on the quality of everyday life.7
Civil disobedience
After outlining the distinct duties of justice as fairness Rawls considers the
case of civil disobedience. There are times when a conflict of duty arises. On
the one hand we have a duty to comply with laws enacted by a legislative
majority. On the other hand we have a right to defend our liberty and a duty
to oppose injustice. What do we do when these two duties conflict? A theory
of justice, argues Rawls, needs a theory of civil disobedience which provides
some guidance for cases when the distinct duties of justice conflict. Let us
consider and assess Rawlss account of civil disobedience.
Rawls sheds light on the content of the principles of natural duty and
obligation by sketching a theory of civil disobedience. He considers the conflict of duties that can arise in what he calls a nearly just society. Rawls does
not provide an exact definition of what qualifies as a nearly just society.
What we are told is that such a society will be democratic and one that is
well-ordered for the most part but in which some serious violations of
justice nevertheless do occur (Rawls, 1999: 319). In such a society the duty
to comply with laws/policies enacted by a legislative majority can conflict
with the right to defend ones liberties and the duty to oppose injustice.
When such a conflict arises which duty should prevail? Rawls outlines a theory
of civil disobedience in an attempt to shed some light on this question.
At first one may be surprised by the suggestion that a theory of justice
should even consider the question of when the duty to comply with majority rule should be overridden. Does justice not require an unconditional commitment to majority rule? The answer to this question, at least for Rawls, is
No. Suppose the majority passes an unjust law that violates the basic rights
and freedoms of minority members of our society. Would we be morally
bound to such an unjust law simply because the majority enacted it? Would
we not have a moral obligation to oppose such an unjust law? Many of the
most important progressive movements in human history challenged the
legitimacy of laws enacted by the majority. The civil rights movement, for
example, was instrumental in dismantling segregation laws. The weight we
place on the value of democracy must be balanced against other fundamental
values, such as freedom and equality.
The just society is, for Rawls, a constitutional democracy. The constitution
ensures that the requirements of the first principle of justice are taken off the
political agenda. The judicial branch of government serves as a check
on majority rule to ensure that citizens basic rights and freedoms are not
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
20
Page 20
violated. But a just and stable society will not be secured by placing this
responsibility solely on judges. Citizens also have a responsibility to ensure
that a legislative majority does not infringe on the demands of justice and a
theory of civil disobedience outlines what is required of us as citizens when
the duties of justice conflict.
Rawls defines civil disobedience as a public, nonviolent, conscientious
yet political act contrary to law usually done with the aim of bringing about
a change in the law or policies of the government (Rawls, 1999: 320). By saying that civil disobedience is a public act Rawls means that it must be done
openly with fair notice. This rules out acts that are secretive or covert. Rawls
compares civil disobedience to public speech. By acting in this way one
addresses the sense of justice of the majority of the community and declares
that in ones considered opinion the principles of social cooperation among
free and equal men are not being respected (Rawls, 1999: 320). As a form of
expression acts of civil disobedience must be non-violent. Any interference
with the civil liberties of others tends to obscure the civilly disobedient quality
of ones act (Rawls, 1999: 321). The nonviolent nature of the act, coupled
with the public nature of the act and the willingness to accept the legal
consequences of ones conduct, expresses ones fidelity to the law.
What makes an act of civil disobedience political is not simply the fact that
it is addressed to the majority that holds political power, but that it is guided
and justified by political principles. The justification for the act in question
must not appeal to principles of personal morality or to religious doctrines.
Instead such acts must appeal to the commonly shared conception of justice
that underlies the political order. When, for example, civil rights activists
challenged the legitimacy of segregation laws they appealed to a common
sense of justice when justifying their actions. Martin Lurther King, Jr often
appealed to Brown v. Board of Education (1954) in which the Supreme Court
of America ruled that segregation was unconstitutional. Such an appeal is a
clear example of how a common sense of justice can be invoked to justify
ones actions.
In order for acts of civil disobedience to be justified, argues Rawls, three
conditions must be met. The first condition concerns the kinds of wrongs
that are appropriate objects of civil disobedience. Rawls claims that these
wrongs must be instances of substantial and clear injustices. These include
serious infringements of the first principle of justice and blatant violations of
fair equality of opportunity. But Rawls discounts violations of the difference
principle because it is too difficult to ascertain to what degree it is violated.
Unless a tax law is clearly designed to attack a basic equal liberty, argues
Rawls, it should not normally be protested by civil disobedience.
The second condition that must be satisfied in order for acts of civil disobedience to be justified is that normal appeals to the political majority must
have already been made in good faith and have failed. Legal protests and
demonstrations, for example, must have been pursued and shown to be
ineffective. Civil disobedience is a last resort. Rawls argues that there may be
cases where this second condition need not be satisfied in order for civil
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 21
21
Rawls does not intend his discussion of civil disobedience to provide precise
principles that clearly decide actual cases but by considering some real
examples you can assess the strengths and weaknesses of his account. Many
activists engage in acts of civil disobedience to raise awareness about a number of causes ranging from animal liberation, gay rights and abortion to globalization and fuel tax.
Which of these, if any, would satisfy Rawlss three conditions for justified
civil disobedience?
Do you agree with Rawlss account of civil disobedience?
By saying all within the normal range Rawls assumes that everyone has
physical needs and psychological capacities within the normal range. Thus
questions of health care and mental capacity do not arise. Such an idealization allows Rawls to construct a theory of justice for the simpler case of a
society of normal, fully cooperating members. Rawlss reason for making
this assumption is not that such issues necessarily fall outside the scope of
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
22
Page 22
justice but that they should be dealt with at the legislative stage when the
prevalence and kinds of these misfortunes are known and the costs of treating them can be ascertained and balanced along with total government
expenditure (Rawls, 1993: 184). One may question the adequacy of Rawlss
bracketing of these issues. If Rawlss methodology is to appeal to our moral
intuitions concerning what justice demands then one may find this idealization clause unsatisfactory. Many would argue that the greatest demands of
justice come from those who are not normal, fully cooperating members of
society and thus Rawlss project is too narrowly conceived.8
Rawls does not attempt to provide a concise, definitive definition of who
qualifies as the least advantaged in a society of full and active participants.
He notes that it seems impossible to avoid a certain arbitrariness in actually
identifying the least favored group (Rawls, 1999: 84). But he does provide
two possible definitions. Firstly, we may define the least advantaged as all
those with approximately the income and wealth of the unskilled worker, or
less. Alternatively, we could define the least advantaged as all persons with
less than half of the median income and wealth.
Several critics of Rawlss theory have criticized his theory for permitting
individuals who, through their own choices, qualify as members of the least
advantaged and are thus entitled to the benefits demanded by the difference
principle. In Primary Goods Reconsidered Richard Arneson (1990) raises
this objection against Rawls. Membership in the least advantaged class
appears to be settled in terms of primary goods that individuals enjoy over
the course of their lives and this, argues Arneson, has counterintuitive
consequences. He illustrates this with the example of the life choices of four
individuals Smith, Black, Jones and Johnson. Smith and Black both graduate from an elite law school with high grades and can choose among several
career options. Black chooses to be a Wall Street lawyer, the work is stressful
but the income is high. Smith opts for the life of a bohemian artist, the
income is meagre but the work is like play. Jones and Johnson did not go to
college and both graduated from formal schooling with very little in terms
of marketable skills. Jones chooses to be a bohemian artist and Johnson an
unskilled labourer.
According to Rawlss definition of the least advantaged, Smith is one of
the least advantaged. That is, his income falls below both the median income
and that which the unskilled worker would get. The difference principle
requires us to maximize the prospects of the least advantaged and both
Smith and Johnson are members of this group. But our moral intuitions tell
us that these two individuals should not be treated the same. Smith had lots
of opportunities. With his law degree he could have chosen a variety of jobs
that would have secured him a high income. But he chose to be a bohemian
artist and the low level of subsistence that comes with it. This contrasts with
Johnson. Due to his low level of marketable skills he never had a choice
between high income and low income jobs. In addition to this, he chose to
work for a living doing hard labour rather than live the life of a bohemian
artist. Johnson is one of the deserving poor, argues Arneson, while Smith is
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 23
23
not. Smith is poor by choice and thus should not receive the same benefits
that Johnson receives. Justice does not require us to compensate individuals
for inequalities they have voluntarily chosen.
In his later writings, Rawls proposes adding leisure to the index of primary goods in order to meet the type of concern raised by Arneson.9 By
including leisure in the index of primary goods Rawls argues that those who
choose not to work will have extra leisure stipulated as equal to the index of
the least advantaged. This means that such individuals would not be entitled
to public funds. This suggestion raises some tricky conceptual difficulties for
Rawls.10 Firstly, we must ask what counts as work. Is work to be equated
with paid employment? Or does it include unpaid work, like domestic
work? Secondly, how should hours of work be made comparable? Is one
hour of intensive, productive work equivalent to one hour of easy, inefficient
work? If Rawlss proposal to include leisure in the index of primary goods is
to be taken seriously then some of these tricky conceptual issues must be
resolved. But even if such issues can be resolved, one would still have to
assess how effectively it deflects the objection Arneson raises. That is, does it
resolve the dilemma presented by the SmithBlackJonesJohnson example?
Arneson thinks it does not and thus he argues that distributive justice
should be concerned with the inequalities in the opportunity sets that individuals face, rather than what use presumably rational individuals make of
their opportunities (Arneson, 1990: 444).
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
24
Page 24
their members basic needs. Such a fact must figure into the reasoning of
parties in an international original position. Like parties in the domestic
original position who seek to mitigate the morally arbitrary distribution of
natural talents, parties in an international original position would seek to
mitigate the influence of the arbitrary distribution of natural resources over
the world. Therefore, the parties would think that resources (or the benefits
derived from them) should be subject to redistribution under a resource
distribution principle (Beitz, 1979: 138). Beitz does not explain how the
countries rich in natural resources are to redistribute them to the poor countries but the main aim of this first argument is to establish that we do have
moral ties to those with whom we do not share membership in a cooperative
scheme.
Beitzs second argument considers the more realistic scenario where the
world is one characterized by economic interdependence between countries.
When there exists a flow of trade and services between countries, argues
Beitz, there exists a global system of cooperation. If social cooperation is the
foundation of distributive justice, then one might think that international
economic interdependence lends support to a principle of global justice
similar to that which applies within the domestic society (Beitz, 1979: 144).
Beitz advances this line of reasoning arguing that international interdependence involves a complex and substantial pattern of social interaction.
Thus, for example, international property rights assign exclusive ownership
and control of a territory and its natural resources to the recognized government of the society established on it, or reserve partial or total control of
common areas (seas and outer space) to the international community. Also,
laws and conventions established or codified by treaty, and thus guaranteed
by the pacta sunt servanada rule of customary international law, protect private foreign investment against expropriation without compensation.
Perhaps most important of all is the rule of nonintervention, which, when
observed, has clear and sweeping effects on the welfare of people everwhere. (Beitz, 1979: 149)
These arrangements produce benefits and burdens that would not exist if
countries were self-sufficient. They contribute to the wealth or poverty of a
country and must be regulated by principles of global justice. National
boundaries do not, argues Beitz, mark the limit of social obligations.
Confining principles of social justice to domestic societies has the effect of
taxing poor nations so that others may benefit from living in just societies
(Beitz, 1979: 150). By seeking to maximize the prospects of the least advantaged in their own society wealthy countries may deny providing aid to
needy peoples in poor countries. Such a scenario is perverse, argues Beitz.
The principles of domestic justice are only genuine principles of justice if
they are consistent with principles of global justice. A fair distribution of the
benefits and burdens of global cooperation requires satisfying a global
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 25
25
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 26
26
Further reading
Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1979).
Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
1 (3), 1972: 22943.
Thomas Pogge, An Egalitarian Law of Peoples, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
23 (3), 1994: 195224.
David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 27
27
The aims of the theory outlined in Political Liberalism are very different,
claims Rawls. The question he is primarily concerned with in this second book
is this: How is it possible for those affirming a religious doctrine that is based
on religious authority, for example, the Church or the Bible, also to hold a
reasonable political conception that supports a just democratic regime? Rawlss
shift to a political conception of justice has divided supporters of his original
work. Some remain faithful to his original project, others see his shift as an
important improvement on the original formulation of the theory and others
think that Rawlss shift does not really represent a substantial change to the
original theory. The main issue which motivated Rawls to modify his theory
was that of stability. A just democratic society must be stable. It must be able to
exist over time and to secure the support of citizens who remain profoundly
divided by reasonable religious, philosophical and moral doctrines. In order for
this to be the case citizens must endorse the political arrangement for the right
reasons. Rawls claims that the theory presented in A Theory of Justice violated
this requirement. It required citizens to hold the same comprehensive doctrines
and this included aspects of Kants comprehensive liberalism.
Before considering some of the details of Rawlss revised formulation of
justice as fairness, it is important that we consider closely the question of
what the justification of his two principles of justice is, as presented in A
Theory of Justice. This will help us to understand the different receptions
Rawlss later work has received. If we ask why citizens should accept the
two principles of justice as the standard for a just basic structure the following three answers can be found in A Theory of Justice:
1 We should accept the two principles of justice because they do a better job
of matching our considered judgements about what is just and unjust
than utilitarianism does.
2 We should accept the two principles of justice because they are the result
of a fair choice. And as such, they can be justified to everyone.
3 We should accept the two principles of justice because acting from the
principles of right and justice as having first priority expresses our freedom from contingency and happenstance.
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
28
Page 28
Allen Buchanan labels these three justifications the principles matching justification,
the conditions matching argument and the Kantian interpretation, respectively.14 The
first two justifications are based on appeals to considered moral judgements
and the third on distinctively Kantian grounds. It is Rawlss invocation of this
third justification that motivates Rawls to revise his original theory. This
reason stipulates that our nature as a free and equal rational being can be fulfilled only by acting on the principles of right and justice as having first priority. It is acting from this precedence that expresses our freedom from
contingency and happenstance (Rawls, 1999: 503). Rawls now claims that
such a reason will not secure stability. Citizens who affirm other reasonable
moral, religious or philosophical doctrines will not be moved by an appeal to
Kantian metaphysics. What is needed, argues Rawls, is a political conception of
justice. A conception that does not criticize any particular theory of the truth
of moral judgements. A political conception adopts a restrained posture
towards such questions and is thus presented as a free-standing view.
Critics of Rawlss revision have taken issue with the way Rawls has characterized his earlier view. Barry, for example, makes reference to Rawlss
comment that while [a political] conception [of justice] is, of course, a moral
conception, it is a moral conception worked out for a specific kind of subject,
namely for political, social and economic institutions (Rawls, 1993: 11). In
reply to this comment Barry argues: On this definition of the political, it is
hard to see why A Theory of Justice should not be said to contain a political
conception of justice. A Theory of Justice is a moral theory, inasmuch as justice
is an aspect of morality (Barry, 1995: 8778). Barrys comments do raise
questions about the adequacy of Rawlss characterization of his original
theory. Justice as fairness, as presented in A Theory of Justice, was designed to
apply to the basic structure of society. While Rawlss invocation of the reason
from the Kantian interpretation does raise problems for his theory, this justification was never central to A Theory of Justice. In the concluding paragraph
of A Theory of Justice, for example, Rawls asks why citizens should accept the
principles chosen in the original position.
[W]hy should we take any interest in [the original position], moral or otherwise? Recall the answer: the conditions embodied in the description of this
situation are ones that we do in fact accept. Or if we do not, then we can be
persuaded to do so by the philosophical considerations of the sort occasionally introduced. Each aspect of the original position can be given a supporting explanation. Thus what we are doing is to combine into one conception
the totality of conditions that we are ready upon due reflection to recognize
as reasonable in our conduct with regard to one another. (Rawls, 1999: 514)
This passage is telling, for Rawls does not try to justify his theory by
appealing to Kantian metaphysics. What he appeals to are the moral considerations embodied in the original position. These are considerations he
believes diverse reasonable persons also accept (for example, impartiality
and fairness).
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 29
29
An overlapping consensus
In Political Liberalism Rawls introduces some new vocabulary. He now talks
about reasonable persons, public reason, the rational and the reasonable
and the burdens of judgement. The extent to which these terms represent a
substantial change to Rawlss theory as opposed to simply clarifying aspects
of his original theory is debatable. One idea that has become more central to
Rawlss revised theory is the idea of an overlapping consensus. Rawls claims
that a political conception of justice is the object of an overlapping consensus of reasonable comprehensive doctrines. He describes a political conception as a module, an essential constituent part, that fits into and can be
supported by various reasonable comprehensive doctrines that endure in
the society regulated by it (Rawls, 1993: 12).
Barry argues that Rawlss emphasis on an overlapping consensus threatens to undermine Rawlss two principles of justice, especially the difference
principle. Barry claims:
No doubt Christianity can be given an egalitarian slant. (We may think of
levelling Protestant sects and the preferential option for the poor of
Liberation Theology.) But mainstream Christian denominations have
always tolerated socioeconomic inequalities (including, in the past, slavery)
vastly in excess of anything that could be justified by Rawlss difference
principle. Islam and Judaism embrace a similar spread of views, while
Hindu and Confucian systems are inegalitarian to the core in a way that no
monotheistic religion can be. It is therefore almost inconceivable that
Rawlss second principle of justice could be presented as an inescapable
implication of all the major religions. (Barry, 1995: 911)
The fact that most societies fall well short of meeting the requirements of
the two principles of justice, especially the difference principle, suggests that
Barry is right and that Rawls is being unrealistic if he assumes that existing
comprehensive doctrines would endorse the main tenets of justice as fairness. Rawls claims that justice as fairness elaborates a political conception as
a free-standing view working from the fundamental idea of society as a fair
system of cooperation and its companion ideas (Rawls, 2001: 189). But to
what extent are the ideas Rawls invokes truly embedded in the public democratic culture of contemporary societies? There is a tension between the
descriptive and normative claims of justice as fairness. One the one hand
Rawls invokes ideals he believes diverse, decent people care about. Ideals
such as equality and impartiality. But on the other hand Rawls recognizes
that these ideals do not always guide everyday politics. Justice as fairness
inspires a public philosophy that is, as Rawls puts it, realistically utopian. This
phrase effectively captures the fundamental tension in Rawlss project. The
tension between articulating a theory that is realistic in the sense that it
appeals to the moral sensibilities of real people, here and now, and yet one
that inspires us to transcend the status quo and move closer to a more decent
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
30
Page 30
political order. As we shall see in the next chapter, other political theorists
appeal to our moral sensibilities but they come to very different conclusions
concerning how our institutions are to be arranged. The ideas of society as a
fair system of cooperation and citizens as free and equal persons could be
invoked to justify a radically different type of political regime. To see how
this is so we shall consider the libertarian argument advanced by Robert
Nozick in Anarchy, State and Utopia.
SUMMARY
In constructing his account of justice Rawls appeals to general and widely shared
moral convictions. The original position represents a fair choice situation that
incorporates and clarifies many of these convictions. In this hypothetical situation
the parties would choose the two principles of justice, argues Rawls, as the principles to govern the basic structure of society.
Critics have questioned many different aspects of Rawlss theory. For example,
the role economic incentives play in his so-called egalitarian theory, whom he
defines as the least advantaged and why distributive principles only apply at the
domestic level.
Since the publication of A Theory of Justice Rawls has modified certain aspects of
justice as fairness. He now presents the theory as a political conception of
justice that could be the focus of an overlapping consensus.
Notes
1 All references to A Theory of Justice are to the revised edition (1999).
2 Rawls distinguishes between two variants of perfectionism. The first version
maintains that society should arrange institutions and define duties and obligations so as to maximize the achievement of human excellence in art, science and
culture. The second, more moderate version, is one in which the principle of perfection is accepted as one among several in an intuitionist theory. For a detailed
discussion of these positions see A Theory of Justice, pp. 28592.
3 See A Theory of Justice, pp. 11218 for full details.
4 See A Theory of Justice, pp. 10912.
5 See Cohen (1992, 1995b, 1997 and 2000).
6 See Kants Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1998).
7 Rawls claims:
The public knowledge that we are living in a society in which we can depend upon others
to come to our assistance in difficult circumstances is itself of great value. It makes little
difference that we never, as things turn out, need this assistance and that occasionally we
are called on to give it . . . The primary value of the principle is not measured by the help we
actually receive but rather by the sense of confidence and trust in other mens good intentions and the knowledge that they are there if we need them. Indeed, it is only necessary to
imagine what a society would be like if it were publicly known that his duty was rejected.
(Rawls, 1999: 298)
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 31
31
8 Some have tried to remedy this deficiency by extending Rawlss theory of justice
to the issue of just health care. See, for example, Norman Danielss Just Health
Care (1985).
9 See Political Liberalism (1993), pp. 1812.
10 Here I draw from Phillipe Van Parijss argument in Real Freedom for All (1995),
pp. 978.
11 See, for example, Rawlss The Law of Peoples (1999), Beitzs Political Theory and
International Relations (1979) and Thomas Pogges An Egalitarian Law of
Peoples (1994).
12 See The Law of Peoples, pp. 11518.
13 A doctrine is comprehensive when it includes conceptions of what is of value in
human life, and ideals of personal character, as well as ideals of friendship and
of familial and associational relationships, and much else that is to inform our
conduct, and in the limit to our life as a whole. A conception is fully comprehensive if it covers all recognized values and virtues within one rather precisely
articulated system. (Rawls, 1993: 13)
14 See Buchanan Marx and Justice (1982).
Farrelly Ch-01.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 32
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 33
Summary Contents
2.1
2.2
2.3
2.4
2.5
2.6
Introduction
The state: is it necessary?
Wilt Chamberlain and the entitlement theory
The principle of initial acquisition
The principle of rectification
Conclusion: self-ownership and private property
33
35
39
41
46
49
2.1 Introduction
The just society, according to Rawls, is one that protects citizens basic
liberties and arranges socio-economic inequalities so that they are to the
greatest benefit of the least advantaged and attached to offices and positions
open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity. This contrasts
with the conception of justice defended by Robert Nozick. Justice, for
Nozick, actually rules out the kind of redistribution that Rawls envisions. In
Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974) Nozick defends the minimal state. The state
should be limited to the narrow functions of protection against force, theft,
fraud, enforcement of contracts and so on (Nozick, 1974: xi). Any state that
extends its functions beyond this narrow range of functions is unjust. So, for
example, the requirements of Rawlss fair equality of opportunity principle
and the difference principle would be ruled out. Such an extensive state,
argues Nozick, violates peoples rights.
In this chapter we shall consider Nozicks argument for the minimal state.
I have included Nozick in this first part of the book, which examines contemporary liberal theory, but it is perhaps more accurate to refer to Nozick
as a libertarian rather than as a liberal. There are certain affinities between
these two doctrines but libertarians hold that a minimal state is the only
justified state.1 Unlike Rawlss attempt to combine considerations of liberty
with those of equality, (right-wing) libertarians are concerned only with the
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
34
Page 34
former. Liberty and equality are, argues Nozick, incompatible. If one is truly
committed to the value of freedom then any attempt to enforce, through the
coercive apparatus of the state, a particular distributive arrangement, be it egalitarian or otherwise, will violate the freedom of individuals and thus be unjust.
Nozicks appeal to the primacy of the value of freedom is a sophisticated one
and we shall examine and assess the main components of his argument.
Central to Nozicks argument is an appeal to moral side constraints. Side
constraints upon action reflect the underlying Kantian principle that individuals are ends and not merely means, they may not be sacrificed or used
for the achieving of other ends without their consent (Nozick, 1974: 301).
Individuals are, argues Nozick, inviolable. Recall that this line of argument
was also central to Rawlss rejection of utilitarianism. By defining the right
as that which maximizes the good utilitarianism fails to take seriously the
distinction between persons. Maximizing utility might justify violating individual rights. But justice, argues Rawls, denies that the loss of freedom for
some is made right by a greater good shared by others. It would thus appear
that Rawls and Nozick share the same starting point. But this is not so. The
scope of individual freedom that Nozick appeals to is more expansive than
that of Rawls. The central issue that divides Rawls and Nozick is the stance
they take on property rights. While Rawls does include among the basic
liberties of the person the right to hold and have the exclusive use of personal
property, he does not include the wider conception of the right that extends
this right to include certain rights of acquisition and bequest, as well as the
right to own means of production and natural resources (Rawls, 1993: 298).
Nozicks libertarian argument is premised on absolute property rights: rights
of ownership over oneself and over things in the world (Wolff, 1991: 4). It is
thus obvious why, for Nozick, freedom and equality are incompatible. If
freedom includes absolute property rights then such freedom will be limited
by the egalitarian measures of, for example, Rawlss difference principle. The
important question is should we accept this wide conception of property
rights? Nozick believes that such a conception of property rights follows
from a commitment to the thesis which underlies our commitment to sideconstraints the thesis of self-ownership. This thesis states that each person is
the morally rightful owner of his own person and powers, and, consequently,
that each is free (morally speaking) to use those powers as he wishes, provided that he does not deploy them aggressively against others (Cohen,
1995a: 67).
The so-called eye lottery example is usually invoked to illustrate the intuitive appeal of the thesis of self-ownership and how it captures our concern
for side constraints.
Suppose that transplant technology reaches such a pitch of perfection that it
becomes possible to transplant eyeballs with a one hundred per cent chance
of success. Anyones eyes may be transplanted into anyone else, without
complications. As some people are born with defective eyes, or with no eyes
at all, should we redistribute eyes? That is, should we take one eye from
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 35
35
some people with two healthy eyes, and give eyes to the blind? Of course,
some people may volunteer their eyes to transplant. But what if there were
not enough volunteers? Should we have a national lottery, and force the
losers to donate an eye? (Wolff, 1991: 78)
The eye lottery example represents a clear case where our commitment to
self-ownership trumps considerations of equality. If one is truly convinced
by the egalitarian aspiration of Rawlss project, a project that seeks to mitigate morally arbitrary factors, then one should support the policy of an eye
lottery, argues Nozick. Nozick claims that an application of the principle of
maximizing the position of those worst off might well involve forceable
redistribution of bodily parts (Nozick, 1974: 206). Those born with two
healthy eyes do not deserve their eyes. If we can mitigate the misfortune of
the natural lottery by adopting an eye lottery, would not such a policy be
just? The fact that we feel that such a policy is unjust is evidence of our
commitment to the thesis of self-ownership. And if we are to take this thesis
seriously, argues Nozick, we should also object to the redistributive policies
of Rawlsian justice. Such policies, like the eye lottery, violate the thesis of
self-ownership. The only institutional arrangement that respects persons as
self-owners is the minimal state.
Rawls would, of course, reject the suggestion that his egalitarian theory
would permit something as heinous as the eye lottery. The difference principle only applies to the social primary goods and not to body parts.
Furthermore, the first principle of justice protects the integrity of the person.
Like Nozick, Rawls would support the intuition that considerations of
liberty should trump those of equality in the case of the eye lottery. But
unlike Nozick, Rawls does not believe that the same can be said in the case
of taxation of earned income. Nozick argues that taxation of earnings from
labor is on a moral par with forced labor (Nozick, 1974: 169). This necessarily
follows, argues Nozick, from a commitment to self-ownership.2 Self-owners
should be free to use their powers as they wish, provided they do not deploy
them aggressively against others. The state violates self-ownership when it
forces people, be it through forced labour or taxation, to help the least
advantaged in society. Nozick is not saying that people should not voluntarily give to help the poor. What he objects to is compulsory redistribution. Such
a policy is incompatible with respecting persons as self-owners. Before
we critically assess Nozicks argument that the only legitimate state is the
minimal state, let us consider the argument he develops in Part One of
Anarchy, State and Utopia that the minimal state itself is morally justified.
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
36
Page 36
conditions for the existence of the state Nozick points out two necessary
conditions. Firstly, following Max Weber,3 Nozick argues that a state has a
monopoly over the use of force. Secondly, a state offers protection to anyone
who resides within its boundaries. Nozick refers to these as the monopoly
element and the redistributive element, respectively. These two features of the
state may appear incompatible with Nozicks commitment to individual
rights.
According to the natural rights tradition Nozick invokes, individuals have
a right to self-defence and to punish those who violate their rights. This
appears to conflict with the monopoly element of the state. The second
feature of a state is that it offers universal protection to everyone in the territory and this might require some redistribution as some may not be able to
afford the taxes required to fund universal protection. This redistributive
element also appears to conflict with self-ownership which requires noninterference with ones person or possessions unless one has consented to it
or one has violated the rights of another. The aim of the first part of Anarchy,
State and Utopia is to show that both the monopoly and redistributive elements
of the state are morally legitimate and do not violate individual rights.
Given Nozicks strong commitment to individual rights one may wonder
why he does not simply endorse anarchism. In order to decide which
arrangement would be more conducive to individual rights, the minimal
state or anarchy, of course depends on how one characterizes what life
would be like without the state. Hobbes, for example, presents a very
pessimistic picture of what life would be like in a state of nature. Life would
be nasty, brutish and short. If we begin with Hobbess portrayal of the state
of nature it would be pretty easy to justify the state. But Nozick does not try
to justify the state in this way. He seeks instead to persuade those who take
a more optimistic view of what life would be like in the state of nature, those
who believe that in the state of nature people would generally satisfy moral
constraints and act as they should. These are the individuals John Locke
describes in his account of the state of nature in Two Treatises of Government.
In a Lockean state of nature individuals are in a State of perfect Freedom to
order their Actions, and dispose of their Possessions, and Persons as they
think fit, within the bounds of the Law of Nature, without asking leave, or
dependency upon the Will of any other man (Locke, 1988: 269). The law of
nature requires that each person have rights to life, liberty and property, and
the right to enforce these rights.
But in such a state of nature problems will arise, even if people do act
morally and respect each others rights. The law of nature does not provide
for every contingency. Disputes will arise due to different interpretations of
the natural law. Resolving such disputes is made even more difficult by the
fact that people are biased in their own favour. Furthermore, individuals will
often lack the power to enforce their rights. Faced with these problems, individuals in the state of nature will engage in behaviour which will result in
the creation of the minimal state. These individuals will not consciously set
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 37
37
out to create a state but this will be the inevitable outcome of their attempts
to overcome the problems they face in the state of nature. Nozick calls this
his invisible hand explanation of the state. The move from the state of nature to
the minimal state involves the following stages of development:
1
2
3
4
5
Let us briefly consider each of these steps. In order to overcome the problems they face in the state of nature, individuals will band together to create
a mutual protection agency. All will answer the call of any member for
defense or for the enforcement of his rights (Nozick, 1974: 12). Such an
arrangement is mutually advantageous to all because there is strength in
numbers. If someone violates your rights you have a much better chance of
exacting compensation if you can rely on the assistance of your fellow
agency members.
Despite the obvious advantages of mutual protection agencies, they do come
with inconveniences. Firstly, everyone is always on call to serve a protective
function. This can be very time-consuming. Secondly, difficulties will arise if
two different members of the same association are in dispute. In order to overcome these inconveniences it is rational to set up commercial protective agencies. Such agencies could take care of a variety of functions ranging from
apprehending transgressors to determining guilt or innocence and carrying out
the appropriate punishment. Such an arrangement would allow individuals to
resolve the problems they face as members of a mutual protection agency.
But the creation of commercial protective agencies will also create some
problems, argues Nozick. Several different protective agencies will offer
their services in the same geographical area and this creates a problem when
a conflict occurs between clients of different agencies. If the agencies reach
different decisions concerning the guilt or innocence of the other client
things could get rather messy. It is not in the interests of either agency to do
battle over such disputes. What the competing agencies will find it in their
interests to do is join forces and create a dominant protection agency. Nozick
summarizes how things have developed this far as follows:
We thus have a situation where almost all persons in a geographical territory are under some common system that adjudicates between their disputes and enforces individuals rights. Out of anarchy, pressed by
spontaneous groupings, mutual-protection associations, division of labor,
market pressures, economies of scale, and rational self-interest there arises
something very much resembling a minimal state or a group of distinct
minimal states. (Nozick, 1974: 1617)
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
38
Page 38
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 39
39
Nozick takes the anarchist challenge seriously and his invisible hand explanation
of the state is an attempt to refute the anarchists claim that any state is
illegitimate.
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
40
Page 40
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 41
41
Third parties who did not voluntarily agree to D2 could claim that this new
distribution was unjust. Future generations, for example, will ask why the
society they live in is one where gross inequalities exist. Is the answer that
your grandparents wanted to see Wilt Chamberlain play basketball and thus
agreed to give up equality for the chance to see him play grounds for a claim
of injustice?
Even if D2 was the result of fully voluntary transactions does that necessarily make it just? What if the fans were insufficiently reflective and did not
think through the full consequences of what they were doing? Do you think
the fans would agree to the transactions if they knew that it would result in
creating an unequal society and all the disadvantages that come with that?
Further reading
G.A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995).
Eric Mack, Self-Ownership, Marxism and Egalitarianism: Part 1: Challenges to
Historical Entitlement, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 1 (1), 2002:
75108.
Eric Mack, Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism: Part II: Challenges to
the Self-ownership Thesis, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 1 (2), 2002:
23776.
Two conditions must be fulfilled in order for an action to count as nonvoluntary for Nozick. Firstly, our options must be restricted by other people.
Secondly, their constraining actions must themselves violate rights (Wolff,
1991: 84).
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
42
Page 42
Let us now consider the issue of what Nozicks entitlement theory says
about the initial acquisition of property. In order for current distributions to
be just they must have been brought about via just steps from a situation
which was itself just. If we push this argument back far enough it must be
the case that there was an initial just situation if current distributions are to
be deemed just by the entitlement theory. Nozick does not, as we shall soon
see, maintain that existing distributions actually fulfil this requirement,
hence the need for a principle of rectification. But he does maintain that, in
principle, it is possible for persons to justly appropriate unowned objects. In
order to develop this aspect of his entitlement theory he once again invokes
the social contract argument of John Locke.
In the Second Treatise Locke puts forward a sophisticated argument for
private appropriation. The argument runs like this (modified from
Christman, 1986: 160):
1 Every man has a property in his own person.
2 Therefore, every man has also a property right in the labor of his body
and the work of his hands.
So,
3 If he removes some object out its natural state by mixing his labor with it.
AND
4 There is enough and as good left in common for others.
AND
5 The object or objects do not exceed [a]s much as anyone can make use
of ... before it spoils.
Then,
6 A person has thereby fixed [a] property in them.
Nozick does not endorse this robust justification of initial acquisition but
instead focuses exclusively on one of the necessary conditions Locke invokes,
the enough and as good proviso. Nozicks strategy is to present a slightly
modified version of this necessary condition as a necessary and sufficient
condition for the appropriation of property. Let us first consider why Nozick
wants to modify the enough and as good proviso.
The proviso needs to be modified, argues Nozick, because it is susceptible
to the following regress argument.
[T]here appears to be an argument for the conclusion that if the proviso no
longer holds, then it cannot ever have held so as to yield permanent and
inheritable property rights. Consider the first person Z for whom there is
not enough and as good left to appropriate. The last person Y to appropriate left Z without his previous liberty to act on an object, and so worsened
Zs situation. So Ys appropriation is not allowed under Lockes proviso.
Therefore the next to last person X to appropriate left Y in a worse position,
for Xs act ended permissible appropriation. Therefore Xs appropriation
wasnt permissible. But then the appropriator two from last, W, ended
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 43
43
If the enough and as good proviso yields the conclusion that appropriating
a scarce resource like land is ruled out then it is obvious why Nozick wants
to modify it. Nozick wants to establish natural, unlimited, rights to property, even in the face of scarcity, and so it is imperative for him to reply to the
zipping back argument (Wolff, 1991: 1078). What Nozick does is distinguish between a stringent and weaker form of the enough and as good
proviso. The stronger form maintains that there must be enough and as
good left for people to appropriate, hence the problem raised by the regress
argument. But the weaker form maintains that there must be enough and as
good left for other people to use, although not necessarily enough left to
appropriate.
But even on this weaker form of the proviso it may appear that appropriating land can be ruled out when such a resource is scarce. So Nozick modifies this weaker form of the proviso to capture what he thinks is the intuitive
appeal of the proviso. Namely that it rules out appropriation when such
actions worsen the situation of others. If my appropriating a plot of unowned
land (object X) worsens your situation then I have violated Nozicks modified Lockean proviso. But the fact that my appropriation means that others
can no longer appropriate it or use it does not necessarily mean that I have
worsened their situation. Nozick believes that a system of private property
actually brings benefits to all.
Is the situation of persons who are unable to appropriate (there being no
more accessible and useful unowned objects) worsened by a system allowing appropriation and permanent property? Here enter the various familiar
social considerations favoring private property: it increases the social product by putting means of production in the hands of those who can use
them most efficiently (profitably); experimentation is encouraged, because
with separate persons controlling resources, there is no one person or small
group whom someone with a new idea must convince to try it out; private
property enables people to decide on the pattern and types of risks they
wish to bear, leading to specialized types of risk bearing; private property
protects future persons by leading some of them to hold back resources
from current consumption for future markets; it provides alternate sources
of employment for unpopular persons who dont have to convince any one
person or small group to hire them, and so on. (Nozick, 1974: 177)
Nozicks modified Lockean proviso requires us to weigh the new opportunities my appropriation of object X creates for others against the loss in
opportunities others incur. If, on balance, I have not worsened their situation
compared to how they were before my appropriation, that is, when object
X was in general use, then my appropriation of object X is legitimate.
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
44
Page 44
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 45
45
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
46
Page 46
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 47
47
be applied to remedy past injustices. Let us consider what Nozick does tell
us before we critically assess his account.
Nozick recognizes that the principle of rectification raises many complex
questions for his entitlement theory of justice:
If past injustice has shaped present holdings in various ways, some identifiable and some not, what now, if anything, ought to be done to rectify these
injustices? What obligations do the performers of injustice have toward
those whose position is worse than it would have been had the injustice not
been done? Or, that it would have been had compensation been paid
promptly? How, if at all, do things change if the beneficiaries and those
made worse off are not the direct parties in an act of injustice, but, for example,
their descendants? How far back must one go in wiping clean the historical
slate of injustices? What may victims of injustice permissibly do in order to
rectify the injustices being done to them, including the many injustices done
by persons acting through their government? (Nozick, 1974: 152)
Given the tough questions raised by the issue of rectification one can
perhaps understand why Nozick chooses to say very little about the issue.
But if his theory cannot adequately resolve these complicated issues then
that casts further doubt on the viability of his entitlement theory. Let us identify some of the distinct issues raised by the principle of rectification.
It is useful to begin by distinguishing between intragenerational rectification
and intergenerational rectification. The former refers to compensation for
victims who are alive to collect rectification awards while the latter encompasses all injustices and, in theory, ensures that the present distribution of entitlements be that which would have obtained had only the principles in
acquisition and justice in transfer been observed throughout history (Litan,
1977: 234). The issue of intergenerational rectification is by far the more difficult
issue and poses perhaps the biggest problem for Nozicks theory. Idealizing
greatly, Nozick describes how a principle of rectification could be produced.
This principle uses historical information about previous situations and
injustice done in them (as defined by the first two principles of justice and
rights against interference), and information about the actual course of
events that flowed from these injustices, until the present, and it yields a
description (or descriptions) of holdings in the society. The principle of
rectification presumably will make use of its best estimate of subjunctive
information about what would have occurred (or a probability distribution
over what might have occurred, using the expected value) if the injustice
had not taken place. If the actual description of holdings turns out not to be
one of the descriptions yielded by the principle, then one of the descriptions
yielded must be realized. (Nozick, 1974: 1523)
In this passage we see that an ideal application of the principle of rectification requires a number of different sorts of information. Firstly, we need
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
48
Page 48
information about past injustices. We need to know who the victims and
perpetrators of an unjust acquisition or transfer are and/or their descendants. Secondly, in order to determine what the appropriate compensation is
we need to know the distribution of holdings that would have obtained had
the injustice not taken place. Gregory Kavka (1982) calls the compensation
requirement of Nozicks rectification principle the No Net Harm Criterion.
This criterion maintains that victims of injustice are sufficiently compensated if they are no worse off (having received compensation) than they
would have been had the injustice not taken place.
There are a number of issues which complicate the implementation of the
rectification principle. Firstly, how far do we go back in time? One hundred
years, three hundred years, a thousand years? The further we go back the
less likely we are to have any information, let alone reliable information,
concerning the victims and perpetrators of injustice. Secondly, the task of
gathering the subjunctive information necessary to calculate the compensation due to a victim is extremely difficult if not impossible. How could we
determine what the life prospects of the current ancestors of, for example,
those once enslaved in America would be if slavery had never occurred?4 This
raises a third problem how do we define what counts as being worse off
in this respect? Are we concerned only with material welfare or with other
things? Suppose that the ancestors of aboriginal peoples in North American
that were treated unjustly by European settlers are not worse off materially,
but are in other ways, would they still have legitimate grounds for demanding rectification? Aboriginal peoples might argue that non-material aspects
of their lives are worse than they would have been if the injustices committed by European settlers had not happened. They would have had more of a
say over how the land was used and thus a better chance of preserving
important aspects of their cultural identity that they value. Finally, we have
a fourth problem of deciding who should pay to compensate victims of past
injustices. Should the descendants of slave-owners compensate the descendants of slaves for the injustices committed against slaves? Should nonaboriginals pay for the injustices committed against aboriginals? Should the
developed countries pay for the injustices committed against the developing
countries? All of these and other important questions must be addressed if
the principle of rectification is to be taken seriously.
Instead of tackling these complex issues Nozick suggests that the best way
to resolve the issue of rectification might be to adopt one of the patterned
principles of distributive justice which he earlier criticized.
Perhaps it is best to view some patterned principles of distributive justice as
rough rules of thumb meant to approximate the general results of applying
the principle of rectification of injustice. For example, lacking much historical
information, and assuming (1) that victims of injustice generally do worse
than they otherwise would and (2) that those from the least well-off group
in the society have the highest probabilities of being the (descendants of)
victims of the most serious injustice who are owed compensation by those
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 49
49
who benefited from the injustices (assumed to be those better off, though
sometimes the perpetrators will be others in the worst-off group), then a
rough rule of thumb for rectifying injustices might seem to be the following:
organize society so as to maximize the position of whatever group ends up
least well-off in society. (Nozick, 1974: 231)
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
50
Page 50
Both policies are unjust for they both violate the thesis of self-ownership. By
taxing the earnings of an individuals income (assuming such taxation
exceeded that needed to fund defence, the police and the administration of
justice) the state violates an individuals right to use his or her powers as
they wish. Wilt Chamberlain and the owners of his team are free to enter into
whatever contract they wish. This right is entailed by the right to selfownership. The same is true of the people with two healthy eyes. They have
exclusive ownership rights over their body and thus the state cannot force
individuals to give an eye to the blind without violating the demands of
self-ownership.
The fact that most people react differently to the issues of taxing the rich
and taking someones eye suggests that Nozick employs the thesis of selfownership in a way that glosses over a number of important issues. Namely,
the distinction between owning ones body and owning external objects. Let
us bring these more particular issues into focus by distinguishing between
the following, increasingly more stringent, interpretations of self-ownership:
S1: Self-owners are the morally rightful owners of their own body and powers.
S2: Self-owners are the morally rightful owners of their own body and
powers and have a right to have and hold their personal property.
S3: Self-owners are the morally rightful owners of their own body and
powers and thus are imbued with rights of acquisition and bequest over
not only their personal property but also over means of production and
natural resources (such as factories, land, etc.).
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
Page 51
51
clearly states in Anarchy, State and Utopia that he does not intend to give these
rights a foundation:
The completely accurate statement of the moral background, including the
precise statement of the moral theory and its underlying basis, would
require a full-scale presentation and is a task for another time. (A lifetime?)
That task is so crucial, the gap left without its accomplishment so yawning,
that it is only a minor comfort to note that we here are following the
respectable tradition of Locke, who does not provide anything remotely
resembling a satisfactory explanation of the status and basis of the law of
nature in his Second Treatise. (Nozick, 1974: 9)
Nozicks failure to provide a basis for the absolute property rights entailed
by his commitment to self-ownership has led some to describe his position
as libertarianism without foundations (Nagel, 1982). If there is no foundation for Nozicks theory then one can justifiably ask why they should accept
it. Why favour a theory that accords so much weight to private property,
especially when such a right will result in extensive socio-economic inequalities? Egalitarian liberals like Rawls endorse S2 because it takes seriously considerations of both liberty and equality. When Rawls claims that justice
denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good
shared by others he does not mean the freedom that is entailed in S3.
The concern for providing a clear and convincing foundation for a theory
of justice is the primary concern of the next liberal theorist we examine
David Gauthier. Unlike Rawls and Nozick, who appeal to our moral sensibilities of fairness, impartiality and the importance of side constraints,
Gauthier constructs a theory of justice that is founded on non-moral
premises. We consider his contractarian argument in the next chapter.
SUMMARY
Nozick defends the minimal state which limits the functions of the state to
protection against force, theft, fraud, enforcement of contracts and so on. Like
Rawls, Nozick believes that justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is
made right by a greater good shared by others. However, Nozick believes that the
redistributive policies of Rawlss second principle of justice violate this dictum.
At the heart of Nozicks libertarianism is the thesis of self-ownership. Respect for
persons as self-owners requires us to abandon the pie-cutting mentality of
justice theorists like Rawls and endorse instead the entitlement theory of justice.
The entitlement theory maintains that whatever arises from a just situation by just
steps is itself just. Nozick utilizes the Wilt Chamberlain example to illustrate the
point that liberty upsets patterns.
An important component of Nozicks entitlement theory of justice is the principle
of rectification. Given that human history is one rife with unjust acquisitions and
Farrelly Ch-02.qxd
11/5/03 2:31 PM
52
Page 52
transfers it is surprising that Nozick spends so little time on this part of his
theory. Nozick does propose temporarily implementing a redistributive principle
like Rawlss difference principle as a rough rule of thumb for rectifying injustices.
Notes
1 Libertarianism, like liberalism, is a varied political theory and there are many
distinct versions of libertarianism. For another version of right-wing libertarianism see Jan Narvesons The Libertarian Idea (1988) and for left-wing versions of
libertarianism see Hillel Steiners An Essay on Rights (1994) and Michael Otsukas
Libertarianism Without Inequality (2003).
2 The only exceptions to this are taxes that are necessary in order to defend rights
to person and property.
3 See Max Weber, Politics as a Vocation (1970).
4 One issue which threatens to unravel the plausibility and appeal of the rectification principle is what is called the existence problem. The rectification principle
requires us to consider how the ancestors of those who were treated unjustly
would have fared if the past injustices did not occur. But in many cases the current generation would never have been born if these past injustices did not occur.
For example, if African slaves were never brought to America then these individuals would have made very different life choices which would have resulted in
them having different children than they actually had. Thus the current generation cannot complain that they would have been better off without slavery as they
would not even exist! For a detailed discussion of this issue and the problems it
poses for Nozick see Kavka (1982).
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 53
Summary Contents
3.1
3.2
3.3
3.4
3.5
Introduction
Hobbes and the state of nature
Gauthier and the compliance problem
What is a rational bargain?
The limits of justice as mutual advantage
53
54
57
63
67
3.1 Introduction
In the first two chapters we examined two competing conceptions of justice
Rawlss theory of justice as fairness and Nozicks entitlement theory of
justice. Despite how radically different their theories are, Rawls and Nozick
both share some important common ground, namely the methodology they
invoke when constructing and defending their theories. Both theories appeal
to the moral sensibilities we have concerning what is just. By characterizing
his original position as the appropriate initial status quo Rawls appeals to
our moral sensibilities of fairness, equality and impartiality. Nozicks
entitlement theory of justice appeals to the weight we place on the thesis of
self-ownership and the importance of moral side constraints.
This approach to political theory is rejected by those who opt for what
Arthur Ripstein calls foundationalism.
Foundationalist political theories attempt to justify political institutions
without presupposing any political considerations. In a foundationalist
theory, some set of considerations is held to support a particular form of
political order, without itself depending on any substantive assumptions
about the legitimacy of particular forms of human interaction. Hence the
metaphor of a foundation, which holds up an edifice without itself being
supported by anything else. (Ripstein, 1987: 115)
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
54
Page 54
that it would be rational for people to agree to accept this arrangement. The
last two decades have witnessed renewed interest in Hobbess argument.1
While rejecting, for obvious reasons, Hobbess conclusion (that is, that an
absolute sovereign is justified), contemporary authors have been inspired by
the foundationalism of the Hobbesian project. This is most evident in the
contractarian theory of David Gauthier, whose theory will be the central
focus of this chapter. Like Rawls, Gauthier appeals to the idea of a social contract, as is evident in the title of his influential book Morals by Agreement. But
unlike Rawls, Gauthier rejects the idea that a theory of justice can be justified
by appealing to our moral intuitions. On the contrary, justice must be based
on non-moral premises. To base justice on moral premises is simply to assume
what one is trying to justify in the first place. The non-moral premises on
which Gauthier founds his moral theory are the premises of rational choice.
Gauthier argues that the rational principles for making choices, or decisions
among possible actions, include some that constrain the actor pursuing his
own interest in an impartial way. These we identify as moral principles
(Gauthier, 1986: 3).
We have already briefly encountered rational choice theory in Rawlss discussion of choice behind a veil of ignorance. The two principles of justice are,
claims Rawls, the rational choice because they guarantee the highest minimum pay-off. But Rawls has, in his later writings, downplayed the role he
places on rational choice theory. In his article Justice as Fairness: Political
Not Metaphysical Rawls argues that the reasonable is prior to the rational2
and he claims that it was an error to describe a theory of justice as part of the
theory of rational choice (Rawls, 1985: 237 footnote 20). But Gauthier wants
to make exactly that argument. Moral duties, he claims, are rationally
grounded (Gauthier, 1986: 2).
Gauthiers argument is a complex one and we could not possibly cover all
of the main elements of his theory in this one chapter. In the next section we
shall consider Hobbess account of life in the state of nature and how the
Prisoners Dilemma has been invoked to illustrate the point that moral constraints can be rational. We then examine how Gauthier proposes to answer
Hobbess Foole who questions why we should accept moral constraints. This
is what is known as the compliance problem. Thirdly, we consider the details
of what constitutes a rational agreement. And finally in the last section of
this chapter we consider some of the shortcomings of Gauthiers contractarianism; in particular its failure to provide an inclusive account of who counts
as a member of the moral community.
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 55
55
In such condition, there is no place for Industry; because the fruit thereof is
uncertain: and consequently no Culture on the Earth; no Navigation, nor
use of the commodities that may be imported by the Sea; no commodious
Building; no Instruments of moving, and removing such things as require
much force; no Knowledge of the face of the Earth; no account of Time; no
Arts; no Letters; no Society; and which is worst of all, continuall feare, and
danger of violent death; And the life of man, solitary, nasty, brutish and
short. (Hobbes, 1996: 89)
This competition for goods gives rise to a second source of conflict diffidence. Individuals in the state of nature do not trust one another. If you
cannot trust others then the rational thing to do, if you want to survive, is
make a preemptive strike. The best defence is a good offence. To make matters
worse, Hobbes claims that our desire for glory gives rise to a third cause of
conflict.
In this state of nature, where life is nasty, brutish and short, there is no
right or wrong, no justice and injustice. Under such conditions Hobbes
claims that individuals have a right to every thing, even to someone elses
body (Hobbes, 1996: 91). Such a right is rational as you have no guarantee
that others will not violate your person in order to satisfy their desire for
self-preservation. The result of this state of war is that no one enjoys the
benefits that come with social cooperation.
Contemporary commentators have described the dilemma people face in
the Hobbesian state of nature as that which individuals face in what is called
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 56
56
B
A
Not invade
Invade
Not invade
(2,2)
(4,1)
Invade
(1,4)
(3,3)
FIGURE 3.1
The most preferred option for each person is to decide to invade and have
the other decide not to invade. This brings with it the biggest pay-off as you
will get to exploit the other and reap the rewards that come with that. The
worst situation is to be the person who gets exploited, that is, to decide not to
invade when the other decides to invade. Each person reasons that the rational thing to do is to invade. This option gives you the chance of realizing the
best scenario (if the other person defects) and it also guards against the worse
possible scenario (you being exploited). The result then is mutual invasion
and both end up in a situation that was their second lowest preference. But
this outcome is not the optimal outcome. Both persons would have been
better off if they both chose not to invade. The Prisoners Dilemma illustrates
how constraints on individual utility-maximizing choice could be rational.
Those who find themselves in the Prisoners Dilemma have a reason to be
moral. This reason has nothing to do with moral intuitions. It simply appeals
to the interests of the individuals concerned, whatever those interests may be.
Hobbes puts forward a number of laws of nature, or theorems, which
direct individuals in the state of nature towards a peaceful existence. These
include the following:
First law: That every man, ought to endeavour peace, as far as he has hope of
obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use, all
helps, and advantages of war.
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 57
57
Second law: That a man be willing, when others are so too, as far-forth, as for
peace, and defence of himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this
right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty against other
men, as he would allow other men against himself.
Third law: That men perform their covenants made.
The laws of nature are to be understood as hypothetical imperatives, with
a rider attached to each of them specifying the conditions under which doing
x is rational (Hampton, 1986: 90). Given the situation of each individual in
the state of nature, it is not rational to accept the dictates of the laws of nature
if you do not have a guarantee that others will also comply with them. The
way to achieve this is to institute an absolute sovereign who will punish
those who break their covenants.
There are several aspects of Hobbess argument for an absolute sovereign
that could be questioned. Even if one accepts Hobbess pessimistic account
of what life would be like in the state of nature, contemporary critics would
claim that an absolute sovereign is unjustified as it is not necessary for securing self-preservation. Self-preservation could be secured by a number of
different institutional arrangements. So why settle for an absolute sovereign
if one could also secure, and better secure, self-preservation under a form of
limited government? This relates to a second objection to Hobbes that his
account of human interests is too narrow. While it is true that we all have an
interest in self-preservation we also have interests which expand beyond
this. We have an interest in certain freedoms (for example, freedom of
religion, occupation, etc.) which could be threatened by instituting an
absolute sovereign. Thirdly, one could question how, given the pessimistic
account of life in the state of nature Hobbes describes, individuals could
come together to create a sovereign in the first place. If there is no sovereign
in place then individuals have no way of knowing for sure that others will
fulfil their end of the bargain when they agree to institute a sovereign. In
order to institute a form of government there must be a certain minimal level
of trust among people. Hobbesian individuals do not possess this minimal
level of trust and thus it seems that they are destined to remain in the state
of war forever.
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
58
Page 58
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 59
59
punished is very small. In such cases the rational choice is to perform the
action which will maximize ones expected utility.
Gauthier rejects the political solution which Hobbes proposes as a reply to
the Foole in favour of a moral constraint. That is, a constraint that is internal,
that operates in the decision making of the agent and is not forced upon her
by an external force. In order for Hobbes to formulate an adequate response
to the Foole he must break the direct connection between reason and benefit.
Hobbes needs to say that it is rational to perform ones covenant even when
performance is not directly to ones benefit, provided it is to ones benefit to
be disposed to perform. But this he never says. And as long as the Foole is
allowed to relate reason directly to benefit in performance, rather than to
benefit in the disposition to perform, he can escape refutation. (Gauthier,
1986: 162)
Gauthiers solution to the Foole is to revise Hobbess conception of rationality. This involves moving from the appraisal of ones choices to the
appraisal of ones dispositions to choose. Gauthier introduces two possible
dispositions rational parties could adopt straightforward maximization
(SM) and constrained maximization (CM). The Foole represents an SM, that
is, a person who seeks to maximize her utility given the strategies of those
with whom she interacts (Gauthier, 1986: 167). An SM will be on the lookout for trustworthy people she can exploit. If she is able to benefit from
breaking her agreement with such individuals she will. This is contrasted
with the disposition of a constrained maximizer. A CM is a person who
seeks in some situations to maximize her utility, given not the strategies but
the utilities of those with whom she interacts (Gauthier, 1986: 167).
Given the choice between opting for the disposition of the straightforward maximizer or the constrained maximizer, what is the rational
choice to make? Which will bring you the most utility? The Foole claims
that the rational choice is straightforward maximization. You should cooperate if and only if cooperating will maximize your expected utility.
Should the opportunity arise where you could do better by breaking an
agreement then the rational thing to do is break the agreement. But an
important issue which the Foole fails to consider is that of how detectable
our true disposition is. Consider, for example, the game of poker. Some
people have a bad poker face. This means that the other players are able
to tell whether that person has a good or bad poker hand. If you have a
bad poker face you will not be able to win any money at poker. Every time
you have a good hand the other players will be able to detect your joy and
will fold before you get the chance to win their money. If you have a bad
hand and try to bluff by betting a lot of money in the hopes that others
will fold everyone else will see that you are sweating and know that you
do not have good cards. People with bad poker faces should not play
poker, at least not for money.
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 60
60
Gauthier thus raises the question of how good our poker faces are. He
considers three different possibilities: that we are transparent, opaque and
translucent. Transparency means that we have very bad poker faces.
Everyone is able to tell the true disposition of everyone else. If we are transparent, then the choice of the disposition of SM would be irrational.
Everyone would know that you are untrustworthy and they would not
include you in their cooperative enterprises. Robbed of the opportunity to
deceive and cooperate with others, an SM would fare very poorly.
The assumption of opacity is the opposite of transparency. If persons are
opaque then they are like professional poker players. No one can tell what
their true disposition is. If persons are opaque then the only solution to the
problem of natural interaction would be something like the political solution Hobbes envisions. If you could never tell what someones true disposition was then it would be irrational to trust others without the peace of
mind that comes from knowing that defection will be punished by the
state.
Between the extremes of transparency and opacity Gauthier claims that
there is a more realistic assumption translucency. To say that people are
translucent means that they are neither transparent nor opaque, so that their
dispositions to co-operate or not may be ascertained by others, not with certainty, but as more than mere guesswork (Gauthier, 1986: 174). Gauthier
accepts the assumption of translucency as the most realistic of the three and
then argues that this fact must figure in our calculations when deciding whether
to be an SM or CM.
Is it rational to adopt the disposition of an SM in a world full of translucent people? Gauthier claims it is not. Let us return to the Prisoners
Dilemma to illustrate how Gauthier develops his argument for CM. Instead
of our individuals having a choice between the two strategies of cooperation
or defection they must choose between the dispositions which yield different behaviour. That is, they must choose to be an SM or a CM. There are four
possible pay-offs, which are, in hierarchical order:
Defection: 1
Cooperation: u (less than 1)
Non-cooperation: u (less than u)
Exploitation: 0 (less than u)
In order to calculate what the expected pay-offs will be for both SMs and
CMs we must consider a number of relevant probabilities. Gauthier introduces the following three probabilities:
The probability that CMs will recognize each other (and thus cooperate): p
The probability that CMs will fail to recognize SMs but will themselves be
recognized (so that defection and exploitation will result): q
The probability that a randomly selected person is a CM: r
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 61
61
With this information to hand, we can now calculate what the expected
utilities for SMs and CMs will be. The average expected utility of an SM will
be equal to ones expected benefits from non-cooperative interactions (u),
plus ones expected benefits from successful exploitation. The latter will
depend on the probability of her interacting with a CM, r, and that she
recognizes her but is not herself recognized as an SM, q. In this case an SM
gains (1 u) over her non-cooperative expectation (u). Gauthier thus presents the expected utililty of an SM as: u + [rq(1 u)]
A CM expects u unless she can successfully cooperate with other CMs or
she is exploited by an SM. The probability of cooperation is arrived at by multiplying the probability that she interacts with a CM, r, by the probability that
they will recognize each other as CMs, p. In this case a CM will gain the difference between cooperation and non-cooperation over her noncooperation expectation (that is, uu). The utility increase a CM can expect
from cooperation is thus represented as [rp(uu)]. The probability of her
being exploited is arrived at by multiplying the probability that she interacts
with an SM (1r) with the probability that she fails to recognize her but is herself recognized by him q, thus giving us (1r)q. In the situation of exploitation
a CM receives a pay-off of 0 and so loses her non-cooperative expectation (u).
Exploitation thus reduces a CMs utility expectation by a value of [(1r)qu].
Bringing the various possibilities for a CM together, Gauthier produces the following formulation of their expected utility: {u + [rp(uu)](1r)qu}
A determination of who can expect the highest pay-off, an SM or a CM,
will depend on the probabilities that Gauthier introduces. Gauthier argues
that these probabilities tip things in favour of CMs as persons improve their
ability to detect the dispositions of those with whom they interact.
Both CMs and SMs must expect to benefit from increasing their ability to
detect the dispositions of others. But if both endeavor to maximize their
abilities (or the expected utility, net of costs, of so doing), then CMs may
expect to improve their position in relation to SMs. For the benefits gained
by SMs, by being better able to detect potential victims, must be on the
whole offset by the losses they suffer as the CMs become better able to
detect them as potential exploiters ... . Those who believe rationality and
morality to be at loggerheads may have failed to recognize the importance
of cultivating their ability to distinguish sincere co-operators from insincere
ones. (Gauthier, 1986: 181)
There are a number of different objections which have been raised against
this aspect of Gauthiers argument. Firstly, we could challenge his claim that
people are translucent. Gauthier simply assumes this without offering any
argument for it. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (1989) claims that people are often
trans-opaque. That is, they deliberately send people misleading signals to
the effect that they are trustworthy even though they are not. Many people,
argues Sayre-McCord, develop winning smiles, travel with a glowing
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
62
Page 62
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 63
63
Further reading
Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, Deceptions and Reasons to be Moral, American
Philosophical Quarterly, 26, 1989: 11322.
David Copp, Contractarianism and Moral Scepticism, in Peter Vallentyne (ed.),
Contractarianism and Rational Choice (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991).
Holly Smith, Deriving Morality from Rationality, in Peter Vallentyne (ed.),
Contractarianism and Rational Choice (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991).
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
64
Page 64
(masters and slaves) could improve their situations. If a bargain were struck
between the slaves and masters, one in which they all stood to benefit, then
surely, as rational agents, such a deal would be viable. So the young master
writes up the terms of such a bargain, called the Bargain of Mutual Benefit.
Under this agreement the masters will free the slaves and dismantle their
coercive apparatus. In return for their freedom the slaves will voluntarily be
the masters servants. All stand to benefit from such an arrangement. The
masters will save money by doing away with coercion and the servants will
receive wages that are better than the living allowance they are given as
slaves.
The young master manages to persuade the majority of masters that such
a deal is viable and they agree to dismantle the institutions of slavery and
enshrine the Bargain of Mutual Benefit in their constitution. So, do the
ex-slaves agree to fulfil their end of the bargain once the institutions of slavery are dismantled? No. It is not rational to become willing slaves. The slaves
agreed to comply with the initial agreement because it did seem rational at
the time. But once the institutions of slavery were dismantled the slaves
realized that they had no reason to voluntarily comply with an arrangement
that was premised on a coercive initial bargaining position. It is only rational, argues Gauthier, to act cooperatively if the initial bargaining position is
non-coercive.
All effects of taking advantage must be removed from the initial bargaining position, claims Gauthier, before it is rational for utility-maximizers to
accept a bargain. But what kind of behaviour constitutes taking advantage
of another and must be removed from the initial bargaining position? To
answer this question Gauthier introduces what he calls the Lockean proviso.
We have already encountered this proviso in Chapter 2 when we examined
Robert Nozicks libertarian argument. The Lockean proviso moralizes the
Hobbesian state of nature. The Hobbesian non-agreement point is the situation of war-against-all, where everyone has a right to everything. But individuals in the Lockean state of nature respect each others rights and do not
better their situation through interaction that worsens the situation of
another. The Lockean proviso thus rules out the kind of predatory behaviour
which the masters were engaged in. Gauthiers initial bargaining position is
thus the hypothetical result of how individuals would fare in the situation of
non-cooperation constrained by the Lockean proviso. That is, how everyone
would fare if they were given exclusive right to the use of their body and its
powers and did not worsen the situation of others.
It is important to note that Gauthier does not think the proviso says anything about equalizing. As he says: the rich man may feast on caviar and
champagne, while the poor woman starves at his gate. And she may not
even take the crumbs from his table, if that would deprive him of his pleasure in feeding them to his birds (Gauthier, 1986: 218). Gauthier illustrates
why this is the case with his example of the sixteen Robinson Crusoes. He
imagines a scenario where sixteen Robinson Crusoes each live on a different
island. The sixteen Crusoes and sixteen islands are all different in terms of
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 65
65
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
66
Page 66
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 67
67
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
68
Page 68
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 69
69
they strike human tissue, slaughter them for food, or bronze them to make
lifelike statues. (Buchanan, 1990: 232)
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
70
Page 70
Animals, like human beings, can feel pain and pleasure. Therefore any plausible moral theory must take their interests into account. But Gauthiers
theory does not do so because he reduces justice to rational self-interest.
Gauthiers account of morality is unfairly biased in favour of human beings.
The social structure of our society may impede the ability of some to contribute. So if we believe that it is important that people contribute to
society surely it is equally important that society take reasonable measures
to ensure that the widest possible range of potential contributors have the
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 71
71
opportunity to fulfil this obligation. We also need to take seriously the question
of what constitutes contributing to society.
Those who criticize Gauthiers theory for failing to take seriously the concerns of the infirm, animals or future generations, etc. are relying on moral
intuitions that cannot be defended. Thus these objections are not pressing.
Gauthiers project requires us to radically reform our conception of morality,
so simply appealing to unsubstantiated intuitions is counterproductive for it
is exactly those intuitions that Gauthiers methodology rules out.
SUMMARY
Gauthier rejects the appeal to moral intuitions and argues that moral duties are
rationally grounded. By doing so, Gauthiers theory must tackle the compliance
problem because he cannot assume that people will fulfil their agreements simply
because it is moral to do so. Central to Gauthiers resolution of the compliance
problem is his assumption that our true dispositions are translucent, hence rational persons would be constrained maximizers.
In order to determine what the content of a rational agreement is one must first
establish an initial bargaining position (the Lockean proviso) and then a set of feasible options that it is rational to choose. The latter is determined by the principle
of minimax relative concession. The political upshot of Gauthiers argument is difficult to ascertain but he does embrace (with a few qualifications) the free market.
He rejects Rawlss egalitarian liberalism on the grounds that, by treating talents
as a common asset, Rawlss theory demands the giving of free rides.
Critics point to the counterintuitive consequences of Gauthiers theory to reveal
how deficient an account of justice it is. The implications of the theory for the treatment of the disabled, the unborn and animals have led many to conclude that
Gauthiers theory should not even be described as a theory of justice.
Notes
1 See, for example, David Gauthier (1986), Jean Hampton (1986), Gregory Kavka
(1986) and Quentin Skinner (1996).
2 For a discussion of the reasonable and the rational see Rawls (1993), pp. 4854.
3 Hampton (1986) distinguishes between the following three accounts: the rationality account of conflict, the passions account and the shortsightedness account. See
her discussion of these distinct accounts in Chapters 2 and 3 of Hobbes and the
Social Contract.
4 For a discussion of how this story relates to a prisoner (hence its being called the
Prisoners Dilemma) see Gauthier (1986), pp. 7980.
5 See James Buchanan (1975).
6 See Morals By Agreement, pp. 13741.
7 For challenges to this see Russell Hardin (1988) and Jean Hampton (1988).
8 Gauthier does have reservations about relying on the market in the real world.
See, for example, his discussion of taxing inheritance in Chapter IX of Morals by
Agreement.
Farrelly Ch-03.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 72
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 73
Dworkin on Equality
Summary Contents
4.1
4.2
4.3
4.4
4.5
Introduction
Dworkin on equality of resources
Welfare reform and the basic income proposal
Political equality and democracy
Against luck egalitarianism
73
75
80
85
89
4.1 Introduction
Our discussion of the various versions of contemporary liberal theory
should make it apparent that liberty is one of the core values that liberals
cherish. Rawls and Nozick, for example, reject utilitarianism because they
believe that a public philosophy that permits the loss of freedom for some in
the interests of the greater overall good is a deficient theory. Despite
Gauthiers attempt to construct a contractarian theory that is devoid of
moral premises even he appeals to the value of liberty when he invokes the
Lockean proviso. But what about the value of equality? Is this not also a
fundamental value for liberals? Much depends on which version of liberalism one is talking about as well as what one means by equality. Nozick, for
example, believes that liberty and equality are incompatible values if by
equality one means that some patterned distributive principle should be
established and maintained. Gauthier rejects any appeal to the notion of
moral equality hence he does not find the consequences of the reciprocity
thesis problematic. But Rawlss egalitarian liberalism has inspired
contemporary liberals to take more seriously the project of reconciling the
values of liberty and equality. In this chapter we shall consider one of the
main theorists who has made equality more central to liberalism Ronald
Dworkin. Liberty, argues Dworkin, is an aspect of equality rather than an
independent political ideal potentially in conflict with it. Dworkins argument for equality of resources has sparked much debate among liberals and
egalitarians and considering this theory will prove useful in helping to see
how egalitarian liberals have developed their position beyond Rawlss
theory as well as illustrate the different practical issues egalitarian liberalism
can be applied to.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
74
Page 74
To set the stage for Dworkins argument it is worth recalling two of the
main concerns expressed in the first chapter with respect to the way Rawls
defined the least advantaged. Firstly, Rawls stipulates that he constructs a
theory of justice for the simpler case of a society of normal, fully cooperating members. But this tactic makes Rawlss theory less attractive to those
who believe that inequalities in the natural lottery of life should be a central
concern for a theory of justice. By excluding the severely handicapped from
the category of the least advantaged Rawlss theory does not take seriously
the egalitarian intuition that inequalities in our natural endowments should
be compensated. Secondly, critics have argued that Rawls includes many of
the undeserving poor in the category of least advantaged and the idea of
maximising the prospects of those who choose to be non-productive does not
cohere with our moral sensibilities. There is a difference between someone
who is less advantaged as a result of circumstances beyond their control (for
example, being born with a severe handicap) and someone who is less advantaged as a result of their own choice (for example, choosing to live off welfare
payments instead of working). A concern for these two issues has given rise to
the position Elizabeth Anderson (1999) calls luck egalitarianism.1 Luck egalitarians construct their theories around what is called the choice/chance (or
choice/circumstances) distinction. Peoples fates are determined by their
choices and their circumstances (Dworkin, 2000: 322) and this must remain,
argue luck egalitarians, a fundamental insight when considering what constitutes a just distribution. Luck egalitarians disagree on exactly what should be
equalized (for example, resources, opportunity for welfare, etc.) but they
believe that inequalities in the advantages that people enjoy are just if they
derive from the choices people have voluntarily made, but that inequalities
deriving from unchosen features of peoples circumstances are unjust.
Ronald Dworkin is one of the main advocates of luck egalitarianism and
his theory will be the focus of this chapter. Dworkin begins Sovereign Virtue
by declaring:
No government is legitimate that does not show equal concern for the fate of
all those citizens over whom it claims dominion and from whom it claims
allegiance. Equal concern is the sovereign virtue of political community
without it government is only tyranny and when a nations wealth is very
unequally distributed, as the wealth of even very prosperous nations now is,
then its equal concern is suspect. For the distribution of wealth is the product
of a legal order: a citizens wealth massively depends on which laws his community has enacted not only its laws governing ownership, theft, contract,
and tort, but its welfare law, tax law, labor law, civil rights law, environmental
regulation law, and laws of practically everything else. (Dworkin, 2000: 1)
Like Rawls, Dworkin believes that the basic structure of society should be
publicly justified to all citizens. But unlike Rawls, Dworkin does not believe
that this can be accomplished by emphasizing a version of political liberalism
that does not invoke ethical assumptions and controversies about the good
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 75
Dworkin on Equality
75
These two principles make different demands on government. The principle of equal importance requires government to adopt laws and policies
that ensure that its citizens fates are, so far as government can achieve this,
insensitive to who they otherwise are their economic background, gender,
race, or particular set of skills and handicaps (Dworkin, 2000: 6). The principle of special responsibility demands that the government work, again as
far as it can achieve this, to make their fates sensitive to the choices they have
made (Dworkin, 2000: 6). Over the course of Sovereign Virtue Dworkin
elaborates on what the content of these twin demands is by considering a
number of theoretical issues and political controversies. In the next section
we shall consider some of the theoretical issues by focusing on Dworkins
argument for equality of resources.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
76
Page 76
Nozick believes that most of us would not agree to be hooked for life to
this machine. Why not? Because we value something else besides merely
experiencing the sensations of pleasure. We want to actually write a great
novel or make friends or read an interesting book and not just experience the
mental sensations that accompany these things.
Those who are dissatisfied with the prospect of equating human welfare
with mental states might find the preference-satisfaction account of utility
more attractive. According to this view, our welfare depends not on experiencing certain mental states but in having our preferences satisfied. The
experience machine does not satisfy our preferences as our preferences are
more extensive than merely experiencing certain mental sensations.
Dworkin calls this version of welfarism success theories of welfare as they
suppose that a persons welfare is a matter of his success in fulfilling his
preferences, goals, and ambitions, and so equality of success, as a conception
of equality of welfare, recommends distribution and transfer of resources
until no further transfer can decrease the extent to which people differ in
such success (Dworkin, 2000: 17).
If we adopt a success theory of welfare we must distinguish between a
number of different kinds of preferences that we will deem illegitimate.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 77
77
Take, for example, those uniformed preferences which may undermine our
welfare. Suppose I have a preference for drinking the contents of the cup on
my desk. That preference is based upon my belief that the cup contains some
cool, refreshing water. But that belief could be mistaken. Perhaps a disgruntled colleague snuck into my office and poisoned my water! If this is the case
then satisfying my preference for drinking the contents of the cup will harm
my welfare. This type of consideration might lead us to add the qualifier that
our welfare involves the satisfying of informed or rational preferences. But
then how do we stipulate what makes a preference informed or rational?
These are difficult questions which those who defend success theories of
welfare must address.
Dworkin introduces three distinctions which success theories must also
consider. These are: political preferences, impersonal preferences, and personal preferences. Political preferences are preferences about how the
goods, resources, and opportunities of the community should be distributed
by others (Dworkin, 2000: 17). An example of a political preference would
be ones desire for a certain political regime (democracy, for example).
Impersonal preferences are preferences about things other than my own or
anyone elses life, such as the preference that a certain species of plant or animal should not become extinct. Personal preferences are preferences about
our own lives, such as my preference for being healthy. Some of the preferences from each of these three categories must be eliminated, argues
Dworkin, from the equalizing calculation if equality of welfare is to be
viable. Suppose, for example, that everyone in our society has a political
preference for a harmonious multicultural society, everyone except Bob. Bob
is a racist and has a political preference for living in a segregated society. If
our society is a harmonious multicultural society then Bobs welfare, with
respect to his political preferences, is less than that of the rest of us. If equality of welfare is the goal then we should compensate Bob for this inequality
by giving him some extra goods. Such a requirement is perverse and equality of welfare will only be an attractive account of distributional equality if it
can rule out counterintuitive cases like this.
Dworkins analysis of the different versions of welfarism is quite detailed
but we need not pursue these points further here. But there are two points
which are worth emphasizing with respect to the appeal of equality of welfare
and its shortcomings. Firstly, its appeal. The ideal of equality of welfare is
appealing in that it coheres with the first of the two principles of ethical
individualism Dworkin emphasizes the principle of equal importance.
Consider, for example, how people with handicaps would be treated in this
society. Their welfare is just as important as the welfare of those who do not
have handicaps. Thus those whose welfare is impeded by such burdens will
receive extra resources so that they can enjoy the same level of welfare as
others. Equality of welfare thus fares well with respect to the principle of
equal importance because it requires that the needy receive more resources.
But equality of welfare fails to accommodate the second principle which
Dworkin takes to be fundamental, the principle of special responsibility. If
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
78
Page 78
equality of welfare is the goal then it cannot provide sufficient room for the
idea that we have special and final responsibility for the success of our lives.
My welfare might be impeded not because of factors beyond my control
(such as a handicap) but because of factors that I can be personally responsible for (expensive tastes, for example). Perhaps I have cultivated expensive
tastes and thus need extra resources in order for me to achieve the same level
of welfare that others (with less expensive tastes) have.2 According to equality of welfare my demand for extra resources, like those of the person with a
handicap, is legitimate. Equality of welfare fails as a distributive ideal
because it does not afford enough room for considerations of personal
responsibility. Like Rawlss difference principle, equality of welfare fails to
distinguish between the deserving and undeserving poor. Dworkin puts forward his account of equality of resources as an alternative distributive ideal
that incorporates both the principle of equal importance and the principle of
special responsibility.
Dworkins argument for equality of resources is a rich and sophisticated
one and we can only briefly consider some of its main components.
Dworkins attempt to merge the two fundamental principles of ethical individualism are most stark in his hypothetical tale of shipwrecked survivors
who are washed up on a desert island that has abundant resources. Let us
assume for the moment that everyone has the same natural talents. The
immigrants agree to divide the resources of the island equally among them.
Each person is given 100 clam shells to bid on the various resources. These
people will obviously have different preferences and this will be reflected in
what they spend their clam shells on. If the majority of immigrants have a
preference for sun tanning on the beach then those parts of the beach will be
very costly. If the majority have a preference for living as farmers then those
parts of the island conducive to agriculture will be very costly, etc. The distribution that would result from such an auction would be ambition sensitive. That is, the bundle of goods people end up with would reflect only
the choices they made. No one could complain that someone else received
preferential treatment as all started with 100 clam shells and were free to bid
on those resources they wanted. Of course some resources will be more
expensive than others but this is not grounds for a complaint as this stems
from your own personal preferences and those of the other immigrants. You
could change your preferences so that you could appropriate more of the
less expensive resources. Such an auction will treat all as equals if it satisfies
what Dworkin calls the envy test. The envy test maintains that no division
of resources is an equal division if, once the distribution is complete, any
immigrant would prefer someone elses bundle of resources to his own
bundle (Dworkin, 2000: 67).
The first part of Dworkins hypothetical story captures the concern for the
special responsibility principle. The initial bundle of goods the immigrants
have are the result of their own ambitions, tastes, etc. But what happens once
the auction is completed and the immigrants begin to produce things? Let us
now drop the initial assumption that all have equal natural talents. Given the
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 79
79
fact that some immigrants will be more skilful, others will fall sick, etc. it will
not be long before the conditions of the envy test will fail to be met. These
events thus threaten to undermine the first fundamental principle of ethical
individualism the principle of equal importance. This principle maintains
that it is important that human lives be successful rather than wasted. But a
starting-gate theory that holds that justice requires equal initial resources
and laissez-faire thereafter will undermine the requirements of this principle.
Dworkin argues that we must not allow the distribution of resources to be
endowment-sensitive, that is, to be affected by differences in ability of the
sort that produce income differences in a laissez-faire economy among people
with the same ambitions (Dworkin, 2000: 89).
Dworkin introduces the hypothetical insurance scheme to alleviate the concerns about abandoning the ideal of an endowment-insensitive distribution.
He modifies the auction story by declaring that, prior to the auction, the
immigrants are denied information about their natural endowments and are
given the opportunity to purchase insurance against handicaps and unequal
skills. Under these conditions of uncertainty people would be willing to part
with some of their 100 clam shells to guard against having disabilities or
lacking skills. Those who fare poorly in these respects will receive compensation in the form of extra resources paid out by these insurance schemes.
Such schemes will be funded by those who are fortunate not to have to make
an insurance claim but will have to pay an insurance premium.
The hypothetical auction Dworkin invokes is likely to cause some confusion in terms of understanding how it relates to the real world, where we
dont begin with equal resources nor do we have insurance schemes in place
for things like skill. Dworkin attempts to make the link between the theory
and the real world by tackling a number of applied topics in Part II of
Sovereign Virtue, including health care, welfare programmes, electoral reform
and affirmative action. In the real world, for example, there is a need for
taxation and redistribution. Income tax is a device society can use to
neutralize the effects of handicaps and differential talents. But a tax system
can only roughly approximate the results of the insurance scheme and will
not achieve a truly ambition-sensitive/endowment-insensitive distribution.
Nor is there one simple solution which will do justice to the demands of the
two fundamental principles of ethical individualism. Dworkin endorses, for
example, a decent minimum of medical care for all citizens and the option to
buy private health insurance. But his endorsement of universal health coverage is not founded on the rescue principle, which instructs us to spend all we
can on health care until the next dollar would buy no gain in health and life
expectancy at all (Dworkin, 2000: 309). Equal concern for all does not necessarily entail that we spend exorbitant amounts of public funds trying to save
the lives of those who have little chance of surviving for long. Society must
make tough decisions regarding which medical tests and procedures should
be deemed necessary and appropriate for coverage under the publicly
funded health care system and also allow individuals to choose for themselves how much more they wish to spend to insure themselves against
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
80
Page 80
Dworkin invokes the example of making ones will to reveal the different considerations which the two theories of equality will bring to the fore. Considering
this example will help bring out some of the potential problems with equality of
welfare. Suppose your children have roughly equal wealth already and, being a
political philosopher, you wish to design your will so as to achieve equality of
welfare among your children. You have five children with different talents and
ambitions. Dworkin provides the following information on the children:
One
One
One
One
One
is
is
is
is
is
blind.
a playboy with expensive tastes.
a prospective politician with expensive ambitions.
a poet with humble needs.
a sculptor who works in expensive material.
If equality of welfare is your goal, how would you divide the inheritance? In order
to answer that question you must consider how you would define welfare and
which of the children would need the largest portion of the inheritance in order
to bring their welfare up to the level of the other children. After considering this
example, debate what you think are the strengths and weaknesses of the ideal
of equality of welfare.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 81
81
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
82
Page 82
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 83
83
Van Parijss argument for this unconditional basic income is complex but the
central contention for it can be stated as follows:
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
84
Page 84
unemployed, will receive. The more income you make from your job the
higher your employment rent.
The main objection critics have made to Van Parijss argument is that it
permits the voluntarily unemployed to free-ride off the those who work.4
Van Parijs replies to this objection by asking us to recognize the realities of
the labour market.
People fail to realize that much of the income that goes to labour in fact
derives from our common inheritance of resources. Most of the income that
is generated by labour in our society is generated in the context of jobs. Now
jobs are very unequally accessible to people and even if everyone had a job
there would still be many jobs that are restricted to a small number of
people because many people do not have the talents that are required in
order to perform them ... So what I ask people who make this free-rider
objection to realise is how large this background of gifts that we receive in
all sorts of forms, actually is. These gifts are appropriated to a very unequal
and unfair extent by the people who happen to be able to contribute by
having the best paid and most attractive jobs. (Van Parijs, 1997: 1415)
The principle of equal concern, for Van Parijs, entails that all have not only
a right to do what one might want to do, but that each person should have
the greatest possible opportunity to do whatever he or she might want to
do. This is achieved when society implements the highest sustainable unconditional basic income. Liberals like Rawls who maintain that Malibu surfers5
should not be entitled to public funds are violating neutrality, argues Van
Parijs, because they are giving preferential treatment to those who prefer to
work. Malibu surfers are entitled to their fair share of societys resources.
The charge that the voluntarily unemployed are taking an unfair share of
societys resources is misguided, argues Van Parijs. [T]hose who take an
unfair share of societys resources are not those who opt for such a lowproduction, low-consumption lifestyle. They are people like myself and
most of my readers, who, thanks to the attractive job they were given, appropriate a huge employment rent (Van Parijs, 1991: 130).
Critically assess Dworkins argument for the welfare state and Van Parijss
basic income proposal.
To what extent do you think the welfare state is compatible with the principle of special responsibility?
Do you agree with Dworkins criticisms of the 1996 Welfare Reform Act?
Van Parijs claims that everyone should be entitled to a basic income, even
those who are not willing to work. What do you think of this radical suggestion?
Should jobs be included among the resources to be equalized, as Van Parijs
suggests?
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 85
Dworkin on Equality
85
Further reading
David Schmidtz and Rober t Goodin, Social Welfare and Individual
Responsibility: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1998).
Robert Goodin, Reasons for Welfare (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1988).
Stuart White, The Civic Minimum (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
86
Page 86
for funds that are used on issue advocacy media campaigns that do not
explicitly urge voters to vote for or against any candidate. Many other democratic countries place a cap on campaign expenditures but similar limits
have been struck down as unconstitutional by the American Supreme Court.
In Buckley v. Valeo (1976),
the Supreme Court ruled that expenditure limits are unconstitutional
because they violate the First Amendment of the United States Constitution,
which provides that Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom of
speech or association. Prohibiting a politician or anyone else from spending
as much money as he wishes to press his political convictions and policies,
the Court said, is restricting his freedom of speech. (Dworkin, 2000: 352)
Support for the ruling in Buckley comes from a popular strategic assumption about the best way to realize and protect democracy. Dworkin calls this
the democratic wager. The democratic wager holds that democracy is best
protected by a principle that forbids government to limit or control political
speech in any way for the purpose of protecting democracy (Dworkin, 2000:
353). This is so because democracy is understood as a political arrangement
designed to enforce the will of the majority. According to this majoritarian
conception of democracy, the democratic ideal lies in a match between political decision and the will of the majority or plurality of opinion (Dworkin,
2000: 357). Free speech is thus paramount for majoritarians and hence why
they believe that the decision in Buckley was correct. The best way of ensuring that citizens have the opportunity to inform themselves as fully as possible and to deliberate about their choices is to permit anyone who wishes
to address the public to do so, in whatever way and at whatever length he
wishes, no matter how unpopular or unworthy the government or other
citizens deem his message to be (Dworkin, 2000: 359).
Rejecting the proposal for limits on campaign expenditures is necessary,
argue majoritarians, because the existing arrangement provides a fuller
opportunity for information and reflection. Allowing the government to
limit what citizens hear limits that opportunity and thus limits democracy.
But this argument will only be persuasive if one assumes that unlimited
expenditures create the fullest opportunity for information and reflection.
But the ballooning of political expenditures has also brought a rise in smear
campaigns, political jingles and sound-bites. How much information and
reflection do these communications convey? Limits on campaign spending
might force political parties to focus more on solving societys problems and
less on fundraising. With only limited funds available political parties might
take a more responsible approach to campaigning so that they focus more on
making a persuasive argument for their main platforms rather than on
negative campaigning and sound-bites.
In place of the majoritarian conception of democracy Dworkin defends the
partnership conception. The partnership conception of democracy has three
dimensions. These are:
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 87
87
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
88
Page 88
America raises doubts about how much control the people actually have.
Judges are not elected by the people nor are they accountable to them and
yet they have the power to override legislation that has been passed by
democratically elected officials. One of Dworkins most competent critics
who criticizes his stance on this issue is Jeremy Waldron. Waldron points
out, for example, that between 1885 and 1930 American state and federal
courts struck down some 150 pieces of legislation concerning labour relations, labour conditions and working hours (Waldron, 1998: 3378). When
unelected officials have so much power how can Dworkin remain faithful to
both judicial review and the partnership conception of democracy?
Those who defend constitutionalism and judicial review argue that it is
necessary to limit majority rule in this way. The constitution guarantees all
citizens those rights we believe are fundamental and thus even a democratically elected majority are not justified in violating them. So those who
defend judicial review believe that it makes society more just. They point, for
example, to cases such as Brown v. Board of Education (1954) in which the
Supreme Court ruled unanimously to end racial segregation in public
schools. But even if we acknowledge that judicial review can serve a positive
role does it not necessarily conflict with the democratic ideal that Dworkin
appeals to? Dworkin believes it does not. In Freedoms Law: The Moral Reading
of the American Constitution Dworkin argues that in some circumstances judicial review does not conflict with democracy but it actually enhances it.
Recall that one of the important dimensions of the partnership conception of
democracy is democratic discourse. Citizens must deliberate together as
individuals. Dworkin believes that constitutional adjudication actually
improves the quality of public debate on important issues.
When an issue is seen as constitutional ... and as one that will ultimately be
resolved by courts applying general constitutional principles, the quality of
public argument is often improved, because the argument concentrates from
the start on questions of public morality ... When a constitutional issue has
been decided by the Supreme Court, and is important enough so that it can
be expected to be elaborated, expanded, contracted, or even reversed by
future decisions, a sustained national debate begins, in newspapers and
other media, in law schools and classrooms, in public meetings and around
dinner tables. (Dworkin, 1996: 345)
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 89
Dworkin on Equality
89
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
90
Page 90
inequality reflects the choices people make but not their circumstances that
they are not responsible for. This is the central tenet of luck egalitarianism.
The two fundamental principles of ethical individualism Dworkin invokes
are utilized by him to help reinforce the intuition that the choice/chance distinction should remain the fundamental insight when considering the issue
of distributional equality. We shall now consider one of the most forceful
arguments against luck egalitarianism. In What is the Point of Equality?
Elizabeth Anderson criticizes theorists like Dworkin and Van Parijs for
making beach bums and the lazy and irresponsible the main focus of debates
about egalitarianism. The aim of equality, she argues, is not to eliminate the
impact of brute luck from human affairs but to end oppression.
Anderson argues that luck egalitarianism fails the most fundamental test
any egalitarian theory must meet: that its principles express equal respect
and concern for all citizens (Anderson, 1999: 289). It fails this test in the
following three ways:
1 It excludes some citizens from enjoying the social conditions of freedom
on the spurious ground that its their fault for losing them.
2 It makes the basis for citizens claims on one another the fact that some
are inferior to others in the worth of their lives, talents and personal
qualities.
3 In attempting to ensure that people take responsibility for their choices,
luck egalitarianism makes demeaning and intrusive judgements about
peoples capacities to exercise responsibility and effectively dictates to
them the appropriate uses of the freedom. (Anderson, 1999: 289)
Let us address these three points in turn, focusing in particular on how
they relate to Dworkins theory. Recall Dworkins insurance analogy.
Dworkin argues that justice demands that the state compensate everyone for
whatever risks of bad brute luck they would have insured themselves
against if all were equally likely to suffer from the risk. But a problem arises
with respect to what Dworkin calls option luck. Brute luck concerns risks
that are not the result of deliberate gambles (such as being born with a severe
mental handicap). Option luck concerns risks that are the result of our
choices (for example, investing all your money in a company that goes bankrupt). Dworkins principle of equal concern requires us to compensate
people for the misfortunes of bad brute luck. We do this by providing, for
example, minimum universal health coverage and welfare programmes. But
the principle of special responsibility tells us that individuals have special
and final responsibility for the success of their lives and thus we are not
collectively responsible for the misfortune people suffer from their option
luck. Taking this line seriously, argues Anderson, has some counterintuitive
results.
She considers a number of cases to illustrate this point. Consider, for
example, the uninsured driver who negligently makes an illegal turn and
causes an accident with someone else. This driver deliberately took a
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 91
91
This relates to the third and final objection Anderson raises against
Dworkin, that luck egalitarianism makes demeaning and intrusive judgements of peoples capacities. It makes private judgements about the value of
its citizens worth as workers publicly recognized opinions and thus disparages the internally disadvantaged and raises private disdain to the status
of officially recognised truths (Anderson, 1999: 306). As such it runs counter
to the true spirit of equality which seeks to promote institutional arrangements that enable the diversity of peoples talents, aspirations, roles, and
cultures to benefit everyone and to be recognised as mutually beneficial
(Anderson, 1999: 308). Anderson favours what she calls democratic equality
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
92
Page 92
SUMMARY
Dworkin endorses a version of comprehensive liberalism which is premised on two
fundamental principles of ethical individualism the principle of equal importance
and the principle of special responsibility. Dworkin favours equality of resources
over equality of welfare as the latter fails to accommodate the principle of special
responsibility. Equality of welfare cannot deal with the problem of expensive
tastes.
Dworkins argument for equality of resources is one of the most developed
accounts of what is known as luck egalitarianism the view that inequalities in the
advantages people enjoy are just if they derive from the choices people have
voluntarily made, but that inequalities deriving from unchosen features of peoples
circumstances are unjust. Dworkin invokes the hypothetical tale of shipwrecked
survivors on an island in order to show that equality of resources justifies a
system of taxation and redistribution.
A number of applied topics are addressed by Dworkin in Sovereign Virtue, ranging
from health care and welfare provision to electoral reform. Critics of Dworkin have
taken issue with both the central tenets of luck egalitarianism and Dworkins
stance on issues like judicial review.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Dworkin on Equality
Page 93
93
Notes
1 Those who endorse this position include, among others, Ronald Dworkin (2000),
Richard Arneson (1989), G.A. Cohen (1989) and Philippe Van Parijs (1995).
2 For example, I might claim that I must have a bigger home and more cars than the
average person if I am to attain the same level of welfare others have.
3 The issue of state neutrality will be a central focus of the communitarian critique
examined in Chapter 5.
4 See Elster (1986), White (1997) and Farrelly (1999).
5 See Political Liberalism, pp. 1812, note 9.
6 It should be noted, however, that Dworkin is also an eminent legal scholar and
has extensively argued in favour of American constitutionalism and believes that
the United Kingdom should adopt the American-style arrangement of judicial
review. See Ronald Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain (1990).
7 Available on the Web at http://www.fec.gov/finance_reports.html.
8 The First Amendment states: Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom
of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to
petition the Government for a redress of grievances.
9 See Chapters 11 and 12 of Sovereign Virtue.
Farrelly Ch-04.qxd
11/5/03 2:32 PM
Page 94
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 95
Part Two:
Alternative Traditions
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 96
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 97
Communitarianism
Summary Contents
5.1
5.2
5.3
5.4
5.5
5.6
Introduction
Deontological liberalism and the unencumbered self
State neutrality
Walzer and complex equality
Miller on nationalism
Conclusion
97
99
102
106
110
115
5.1 Introduction
Stuart Hampshire succinctly captures one of the core commitments of
liberals when he claims that the essence of a liberal morality is the rejection
of any final and exclusive authority, natural or supernatural, and of the
accompanying compulsion and censorship (Hampshire, 2000: 35). Central
to the liberal morality is the belief that individual rights should be given a
high priority. The emphasis liberals place on individual rights has given rise
to a distinct criticism which dominated many of the debates in political theory
in the 1980s and 1990s communitarianism. The liberalcommunitarian
debate covers a varied range of issues and theorists and there is no simple
contrast between liberalism and communitarianism. In this chapter we shall
focus on two prominent communitarian critics Michael Sandel and
Michael Walzer.1 These two theorists challenge distinct aspects of liberalism
and they effectively illustrate the practical significance of the liberal
communitarian debate. Michael Sandels two influential books Liberalism and
the Limits of Justice2 and Democracys Discontent examine the conception of the
self implicit in contemporary liberalism. Sandel calls this conception of
the self the unencumbered (or voluntarist) conception of the self. This vision of
the self, argues Sandel, informs the public philosophy of contemporary
American politics. Sandel labels this public philosophy the procedural republic.
He claims:
The political philosophy by which we live is a certain version of liberal
political theory. Its central idea is that government should be neutral toward
the moral and religious views its citizens espouse. Since people disagree
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
98
Page 98
about the best way to live, government should not affirm in law any particular
vision of the good life. Instead, it should provide a framework of rights that
respects persons as free and independent selves, capable of choosing their
own values and ends. Since this liberalism asserts the priority of fair procedures over particular ends, the public life it informs might be called the procedural republic. (Sandel, 1996: 4)
The procedural republic is ill-equipped, argues Sandel, to deal with the two
fears that define the anxiety of contemporary American politics the fear of
losing control of the forces that govern our lives and the fear that the moral
fabric of community is eroding. In the following two sections we examine
the two prongs of Sandels communitarian critique. Firstly, that liberalism is
premised on the unencumbered conception of the self. And secondly, that
this conception of the self gives rise to a public philosophy that has the costly
consequences Sandel claims it has.
Michael Walzers communitarian critique also focuses on American politics but Walzers concern is not with the conception of the self liberalism
invokes. Walzer takes issue with the methodology many contemporary
liberals invoke when constructing a theory of justice. His argument is radically pluralistic and he rejects the universalist aspirations of liberals who
seek to construct a theory of justice that can be applied universally to all
cultures. Justice, argues Walzer, is a human construction and thus we cannot
arrive at answers to the difficult questions justice raises if we conceive of justice
in a way that ignores the particularist claims that are bound to arise when
one considers the history, culture and membership of different societies. We
cannot derive principles of justice from an abstract thought experiment
which asks what principles rational persons would choose if they knew
nothing of their situation except that they desired an abstract set of primary
goods. Each community creates its own social goods and thus what each
community thinks should be justly distributed will vary from culture to
culture. What members of hierarchies and caste societies value is very
different from what members of liberal democratic societies value.
Furthermore, even within one community there will be a plurality of principles to regulate the plurality of goods. There arent one or two fundamental
principles that govern the regulation of all social goods. The principle that is
appropriate for these different goods is determined by the social meaning of
the good in question. How we should distribute health care or education, for
example, will depend on what we take these goods to mean. We do not begin
with abstract principles and then simply apply them to these goods. In addition to criticizing the universalist aspirations of liberalism, Walzer puts forth
his own positive theory of distributive justice what he calls complex equality.
We shall examine the details of that account and some of the concerns that
have been raised against Walzers theory.
In section 5.5 we shall consider how the particularist approach advocated
by Walzer has been applied to the issue of nationalism by David Miller (1995).
If, as communitarians argue, we are social beings and this fact should inform
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 99
Communitarianism
99
our account of the demands of justice, then what are the implications of this
view for international justice? Does the fact that we inherit distinct national
identities justify our giving a priority to the interests of our compatriots over
those of non-nationals? If national boundaries do have ethical significance
what duties do we have to non-nationals and what justifies those duties?
Examining Millers argument will thus further illustrate the practical significance of the issues at stake in the liberalcommunitarian debate.
Liberals like Mill and Locke, claims Sandel, are committed to D1. Rawls is
also committed to D1. His critique of utilitarianism captures the moral sense
in which Rawls argues for the priority of justice. But Rawls is also committed, argues Sandel, to D2. This is what makes his version of liberalism, like
Kants moral philosophy, deontological. The priority of the right over the
good is, according to Sandels interpretation of deontology, an epistemological
and not merely moral claim. It claims that we can know what the right is
independently of the good.
If Rawlss theory of justice is derived independently of the good then one
must ask what his theory is premised on. Sandel claims that it is premised
on a particular conception of the self.
For justice to be the first virtue, certain things must be true of us. We must
be creatures of a certain kind, related to human circumstance in a certain
way. We must stand at a certain distance from our circumstance, whether as
transcendental subject in the case of Kant, or as essentially unencumbered
subject of possession in the case of Rawls. (Sandel, 1998: 175)
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
100
Page 100
Sandel points to two key aspects of Rawlss theory to support his claim that
Rawls relies on this unencumbered conception of the self: the original position and Rawlss direct argument for the second principle of justice. In the
original position the parties are mutually disinterested. The assumption of
mutual disinterest is not just a psychological assumption, argues Sandel, it is
also an epistemological claim. A claim about the forms of self-knowledge of
which we are capable (Sandel, 1998: 54). Sandel points to the following
passage from A Theory of Justice as evidence of this epistemological claim:
... I make no restrictive assumptions about the parties conceptions of the
good except that they are rational long-term plans. While these plans determine the aims and interests of a self, the aims and interests are not presumed
to be egoistic or selfish. Whether this is the case depends upon the kinds of
ends which a person pursues. If wealth, position, and influence, and the
accolades of social prestige are a persons final purposes, then surely his
conception of the good is egoistic. His dominant interests are in himself, not
merely, as they must always be, interests of a self. (Rawls, 1999: 111, emphasis added by Sandel)
The claim that interests are interests of a self, argues Sandel, shows that
Rawls conceives of the self as a subject of possession.
In so far as I possess something, I am at once related to it and distanced from
it. To say that I possess a certain trait or desire or ambition is to say that I am
related to it in a certain way it is mine rather than yours and also that I
am distanced from it in a certain way that it is mine rather than me.
(Sandel, 1998: 55)
What the liberal conception of the self cannot make sense of, argues
Sandel, is that some of our ends are constitutive ends, ends that we are bound
to even though we might not have voluntarily chosen them. He provides the
example of Robert E. Lee to illustrate this.3 On the eve of the American Civil
War Lee found himself in a dilemma as he was a Virginian and yet, as an
officer in the Union army, regarded secession as treason. When the Civil War
broke out he thus found his devotions pulled him in two directions. The
moral ties he felt to his native State were not ones he voluntarily chose, but
he felt bound by them nonetheless. His decision to fight for the South reflects
a quality we often admire in people. That quality is
the disposition to see and bear ones life circumstance as a reflectively situated being claimed by the history that implicates me in a particular life,
but self-conscious of its particularity, and so alive to other ways, wider horizons. But this is precisely the quality that is lacking in those who would
think of themselves as unencumbered selves, bound only by the obligations
they choose to incur. (Sandel, 1996: 16)
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 101
101
One might argue that Sandel misconstrues both the original position and
the argument from arbitrariness in order to support his interpretation of
deontological liberalism and there is some validity to this charge. Far from
being an argument about the dispossession of the self, the main issue that
the argument from arbitrariness addresses is how economic institutions are
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 102
102
The confusion concerning the role the unencumbered self plays in Rawlss
liberalism stems from the fact that Rawls actually posits diverse justifications
for his two principles of justice. Recall that Buchanan (1982) distinguishes
between the principles matching justification, the conditions matching argument
and the Kantian interpretation.5 The first two justifications would only appeal to
embedded persons, those who have the moral sensibilities that justice as fairness invokes. But the third justification supports Sandels position. One might
argue that this justification is not central to Rawlss position but Rawlss recent
shift to a political conception of justice suggests that even Rawls himself
believes that his early theory relies on the Kantian conception of the self.
Debates about the textual accuracy of Sandels interpretation of Rawlsian
liberalism should not detract one from the practical significance of Sandels
communitarian critique. In his second book, Democracys Discontent, Sandel
argues that this vision of the unencumbered self informs public debate in
contemporary America and that this has costly consequences. If American
constitutional law and debates about the political economy do appeal to the
unencumbered conception of the self and this undermines self-government
and community, as Sandel maintains, then liberals must take seriously his
communitarian critique.
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 103
103
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
104
Page 104
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 105
105
With the decline of community has come a decline in concern for the
common good. Politics, argues Sandel, needs to be concerned with restoring
civic spaces, places where people can engage in debate about the common
good, such as churches, schools and community centres. But this formative
ambition runs counter to the dictates of state neutrality. The neutral state is
not concerned with cultivating civic virtues. Respect for persons requires
respecting them as independent selves, unencumbered by moral or civic ties
they have not chosen. Thus contemporary liberalism cannot inspire a public
philosophy that can remedy the discontents of American politics.
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
106
Page 106
Further reading
George Sher, Beyond Neutrality: Per fectionism and Politics (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Harry Brighouse, Neutrality, Publicity, and State Funding of the Arts,
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 24 (1), 1995: 3663.
William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues and Duties in the Liberal
State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 107
Communitarianism
107
Like Nozick, Walzer is critical of theorists who treat goods as if they were
manna from the heavens.8 Before goods are distributed they are conceived
and created. Walzer wants to shift our attention from distribution itself to
conception and creation: the naming of the goods, and the giving of meaning, and the collective making (Walzer, 1983: 7). Each community creates it
own social goods and thus the list of goods governed by principles of distributive justice will differ from society to society. Walzer rejects the idea of
a single set of primary goods which are applicable across all moral and
material worlds. Even something as basic as food can have different meanings in different societies. Bread is the staff of life, the body of Christ, the
symbol of the Sabbath, the means of hospitality, and so on (Walzer, 1983: 8).
Walzer devotes whole chapters to a diverse list of goods which most
societies value, though the meanings of these goods differ from culture to
culture. These goods, in the order in which he addresses them are:
Membership
Security and welfare
Money and commodities
Office (i.e. positions of employment)
Hard work
Free time
Education
Kinship and love
Divine grace
Recognition
Political power.
What distributive principle(s) could cover such a diverse range of goods?
By making the theory of goods central to his account of distributive justice
Walzer effectively demonstrates his point that there is no single criterion, or
a single set of interconnected criteria, for all distributions. It is appropriate to
distribute some goods in accordance with the principle of free exchange (e.g.
money), others with desert (e.g. punishment and honours) and still others
with need (e.g. security and welfare). A determination of which distributive
criterion is just for each different good depends, argues Walzer, on the meaning of the social good itself. Take a social good like health care. Walzer notes
that, until recent times, the practice of medicine was mostly a matter of free
enterprise. Doctors were often attached to noble houses and royal courts and
thus the benefits of medical care were limited to an elite minority. But in
time our attitudes, and our institutions, changed. In contemporary liberal
societies the social understanding of health care prescribes some form of
communal care instead of a market regulation of medical care. We believe
that care should be provided according to need and not to wealth. Walzer
claims that among modern citizens, longevity is a socially recognized need;
and increasingly every effort is made to see that it is widely and equally
distributed, that every citizen has an equal chance at a long and healthy life:
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
108
Page 108
Amy Gutmann (1995) expresses a similar concern when she argues that the
social meanings of some goods are multiple and the multiple meanings
sometimes conflict. Gutmann considers the example of productive employment in America. One meaning of the good productive employment means
careers, and thus the appropriate distributive criterion would be careers
open to talent. The relevant consideration that should govern the distribution of careers should be the qualifications of the candidates. But, argues
Gutmann, people also need productive employment in order to live a decent
life in our society, where the decency of our lives includes our being
respected by our fellow citizens, being treated as equals (Gutmann, 1995:
103). This need standard competes with the qualification standards. The
resolution of these competing distributive principles cannot be solved by
deciding what jobs really means in our society. In order to resolve this kind
of conflict Gutmann argues that we must bring in moral considerations, considerations that go beyond the social meanings of the good in question.
The concerns expressed by Dworkin and Gutmann raise serious problems
for the viability of Walzers interpretive approach. Another concern critics
raise is the relativistic and conservative consequences of Walzers position.
If we are to turn to existing conventions for guidance on what the appropriate distributive criteria are does this not simply legitimize the status quo? On
what basis can we even criticize our own conventions let alone those of
authoritarian regimes? Justice, argues Dworkin, is our critic and not our mirror and thus Walzers relativism is faithless to the single most important
social practice we have: the practice of worrying about what justice is
(Dworkin, 1985: 219). But surprisingly, the main focus of Spheres of Justice is
actually the development of a radical account of distributive justice called
complex equality. Let us briefly consider this account as it will reveal the
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 109
109
Complex equality
Despite the obvious relativistic and conservative implications of Walzers
particularist methodology he actually defends a theory of distributive justice
that is very radical. He calls this theory complex equality. Each social good
represents a distinct sphere of justice and complex equality obtains when
No citizens standing in one sphere or with regard to one social good can be
undercut by his standing in some other sphere, with regard to some other
good. Thus, citizen X may be chosen over citizen Y for political office, and
then the two of them will be unequal in the sphere of politics. But they will
not be unequal generally so long as Xs office gives him no advantages over
Y in any other sphere superior medical care, access to better schools for his
children, entrepreneurial opportunities, and so on. (Walzer, 1983: 19)
Walzers ideal of complex equality could be utilized to criticize many different aspects of Western democratic societies. Walzers concern with nondomination, for example, is well suited to feminism which is concerned with
male dominance. This issue will be more fully addressed in Chapter 8. But
let us briefly consider Walzers comments on the family for they reveal what
is a fundamental tension between Walzers methodology and his normative
conclusions.
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 110
110
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 111
111
as unencumbered selves and little attention is paid to the fact that social
goods have different meanings for different communities. The particularist
approach advocated by communitarians has significant implications for not
only domestic justice, but also for the way we conceive of global justice. The
liberal aspiration for universalism has led some, such as Beitz, to proclaim
that the demands of justice should apply globally and thus we are not justified in giving preferential treatment to compatriots. Beitzs argument is a
form of ethical universalism. Ethical universalism maintains that all persons
ought to be treated with equal and impartial consideration for their respective goods or interests (Gewirth, 1988: 283). National boundaries have no
significant ethical relevance for ethical univeralists because considerations
such as ones nationality are irrelevant to the issue of what we owe to each
other. If person X is suffering and will die without my intervention the fact
that person X is not a compatriot is irrelevant. They are a human being, and
that is sufficient for saying that I have a duty to aid them.
Ethical particularists do not deny that we have some duties to non-nationals,
but they defend a competing account of the structure of ethical life. As David
Miller puts it, ethical particularists hold that relations between persons are
part of the basic subject-matter of ethics, so that fundamental principles may
be attached directly to these relations (Miller, 1995: 50). Relations such as the
fact that person X is my brother or a compatriot play a significant role in
determining how much consideration I ought to (and can) place on person
X. Ethical particularism, argues Miller, treats agents as already encumbered
with a variety of ties and commitments to particular other agents, or to
groups or collectivities, and they begin their ethical reasoning from those
commitments (Miller, 1995: 50). Miller defends ethical particularism and
applies it to the issue of nationalism. Let us consider some of the details of
Millers argument for nationalism as it will further illustrate the practical
significance of the communitarian critique of liberalism.
Miller argues that national boundaries are ethically significant. The duties
we owe to our compatriots may be more extensive than the duties we owe
to strangers, simply because they are compatriots (Miller, 1988: 647).
Millers defence of nationalism rests on three interconnected propositions.
These are:
1 It may properly be part of someones identity that they belong to this or
that national grouping.
2 Nations are ethical communities.
3 People who form a national community have a good claim to political
self-determination (Miller, 1995: 1011).
Let us briefly consider each of these in some detail. The first proposition
divides into two further propositions, one more contentious than the other.
The non-contentious claim is that nations really exist. Miller distinguishes
between a nation and a state. These two terms are often used synonymously
but it is important to distinguish between them. A state is a body that
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
112
Page 112
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 113
113
why not subject the members of these states to benign outside rule? ... Why
make a fetish of self-government if your basic rights will be better protected
by outsiders? (Miller, 1995: 78)
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
114
Page 114
their obliteration an intelligent goal (Miller, 1995: 184). Thus the humanitarian
sentiment that every human being should matter equally to us is unrealistic.
But despite this obvious difference between Miller and Beitz, Millers ethical
particularism does recognize a diverse array of duties that states must fulfil
if they are to take the principle of national self-determination seriously.
Millers argument shows that one need not invoke a vision of global citizenship in order to generate international duties. But ethical universalists will
charge that these duties are not stringent enough. By permitting us to place
greater concern on our compatriots the duties entailed even by the principle
of national self-determination can be undermined. If, for example, the obligation to ensure a fair distribution of natural resources means that the richest
countries will have to give to the poor countries to such a degree that the
quality of life in the richest countries would decline, nationalists can simply
ignore this duty by claiming that duties to their compatriots trump those
they owe to non-nationals. This is why Beitz criticizes Rawls for limiting the
difference principle to the domestic realm. While the difference principle
appears to be very egalitarian, by limiting its application to the domestic
sphere it has costly consequences for the most disadvantaged in the world.
The challenge facing nationalists like Miller is to provide an account of when
the redistributive duties entailed by the principle of national self-determination
can override the special duties we have to compatriots. Many would argue
that the disparity between the standards of living in the richest and poorest
countries stems from the fact that members of the rich countries place too
much weight on their national identification, to the detriment of those who
live in extreme poverty.
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 115
115
5.6 Conclusion
Assessing the liberalcommunitarian debate is difficult as liberals and
communitarians advance many different claims, some of which are more
compatible than others. The invocation of the ideal of community can mean
different things and thus it can sometimes be used to inspire an emancipatory public philosophy or be used to legitimize repressive customs and traditions. Those attracted to communitarianism see its potential to achieve the
former whilst those critical of communitarianism believe it cannot escape the
tendency of the latter.
Andrew Mason (2000) makes a number of useful distinctions that are
worth bearing in mind when assessing the liberalcommunitarian debate.
The first distinction is that between a mere association of people and the
ordinary concept of community. A mere association consists of people who
interact with one another primarily on a contractual basis, in order to further
their own self-regarding interests (Mason, 2000: 20). This contrasts with the
ordinary concept of community. A community is constituted by a group of
people who share a range of values, a way of life, identify with the group
and its practices and recognize each other as members of that group
(Mason, 2000: 21). Of the different versions of liberalism examined in Part
One of this present book, Gauthiers contractarian project relies on a mere
association of people and not a community. What binds utility-maximizers
to the dictates of minimax relative concession is their concern for their own
self-interest, not shared values or a way of life. Nor do these individuals
recognize each other as members of a group when they only extend
membership in the cooperative enterprise to those who can fulfil the requirements of the reciprocity thesis. Of the different versions of liberalism we
have examined Gauthiers is the most susceptible to the charge that it
neglects or undermines community.
The charge that the liberalisms of Rawls, Nozick or Dworkin undermine
community is arguably harder to establish. This is due to the fact that, as
Mason points out, the moralized concept of community includes the additional conditions that there be solidarity between its members and no
systematic exploitation. These additional conditions are subject to different
interpretations. Nozick could argue that his minimal state fulfils these two
further conditions of community. The Kantian dictum on which Nozick
premises his entitlement theory treat individuals as ends-in-themselves
and never as a means only requires members to give each others interests
some non-instrumental weight. So citizens who internalize that dictum have
a sense of solidarity. Furthermore, Nozick would argue that by ruling out
redistributive policies the minimal state ensures that there will be no systematic exploitation. Such exploitation exists when the state forces people,
through taxation, to support the policies of, for example, the welfare state.
Many people would challenge Nozicks conception of both solidarity and
exploitation and thus argue that his moralized conception of community is
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
116
Page 116
SUMMARY
Sandel argues that contemporary liberal theory is premised on the unencumbered conception of the self and that this conception of the self gives
rise to a public philosophy that undermines self-government and a sense of
community. He cites examples ranging from the regulation of freedom of
expression to debates about the political economy to illustrate the costly
consequences of state neutrality.
In Spheres of Justice Walzer criticizes the abstract, universalist approach liberals take to the issue of distributive justice. Walzer rejects the idea that
there is a single set of primary goods which are applicable across different
societies. Despite the obvious relativistic and conservative implications of
Walzers methodology he actually endorses a radical conception of justice
entitled complex equality.
Miller defends a version of nationalism that is premised on the communitarian insight that agents are encumbered with a variety of ties and commitments to particular agents or to groups or collectivities. Miller argues,
contra ethical univeralists, that national boundaries are ethically significant.
This has important ramifications for determining what the demands of international justice are.
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Communitarianism
Page 117
117
Notes
1 Other important communitarians include Charles Taylor (1985, 1990) and Alisdair
MacIntyre (1981). There is a vast literature on the liberalcommunitarian debate.
For a comprehensive examination of the main theorists in this debate see Mulhall
and Swift (1992).
2 References to this work are to the second edition published in 1998.
3 See Democracys Discontent, pp. 1516.
4 See Thomas Pogges Realizing Rawls (1989), Chapter 2, for extensive criticism of
Sandels argument.
5 See section 1.8 in Chapter 1 of this book.
6 George Sher (1997) provides a more expansive account of the reasons why
liberals endorse neutrality. These are:
1
2
3
7 Many political theorists have recently turned to the republican tradition to offer
an alternative to contemporary liberalism. See, for example, Pettit (1997) and
Dagger (1997).
8 But, as will become apparent shortly, Walzer does not endorse Nozicks
libertarianism.
9 See David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature and David Miller (1981).
Farrelly Ch-05.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 118
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 119
Multiculturalism
Summary Contents
6.1
6.2
6.3
6.4
119
122
127
131
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
120
Page 120
The liberal theories of justice canvassed in Part One ignore the fact that
many modern democratic societies are multinational and/or polyethnic. The
former are states that have incorporated previously self-governing cultures
such as aboriginal peoples whilst the latter are states where cultural diversity arises from immigration. Canada is an example of a country that is both
multinational and polyethnic. It has national minorities (such as aboriginal
peoples and the Qubcois) as well as a significant immigrant population.
The politics of equal citizenship and economic redistribution are not fully
equipped, argue multiculturalists, to deal with the diverse concerns which
are raised in multinational and polyethnic states. Multiculturalists thus
endorse the politics of recognition (Taylor, 1993) which inspires a public
philosophy premised on the concepts of identify and difference instead of
the principle of equal citizenship. The politics of recognition does, like the
politics of equal citizenship, have a universal basis but that basis is not that
everyone should be treated the same. On the contrary, the politics of recognition requires that everyone should be recognized for his or her unique
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 121
121
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
122
Page 122
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 123
123
From childhood on, we become aware both that we are already participants
in certain forms of life (familial, religious, sexual, educational, etc.), and that
there are other ways of life which offer alternative models and roles that we
may, in time, come to endorse. We decide how to lead our lives by situating
ourselves in these cultural narratives, by adopting roles that have struck us
as worthwhile ones, as ones worth living (which may, of course, include the
roles we were brought up to occupy). (Kymlicka, 1989a: 165)
The cultural structure of our society determines the context of choice that
autonomous individuals can chose from when deciding what sort of lives to
pursue. The list of occupations that one is free to choose from, for example,
will be determined by the cultural characteristics of ones society. For example,
making a living being a computer analyst, farmer, cosmetic surgeon or
shepherd are only real options in societies that have the requisite cultural
characteristics. The option of making a living being a shepherd is not on the
list of options open to individuals growing up in the hustle and bustle of
urban life in New York City. Because cultural heritage is inextricably linked
to our autonomy and self-respect liberals ought to pay greater attention to it,
argues Kymlicka. He suggests that cultural membership be treated as one of
Rawlss primary goods. Recall that these are goods every rational person is
presumed to have an interest in. The rational parties in the original position
would have an interest in cultural membership because they have an interest in leading a good life. The ability to lead a good life is impaired when one
does not enjoy cultural membership because the options open to one are
alien or at least are much more narrow than the options open to individuals
who enjoy cultural membership. Imagine how different the life prospects of
the parties in the original position would be if, once the veil of ignorance was
lifted, it turned out that the dominant culture of their society communicated
in a different language and valued ways of life radically different from the
ones they had grown up with. Let us expand on this point by turning to the
second part of Kymlickas argument for minority self-government rights.
The second stage of Kymlickas argument is to establish the point that
members of minority cultural communities may face particular kinds of disadvantages (with respect to the good of cultural membership) and that these
disadvantages require and justify the provision of minority rights. To make
this point Kymlicka suggests we revisit Dworkins auction tale of the shipwrecked survivors on the desert island. But Kymlicka slightly modifies the
example. Instead of survivors from one ship being washed up on a desert
island Kymlicka asks us to image two ships, one large and one small, are
shipwrecked on the island and the passengers of the two ships proceed with
Dworkins auction without ever leaving their ships.3 Once all of the islands
resources have been bid on, and the conditions of the envy test satisfied, the
passengers from the two ships disembark eager to start utilizing the different resources they have acquired. But it turns out that the two ships are from
different nationalities. The passengers from the small ship now find themselves in a disadvantaged position.
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
124
Page 124
The members of the minority culture are now in a very undesirable position.
Assuming, as is reasonable, that their resources are distributed evenly across
the island, they will now be forced to try to execute their chosen lifestyles in
an alien culture e.g. in their work, and, when the state superstructure is
built, in the courts, schools, legislatures, etc. (Kymlicka, 1989a: 188)
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 125
125
the good of cultural membership for some other good (for example,
economic prosperity).
The case of refugees represents an interesting case for Kymlickas argument. Unlike immigrants, refugees do not have the option of staying in their
original culture (without jeopardizing their safety). So the cultural inequality they experience when they move to a foreign culture stems from circumstances beyond their control. But justice does not require, argues Kymlicka,
that refugees be treated as national minorities. Long-term refugees do suffer
an injustice but this injustice was committed by their home government,
and it is not clear that we can realistically ask host governments to redress it
(Kymlicka, 1995a: 99). The best refugees could hope for is to be treated as
immigrants.
Both liberals and multiculturalists could raise concerns against Kymlickas
argument for minority rights. As Kymlicka (1989a: ch. 13) notes, apartheid is
the most common example used by critics of minority rights. White South
Africans could justify limiting the rights of black South Africans on the
grounds that this is necessary to protect the culture of white South Africans.
Thus talk of minority rights could be used to conceal unjust racist policies.
Kymlicka notes that one cannot deny the prima facie applicability of minority rights to white South Africans. But he argues that the actual policies of
apartheid are not justified by the argument he develops. Petty apartheid
(segregation in washrooms, swimming pools, etc.), for example, could not be
justified on his account of minority rights as such measures do not aim at
cultural security but rather are premised on blatant racism (Kymlicka, 1989a:
246). Furthermore, the land claims of white South Africans (to the majority
of land) and the policy of forcing the remaining population into discrete
homelands against their will violate both the principles of equal respect and
equalizing cultural circumstances that inform Kymlickas liberal defence of
minority rights. Thus Kymlicka believes that endorsing minority rights will
not lead to justifying blatantly unjust policies like apartheid.
Liberals may feel uneasy about endorsing self-government rights for
national minorities for fears that this will encourage secession and thus
threaten the social unity needed to keep society stable. Kymlicka acknowledges that these fears are valid given that the sense of being a distinct nation
within a larger country is potentially destabilizing (Kymlicka, 1995a: 192).
However, he argues that denying national minorities these rights is also
destabilizing and perhaps more likely to lead to secession as national
minorities will feel resentful that the dominant culture refused to accommodate their concerns. Thus liberals cannot escape concerns about social unity.
The important question is what poses the greatest threat to instability
granting or refusing self-government rights?
Multiculturalists have criticized Kymlickas liberal defence of minority
rights. Parekh, for example, questions Kymlickas claim that immigrants
waive the right to live by their culture when they leave their country of
origin. Since culture is for Kymlicka a primary good, it is difficult to see how
one can abandon ones right to it any more than to ones life or liberty
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
126
Page 126
(Parekh, 2000: 103). Furthermore, Parekh does not believe that Kymlickas
liberal justification of minority rights is fair to nonliberal cultures because it
does not respect them in their authentic otherness (Parekh, 2000: 108).
Aboriginal peoples are not the immigrants of the small ship envisioned in
the Dworkinian tale and by characterizing the demands of multinationals in
this way Parekh believes that Kymlickas approach to cultural diversity is
deficient. Kymlickas liberal defence of minority rights is an instrumental
approach to cultural diversity as the real concern behind valuing cultural
diversity is the concern for autonomy. But this public philosophy will not
express true concern for people of culturally diverse societies, argue Parekh.
Respect for a person ... involves locating him against his cultural background, sympathetically entering into his world of thought, and interpreting
his conduct in terms of its system of meaning (Parekh, 2000: 2401).
Kymlickas argument does not require this. Respect for minority rights is
premised on the modified Dworkinian hypothetical shipwreck tale and the
egalitarian liberals aspiration to achieve an ambition-sensitive/endowmentinsensitive distribution.4
Charles Taylor argues that Kymlickas argument fails to recapture the
actual demands made by the groups concerned, such as aboriginal peoples.
Taylor claims:
Kymlickas reasoning is valid (perhaps) for existing people who find themselves trapped within a culture under pressure, and can flourish within it or
not at all. But it doesnt justify measures designed to ensure survival
through indefinite future generations. For the populations concerned, however, that is what is at stake. (Taylor, 1993: 41 note 16)
Taylors criticism seems valid if one considers what Kymlicka says about
the children of parents who emigrate. Kymlicka claims that it is important
that governments should strive to make the children of immigrants feel at
home in the mainstream culture, to feel that it is their culture (Kymlicka,
1995a: 216 note 19). But one can then ask why should we not support the
same policy for the children of national minorities? While existing, adult
members of these minority groups face the disadvantage of being unequal in
cultural circumstances, a policy of assimilating that minority culture would
ensure such inequalities are not passed on to future generations. So why
should society not pursue a policy of assimilating national minorities if that
will eliminate inequality in cultural circumstances in the long term rather
than implement permanent minority rights for the sake of the existing generation? Concerns about cultural inequality, like those concerning economic
inequality, are complicated by considerations of both intragenerational and
intergenerational justice and these considerations must be addressed when
considering what particular policy we should endorse concerning the efforts
to mitigate cultural inequalities.
The discussion of Kymlickas defence of minority rights in this section
has focused only generally on the issue of self-government rights but the
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 127
Multiculturalism
127
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
128
Page 128
individuals had to make a choice that members of other religious groups did
not have to make that between adhering to their religious beliefs (which
involve wearing a turban) or travelling by motorcycle. But liberals would
deny that such a law is unequal. According to the liberal vision of equal
citizenship there is no inequality here as all citizens enjoy the same rights.
The helmet law is not discriminatory because it does not explicitly declare
that Sikhs shall not ride motorcycles. What prevents a Sikh from riding a
motorcycle is his religion and not the law, liberals will retort.5
But the helmet law was amended in 1976 and Sikhs were exempted from
wearing helmets. Multiculturalists believe this change to the law was the
right thing to do. The turban met the appropriate safety standards and thus
it was deemed an adequate substitute for the helmet. Since the justification
for requiring motorcyclists to wear a helmet was concerns for their safety
and wearing a turban also satisfies that aim then there is no reason not to
permit turban-wearing Sikhs to be excluded from the law. Such a measure is
a way of accommodating cultural diversity; it locates individuals against
their cultural background and shows respect for the different beliefs and
practices citizens of a pluralistic society have.
Similar concerns arise in the case of humane slaughter regulations. Many
countries have passed legislation requiring the humane slaughter of animals
for consumption (for example, stunning the animals prior to killing them).
Most Western countries have exemptions from humane slaughter regulations so that Jews and Muslims can slaughter animals in accordance with
traditional methods that violate the procedures for humane slaughter. Are
such exemptions justified? Multiculturalists argue that such exemptions are
necessary as they show respect for the importance of the religious practices
of Orthodox Jews and observant Muslims. This issue is more complex than
the case of exemptions from motorcycle helmets, as granting an exemption
in the case of the latter was seen as consistent with the aim of the legislation
(safety). But in the case of humane slaughter regulations the aim is to minimize the suffering of animals and permitting ritual slaughters6 is not consistent with that aim. Unlike the helmet law example, where the aim of public
safety could be achieved by having an exemption to the rule, in the case of
humane slaughter regulations we have competing aims minimize the
suffering of animals or tolerate religious practices of butchery. Multiculturalists
argue that such exemptions are a reasonable compromise between these two
aims. Such a measure shows respect for the value some people place on
religion. But the difficulty with this position is deciding where to draw the
line. If respect for custom can override the aim of protecting animal welfare
when it comes to slaughtering them then why not permit something like
cockfighting? Furthermore, customs change and if one truly believes that
humane slaughter regulations promote an important interest then one will
not view exemptions from these regulations as a reasonable compromise. As
Barry notes, it is hard to see why some cows and sheep should have to suffer in ways that are unacceptable generally in order to enable people with
certain religious beliefs to eat their carcasses (Barry, 2001: 43).
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 129
129
Eventually it was ruled that pupils could wear discreet religious symbols
(such as the cross) but not ostentatious symbols which in themselves constitute elements of proselytism or discrimination (cited in Parekh, 2001: 250)
and the hijab was deemed to fall into this latter category and thus banned.
The headscarves affair deeply divided the French, as different positions were
taken with respect to the importance of symbolic significance. As Parekh
notes, the main opposition to permitting the wearing of the hijab was that it
went against the principle of secularism, which is part of the French identity.
To become French one must integrate, and the school is a central mechanism
by which people are assimilated into French culture. But Parekh criticizes the
French decision, claiming that the decision to permit the cross and other
Christian symbols but not the hijab amounted to treating Muslim girls
unequally (Parekh, 2000: 253). Furthermore, the belief that the hijab symbolizes and reinforces female subordination, which Parekh argues was popular
among most secular Frenchmen and feminists, fails to appreciate the complex processes of social change and intercultural negotiation [which the
hijab] symbolized and triggered (Parekh, 2000: 254). Parekh argues:
Muslim immigrants in France, Britain and elsewhere are deeply fearful of
their girls entering the public world including the school. By wearing the
hijab their daughters seek to reassure them that they can be culturally
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
130
Page 130
trusted and will not be corrupted by the norms and values of the school.
At the same time they also reshape the semi-public world of the school and
protect themselves against its pressures and temptations by subtly getting
white and Muslim boys to see them differently to the way they eye white
girls. The hijab puts the girls out of bounds and enables them to dictate
how they wish to be treated. Traditional at one level, the hijab is transgressive at another, and enables Muslim girls to transform both their parental
and public cultures. (Parekh, 2000: 2534)
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 131
Multiculturalism
131
be going on, argues Levy. The liberalism of fear helps explain what this
something is. The restrictions on Turkish names is historically and intentionally linked with violence and cruelty toward excluded communities.
Such a policy represents a much greater threat to peace and justice than the
policy which disallows Princes name change. Levys point is that it is
important to take into consideration the significance people place on their
ethnic identities and practices, not because these things should be accorded
significant moral weight, but because doing so will help us avoid violence
(such as inter-ethnic civil wars), cruelty and political humiliation.
The cases of exemptions from motorcycle helmet laws, humane slaughter
regulations and the regulations of dress in both schools and the workplace8
are a few examples of the difficult cases polyethnic states face. Multiculturalists utilize these examples, and the fact that many state symbols such
as flags and anthems reflect a particular ethnic or religious background, to
show that the claim that the state and ethnicity are (or can be) separated
is a myth. The public philosophy inspired by contemporary liberalism is
difference-blind (Taylor, 1993: 62) and thus ill-equipped to resolve the difficulties that arise in multicultural societies. In the following section we conclude our discussion of multiculturalism by considering some of the liberal
objections that have been raised against multiculturalism.
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
132
Page 132
of the culture of Orthodox Jews and observant Muslims that they butcher
animals in a way that contravenes those regulations. But this kind of reasoning provides grounds for justifying unjust historical practices (such as slavery)
as well as falsely assuming that human beings do not have a capacity for
cultural adaptation. Culture is no excuse, argues Barry.
If there are sound reasons against doing something, these cannot be
trumped by saying even if it is true that doing it is part of your culture.
The fact that you (or your ancestors) have been doing something for a long
time does nothing in itself to justify your continuing to do it. ... If slaveowners in the South had had access to the currently fashionable vocabulary,
they would doubtless have explained that their culture was inextricably
linked with the peculiar institution and would have complained that abolitionists failed to accord them recognition. But this simply illustrates that
the appeal to culture establishes nothing. Some cultures are admirable,
others are vile. Reasons for doing things that can be advanced within the
former will tend to be good, and reasons that can be advanced within the
latter will tend to be bad. But in neither case is somethings being part of
the culture itself a reason for doing anything. (Barry, 2001: 258)
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 133
133
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Page 134
134
Further reading
Brian Barry, Culture and Equality (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press,
2001).
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
Multiculturalism
Page 135
135
SUMMARY
Multiculturalist critics of liberalism argue that the liberalisms of the distributive
paradigm do not take cultural plurality seriously enough. Thus the politics of equal
citizenship and redistribution is ill-equipped to tackle the myriad of issues that
arise in multinational and polyethnic societies. Taylors politics of recognition
requires that everyone be recognized for his or her unique identity.
Kymlicka provides a liberal defence of minority rights. He emphasizes the importance cultural membership has for the values of autonomy and self-respect.
National minorities face disadvantages (with respect to the good of cultural membership) that members of the majority culture do not face and thus they should be
compensated for these unchosen inequalities. The appropriate form of compensation, argues Kymlicka, is the granting of minority rights.
Multiculturalists also defend polyethnic rights, such as granting special exemptions from humane slaughter regulations. Liberal critics like Barry argue that multiculturalists permit people to abuse culture by utilizing it as a defence of
reprehensible cultural practices. Furthermore, the emphasis on preserving group
identities leads to the systematic neglect of other causes of group disadvantage.
Notes
1
Farrelly Ch-06.qxd
11/5/03 2:34 PM
136
Page 136
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 137
Deliberative Democracy
Summary Contents
7.1
7.2
7.3
7.4
7.5
137
139
144
148
150
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
138
Page 138
Effective participation.
Equality in voting.
Gaining enlightened understanding.
Exercising final control over the agenda.
Inclusion of adults (Dahl, 1998: 38).2
Utilizing Dahls criteria of democracy will provide us with a useful introduction to the themes of deliberative democracy that we shall further
explore in the other sections of this chapter. In the next section will shall contrast deliberative democracy with the aggregative model of democracy
which will bring the first three criteria to the fore. While both models will
endorse the criterion of equality in voting, the aggregative model conceives
of voting as the primary political activity because it maintains that policy
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 139
Deliberative Democracy
139
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
140
Page 140
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 141
141
By engaging in deliberation with those we disagree with we are expressing a willingness to listen to others, to take their concerns seriously and to
find some common ground so that a just compromise can be achieved.
Gutmann and Thompson consider a number of contentious policy issues,
ranging from abortion and trade policy to welfare policy, to illustrate how
the deliberative process fosters enlightened understanding and moral
accommodation. But mutual respect does not mean that we must always
accept the claims of those we disagree with, but it does require that we
listen to their concerns and that we justify our decisions by appealing to
reasons we genuinely believe all reasonable persons could accept. Gutmann
and Thompson provide an example from public education to illustrate this
point. In 1983 the board of education in Hawkins County, Tennessee adopted
a basic reading series that was to be used in all public schools. The aim of
this reading curriculum was to teach both reading skills and the values of
democratic citizenship. But a group of fundamentalist Christian parents
asked that their children not be required to use the books on the curriculum.
The books conflicted with their religious convictions and the parents did not
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
142
Page 142
want their children to be exposed to other ways of life that conflict with what
the Bible says. Gutmann and Thompson identify the following specific parts
of the curriculum that the parents objected to:
The boards decision was justified, argue Gutmann and Thompson, because
the curriculum is a reasonable way for a public school system to teach democratic values. The reasons for rejecting the parents wish to have their children
exempted from the curriculum are thus public reasons, reasons that all parents,
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 143
143
regardless of their conception of the good, can reasonably accept. This is very
different from telling the parents that their objections are rejected simply
because the majority of parents do not share their concerns. Gutmann and
Thompson believe that the school boards decision to reject exemptions from
the reading curriculum was a reasonable policy, despite the fact that no actual
accommodation took place. Mutual respect does not mean that we must
always accept the claims of those we disagree with, but it does require that we
listen to their concerns and that we justify our decisions by appealing to
reasons we genuinely believe all reasonable persons could accept. We do not
reject their demands out of hand simply because they are in the minority.
By seeking terms of agreement that are acceptable to all, the deliberative
model of democracy better secures two of Dahls criteria for democracy
effective participation and enlightened understanding than does the
aggregative model of democracy. The emphasis on voting and bargaining,
which are the central political activities of the aggregative model, are
replaced by the emphasis on searching for a consensus, being open-minded
and respecting, and even accommodating, your opponents position. To
participate in the consensus-building process envisioned by deliberative
democrats is to engage in a transformative process.
Further reading
William Galston, Diversity, Toleration and Deliberative Democracy: Religious
Minorities and Public Schooling in Stephen Macedo (ed.), Deliberative
Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1999).
Amy Gutmann, Civic Education and Social Diversity, Ethics, 105 (3), 1995:
55779.
Stephen Macedo, Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural
Democracy. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
Eamonn Callan, Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
144
Page 144
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 145
145
should and should not determine what the principles of justice are. So one
concern that can be raised against the proceduralist conception of legitimacy
advocated by theorists like Habermas is that by subjecting the demands of
justice to the democratic process proceduralists run the risk of legitimizing
unjust outcomes. If the majority of citizens democratically decide to limit the
rights of a particular religious group, for example, then such a law must be
construed as legitimate by proceduralists because it was arrived at via a
democratic procedure. Constitutional democrats will thus want to qualify
Dahls fourth criterion of democracy by stipulating that the opportunity for
exercising final control over the agenda must be limited. If the legislature has
complete control over the political agenda then this could lead to unjust outcomes. Rights, argue constitutional democrats, have priority over the democratic process and a purely procedural conception of legitimacy violates this
requirement.
Deliberative democrats can respond to this kind of concern in a number of
different ways. They might argue that such an unjust outcome might occur
in a democratic process where legitimacy is simply equated with the will of
the majority in a show of hands vote but that is not what constitutes legitimacy for proceduralists like Habermas. In order for a law to be legitimate all
must be able to consent to it and the minority in question would obviously
not consent to such a measure. The idealizing requirements of Habermass
discourse ethics4 thus builds in protections for certain rights and opportunities that rule out the kind of repressive policy just mentioned. So even proceduralists like Habermas believe that it is necessary to build guarantees of
basic liberty and opportunity into the ideal conditions of deliberation. Such
measures are to be viewed as those necessary for a fair democratic process.
In his earlier work on discourse ethics Habermas lists the following as some
of the inescapable presuppositions of discourse:
(3.1) Every subject with the competence to speak and act is allowed to take
part in a discourse.
(3.2) a. Everyone is allowed to question any assertion whatever.
b Everyone is allowed to introduce any assertion whatever into the
discourse.
c. Everyone is allowed to express his attitudes, desires, and needs.
(3.3) No speaker may be prevented, by internal or external coercion, from
exercising his rights as laid down in (3.1) and (3.2) (Habermas, 1990: 89).
If the outcome of the deliberative decision-making process must meet
with the assent of all participants then these participants have a right to
express their views, challenge the claims of their opponents and have a say
in the final decision. To engage in the deliberative process is to seek a consensus and persuade your opponents by argumentation, not force or coercion. Thus by committing oneself to deliberation one is already implicitly
endorsing certain ethical principles, hence the reason why Habermas
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
146
Page 146
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 147
147
yet these principles themselves are not the outcome of any real democratic
process. For example, in What Sort of Political Equality Does Deliberative
Democracy Require? Jack Knight and James Johnson examine the different
kinds of equality deliberative democrats should endorse. They argue that
democratic deliberation requires equal opportunity of access to political influence (Knight and Johnson, 1997: 292). Because deliberative democrats are
concerned with the effects the social distribution of power has on effective
participation in the deliberative process they themselves are engaged in an
equality of what? debate in the same way that justice theorists are. And
thus the gulf between theoreticians of justice and democracy seems to
narrow significantly. Like justice theorists, deliberative democrats are concerned with the distribution of material resources. The resources individuals
command have an impact on their position in the deliberative process and
thus deliberative democrats must consider the effects the social distribution
of power and resources have on effective participation in the deliberative
process.
Even some proceduralists now endorse substantive principles. In
Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy Joshua Cohen, who
was influential in formulating the procedural account of democratic legitimacy, argues that deliberative democracy presupposes substantive principles. He argues that the deliberative view accommodates a principle of
participation the requirements of which are quite extensive.
According to that principle, democratic collective choice institutionalizing
the tie between deliberative justification and the exercise of public power
must ensure equal rights of participation, including rights of voting, association, and political expression, with a strong presumption against restrictions
on the content or viewpoint of expression; rights to hold office; a strong
presumption in favor of equally weighted votes; and a more general
requirement of equal opportunities for effective influence. This last requirement condemns inequalities in opportunities for office-holding and political
influence that result from the design of arrangements of collective decisionmaking. (Cohen, 1996: 1067)
Cohens claim that the principle of participation entails a strong presumption against restrictions on the content or viewpoint of expression is particularly interesting given that that is a rather specific claim about the content of
law that is derived, not from a Kantian conception of the self (recall Sandels
critique of neutrality in Chapter 5), but from the idea of democratic legitimacy. It thus looks as though deliberative democrats who endorse substantive principles of democracy end up sharing more common ground with
justice theorists like Rawls and Dworkin than one might have initially suspected given the formers desire to distance themselves from the armchair
theorizing of justice theorists. Both deliberative democrats and egalitarianliberals are concerned with basic liberties, equality of opportunity and
economic inequalities. But the reason deliberative democrats are concerned
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
148
Page 148
with these rights, opportunities and inequalities stems from their concern
with the principle of democratic legitimacy. Deliberative democrats are
concerned with economic inequality, for example, not because they believe
justice requires that we mitigate morally arbitrary factors or strive for an
ambition-sensitive/endowment-insensitive distribution, but because structural inequalities (such as social and economic power) threaten the ideal of
deliberative democracy itself.
Justice theorists could charge that deliberative democrats are simply
caught up in a logical circle. On the one hand these theorists do not want to
posit an account of distributive justice that would pre-empt the decisions of
the democratic process itself. Yet deliberative democrats do not wish to go
along with the outcomes of existing democratic arrangements as these are
ones that fail to live up to the idealizing requirements of deliberative democracy. So deliberative democrats endorse substantive principles (for example,
the principle of participation) that must be satisfied before the outcome of
the democratic process can be deemed legitimate yet it is exactly this kind of
armchair theorizing that democratic theorists criticize because it preempts
the real democratic process as those principles are not ones that people have
actually assented to.
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 149
149
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
150
Page 150
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 151
151
process could undermine the very aim it was designed to resolve. Namely,
to figure out where to go for dinner. The friends, who wish to be courteous
interlocutors and thus give each participant a chance to air their concerns,
could spend the whole night deliberating the pros and cons of the various
restaurants thus skipping dinner altogether! The transformative process of
deliberation can be very time-consuming and thus we must be able to say
that there comes a point when more deliberation would not resolve disagreements, in fact, it might make things worse. So how much deliberation
is enough? When does the virtue of efficiency, for example, trump the virtues
of deliberation? If we have to wait till a consensus emerges before decisions
can be deemed legitimate then we will never be able to make justified decisions about the pressing policy issues that face us in everyday politics, issues
ranging from the economy and health care provisions to the environment
and foreign policy.
The urgency to resolve some political disagreements thus threatens to
undermine the priority deliberative democrats place on the value of reasoning together. Environmentalists, for example, might welcome the opportunity to debate with their opponents the pros and cons of legislation that
aims to limit gas emissions harmful to the environment. However, if environmentalists believe that immediate action is necessary to avert ecological
disaster then they will view a prolonged discursive process as harmful, not
beneficial. Sometimes we simply cannot afford to pursue, let alone wait for,
a consensus to emerge before we act. Nor is it always possible to have a
genuine open debate on certain issues. As Daniel Bell (1999) notes, sound
foreign policy, for example, does not readily lend itself to open debate. This
point is very pertinent given the current debates about the war on terrorism
that have ensued in the wake of the terrorist attacks on September 11th, 2001.
Open and constructive debate requires public access to reliable information
but if this information is only available to military and political elites then
genuine debate on these issues will be hampered. To insist that this information be made public for the sake of having an open debate could compromise national security because it would reveal sensitive information (for
example, surveillance operations or tactics) that needs to remain secret for
reasons of national security. So by making deliberation the focus of their
account of politics, deliberative democrats run the danger of subordinating
other important values, such as efficiency and security. Deliberative democrats must make room for these other values if they are to avoid the criticism
that they ignore the potentially destructive effects of deliberation.
In order to avoid the pitfalls of deliberation Bell emphasizes the preconditions that make constructive moral deliberations more likely.7 One of these
preconditions is that deliberation is more likely to be effective if the political
culture values decision-making by intellectual elites. This is so, argues Bell,
because talented elites with the motivation and the ability to understand
and apply moral principles to complex political controversies with national
(and international) implications are more likely to engage in constructive
deliberations (Bell, 1999: 74). Bell claims that this is a relatively controversial
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
152
Page 152
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 153
153
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
154
Page 154
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Deliberative Democracy
Page 155
155
SUMMARY
Deliberative democrats conceive of the democratic process as a transformative
process, one that requires citizens to participate in authentic deliberation as
opposed to simply expressing their existing preferences. They thus reject the
aggregative model of democracy which conceives of voting as the primary political
act. Instead, deliberative democrats emphasize the importance of being openminded and respecting, and even accommodating, your opponents position.
Some deliberative democrats (e.g. Habermas) endorse purely procedural principles whilst others (e.g. Gutmann and Thompson) endorse substantive as well as
procedural principles. Concerns about the apparent assimilation to liberal constitutionalism have led some critical theorists to re-cast the idea of deliberative
democracy in a more critical light. For example, Dryzek defends what he calls
discursive democracy and Young communicative democracy.
In order to avoid the charges that deliberative democracy is potentially destructive
and/or utopian deliberative democrats must provide an account of how other
important values (e.g. efficiency, national security, etc.) are to be balanced against
concerns for open public debate. Furthermore, given the size of democratic
societies, deliberative democrats must address the concern that it is unrealistic
to think that we can have both deliberation and mass participation.
Notes
1 This is debatable, especially for Rawls and Dworkin, given Rawlss later writings
Political Liberalism (1993) and The Law of Peoples (1999) and Dworkins discussion
in Sovereign Virtue (2000) of the partnership conception of democracy.
2 When considering Dahls criteria for democracy it is important to bear in mind
that, as Iris Marion Young notes, democracy is not an all-or-nothing affair, but a
matter of degree; societies can vary in both the extent and the intensity of their
commitment to democratic practice (Young, 2000: 5). Dahl himself admits that in
the real world it is unlikely that every member of society will truly have equal
opportunities to participate or influence the agenda. But this does not render
these criteria useless. These criteria provide standards against which to measure
the performance of actual associations that claim to be democratic. They can serve
as guides for shaping and reshaping concrete arrangements, constitutions, and
political institutions (Dahl, 1998: 42).
3 See Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1999: 745).
4 See Habermas (1990, 1993).
5 In his later writings Habermas elaborates on the rights presupposed in his procedural model by claiming that the normative ideal of self-government, coupled
with the aim of regulating human interactions through the medium of law, gives
rise to five categories of rights. See Habermas (1996, ch. 3).
6 Habermas does this. See, for example, Habermass article Constitutional
Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles? (2001) where he
argues that constitutionalism and democracy are interdependent. But Gutmann
and Thompson (1996) believe that their account of deliberative democracy
transcends the dichotomy between procedural and constitutional democrats.
Farrelly Ch-07.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
156
Page 156
7 These are:
1
2
3
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 157
Feminism
Summary Contents
8.1
8.2
8.3
8.4
8.5
Introduction
Liberal feminism
The public/private dichotomy
The politics of difference
Conclusion
157
159
164
169
174
8.1 Introduction
As a political theory feminism covers a wide range of distinct issues and
concerns. Some feminists align themselves with liberalism whilst others see
liberalism as a thoroughly patriarchal ideology and thus they construct their
normative theories in response to what they take the deficiencies of liberalism to be. Depending on which version of feminism one endorses, feminism
may or may not be compatible with liberalism or other normative theories,
such as communitarianism or multiculturalism. What makes a political
theory feminist is the emphasis it places on eliminating the oppression of
women. Thus a liberal feminist believes that a liberal framework of rights,
correctly conceived, could put an end to the subordination of women whilst
a socialist feminist believes that class exploitation and gender exploitation
are interconnected and thus the latter could not be achieved without eliminating the former.
Feminists emphasize the fact that gender distinctions are socially constructed. Gender is the deeply entrenched institutionalization of sexual difference (Okin, 1989: 6). While it is an obvious biological fact that men and
women will necessarily be different in some respects (for example, only
women have the ability to give birth) many of the differences between men
and women stem from an unjust social structure. For example, it is women
who typically sacrifice their careers for parenthood, do the majority of
unpaid domestic work and are made vulnerable by the institution of
marriage. These differences between men and women do not stem from biological differences but from unequal power relations. Whilst feminists are
united in their concern for liberating women they adopt diverse theoretical
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
158
Page 158
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Feminism
Page 159
159
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
160
Page 160
Taught from infancy that beauty is womans sceptre, the mind shapes itself
to the body, and, roaming round its gilt cage, only seeks to adorn its prison.
Men have various employments and pursuits which engage their attention,
and give a character to the opening mind; but women, confined to one, and
having their thoughts constantly directed to the most insignificant part of
themselves, seldom extend their views beyond the triumph of the hour.
(Wollstonecraft, 1995: 116)
Liberal feminists like Wollstonecraft argue that women have the same
potential for rationality that men have and thus there is no reason why
women should not enjoy the same status that men enjoy. Liberal feminists
thus emphasis the equal worth of all human beings, male and female, when
theorizing about what kind of society we ought to be aspiring towards and
what changes are needed to bring us closer to this more humane arrangement. As equals women should be entitled to the same benefits that men
enjoy from social cooperation. Practices of sexual discrimination, for example, contravene the demands of our shared humanity. The arbitrary or irrational use of gender in the awarding of benefits or positions is unjust and
incompatible with liberalism in the same way that discrimination based on
race or a persons religious beliefs would be.
Some liberal feminists explicitly found their theory on more than our
shared humanity and believe that justice requires more than merely the elimination of sexual discrimination. In Sex and Social Justice, for example, Martha
Nussbaum defends a conception of feminism that has the following five
features it is internationalist, humanist, liberal, concerned with the social
shaping of preference and desire and concerned with sympathetic understanding. By considering the five features of Nussbaums conception of
feminism we shall see how liberal feminists can incorporate the concerns of
the oppression of women into a liberal political theory.
The first feature of Nussbaums feminism is that it is internationalist. This
means that it is a version of feminism that is informed by the fact that the
gender-related problems that women face will vary from society to society.
Feminists should not, argues Nussbaum, become inward looking and just
focus on the problems that women face in America or the United Kingdom.
While there are certain universal concerns that women face in all societies
(such as sexual harassment, rape, etc.) there are also important issues that
may be marginalized by focusing exclusively on the experiences of women
in the developed countries, issues like the denial of the right to work,
sex-selective infanticide and abortion and sex discrimination in religious
courts of family law.
The second feature of Nussbaums feminism is humanism, which emphasizes the equal worth of all human beings. Her conception of feminism is
thus a version of ethical universalism. Recall from Chapter 4 Millers contrast between ethical universalism and ethical particularism. Nussbaums
commitment to the former is evident when she says:
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 161
Feminism
161
The view developed here seeks justice for human beings as such, believing
all human beings to be fundamentally equal in worth. It also holds that
human beings have common resources and common problems wherever
they live, and that their special dilemmas can best be seen as growing out
of special circumstances, rather than out of a nature or identity that is
altogether unlike that of other humans. (Nussbaum, 1999: 7)
Life.
Bodily health.
Bodily integrity.
Senses, imagination, thought.
Emotions.
Practical reason.
Affiliation.
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
162
Page 162
8 Other species.
9 Play.
10 Control over ones environment (political and material). (Nussbaum,
1999: 412)
Nussbaums list of capabilities is similar to Rawlss list of primary goods
but Nussbaum believes that the capabilities approach is more attractive
because it includes more than Rawlss list and it is more definitive than the
goods Rawls identifies. Recall, for example, the way Rawls defines the least
advantaged members of society. He focuses exclusively on wealth and
income. But this neglects the fact that
people have varying needs for resources: a pregnant woman, for example,
needs more calories than a non-pregnant woman, a child more protein than
an adult. They also have different abilities to convert resources into functioning. A person in a wheelchair will need more resources to become
mobile than a person with unimpaired limbs; a woman in a society that has
defined employment outside the home as off limits to women needs more
resources to become a productive worker than one who does not face such
struggles. In short, the Rawlsian approach does not probe deeply enough to
show us how resources do or do not go to work in making people able to
function. (Nussbaum, 1999: 34)
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
Feminism
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 163
163
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
164
Page 164
subordination and those who suggest that womens ability to care for others
is part of a distinct moral ethic (that is, an ethic of care). In doing so
Nussbaum has the difficult task of combining a radical feminist critique of
sex relations with the possibilities of trust and understanding. Many feminists will remain sceptical about the possibilities of trust and understanding
given the existing inequalities between the sexes. If genuine trust and understanding is to exist between the sexes then we must take seriously, as Okin
(1989) argues, the justice of gender. This takes us into a discussion of the
feminist slogan the personal is political.
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
Feminism
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 165
165
Power, a distinguishing feature of the political, can exist within the family.
The domestic sphere itself is the result of political decisions.
Domestic life is where most of our early socialization takes place.
The division of labour within most families raises psychological as well
as practical barriers against women in all other spheres. (Okin, 1989:
12833)
The first point emphasizes the fact that power relations can and often do
exist within the family. Thus domestic and personal life cannot be beyond
the reach of the demands of justice as justice is primarily concerned with
power relations. If, for example, family life is such that a husband can beat
his wife without fear of punishment this would obviously be unjust. But all
liberals would agree with this first point. The rights of citizenship should
apply to all citizens, including women. By entering into marriage women do
not forfeit those rights. So the first way Okin employs the slogan the personal is political is likely to be supported by both liberals and feminists.
The second way the personal is political, argues Okin, is that the domestic
sphere is itself created by political decisions. The notion that family life is a
private sphere is a myth.
In innumerable ways, the state determines and enforces the terms of
marriage. For hundreds of years, the common law deprived women of their
legal personhood upon marriage. It enforced the rights of husbands to their
wives property and even to their wives bodies, and made it virtually
impossible for women to divorce or even to live separately from their
husbands. (Okin, 1989: 12930)
Okins second point is, once again, one that many liberals would and do
endorse. As we noted above, liberals like Barry point out that historically the
state has unjustly interfered in family life and that it has been liberals who
have been at the forefront of efforts to remove the legal disabilities against
women. It is thus perhaps more accurate to say that Okins first two points
are more problematic for communitarians and conservatives than liberals.
Recall Walzers appeal to shared social meanings. Such an appeal, when
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
166
Page 166
applied to something like the family, may make us blind to the structural
inequalities of our society that influence and shape the family. By invoking
the slogan the personal is political feminists are encouraging us to be wary
of appeals to tradition, or so-called family values, as such appeals often
ignore the fact that the domestic sphere is itself shaped by the political
sphere so inequalities in the latter can, and often are, translated into inequalities in the former.
The debate between liberals and feminists becomes more complicated once
we move on to consider the last two ways in which Okin believes the personal is political. These are the claims that domestic life is where most of our
early socialization takes place and that the division of labour within most
families raises psychological as well as practical barriers against women in all
other spheres. Okin argues that the family is an important formative influence that shapes the gendered selves we become. When girls are brought up,
for example, with the expectations that they will themselves become the
primary caregiver of children and/or that they are responsible for the domestic chores in the home then the existing gender structure is simply reinforced.
Okin argues that a just family is one which is internally regulated by the principles of justice. A humanist conception of justice is one that seeks genuine
equality between men and women in terms of the paid and unpaid work they
do, as well as their opportunities and obligations in general.
Many liberals have resisted Okins suggestion that we endorse the proposal to apply the principles of justice internally to the family. Rawls, for
example, while arguing that the principles of justice do impose essential
constraints on the family as an institution (for example, to guarantee basic
rights and liberties and fair opportunities), rejects the suggestion that they
should apply directly to the internal life of the family. Such a proposal is,
argues Rawls, out of place (Rawls, 2001: 165). At some point, he continues,
society has to trust to [sic] the natural affection and goodwill of parents
(Rawls, 2001: 165). But this suggestion will not ease the concerns of feminists, who would retort that there is no basis for granting the trust Rawls
speaks of. Parents may genuinely love and care for their children but unwittingly reinforce gender structures by continuing the cycle of gendered
socialization that they were themselves brought up in.
Some critics of Okin seek to undermine her argument by pushing her on
the issue of what it would mean to say that the family should be regulated
by the principles of justice. Stephen de Wijze (2000), for example, argues that
Okins proposal would violate pluralism as there would not be just one way
of justly arranging the family.
A family may organise the division of labour according to who likes various
tasks; one person loves shopping and cooking while the other prefers
bathing, dressing and ferrying children to their various activities. Another
family may divide labour according to who is the most competent at doing
the various tasks, while another may decide that a just division is made
according to shared religious beliefs about the roles of men and women in
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
Feminism
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 167
167
the family. In all these examples, the division of labour within the family is
not necessarily equal but each has a plausible sense of justice and fairness
motivating who does what and why. (De Wijze, 2000: 279)
But once again feminists are not going to find this liberal response
compelling. Firstly, the reality is that most women, even those that work outside the home, do by far the majority of unpaid labour in the home. Okin
estimates that fully employed husbands do, at most, approximately half as
much as their fully employed wives, and some studies show a much greater
discrepancy (Okin, 1989: 153). Secondly, De Wijzes appeal to the existing
preferences women and men have for dividing domestic labour is problematic because those very preferences have themselves been shaped by a
gendered social structure. De Wijzes description of how men and women
decide on dividing domestic chores presupposes a version of the unencumbered self that communitarians have criticized. Consider, for example, De
Wijzes last point, the scenario where a couple decide to divide domestic
chores in accordance with shared religious beliefs about the roles of women
and men. According to De Wijze, if these religious roles say that a woman
should do most (if not all) of the domestic labour then this is not unfair or
unjust because she has voluntarily chosen that end. But if we recognize, as
communitarians have argued, that we are embedded selves, then we will not
be as quick as De Wijze is to describe this family arrangement as being plausibly justice or fair. The women who supposedly consent to taking on the
bulk of domestic chores are simply fulfilling the social roles they have been
encouraged (or even compelled) to take on since birth.
De Wijzes argument is further undermined once one recognizes that what
counts as a fair division of paid and unpaid work between women and men
will reflect biased judgements about the worth of paid and unpaid work. As
Okin points out, a husbands income and job prestige are inversely related to
his involvement in household chores (Okin, 1989: 153). When society places
great value on paid employment and undervalues unpaid domestic labour,
then these attitudes will also distort what constitutes a fair division of
labour between family members. A husband who brings in a large income
and/or has a prestigious job is likely to be judged as doing his fair share (or
even more than his fair share) and thus be exempt from domestic chores. The
problem is that gender inequalities have tainted attitudes concerning the
value of the different kinds of work that need to be done. De Wijzes appeal
to existing attitudes concerning what constitutes a fair division of work is
thus a non-starter because it merely reinforces the status quo and thus does
not effectively address the unjust power relationships between men and
women.
If we find Okins argument compelling then the important practical question is What is to be done? What, exactly, does taking the slogan the personal is political entail in terms of public policy? Critics will charge that the
slogan gives licence to totalitarianism as there is thus no domain which is
safe from state interference. But such a concern presupposes that feminists
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
168
Page 168
seek to completely abolish the public/private distinction. But this is not so.
What they seek to do is redefine where the divide between the public and
private is. By doing this we expand the domain which the principles of
justice must apply to. They apply to the family in the way liberals like Barry
and Rawls acknowledge (for example, guarantee basic rights to all family
members) but they also apply within the family. But what would this actually mean? We cannot police the family, ensuring that men and women do
an equal share of paid and unpaid labour. One suggestion Okin makes is to
have employers make out wage checks equally divided between the earner
and the partner who provides all or most of his or her unpaid domestic
services (Okin, 1989: 181). This would alter the power relations in the family
by giving some public recognition to the fact that unpaid labour is just as
important as paid labour. This would make a significant difference to the
power relations within the family, argues Okin.
It would make a difference in cases where the earning or higher-earning
partner now directly exploits his power, by refusing to make significant
spending decisions jointly, by failing to share the income, or by psychologically or physically abusing the nonearning or low-earning partner, reinforced by the notion that she (almost always the wife) has little option but
to put up with such abuse or to take herself and her children into a state of
destitution. It would make a difference, too, in cases where the higherearning partner indirectly exploits this earning power in order to perpetuate the existing division of labor in the family. In such instances considerable
changes in the balance of power would be likely to result from the legal and
societal recognition that the partner who does most of the domestic work of
the family contributes to its well-being just as much, and therefore rightly
earns just as much, as the partner who does most of the workplace work.
(Okin, 1989: 181)
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 169
Feminism
169
children, direct government subsidies (not tax credits, which benefit the
better-off) should make up the difference between the cost of high-quality
day care and what less well-paid parents could reasonably be expected to
pay. (Okin, 1989: 17677)
Further reading
Susan Okin, Justice, Gender and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989).
Joan Landes (ed.), Feminism, the Public and the Private (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1998).
Chris Armstrong and Judith Squires, Beyond the Public/Private Dichotomy:
Relational Space and Sexual Inequalities, Contemporary Political Theory,
1 (3), 2002: 26183.
Carol Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,
1988).
Alison Jagger, Feminist Politics and Human Nature (Sussex: The Harverster
Press, 1983).
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
170
Page 170
thus women should enjoy the same rights of citizenship that men enjoy.
Okin goes so far as to argue that we should aspire to create a genderless
society, one where public policies and law assume no social differentiation of
the sexes. But there is an important feminist tradition that rejects the idea
that we should emphasize the similarities between men and women. This
tradition maintains that the only way of liberating women is to emphasize
difference. In Justice and the Politics of Difference Iris Marion Young, for example, argues that liberalism cannot adequately deal with difference. Young
believes that it is a mistake to reduce social justice to redistribution, as egalitarian liberals like Rawls and Dworkin tend to do. She identifies two problems with what she calls the distributive paradigm. The first problem is that
it tends to focus thinking about social justice on the allocation of material
goods such as things, resources, income and wealth, or on the distribution of
social positions, especially jobs. This focus tends to ignore the social structure and institutional context that often help determine distributive patterns
(Young, 1990: 15).
Young provides some examples to illustrate this concern. She considers
the case of a large employer that decides to close its plant in a small city. Such
an action will have a devastating impact on the small community as the
plant employs a large portion of the citys workers. This example raises concerns that go beyond those of the distributive paradigm, argues Young.
What is at stake in this example is not simply a concern about the justice of
material distributions but the justice of decision-making power and procedures. The just remedy in situations like this might not entail achieving a certain distributive pattern but giving the workers and community the option
of taking over and operating the plant themselves.
Young argues that injustices in the division of labour and of cultural
imagery and symbols are further examples that cannot be subsumed within
the distributive paradigm. Media stereotyping of women and ethnic minorities, for example, raises concerns that are not primarily about the distribution
of income or resources. The differences between social groups are brought to
the fore by making the concepts of domination and oppression, and not distribution, the central concern of justice. Young argues that where social
group differences exist and some groups are privileged while others are
oppressed, social justice requires explicitly acknowledging and attending to
those group differences in order to undermine oppression (Young, 1990: 3).
The second shortcoming of the distributive paradigm, argues Young, is
that even when distributive theorists extend the demands of justice to nonmaterial social goods like rights, opportunities and self-respect, by doing so
they mistakenly ascribe material-like properties to goods that do not have
these properties. Thus liberals obscure the institutional and social bases of
these values. Take, for example, rights. Young asks:
What can it mean to distribute rights that do not refer to resources or things,
like the right of free speech, or the right of trial by jury? We can conceive of
a society in which some persons are granted these rights while others are
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
Feminism
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 171
171
not, but this does not mean that some people have a certain amount or
portion of a good while others have less. Altering the situation so that
everyone has these rights, moreover, would not entail that the formerly
privileged group gives over some of its right of free speech or trial by jury
to the rest of societys members, on analogy with a redistribution of income.
(Young, 1990: 25)
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
172
Page 172
debate about the common good, such as churches, schools and community
centres. While Young is also concerned with preserving civic (or public)
spaces, she does not embrace the ideal of community. Such an ideal paints
an unrealistic picture of public spaces (for example, as a realm of unity and
mutual understanding). Young argues that it is precisely because public
spaces are diverse that they are exciting and vital. Streets, parks and plazas
bring people of diverse groups and experiences together. When people are
brought together it is not to affirm a common end, argues Young, but to
speak and listen to each other. Public spaces are valued not because they
assimilate citizens, but because they are venues for celebrating our distinctive characteristics and cultures. The public is heterogeneous, plural, and
playful, a place where people witness and appreciate diverse cultural
expressions that they do not share and do not fully understand (Young,
1990: 241).
A democratic public, argues Young, should provide mechanisms for the
effective recognition and representation of the distinct voices and perspectives of those of its constituent groups that are oppressed or disadvantaged
(Young, 1990: 184). In The Politics of Presence Anne Phillips seeks to take
Youngs concerns about group difference seriously by challenging the conventional understanding of democracy, what Phillips calls the politics of ideas.
The politics of ideas conceives of difference as a matter of different ideas.
This is what liberals like Rawls mean when they talk about the fact of reasonable pluralism. What liberals mean when they talk about difference is
that people endorse different, even conflicting, conceptions of the good life.
Some people are Christian, some Muslim and others atheist. But when difference is conceived of as a matter of different ideas democratic politics is
dominated by party politics where political loyalties develop around policies rather than people. The move from direct to representative democracy
has shifted the emphasis, argues Phillips, from who the politicians are to
what (policies, preferences, ideas) they represent, and in doing so has made
accountability to the electorate the pre-eminent radical concern (Phillips,
1995: 4).
One shortcoming of the politics of ideas is that it adopts a narrow conception of what constitutes political exclusion. For example, the fact that the
vast majority of elected officials in legislative assemblies are white, middleclass males does not, in itself, suggest a polity is exclusionary. The key issue,
for the politics of ideas, is that the policies these politicians endorse are ones
that reflect the beliefs and ideals of the citizenry. But, argues Phillips, once
difference is conceived
in relation to those experiences and identities that may constitute different
kinds of groups, it is far harder to meet demands of political inclusion without also including the members of such groups. Men may conceivably stand
in for women when what is at issue is the representation of agreed policies
or programmes or ideals. But how can men legitimately stand in for women
when what is at issue is the representation of women per se? White people
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 173
Feminism
173
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
174
Page 174
8.5 Conclusion
The arguments of Nussbaum and Young are interesting to compare and contrast as these feminist theorists react differently to the so-called distributive
paradigm of contemporary political theory. Nussbaums liberal feminism
functions from within the distributive paradigm and she premises her position on our shared humanity. The internationalist dimension of her feminism
brings it into tension with (some of) the arguments developed by communitarians and multiculturalists. The capabilities approach presupposes that
there are some universal goods that all people, regardless of their culture,
have an interest in. For example, being able to live to the end of a human life
of normal length, being able to live for and in relation to others, and being
able to participate effectively in political choices that govern ones life.
Furthermore, Nussbaums emphasis on capabilities, as opposed to material
goods (such as wealth), means that her theory of justice may not be as susceptible to the charge that it fails to recognize the fact that social structure
and institutional context often help determine distributive patterns.
Youngs feminism rejects the emphasis on sameness and redistribution.
For Young the key concepts are oppression and domination. By focusing on
end-state patterns (for example, the difference principle, equality of
resources) justice-theorists like Rawls and Dworkin ignore social processes
that undermine the equality of disadvantaged groups. Youngs politics of
difference thus shares much common ground with multiculturalist arguments,
such as Taylors politics of recognition. Both Young and Taylor emphasize the
importance of group rights and seek to inspire a public philosophy that
goes beyond the vision of equal citizenship embraced by liberals. The
emphasis on difference also influences, as we saw in the chapter on deliberative democracy, how Young conceives of political communication. Not all
cultures express themselves in speech that is assertive and confrontational.
Thus Young argues that deliberative democrats should endorse an expanded
conception of political communication, one that conceives of greeting,
rhetoric and storytelling, in addition to argument, as contributing to political
discussion.
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
Feminism
11/5/03 2:35 PM
Page 175
175
It is not surprising that some commentators find merits in both the appeal
to redistribution and the emphasis on difference, and thus some argue that
attention should be given to both things. Nancy Fraser (1995), for example,
rejects Youngs wholesale endorsement of the politics of difference. Fraser
argues that some oppressions are rooted in political economy whilst others
are rooted in culture. Exploitation, marginalization and powerlessness are
rooted in the former whilst cultural imperialism and violence are rooted in
culture. By considering some real-world applications that concern different
cases of oppressed groups, such as working-class non-professionals, women,
and African-Americans, Fraser argues that the politics of difference is not
globally applicable.
In some cases, such as that of nonprofessional workers, it is simply askew of
the nature of the group and its oppression. In other cases, in contrast, such
as gays and lesbians, the politics of difference is absolutely crucial for
remedying oppression. The hardest cases, of course, are those, such as
gender and race, in which both redistribution and recognition are required
to overcome a complex of oppression that is multiple and multiply-rooted.
(Fraser, 1995: 179)
Farrelly Ch-08.qxd
11/5/03 2:35 PM
176
Page 176
SUMMARY
Feminism is a varied political theory which is primarily concerned with the
liberation of women. Liberal feminists believe that an enlightened version of
liberalism can inspire a public philosophy that will seek to remedy existing
social injustices. But many feminists believe that liberalism is the source of
the problem and not the solution.
The feminist slogan the personal is political is often invoked as a way of
bringing to the fore how deeply entrenched sexual differences are in society.
In particular, the slogan requires us to consider more closely the role of the
family and how it perpetuates social inequalities. Feminists reject the idea
that the family is part of a private realm that is beyond the demands of the
principles of justice.
Young emphasizes the importance of difference, something which both liberal theories of justice and appeals to community are ill-equipped to deal
with. Youngs politics of difference links feminist concerns with the concerns
of other theories, such as deliberative democracy and multiculturalism.
Notes
1 See, for example, Amartya Sen (1992).
2 In her later writings Nussbaum explicitly denies the claim that the capabilities
view is indifferent to inequalities. She claims:
A list of the central capabilities is not a complete theory of justice. Such a list gives us the
basis for determining a decent social minimum in a variety of areas. I argue that the structure of social and political institutions should be chosen, at least in part, with a view to
promoting at least a threshold level of these human capabilities. But the provision of a
threshold level of capability, exigent though that goal is, may not suffice for justice. ...
(Nussbaum, 2000a: 75)
Farrelly biblio.qxd
11/5/03 2:37 PM
Page 177
Bibliography
Ackerman, Bruce and Fishkin, James (2002) Deliberation Day, Journal of Political
Philosophy, 10 (2): 129152.
Anderson, Elizabeth (1999) What is the Point of Equality?, Ethics, 109 (2): 287337.
Arneson, Richard (1989) Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, Philosophical
Studies, 56: 7793.
Arneson, Richard (1990) Primary Goods Reconsidered, Nous, 24: 42954.
Arneson, Richard (2000) Perfectionism and Politics, Ethics, 111 (1): 3763.
Barry, Brian (1989) Theories of Justice. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Barry, Brian (1995) John Rawls and the Search for Stability, Ethics, 105 (4): 874915.
Barry, Brian (2001) Culture and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Bell, Daniel (1999) Democratic Deliberation: The Problem of Implementation, in
Stephen Macedo (ed.), Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Beitz, Charles (1979) Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Bentham, Jeremy (1996) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, in
D. Wootton (ed.), Modern Political Thought. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing
Company.
Braybooke, David (1987) Social Contract Theorys Fanciest Flight, Ethics, 97 (4):
75064.
Buchanan, Allen (1982) Marx and Justice: The Radical Critique of Liberalism. London:
Methuen.
Buchanan, Allen (1990) Justice as Reciprocity versus Subject-centered Justice,
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19 (3): 22752.
Buchanan, James (1975) The Limits of Liberty. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Christman, John (1986) Can Ownership be Justified by Natural Rights?, Philosophy
and Public Affairs, 15 (2): 15677.
Cohen, G.A. (1989) On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, Ethics, 99 (4): 90644.
Cohen, G.A. (1992) Incentives, Inequality, and Community, in Grethe Peterson (ed.),
The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 13. Salt Lake City, UT: University of Utah Press.
Cohen, G.A. (1995a) Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cohen, G.A. (1995b) The Pareto Argument for Inequality, Social Philosophy and
Policy, 12: 16085.
Cohen, G.A. (1997) Where the Action Is: On the Side of Distributive Justice,
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26 (1): 330.
Cohen, G.A. (2000) If Youre An Egalitarian, How Come Youre So Rich? Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Farrelly biblio.qxd
11/5/03 2:37 PM
178
Page 178
Farrelly biblio.qxd
Bibliography
11/5/03 2:37 PM
Page 179
179
Farrelly biblio.qxd
11/5/03 2:37 PM
180
Page 180
Farrelly biblio.qxd
Bibliography
11/5/03 2:37 PM
Page 181
181
Farrelly biblio.qxd
11/5/03 2:37 PM
182
Page 182
Young, Iris Marion (1986) The Ideal of Community and the Politics of Difference,
Social Theory and Practice, 12 (1): 126.
Young, Iris Marion (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Young, Iris Marion (1996) Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative
Democracy, in Seyla Benhabib (ed.), Democracy and Difference. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Young, Iris Marion (1999) Justice, Inclusion, and Deliberative Democracy, in
Stephen Macedo (ed.), Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Young, Iris Marion (2000) Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Zurn, Christopher (2002) Deliberative Democracy and Constitutional Review, Law
and Philosophy, 21: 467542.
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 183
Index
aboriginal people 48, 122, 126
abortion 88
accountability principle
deliberative democracy 152
Ackerman, Bruce 1534
agenda, final control over (democracy
criterion) 138, 139, 144, 146
aggregative democracy model 138, 13943
anarchism 36
Anarchy, State and Utopia (Robert Nozick)
33, 46, 49, 51, 76
Anderson, Elizabeth 74, 901
apartheid 125
Archimedean point 67
Aristotle 161
armchair theorizing 146, 147
Arneson, Richard 223, 26, 163
assimilation 119, 121, 126
associations 115, 138
autonomy 122
Bargain of Mutual Benefit 64
Barry, Brian 11, 28, 29, 1314, 164
basic structure of society 3, 15, 74
Beitz, Charles 236, 111
David Miller distinguished 113, 114
Bell, Daniel 1512
Bentham, Jeremy 4, 5, 76
brute luck 90, 91
Buchanan, Allen 28, 689, 102
Bulgaria 130
Bush, George 85
Canada 120, 122, 127
capabilities approach 1613, 174
capital punishment 889
Chamberlain, Wilt (entitlement theory)
3941, 50
citizen democracy 87, 89
civic spaces 105, 1712
civil disobedience 1921
Clinton, Bill 81, 82
CM (constrained maximation) 59, 60, 61, 62
Cohen, G. A. 1517, 44, 45
Cohen, Joshua 144, 146, 147
colour-blind society 120
commercial protective agencies 378
common good 149
common ownership 46
communicative democracy 150
communitarianism 97117
complex equality (Walzer) 98, 108, 10910
embedded selves 167
feminist view 171
liberalism 97, 99, 11314, 115, 119, 121
deontological 99102
nationalism 989, 11014
political economy 105
Sandel, views of 97106
solidarity 115
state neutrality 1026
community
criticism of notion 171
cultural 120
ideal 115, 172
complex equality 98, 108, 10910
compliance problem (mutual advantage,
justice as) 5763
comprehensive liberalism 75
conception of self see self, conception of
conditions matching argument (justice)
28, 102
conflict
rationality account 55
conscious-state theories 76
constitutionalism 1920, 87, 88, 89, 148
constrained maximation (CM) 59, 60, 61, 62
cooperative surplus 66
cultural diversity 120, 126
cultural heritage 122, 123
culturalism see pluralism
Culture and Equality (Brian Barry) 131
curriculum, school see education curriculum
Dahl, Robert 138, 141, 144
Danielson, Peter 65
De Wijze, Stephen 1667
Deliberation Day (proposed national
holiday) 1534
deliberative democracy see democracy:
deliberative
deliberative turn 137
democracy
agenda, final control over 138, 139,
144, 146
aggregative model 138, 13943
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 184
184
democracy cont.
citizen 87, 89
communicative 150
constitutional 1920, 145
criteria 138
deliberative 13756
accountability principle 152
armchair theorizing 146, 147
authentic deliberation 140
and feminism 163, 174
ideal, critical assessment 1505
procedural test 144, 145, 147
publicity principle 151, 152
reciprocity principle 141, 142, 152
show of hands approach 139, 140,
142, 144, 145
as transformative process 140, 143, 149
utopian ideal 152
discursive 1489
enlightened understanding 138, 141, 143
ideal 138
assessment of 1504
utopian 152
importance of 1379
and justice 137, 154
majority decision 138
participation, effective 138, 140, 143, 147
partnership conception (Dworkin) 86,
87, 89
and political equality 859, 92
democratic wager 86, 87
substantive principles 139, 1448
Democracy and Disagreement (Amy
Gutmann/Dennis Thompson) 146
Democracys Discontent (Michael Sandel) 97, 102
democratic discourse 87
democratic equality 12, 13, 912
deontological theories 45
liberalism 99102
difference
politics of 1589, 16973, 174, 175
difference principle (of justice)
defined 3
domestic justice 26, 114
egalitarian critique 1516
and equality of welfare 78
global justice 26, 114
least advantaged 21
moral implications 10
and order of principles 4
overlapping consensus 29
rectification principle 49
diffidence
as source of conflict 55
discourse ethics 1456
discursive democracy 1489
distributional equality 75, 77, 85, 92
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 185
Index
environmentalism 151
equal basic liberties principle 3
equal citizenship principle 120, 121
equal concern principle 84, 85, 90, 91
equal importance principle 75, 77, 79
equal opportunity 1015
efficiency 1315
egalitarian critique (G. A. Cohen) 1517
formal 10, 11
liberal equality 11, 12
lotteries (three) 11
luck egalitarianism 74, 8992
natural liberty 10, 12, 101
principles of justice 3
and talents 10
equality
citizen 87, 89
complex 98, 108, 10910
democratic 12, 13, 912
distributional 75, 77, 85, 92
Dworkin on 7393
and freedom 34
justice (initial position) 7, 8
liberal 11, 12, 101
and liberty 34, 73
moral 73
of outcomes 13
political (and democracy) 859
of resources 73, 7580, 81, 82, 83, 138
see also self-ownership
of welfare 75, 77, 78
see also equal opportunity; inequality
ethical communities
nations as 112
ethical particularism/universalism 111, 113, 1601
Exdell, John 46
eye lottery example
entitlement theory of justice 345, 49, 50
fair equality of opportunity principle 3
fairness, justice as 331
assumptions, shared 67
basic structure of society 3, 15, 74
civil disobedience 1921
efficiency 56, 1315
egalitarian critique (G. A. Cohen) 1517
equal opportunity see equal opportunity
least advantaged, identity of 10, 213, 74
nearly just society 19
original position 710, 100, 1445
political conception 2630
consensus, overlapping 2930
right and good 46
theory (John Rawls) 67, 53
criticism 1517, 22
utilitarianism 4, 56
see also principles of justice
185
families
and feminism 1648
fear, liberalism of 130, 131
Federal Election Commission 85
feminism 15776
capabilities approach 1613, 174
and complex equality 110
deliberative democracy 163, 174
distributive paradigm 158, 170, 174
and equal worth of human beings 160
and families 1648
gender distinctions 1578, 159, 164
human life, development of 161
and humanism 160
internationalist 160, 163, 164, 174
labour, division of 167, 170
liberal 158, 15964, 166, 175
and marriage 169
Nussbaum on 158, 1604, 174
Okin on 110, 157, 1649
politics of difference 1589, 16973, 174, 175
public/private dichotomy 158, 1649
and rights 1701
women, domination of 110, 157, 171
Young on 139, 14950, 158, 170, 174
Feminist Politics and Human Nature
(Alison Jagger) 159
Fishkin, James 1534
Foole, Hobbesian theory 589, 62
foundationalism 534, 58, 62, 65
France
headscarves affair 129
Fraser, Nancy 175
free exchange principle 107
free-riders 68, 84
freedom 34, 823
Freedoms Law: The Moral Reading of
the American Constitution (Ronald
Dworkin) 88
Gauthier, David 5371, 73, 115
and compliance problem 5763
and liberal feminism 159
gender distinctions 1578, 159, 164
genderless society, creation 168
Glaucon 58
global justice 236, 111, 113
good, the (ethical theory) 46, 99
goods
competition for 55
primary 9, 107, 122, 123, 125, 162
Gore, Al 85
greatest happiness principle 76
Gutmann, Amy 108, 1413, 146, 149, 150, 152
Habermas, Jurgen 144, 1456
Hampshire, Stuart 97
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 186
186
Hampton, Jean 55
handicapped people 69, 74, 77, 80
harm principle 164
Harsanyi, John 910
Hawking, Stephen 79
headscarves affair (France) 129
health care 107, 108
health coverage, universal 79, 80
hedonism 76
helmet law 122, 1278, 131
heritage, cultural 122, 123
hijab 12930, 131
Hobbes, Thomas 36, 536, 579, 63, 64
homosexuality 164
household chores 167, 170
humanism 160
Hume, David 4, 112
ideas, politics of 172
immigrants 120, 124, 125
impersonal preferences 77
incentives 14, 16, 153
inclusion principle
deliberative democracy 149
inequality
and efficiency 13, 14
immigrants and 124, 125
natural 80
Pareto argument for 15
informed preferences 77
initial acquisition principle
entitlement theory (of justice) 416
initial bargaining position 63
injustice 20, 171
insurance scheme analogy (Dworkin) 79,
80, 81, 82, 90
Jagger, Alison 159
Jews, Orthodox 127, 132
Johnson, James 147
judicial review 87, 88, 89, 139, 146
justice
and democracy 137, 154
descriptive claim 5, 29
distributive see distributive justice
entitlement theory see entitlement theory
(of justice)
as fairness see fairness, justice as
Gauthier on see Gauthier, David
global (Charles Beitz on) 236, 111, 113
as human construction 98
and injustices 20, 171
as mutual advantage see mutual
advantage, justice as
normative claim 29
Nozick on see Nozick, Robert
pie-cutting approach 39, 40, 51
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 187
Index
minimax relative concession (MRC) 667, 1378
minorities, rights of 1227
monism 121
Morals by Agreement (David Gauthier) 54, 67, 70
MRC (minimax relative concession)
667, 1378
multiculturalism 11936
Barry on 1314
national minorities, rights of 1227
politics of recognition 11922
polyethnic rights 120, 12731
Multiculturalism of Fear (Jacob Levy) 130
Muslims 127, 132
mutual advantage, justice as 5371
compliance problem 5763
constrained maximization (CM) 59, 60,
61, 62
cooperative surplus 66
free-riders 68
and liberal feminism 159
limits of 6770
moral intuitions 54
non-moral premises 54
opacity 60
and poker game 5960
rational bargain, defined 637
reciprocity thesis 68, 73
rough equality clause 578, 68, 69
state of nature 547
straightforward maximization (SM) 59,
60, 61, 62
translucency 60, 61
transparency 60
mutual protection agencies 37
mutual respect 141, 143, 146
nation
meaning 112
nationalism 989, 11014
natural resources 34
global justice 234
natural rights tradition 36
naturalism 121
nature-nurture debate
feminism 159
neutrality doctrine 83, 84
Northern Ireland
Orange Order 132
Nozick, Robert
and community 11516
and conscious-state theories 76
entitlement theory of justice see
entitlement theory (of justice)
and Rawlss theory contrasted 53
and utilitarianism 73
and Walzer 107
Nussbaum, Martha 158, 1604, 174
187
obligations
distinguished from natural duties 1718
Okin, Susan 110, 157, 1649
On Liberty (John Stuart Mill) 164
opacity 60
oppression concept
feminism 171
option luck 90
Orange Order (Northern Ireland) 132
original position (justice as fairness
theory) 710
as appropriate initial status quo 8, 53
communitarianism 100
democracy, substantive principles 1445
formal constraints of the right 8
rationality of parties 89
veil of ignorance 8, 54, 123
Parekh, Bhikhu 120, 121, 1256, 12930
Pareto optimal/Pareto argument for
inequality 14, 15
participation, effective
deliberative democracy 138, 140, 143, 147
particularism 106
ethical 111, 113, 160
partnership conception 86, 87, 89
personal preferences 77
Phillips, Anne 1723
pie-cutting justice theory 39, 40, 51
Plato 58
pleasure principle 76
pluralism 6, 120, 121, 166, 172
political conception of justice 2630
political economy 105
political equality 859, 92
constitutionalism 87, 88, 89
democratic wager 86, 87
judicial review 87, 88, 89
partnership conception 86, 87, 89
political liberalism 745
Political Liberalism (John Rawls) 3, 26, 27
political preferences 77
Political Theory and International Relations
(Charles Beitz) 23
politics of difference 1589, 16973, 174, 175
politics of ideas 172
Politics of Presence (Anne Phillips) 172, 173
politics of recognition 1201, 133
feminism 158, 174
polyethnic rights 120, 12731
popular sovereignty 87
pornography, law against 104
preferences, and welfare 767
presence, politics of 172, 173
primary goods 9, 107, 122, 123, 125, 162
principles of justice
argument for 910
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 188
188
principles of justice cont.
defined 3
difference principle see difference
principle (of justice)
domestic 24
duties/obligations 1718
and families 166
formal constraints of the right 8
individuals, applicable to 1721
initial acquisition 416
justifications 278
lexical order 4
maximin rule 9, 10
original position 710, 100, 1445
rationality 54
reflective equilibrium 67
and self-respect 18
veil of ignorance 8, 54, 123
see also fairness, justice as; justice
principles matching justification (justice)
28, 102
Prisoners Dilemma 54, 556
private property
natural rights to 45
and self-ownership 4951
private sphere
families belonging to 1645
procedural republic 978
property rights 34, 42, 50, 51
see also private property
publicity principle
deliberative democracy 151, 152
racism 103, 104, 125
rational bargain, defined 637
Bargain of Mutual Benefit 64
cooperative surplus 66
initial bargaining position 63
Lockean proviso 64, 65, 67
minimax relative concession (MRC)
667, 1378
rational preferences 77
rationality account of conflict 55
rationality of parties
justice as fairness theory 89, 54
Rawls, John
and deliberative democracy 152, 153
and egalitarian theory 13, 35, 73
critique by Cohen 1517
see also equal opportunity; equality
and ethics 45, 99
on least advantaged, definition 10, 213, 74
methodology 67, 53
criticism 1517, 22
and morality 54
and pluralism 172
primary goods 9, 107, 122, 123, 125, 162
Farrelly Index.qxd
11/5/03 2:36 PM
Page 189
Index
Shaw, William 4
Shklar, Judith 130
show of hands approach
deliberative democracy 139, 140, 142,
144, 145
Sidgwick, Henry 5
Sikhs
and helmet law 1278, 131
Skokie controversy (19778) 103
slaughter regulations 122, 1289, 131
SM (straightforward maximization) 59,
60, 61, 62
Smith, Adam 4, 10
social contract 4
social goods 9, 107, 108
Socrates 58
solidarity 11516, 133
South Africa 125
Sovereign Virtue (Ronald Dworkin) 74, 75,
79, 92
sovereignty
popular 87
special responsibility principle 75, 779
state
dominant protective association as 38
minimal, argument for 33, 37, 38
necessity for 359
ultra-minimal 38
state of nature
entitlement theory of justice 36
mutual advantage theory 547
and original position 7
theorems 567
state neutrality
communitarianism 1026
straightforward maximization (SM) 59,
60, 61, 62
taxation of earnings 35, 49, 50, 79, 83
tax cuts 15, 16
Taylor, Charles 126
teleological theory 4, 5
terrorism 151
Thatcher, Margaret 15, 16
Theory of Justice (John Rawls) 3, 4, 17, 23,
26, 28, 100
Thompson, Dennis 1413, 146, 149, 150, 152
translucency 60, 61
transparency 60
Tully, James 133
Turkish names, use of 130, 131
Two Treatises of Government (John Locke) 36
unemployment insurance scheme
(hypothetical) 79, 80, 81, 82, 90
United Kingdom
helmet law 1278, 131
189
United States
aboriginal population 122
American Civil War 100
complex equality 109
contemporary politics, public philosophy
978, 102
democracy in 87
health care 108
political economy 105
political equality 856, 878
productive employment in 108
state neutrality 1034
welfare reform 823
universalism 106
ethical 111, 1601
utilitarianism
description 76
Nozicks critique 73
Rawlss critique 4, 56, 9, 34, 73
utility
preference-satisfaction account of 76
utilitarians on 4
Van Parijs, Phillipe 824, 90
veil of ignorance 8, 54, 123
Vindication of the Rights of Women (Mary
Wollstonecraft) 159
voting 1389, 140
Waldron, Jeremy 88, 133, 146
Walzer, Michael
and communitarianism 97, 98, 10610, 116
and democracy 152
and feminism 162, 1656
Wealth of Nations (Adam Smith) 10
Weber, Max 36
welfare
Bentham on 76
equality of 75, 77, 78
preferences 767
success theories 76
welfare reform
and basic income proposal 805
Welfare Reform Act (1996) 81, 82
welfare state 38, 39
Wolf, Susan 163
Wollstonecraft, Mary 159, 160
women
domination of 110, 157, 171
quotas for 173, 175
see also feminism
World Institute for Development
Economics Research 161
Young, Iris Marion 139, 14950, 158,
170, 174