Critical Theory Crisis of Social Theory
Critical Theory Crisis of Social Theory
Critical Theory Crisis of Social Theory
By Douglas Kellner
(http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/kellner.html)
Social theory today is in crisis. During the 1960s, a variety of new theoretical paradigms
emerged which put in question the prevailing quantitative, empiricist, and positivist conceptions
of social theory and social research. Growing dissatisfaction with the dominant methodologies
and theories produced by the mainstream promoted a search for alternative methodologies and
conceptions of social theory and research. The new paradigms of phenomenology, enthnomethodology, structuralism, Marxism, feminism, and other critical theories offered new
conceptions which claimed to be more adequate in characterizing contemporary society and in
providing inspiration and guidance for transforming it. These theories have caused much ferment
in the field of social theory and have inspired heated debates over the nature, methods, and goals
of critical social theory.
More recently, poststructuralist and postmodern social theory have further challenged
mainstream social theory and science, attacking their basic presuppositions. In addition, these
new critical discourses have sharply criticized Marxism, structuralism, phenomenology, and
other critical paradigms for participating too staunchly in the premises and methods of modern,
enlightenment rationality and traditional social theory (Kellner 1988 and 1989b). While debates
have emerged between advocates of critical theory and the newer, postmodern approaches which
I shall discuss later in the paper, there are also common positions. Like some of the new French
theories, the critical theory of the so-called Frankfurt school offers a multi-disciplinary approach
for social theory which combines perspectives drawn from political economy, sociology, cultural
theory, philosophy, anthropology, and history. It thus overcomes the fragmentation endemic to
established academic disciplines in order to address issues of broader interest.
Both new French theory and critical theory therefore put in question the boundaries established
by the academic division of labor which separates social theory from other disciplines. Both
claim that there are epistemological and metaphysical problems with abstracting from the
interconnectedness of phenomena in the world, or from our experience of it. On this view,
philosophy, for example, that abstracts from sociology and economics, or political science that
excludes, say, economics or culture from its conceptual boundaries, is by nature one-sided,
limited, and flawed. Both critical theory and new French theory therefore transgress established
disciplinary boundaries and create new theories and discourses that avoid the deficiencies of the
traditional academic division of labor.
In this paper, I shall argue that as an antidote to the frequently non-critical quantitative
approaches within mainstream social science and theory, critical theory provides a potentially
more useful and politically relevant alternative than poststructuralist and postmodernist theory.
In opposition to the subjectivism and relativism, often bordering on nihilism, advanced by some
synthesis of social science and philosophy, and therefore provides a useful introduction to the
Institute's project.
Horkheimer begins by pointing to the limitations of the classical German social theories of Kant
and Hegel, and the limitations of contemporary metaphysical and positivist philosophies. This
exercise typifies Horkheimer's method of clarifying his own position through criticism of
opposing positions. Kant is criticized for grounding social philosophy in the experience and
faculties of the particular individual (ibid:33ff). Hegel's attempt to situate philosophy within
society and history is presented as an improvement over Kant, yet Hegel's idealism and tendency
to justify the existing order is rejected (ibid:34-37). Then Horkheimer criticizes the current forms
of idealism in the neo-Kantian, neo-Hegelian, phenomenological, and existential philosophies for
their questionable speculative metaphysics and for their tendencies to celebrate a higher
transcendental sphere of Being (Sein) and meaning (Sinn) over concrete existence (ibid:38-39).
The positivist schools which root their theories in isolated facts are also criticized for their
unsupportable metaphysical presuppositions and methodological limitations (ibid:39).
Horkheimer concludes that none of the dominant philosophical schools contain an adequate
social philosophy. He assumes that social philosophy encompasses "the entire material and
spiritual culture of humanity." Consequently, he rejects the claims of the specific social sciences
such as "material sociology" to provide adequate knowledge since the specialized sciences
abstract from the structure and organization of society as a whole to describe limited domains of
social experience. In opposing the separation between social theory, science, and philosophy
which was dominant at the time, and which continues to be dominant today, Horkheimer calls
for a new sort of synthesis between philosophy and the specialized sciences.
Consequently, while Comte, Durkheim, positivists, and others want to purge philosophy from
social theory, Horkheimer defends its importance for critical social theory. He claims that the
positivist conception that philosophy "is perhaps beautiful, but scientifically fruitless because it
is not subject to controls," verification, experiments and the like, must be rejected, as must as
well the philosopher's prejudice that he or she is dealing with the essential while the scientist is
dealing with bare, trival facts (ibid:40). These conflicting claims to the primacy of science and
philosophy must be overcome in favor of a "dialectical penetration and development of
philosophical theory and the praxis of the individual disciplines" (ibid:40). For Horkheimer, the
philosophical drive toward the universal and essential should be the animating spirit for social
research, but philosophy must be at the same time "sufficiently open to the world to allow itself
to be impressed with, and transformed by, progress in concrete studies" (ibid:41).
To fulfill these goals, Horkheimer envisaged a program of supradisciplinary research which
would investigate current social and political problems. This project would unite "philosophers,
sociologists, economists, historians, and psychologists in an ongoing research community who
would do together what in other disciplines one individual does alone in the laboratory, -- which
is what genuine scientists have always done: namely, to pursue the great philosophical questions
using the most refined scientific methods; to reformulate and to make more precise the questions
in the course of work as demanded by the object; and to develop new methods without losing
sight of the universal" (ibid:41).
After praising his predecessor Carl Grundberg's legacy and contributions, Horkheimer stresses
that the Institute will now undertake a "new start" directed at "new tasks" (ibid:42). He claims
that the Institute's new multidisciplinary program will allow its members to raise the question of
"the interconnections between the economic life of society, the psychic development of the
individual and transformations in the realm of culture... including not only the so-called spiritual
contents of science, art and religion, but also law, ethics, fashion, public opinion, sport,
amusement, life style, etc." (ibid:43). This research program is somewhat unorthodox for a
Marxian social theory which in the past tended to neglect the dimension of individual and social
psychology, and which also downplayed the study of culture and leisure. Attention to these
topics would eventually produce many of the distinctive contributions of critical theory.
In his inaugural address, Horkheimer distances his conception of social theory from a crude
Marxian materialism. He proclaims that the Institute will not subscribe to any metaphysical
theses, such as idealism or materialism, on the relation between the economy, society, culture,
and consciousness. Horkheimer notes that the attempt to derive all forms of life from one
metaphysical substance is "bad Spinozaism." From the very beginning, therefore, Horkheimer
rejects all metaphysical absolutism and all philosophical reductionism. He argues that an illusory
idealism that derives everything from the Idea is "an abstract and therefore badly understood
Hegel," just as the attempt to derive everything from an economy which is understood merely as
material being is "an abstract and therefore badly understood Marx" (ibid:43). Such theses posit
an "uncritical, obsolete and highly problematic cleavage of spirit and reality into naive absolutes"
and must be dialectically overcome (ibid:43).
Critical social philosophy, by contrast, describes the complex set of mediations that interconnect
consciousness and society, culture and economy, state and citizens. These relations can best be
clarified and developed in concrete historical contexts in which one asks: "which
interconnections exist in a definite social group, in a definite period of time and in a definite
country, between the role of this group in the economic process, the transformation of the
psychic structures of its individual members, and the totality of the system that affects and
produces its thoughts and mechanism" (ibid:44).
To begin this task, the Institute proposed to study technically qualified workers and employees
in Germany by gathering empirical material on their psychological, social, and political attitudes
which would be interpreted in a theoretical framework that encompasses economic theory,
sociology, and psychology. Horkheimer illustrated the project of the Institute's social theory by
indicating that an empirical study of the white-collar working class would be its first research
project. In addition, he indicated that his colleagues would predominantly undertake studies in
"theoretical economics, economic history, and the history of the working class movement"
(ibid:45). Thus, at least during the early Horkheimer years, the Institute sought to continue many
of Grunberg's projects with regard to topics central to classical Marxism and socialist politics,
in which objective conditions help constitute the subject, while the subject in turn helps
constitute objective (material, historical) conditions. For Horkheimer:
"A dialectical process is negatively characterized by the fact that it is not to be
conceived as the result of individual unchanging factors. To put it positively, its
elements continuously change in relation to each other within the process, so that
they are not even to be radically distinguished from each other. Thus the
development of human character, for example, is conditioned both by the
economic situation and by the individual powers of the person in question. But
both these elements determine each other continuously, so that in the total
development neither of them is to be prsented as an effective factor without
giving the other its role" (ibid:28).
Horkheimer and his colleagues consistently followed this dialectical conception which stressed
the relative autonomy of thought, culture, and all other "superstructural" phenomena in a process
of reciprocal interaction with a socio-economic "base." They thereby rejected all versions of
economic determinism and reductionism and provided conceptual space for analyzing the often
important causal role of cultural factors in history and society. A dialectical social theory thus
analyzes the relationships between different aspects of society rather than providing a
unidimensional determinist model that appeals to the economic dimension of society as the sole
causal factor in explaining social development and structure.
Furthermore, the Institute's version of "dialectical materialism" is thoroughly historical because
it stresses that our experience, views of the world, and concepts change in relation to historical
development, and that therefore both our theories and perceptual apparatuses, as well as the
objects of knowledge, are historical: "Materialism, unlike idealism, always understands thinking
to be the thinking of particular men within a particular period of time. It challenges every claim
to the autonomy of thought" (ibid:32).
In sum, for Horkheimer, "materialism is not interested in a worldview or in the souls of men. It
is concerned with changing the concrete conditions under which humans suffer and in which, of
course, their souls must become stunted. This concern may be comprehended historically and
psychologically; it cannot be grounded in general principles" (ibid:32). Horkheimer believes that
it is primarily materialist theories which are currently concerned with human suffering, and with
transforming the material conditions which produce human suffering to produce a more rational
society and a more humane form of existence. This analysis assumes that "the wretchedness of
our own time is connected with the structure of society; social theory therefore forms the main
content of contemporary materialism" (ibid, p. 24). In particular, "the fundamental historical role
of economic relations is characteristic of the materialist position... Understanding of the present
becomes more idealist, the more it avoids the economic causes of material need and looks to a
psychologically naive elaboration of so-called 'basic elements of human existence'" (ibid:25-26).
Horkheimer's materialist social theory thus focuses on human needs and suffering, the ways that
economic conditions produce suffering, and the changes necessary to eliminate human suffering
and to increase human well-being. Such a project requires a critical social theory which
confronts the social problems of the present age: "If materialist theory is an aspect of efforts to
improve the human situation, it inevitably opposes every attempt to reduce social problems to
second place" (ibid:26). The social theory in turn is produced by a synthesis of philosophy and
the sciences (ibid:34ff).
For the Institute, philosophy without empirical scientific research is empty, just as science
without philosophy is blind. In the mid-1930s, Horkheimer's unification of science and
philosophy seemed to involve a dialectical interpenetration and mediation of science and
philosophy, without making one superordinate to the other. [3] Consequently, Horkheimer
rejects both metaphysics and positivist concepts of science which profess "'the dogma of the
invariability of natural laws'" (ibid, p. 36). Dominant positivist conceptions of science, according
to Horkheimer, are "unhistorical," and "science" for critical theory will not be privileged above
philosophy and social theory. Yet Horkheimer maintains that: "materialism has in common with
positivism that it acknowledges as real only what is given in sense experience, and it has done so
since its beginnings" (ibid:42). Sense experience, however, is mediated through concepts, and
both sense perception and cognition are subject to social conditions and historical change. Thus,
notions of absolute intuition, whether through the senses or cognition, are to be rejected.
Horkheimer and his colleagues therefore subscribe to a non-transcendental materialist theory of
knowledge which acknowledges, with Kant and the idealists, that forms of cognition and theories
determine our experience of the external world, but which acknowledges as well that objective
material conditions in turn condition forms of thought and knowledge. The results of postmetaphysical, materialist social theory are thus always provisional, contextual, and subject to
revision.
Critical Theory
The term "critical theory" was first coined in 1937 after the majority of the Institute's members
had already emigrated to the United States following the triumph of Hitler. For many years,
"critical theory" stood as a codeword for the Institute's Marxism and for its attempt to found a
radical supradisciplinary social theory rooted in Hegelian-Marxian dialectics, historical
materialism, and the Marxian critique of political economy and theory of revolution. Note that I
said supradisciplinary and not "interdisciplinary." The critical theory project initially involved
attempts of individuals from various disciplines to work together collectively to develop a
historical and systematic theory of contemporary society rather than just bringing individuals
from separate disciplines together to chat, or assigning various specialists different topics for
research and inquiry. As Lowenthal (1980:109) put it:
the term "interdisciplinary work" simply "means nothing more than to leave the disciplines as
they are while developing certain techniques which foster a kind of acquaintance between them
without forcing them to give up their self-sufficiency or individual claims." Critical theory, on
the contrary, criticized the validity claims of the separate disciplines and attempted to create a
new kind of social theory.
Critical theorists privileged Marxian categories in their supradisciplinary discourse, arguing that
Marx's concepts of commodity, money, value, exchange, and fetishism characterize not only the
capitalist economy but also social relations under capitalism where human relations and all forms
of life are governed by commodity and exchange relations and values. Building on Lukacs'
theory of reification (1971), they argued that capitalist society produced a rigid, reified structure
wherein human beings were transformed into things. On this theory, through the process of
reification, the unnatural conditions of the capitalist economy and labor process, the
commodification of all goods, services, and objects, and the new modes of thought promoted by
the mass media and positivist science appear to be "natural" and to form a system impervious to
human control or intervention.
Horkheimer's essay "Traditional and Critical Theory" (1972) provides the most systematic and
comprehensive presentation of the Institute's conception of social theory, while spelling out the
presuppositions of their project and its relation to traditional theory. Traditional theory from
Descartes through positivism is characterized by what is now called "foundationalism" i.e the
attempt to ground theory in theoretical postulates which form the foundation of its theory upon
which the traditional theorist builds its theoretical constructions. Traditional theory tends to be
deductive, privileging natural science and mathematics; its goal, Horkheimer claims, is unity and
harmony, with mathematics as its model (1972:190).
Horkheimer suggests that traditional theory is thus a projection of the bourgeois ideal of the
harmonious capitalist market unified by calculable laws of supply and demand. Critical theory
frequently shows the relationships between ideas and theoretical positions and their social
environment, and thus attempts to contextualize or historicize ideas in terms of their roots within
social processes. Following this line of inquiry, Horkheimer suggests that traditional theory is
itself part of the social practices that constituted capitalism and bourgeois society. Its tendencies
toward mechanistic materialism reproduced the mechanistic thought and practice of the
industrial revolution according to which the world was conceptualized as a machine during an
era in which machines came to dominate human beings. The dominant bourgeois trends of
abstract and quantitative thought which informed traditional theory reproduced the tendencies
toward abstraction and a mode of quantification that was based on exchange in the capitalist
market where value was expressed in abstract, quantitative terms. Just as a bourgeois society
governed by exchange value abstracted from values, goals, sentiments, and qualities, so too did
traditional theory. And, finally, the fragmentation and division of the sciences reproduces the
bourgeois division of labor under capitalism whereby specialization and fragmentation are
dominant features of the structure of society.
Social theories, for critical theory, are thus forms of social practice which reproduce dominant
forms of social activity. [4] Traditional theory is, Horkheimer claims, unaware of the ways in
which it is bound together with social processes and thus fails to see its lack of autonomy and
social determination. As it became increasingly involved in social processes of production and
reproduction, it became increasingly conformist, uncritically submitting to the dominant
instrumental, quantitative, and capitalist values. Unaware of its social determination, "theory was
of historical alternatives and normative values which can be used to criticize existing states of
affairs and to argue for alternative values and organization of society.
Critical theory is thus intrinsically global and historical, and attempts to provide the "Big
Picture" that sketches the fundamental outlines of socio-economic development and the ways in
which capitalism structures social life, as well as the dynamics through which a capitalist society
can be replaced by a socialist one. Yet the Institute was constantly on the alert to avoid any sort
of economic reductionism and was especially concerned to trace the linkages between the
economy and the political, social, cultural, and psychic realms while stressing the relative
autonomy of the superstructures. The critical theorists thus described the mediations, or
interconnections, between these spheres as well as the contradictions, and thus produced what
might be called a "mediated totality." That is, the critical theorists believed that the boundaries
between the various realms of existence reproduced in the fragmentation of the disciplinary
sciences are artificial and abstract. Consequently, to intelligently pursue theoretical and political
issues requires supradisciplinary research and a dialectical method of presentation that
demonstrates in concrete detail the interconnections and conflicts between the primary areas of
the socio-historical system that constitutes the context and framework for thought and action.
Dialectics for the Institute involved model-building and the making of connections or
mediations. Social theory therefore involves construction of a model of the current society and a
demonstration of the fundamental connections -- as well as of the contradictions and conflicts -among the various domains of the current social system. Consequently, critical theory provides
analyses of a mediated social totality that describe various relations among spheres of reality,
rather than reducing all of society to the dynamics of the economy.
Critical theory is thus systemic, totalizing, integrating, and global. Social theory therefore has a
mediating function for the critical theorists, integrating science and philosophy and mediating
between research (Forschung) and theoretical construction and presentation (Darstellung)
(Dubiel 1985). Critical theory mediates between various domains of reality, between parts and
whole, between appearance and essence, and between theory and practice. The now "classical"
1930s model of critical theory thus synthesizes social theory, research, and radical politics in a
critical global theory of the present age. Critical theory today, as I shall argue in the remainder of
this essay, confronts the challenge of reconstructing its theory of capitalist society in the light of
new social conditions and developments.
Conflicting Paradigms and the Critical Theory of Society
In discussions within the Institute, Marcuse argued that Horkheimer's "manifesto" underplayed
the importance of philosophy and consequently he wrote a systematic essay on "Philosophy and
Critical Theory" (1968). Horkheimer seemed to agree with this position and himself contributed
a "Postscript" which highlighted the role of philosophy (1972:244ff). Critical theory's goal of
helping to create a rational society, Horkheimer suggests, follows rationalist philosophy's
demand that reason should shape the totality of life and follows as well its activist concept of
rational/critical activity (ibid:244ff.). Yet critical theory "never aims simply at an increase of
competitive capitalism into monopoly capitalism and fascism, and hoped to be part of a historical
process through which capitalism would be replaced by socialism. Their categories were
intended to criticize the existing organization of society and to provide utopian sketches of a
better society. Critical theory is thus motivated by an interest in emancipation from capitalism
and provides a philosophy of social practice engaged in "the struggle for the future." Critical
theory, Horkheimer argued, must remain loyal to the "idea of a future society as the community
of free human beings, insofar as such a society is possible, given the present technical means"
(1972:245).
Pollock's "State Capitalism" (Bronner and Kellner 1989:95-118) established a framework for the
Institute's later analysis of the new relations between the state and the economy during the
postwar era. Pollock claims that state capitalism -- in both its "democratic" and "totalitarian"
forms -- produces a "command economy" exhibiting a "primacy of the political" whereby the
state comes to manage the economy. Against Neumann's analysis of fascism in Behemoth
(1941), Pollock maintained that "the profit motive is superseded by the power motive." Indeed,
the Institute members never agreed about whether economic or political imperatives were
primary for the new fascist state. Building on the Austrian Social Democrat Rudolf's Hilferding's
Finance Capital (1910), Pollock's essay laid the foundation for later claims regarding the
integration of the economy, the state, and the public sphere. It also maintained that capitalism
had discovered new strategies to avoid economic crisis and provided the basis for the burgeoning
belief that capitalism could henceforth stabilize itself and prevent the realization of socialism.
Thus, it raised new doubts concerning the revolutionary role of the working class which was so
central to the classical Marxian theory.
For Marx, the industrial proletariat was to serve as the agent of socialist revolution because it
was the largest, most exploited, and the most militant class. Bearing the burden of industrial
production, the working class was seen as the logical subject of revolution due to its crucial
position in the production process and its potential for organization in highly centralized, largescale industries. The Marxian theory of revolution also predicted severe capitalist economic
crises which would lead the working class to revolt against poverty-stricken conditions where it
had "nothing to lose but its chains." Even as capitalism was undergoing one of its most intense
crises in the 1930s, however, the powerful parties and unions of the European working classes
were defeated by the forces of fascism. Indeed, following that defeat, the prospects for socialist
revolution looked ever bleaker to the Institute theorists.
As a consequence, the critical theorists increasingly distanced themselves from the traditional
Marxist position which claimed that socialist revolution was inevitable and that historical
progress would necessarily lead from capitalism to socialism. Henceforth, their relation to
Marxism would become more ambivalent and complex. While individuals like Horkheimer
would eventually abandon Marxism altogether for a form of mystical irrationalism derived from
Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, Marcuse and others would continue to develop their own particular
versions of the Marxian theory.
included analyses of working class integration within contemporary capitalist societies and new
techniques of capitalist stabilization which severely questioned the Marxian theory of revolution.
According to many critical theorists, new forms of technology, new modes of organizing
production, new configurations of class, and new methods of social control were producing a
"one-dimensional" society without opposition. It also seemed that new forms of political, social,
and especially cultural conformity, were becoming institutionalized (Marcuse 1964; Kellner
1984).
The development of a "totally administered society" led Adorno and Horkheimer to theorize
"the end of the individual" and to stress the importance of preserving subjectivity in order to
fulfill the goals of liberalism and socialism alike. The erosion of subjectivity, they believed,
betrayed the promise of modernity which was itself predicated on the belief that the
augmentation of science and technology would improve human control over nature and produce
greater freedom, individuality, and happiness. Instead, the critical theorists argued, the
institutions and practices of "advanced industrial society" were producing ever greater
conformity and social domination. Ultimately, in his highly esoteric Negative Dialectics and
Aesthetic Theory this situation led Adorno to attempt the resurrection of a repressed subjectivity
against mass society and its philosophical expressions like existentialism and positivism. [7]
It was ultimately Marcuse who provided the most comprehensive formulation of the theory of
one-dimensional society in One Dimensional Man (1964). In his now-classic analysis, advanced
industrial society integrates and absorbs all forces of opposition so that the "subjective"
conditions for conflict between classes, as well as between the individual and society vanish at
the very time that the "objective" reality of exploitation and injustice intensifies. Marcuse
analyzes the new forms of social control in "one-dimensional society" and the diminution of the
"other dimension" of social critique, rebellion, and utopian thinking, which presents alternatives
to the existing order. Against "one-dimensionality," he advocated the "power of negative
thinking" and the "great refusal." These slogans found empirical referents duringthe 1960s in the
New Left and the counterculture which, to some extent, embraced Marcuse as a theoretical
spokesperson (Kellner 1984).
During the 1950s, however, there were divergences between the work of the Institute relocated
in Frankfurt and Fromm, Lowenthal, Marcuse, and others who did not return to Germany and
who frequently developed theories that were at odds with both the current and earlier work of
Horkheimer and Adorno. Thus, it is misleading to consider the work of various critical theorists
during the postWar period as members of a monolithic "Frankfurt School." Whereas there was
both a shared sense of purpose and collective work on supradisciplinary social theory from 1930
to the early 1940s, thereafter critical theorists frequently diverge and during the 1950s and 1960s
the term the "Frankfurt School" can really only be applied to the work of those associated with
the Institute in Germany.
It is therefore impossible to characterize the "Frankfurt School" as a whole since its work
spanned several decades and involved a variety of thinkers who later engaged in sharp debates
with each other. Rather, one should perceive various phases of Institute work: 1) the empiricalhistorical studies of the Grunberg era; 2) the attempts in the early to mid-1930s to establish a
materialist supradisciplinary social theory under Horkheimer's directorship; 3) the attempts to
develop a critical theory of society during the exile period from about 1937 to the early 1940s; 4)
the dispersion of Institute members in the 1940s and the new directions sketched out by
Horkheimer and Adorno; 5) the return of the Institute to Germany and its work in Frankfurt
during the 1950s and 1960s; 6) the development of critical theory in various directions by
Fromm, Lowenthal, Marcuse, and others who remained in the U.S.; 7) the continuation of
Institute projects and development of critical theory in Germany by Jurgen Habermas, Oskar
Negt, Alfred Schmidt, and others in the 1970s and 1980s; and, finally, 8) contributions to critical
theory by a variety of younger theorists and scholars currently active in Europe and the United
States.
In retrospect, one can see that a crisis of critical theory emerged with its fragmentation after
World War II (Kellner 1989a). In effect, its social theory stopped developing, despite some
empirical research projects and sustained metatheoretical analyses by certain of its members,
especially Adorno. Consequently, while I believe that critical theory provides the most advanced
theoretical perspectives within contemporary social theory from the 1930s through the early
1960s (Kellner 1989a), new socio-cultural developments since then have rendered obsolete some
of its theses concerning one-dimensional society, the media, technology, and so on. In particular,
critical theory has not continued to theorize new technologies, new developments in the media,
changes in socialization practices, and new cultural developments. This is somewhat surprising
since its earlier contributions were precisely in these areas. [8]
The reasons for the failure of most critical theorists to update and develop their substantive
social theory are many and complex. Horkheimer seems to have burned out by the 1950s and
provided few important contributions during his later years. Adorno did a great deal of work in
social theory in the 1950s and 1960s, as well as turning out an incredible profusion of texts in the
areas of literary criticism, cultural critique, philosophy, and aesthetics. But his work turned more
and more from supradisciplinary research to philosophical reflections. Habermas also tended to
focus his attention increasingly on philosophical theorizing, although his book Legitimation
Crisis (1975) provides some important new perspectives for critical social theory, as do many of
his later texts, especially Theory of Communicative Action (two volumes, 1984, 1987) and The
Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (1987). [9]
In Germany and the United States, most of the work in critical theory during the last decade has
followed Habermas in attempting to develop more adequate philosophical foundations for
critical theory (see, especially, Benhabib 1986), or to delineate philosophical aspects of critical
theory. Thus, there has been a deficit of social research and elaboration of new theoretical
perspectives in the domain of social theory. Contributions of this sort have come, by contrast,
from members of the postmodern camp who have attempted to theorize the impact of new
technologies, new media, and other socio-cultural developments (see Kellner 1988 and 1989b
and 1989c). The response of critical theory has been by and large to polemicize against
postmodern theory as a new form of irrationalism (Habermas 1987 and the discussion in Kellner
1989a). Yet if critical theory wishes to meet the postmodern challenge and win back its role as
the cutting edge of radical social theory, it must seek new directions and provide theoretical
accounts of contemporary developments in a wide range of domains.
New Directions; New Perspectives
With its fragmentation, trivialization, and academicization, social theory today is in acute crisis
and needs new directions and new perspectives to which critical theory can contribute. While
critical theory stopped developing and articulating new social conditions and developments,
postmodern social theory and theories of postindustrial society lack the sustained commitment to
social research, social critique, and political practice found in the best contributors to critical
theory. While both schools provide a powerful challenge to mainstream theory, I believe that
critical theory's sustained criticism of mainstream theory's presuppositions, methodologies, and
lack of critical reflexivity, provides a more sustained critique than postmodern theory. Moreover,
I believe that critical theory's traditional goal of providing a theory of the present age and radical
politics provides superior perspectives to the often corrosive skepticism and nihilism found in
much postmodern theory which disables both theoretical inquiry and political practice (Kellner
1989b).
But if critical theory seeks to contribute to finding the way out of the contemporary crisis of
social theory, it must itself develop new perspectives. In opposition to the previous model of
"one-dimensional society," critical theorists today should focus on the contradictions, conflicts,
and crisis tendencies within contemporary capitalist societies. To the neglect of political
economy and empirical research found in much critical theory, we should respond with
theoretical analyses of developments within the capitalist economy and of changes in class
stratification, the labor process, new technologies, the media, and politics. In opposition to the
apolitical and even depoliticized versions of critical theory that continue to circulate, those who
wish to revitalize critical theory should attempt to politicize it, to connect it with new social
movements and existing political struggles. As we move into the 1990s and toward the end of the
century, many theoretical and political tasks stand before us. If critical theory wishes to
participate in the Left Turn needed to eliminate the current hegemony of the Right and to help to
build a better society, it needs to develop both its analysis of the present situation and a new
politics in order to become once again the cutting edge of radical social theory. [10]
Notes
1 On critical theory and the Institute for Social Research, see Jay (1973), Wiggershaus (1986),
and Kellner (1989a). I shall draw upon this book here, as well as the introduction to Bronner and
Kellner (1989) and Kellner (1989c).
2 Most of the early sections of this paper focus on Horkheimer because as Director of the
Institute he generally presented the key methodological arguments defining critical theory during
the 1930s. Later, Marcuse, Adorno, and Habermas would develop somewhat different
conceptions. To a reader wishing a first introduction to critical theory, I would suggest reading
the aphorisms in Horkheimer (1978), the essays in Horkheimer (1972), Marcuse (1968), and
Bronner and Kellner (1989).
3 I would reject Brunkhorst's claim (1985) that Horkheimer was at the time "anti-philosophy"
(1985:357), or that he performed "a sublation (Aufhebung) of philosophy into science"
(1985:379). Instead, I am arguing that all phases of critical theory are characterized by a
synthesis, a dialectical mediation, of science and philosophy, although the relationship is
portrayed differently at different stages and in different texts and theorists. For example,
throughout his career, Horkheimer would present different, usually aphoristic, notions of
philosophy and science and their relationships. (Compare, e.g., Horkheimer 1972:34ff., 182ff.,
and 188ff. Consequently, his concepts of philosophy, science, and their relationships are
constantly shifting, though after Dialectic of Enlightenment he was generally critical of science,
technology, and instrumental rationality.
4 For elaborations of this position, see Sohn-Rethel (1978) and Young (1977).
5 On varying conceptions of the concept of totality, see Jay (1984) and for a "war on totality,"
see Lyotard (1984). New French theory tends to draw semantic and theoretico-political
connections between "totality" and "totalitarian" and to reject all totalizing modes of thought as
inherently repressive, reductionist and totalitarian. Such broadside polemics erase differences
between varying concepts and uses of totality, however, and are themselves totalizing and
reductive, covering over the multiplicity of modes of totalizing theories.
6 For the Institute analyses of fascism see the articles collected in Bronner and Kellner (1989)
and the discussion in Kellner (1989a).
7 On Adorno's contributions to critical theory, see Buck-Morss (1977) and Kellner (1989a).
8 See the documentation in Wiggershaus (1986) and Kellner (1989a).
9 Because of space considerations, I am omitting detailed discussion of Habermas' later
methodological and substantive developments of critical theory which are discussed in McCarthy
(1978) and Kellner (1989a).
10 I attempt to develop such an analysis in Kellner 1990.
References
Adorno, Theodor W. 1973. Negative Dialectics.New York: Seabury.