Race Consciousness, Gary Peller

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 63
At a glance
Powered by AI
Some of the key ideas discussed are the emergence of critical race theory and new scholarship by people of color that reinterprets civil rights from different perspectives, as well as a rejection of the dominant view that locates racial oppression in prejudice and stereotypes alone.

Critical race theorists embrace an explicit race consciousness and perspective that locates oneself in the social structure of race relations. They argue that legal categories and institutions embody dominant white cultural assumptions.

The author characterizes the dominant past view as 'integrationist ideology' that locates racial oppression in social structures of prejudice/stereotype based on skin color and identifies progress with transcending racial consciousness.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

1990 Duke L.J. 758 Duke Law Journal September, 1990 Frontiers of Legal Thought III RACE CONSCIOUSNESS Gary Peller a Copyright 1990 by Gary Peller The entire civil rights struggle needs a new interpretation, a broader interpretation. We need to look at this civil rights thing from another anglefrom the inside as well as from the outside. To those of us whose philosophy is black nationalism, the only way you can get involved in the civil rights struggle is to give it a new interpretation. The old interpretation excluded us. It kept us out. 1

Malcolm X, 1963 This Essay is, in part, a reaction to the emergence of critical race theory, the new scholarship about race being produced by people of color in American law schools. 2 As I see it, one of the historically significant features of the critical race theory movement is that, after nearly two decades of relative consensus about what a progressive race reform agenda encompasses, a new generation of scholars is in a sense following Malcolm X's advice, and reinterpreting the meaning of this civil rights thing. The reappearance and refinement of race consciousness in many critical race theory works symbolizes the break with the dominant civil rights discourse. For example, Mari Matsuda calls for a new jurisprudence that would look to the bottom, with the central idea that one's position in the social structure of race relations makes a qualitative difference in how one sees and experiences the world. 3 Kimberl Crenshaw argues that everyday institutional practices embody white norms that are camouflaged by a stance of cultural neutrality presented as perspectivelessness. 4 *759 Gerald Torres demonstrates how legal categories embody dominant cultural assumptions that mistranslate the inner reality of Native American communities and require cultural conformity as the price of legal recognition. 5 And Richard Delgado more generally contends that race makes a substantial difference in how scholars approach legal topics; he emphasizes storytelling and narrative as elements of a distinctive voice employed by people of color. 6 The commitment to a race-conscious perspective by many critical race theorists is dramatic because explicit race consciousness has been considered taboo for at least fifteen years within mainstream American politics and for far longer within the particular conventions of law and legal scholarship. Instead, race has been understood through a set of beliefswhat I call integrationist ideologythat locates racial oppression *760 in the social structure of prejudice and stereotype based on skin color, and that identifies progress with the transcendence of a racial consciousness about the world. In 1964, when Malcolm X asserted that this conventional interpretation of civil rights excluded black nationalists, he could not have foreseen that nationalist activism would revitalize and transform the struggle against racial oppression in the late 1960s and early 1970s, only to be relegated once more to the cultural margins and the desperate streets in the 1980s.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

But Malcolm X did identify the basic racial compromise that the incorporation of the the civil rights struggle into mainstream American culture would eventually embody: Along with the suppression of white racism that was the widely celebrated aim of civil rights reform, the dominant conception of racial justice was framed to require that black nationalists be equated with white supremacists, and that race consciousness on the part of either whites or blacks be marginalized as beyond the good sense of enlightened American culture. When a new generation of scholars embraced race consciousness as a fundamental prism through which to organize social analysis in the latter half of the 1980s, a negative reaction from mainstream academics was predictable. That is, Randall Kennedy's criticism of the work of critical race theorists for being based on racial stereotypes and status-based standards 7 is coherent from the vantage point of the reigning interpretation of racial justice. And it was the exclusionary borders of this ideology that Malcolm X identified. In this Essay, I want to explore the ideological roots of this particular political momentin which the repudiation of race consciousness defines conventional civil rights thinkingby contrasting integrationist and black nationalist images of racial justice, and by comparing the ways that white and black communities have understood race. My argument, in summary form, is that the boundaries of today's dominant rhetoric about race were set in the late 1960s and early 1970s, in the context of an intense cultural clash between black nationalists on one side, and integrationists (white and black) on the other. Current mainstream race reform discourse reflects the resolution of that conflict through a tacit, enlightened consensus that integrationismunderstood as the replacement of prejudice and discrimination with reason and neutralityis the proper way to conceive of racial justice, and that the price of the national commitment to suppress white supremacists would be the rejection of race consciousness among African Americans. *761 To understand the dynamics that produced this particular cultural bargain, it is important to comprehend the different meaning that race consciousness historically represents for whites and blacks in America. Within the white community, the conflict over race traditionally has been structured around an opposition between white supremacists who supported segregation, and white liberals and progressives committed to integration and civil rights of reform. To white liberals and progressives, looking through the prism of integrationist ideology, a nationalist conception of racial identity was understood to distinguish backward, ignorant whites from cosmopolitan, educated whites. Whites who took race as central to their self-identity thereby expressed a commitment to racial supremacy, whereas whites who opposed racism understood that opposition to require the transcendence of racial identity in favor of integration and color-blindness. In other words, most white liberals and progressives, projecting themselves as the enlightened avant garde of the white community, automatically associated race nationalism with the repressive history of white supremacy, and never developed either a consciousness or a political practice that comprehended racial identity and power as centrally formative factors in American social relations. In contrast, within at least a faction of the African American community, advocates of black nationalism consistently have opposed an integrationist understanding of racial progress. Instead, black nationalists asserted a positive and liberating role for race consciousness, as a source of community, culture, and solidarity to build upon rather than transcend. They developed a thoroughgoing critique of integrationism as either inevitably, or at the very least historically, linked to assimilation. Within the white community, the issue of race consciousness symbolically divided whites committed to racial justice from whites committed to racial domination. But within the black community, the issue of race consciousness historically divided those committed to norms of racial solidarity from two groups: first, from assimilationists who found white culture more attractive; and second from those who concluded that if the price of black racial identity was the continuation of white racial identity in its traditional, repressive form, then integration was preferable. The conflict between nationalists and integrationists in the late 1960s and early 1970s represented a critical juncture in American race relations. At that time, black nationalism arguably had overtaken integrationism as the dominant ideology of racial liberation among African Americans, while virtually all liberal and progressive whites embraced a theory of integration as the ultimate definition of racial justice. Although there has been some refinement since this historical moment particularly

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

with the development of a national commitment to a limited form *762 of cultural pluralism 8 the basic boundaries of contemporary mainstream thinking about race were set in the early 1970s when a loose coalition of moderate African Americans joined with liberal and progressive whites to resistand equateblack nationalists and white supremacists. The reemergence of race consciousness among scholars of color should be an occasion for liberal and progressive whites to reevaluate our position concerning the racial compromise that mainstream visions of racial justice embody. I believe that the failure of the progressive and liberal white community to comprehend the possibility of a liberating rather than repressive meaning of race consciousness has distorted our understanding of the politics of race in the past and obscures the ways that we might contribute to a meaningful transformation of race relations in the future. Specifically, deep-rooted assumptions of cultural universality and neutrality have removed from critical view the ways that American institutions reflect dominant racial and ethnic characteristics, with the consequence that race reform has proceeded on the basis of integration into white cultural practicespractices that many whites mistake as racially neutral. And even when a commitment to consider the possible ethnocentrism of institutional practices exists, the attempt to construct a racially neutral culture has commonly produced only bland institutional forms whose antiseptic attempts at universalism have ensured the alienation of anyone with any cultural identity at all. 9 It is now time to rethink the ways that racial justice has been understood in dominant discourse for the past several decades. The civil rights era consensus among the enlightened over how to effectuate racial progress has ended. In our times, conservatives utilize the very rhetoric of tolerance, color-blindness, and equal opportunity that once characterized progressive discourse to mark the limits of reform. 10 But it would be a mistake to think that today's conservative discourse is simply a bad faith distortion of a progressive worldview. Serious limits to the integrationist vision existed from the beginning. The fact that support for substantively reformist programs such as affirmative action is articulated in the defensive rhetoric of remedy or diversity, posed as counterbalancing factors to lack of merit, is only one manifestation of deeper ways that civil *763 rights reformism has worked to legitimate the very social relations that originally were to be reformed. In order to comprehend the historical frame within which contemporary race reform discourse operates, it is necessary to review the ideological and cultural dynamics that led to the installation of integrationism as the dominant and enlightened way to understand race, and to the rejection of black nationalism as an extremist and backward doctrine. Of course, this is a complex story; I want simply to describe this cultural development in broad outline form. To that end, Part I summarizes the central analytics and assumptions of the integrationist worldview, roughly in the form that it was understood in the 1960s and 1970s. In Part II, I contrast integrationism with black nationalism as it was articulated during the 1960s by Malcolm X and others. My purpose in these first two parts is to depict integrationism and nationalism as starkly contrasting discourses of racial justice in part to identify integrationism as a particular racial ideology, depending for its persuasiveness on certain background images of social life that are controversial rather than self-evidentand in part to present black nationalism in a systematic, theoretical frame, to counter the deep-seated image in dominant discourse that black nationalism embodied merely an emotional and angry reaction to oppression, rather than an alternative, coherent, and reasoned analysis of the meaning of racial domination. In Part III, I discuss the different ways that integrationism and nationalism can manifest themselves, suggesting that the two worldviews do not necessarily need to take the kind of pure and bipolar forms that I describe. Nevertheless, I argue in Part IV that the contemporary mainstream image of racial justice in terms of transcending race consciousness was embraced in part to resolve the particular threat that black nationalism represented in the late 1960s and early 1970s: In the background of today's dominant discourse about race are the traces of profound cultural anxiety rooted in the broad-ranging critique that militant nationalists lodged against the assumptions of everyday life in American institutions.

I. THE ANALYTICS AND ASSUMPTIONS OF INTEGRATIONISM

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

[A] segregated school system isn't necessarily the same situation that exists in an all-white neighborhood. A school system in an all-white neighborhood is not a segregated school system. The only time it's segregated is when it is in a community other than white, but at the same time is controlled by the whites. So my understanding of a segregated school system, or a segregated community, or a segregated school, is a school that's controlled by people other than those that go there. . . . On the other hand, if we can get an all-black school, that we can control, staff it ourselves with the type of teachers that have our *764 good at heart, with the type of books that have in them many of the missing ingredients that have produced this inferiority complex in our people, then we don't feel that an all-black school is necessarily a segregated school. It's only segregated when it's controlled by someone from outside. I hope I'm making my point. I just can't see where if white people can go to a white classroom and there are no Negroes present and it doesn't affect the academic diet they're receiving, then I don't see where an all-black classroom can be affected by the absence of white children. . . . So, what the integrationists, in my opinion, are saying, when they say that whites and blacks must go to school together, is that the whites are so much superior that just their presence in a black classroom balances it out. I can't go along with that. 11

Malcolm X, 1963 Today the story of the civil rights struggle commonly is told in linear fashion, as if progress in race relations followed a teleological evolutionfrom an ignorant time when racial status was taken to signify real and meaningful differences between people, to the present, enlightened time, when race properly is understood in mainstream culture not to make a difference except as vestiges of unfortunate historical oppression or in terms of a vague and largely privatized ethnic heritage. This sense of linear evolution has lent an aura of inevitability to the story, as if progression from the racial caste system of American slavery to the widespread acceptance of integration and the transcendence of race consciousness as the unquestioned goals of social progress was historically determined. But the process has been neither linear nor inevitable. The institution of racial integration as a social norm results from a cultural struggleplayed out in various theaters of social powerover the meaning of racial domination and racial justice in America. The sense of integrationism as the inevitable means to achieve racial enlightenment reflects both the institutionalization of a particular understanding of what racism means and the marginalization, not only of white supremacists, but also of the opposing analysis represented in the 1960s by Malcolm X and other black nationalists. It is no longer controversial within mainstream American culture that the goal of racial justice consists of something called integration. The disagreements today revolve around how to achieve integration and identify its violation, or, more generally, over how widely to enforce integrationist norms. Conservatives and liberals distinguish themselves according to their positions on affirmative action; 12 on whether intent must *765 exist for a determination of discrimination; 13 on whether rights against discrimination should be understood on a de jure or de facto basis; and whether there is merely a negative right against segregation, rather than *766 an affirmative right to attend integrated institutions. 14 To be sure, these are important issues, and often the choice between a narrow or a wide interpretation of the integrationist vision makes a real, material difference. But the constant and repetitive struggle over the proper way to implement integrationist norms suppresses from consideration the fact that the disagreements occur only within the confines of a shared set of beliefs that comprehend racism as a form of discrimination. I want to discuss here how integrationism has come to define official racial enlightenment less than thirty years after the goal of racial integration symbolized demands for radical reform of American society. I argue that integrationism has achieved mainstream, institutionalized status in part because it has been domesticated. Rather than constituting a broad-ranging indictment of the reigning social structure, as it once did, the goal of civil rights itself has been integrated into the dominant cultural rhetoric. Seen through the universalizing lenses of the liberal American ideology of progress and enlightenment, racial integration appears as part of a general societal discourse that comprehends legitimacy in terms of policing borders between rationality and objectivity on the one hand and prejudice and bias on the other.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

In the first Section, I describe the analytic components of integrationism as it has been understood in mainstream American culture; in the second, I relate the integrationist categories of prejudice, discrimination, and segregation to background images of rationality and universality in liberal and enlightenment thought. I then suggest that this way of thinking about race can serve not only to criticize, but also to legitimate *767 various social practices; this analysis concludes with a discussion of how the integrationist reform of public schools reflects at a practical, institutional level the features that I describe at an ideological level. The point of discussing integrationism in this way is to show that the currently dominant vision of racial justice is not inevitable or self-evident, but rather is situated within the confines of a particular set of social, cultural, and philosophical assumptions about the world. Its dominance presupposes a set of political and social choices that could have beenand can bemade differently. After describing integrationism, I contrast it with the opposing black nationalist analysis of race.

A. The Analytic Components of Integrationism The goal of racial integration has taken many forms and has been supported by various worldviews. At one time, the idea of racial integration represented a powerful, spiritually-rooted social resistance movement that threatened to destabilize the status quo of American institutional life in profound ways. Under the banner of integrationism, hundreds of thousands of people mobilized to challenge the political, economic, and cultural power relations in cities and towns across the country, employing tactics that included mass protest, economic boycotts, civil disobedience, sit-ins, and strikes. 15 There is therefore nothing intrinsic to the concept of racial integration that demands that it be understood in the way I am about to describe it. What I want to capture here is the general cultural sense that became dominant in the 1960s and 1970s of what racism consists of and how to overcome it. From this perspective, integrationism should be understood to comprise a set of attitudes and beliefs for perceiving the meaning of racist domination and for identifying the goals of racial justice. The concepts *768 of prejudice, discrimination, and segregation are the key structural elements of this ideology. Each idea embodies a different manifestation of what is seen as the central aspect of racismthe distortion of reason through the prism of myth and ignorance. In the integrationist perspective, racism is rooted in consciousness, in the cognitive process that attributes social significance to the arbitrary fact of skin color. The mental side of racism is accordingly represented as either prejudicethe prejudging of a person according to mythological stereotypesor biasthe process of being influenced by subjective factors. The key image here is of irrationalismthe problem with prejudice is that it obscures the work of reason by clouding perception with beliefs rooted in superstition. 16 The paradigmatic manifestation is the white supremacist myth structure that asserts natural, biological differences between blacks and whitesthe familiar identification of whites with the qualities of intelligence, industriousness, and piousness, and the corresponding association of blacks with the qualities of dullness, laziness and lustfulness. 17 The opposite of the ignorance that appears as racism *769 is knowledgeknowledge gleaned from actual interracial experience rather than mythologies of stereotype. In the integrationist ideology, racism achieves social form when the distortion of prejudice in consciousness subsequently translates into practice. Here racism manifests itself in the practice of discrimination, in the disparate treatment of whites and blacks that the irrational attribution of difference is supposed to justify. The paradigm practice of racism in its systematic, social form was the Jim Crow system of de jure segregation, which institutionalized racial apartheid on the basis of an ideology of white supremacy. 18 And just as prejudice is implicitly contrasted with knowledge, discrimination is contrasted with neutrality the social practice of equal treatment.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

The solution to segregation, then, is integration, understood as a social vision opposed to racism, in each realm in which racism manifests itself. Within consciousness, integration means overcoming prejudice based on skin color. Therefore, reflecting one dimension of integrationist ideology, people began to understand themselves as possible racists to the extent they believed in irrational images of people based on skin-color stereotypes. The ideal was to transcend stereotypes in favor of treating people as individuals, free from racial group identification. 19 *770 At the level of practice, the integrationist cure for discrimination is equal treatment according to neutral norms. And at the institutional level, integrationism obviously means an end to the social system of racial segregation. In sum, the cure for racism would be equal treatment on an individual level and integration on an institutional level. In any event, integrationists believed the two would go hand in hand. Once neutrality replaced discrimination, equal opportunity would lead to integrated institutions; 20 experience in integrated institutions would, in turn, replace the ignorance of racism with the knowledge that actual contact provides. This deep link between racism and ignorance on the one hand, and integration and knowledge on the other, helps explain the initial focus of integrationists on public education: Children who attended integrated schools would learn the truth about each others' unique individuality before they came to believe stereotypes rooted in ignorance. By attending the same schools, children would in turn have equal opportunity at the various roles in American social life. 21 *771 The integrationists' diagnosis of the distortions of the white supremacy ideology focuses on the failure of white supremacists to recognize the universal characteristics shared by whites and blacks. According to the integrationists, white racists perceive the world through a false structure of same and other that utilizes a concept of blacks as other and denies that the attributes that characterize whites exist in blacks. Thus the rationality and piousness that supposedly characterize whites are, within racist ideology, denied to blacks. The integrationist proposes to correct this situation by distributing these characteristics across race lines: Blacks can be rational and pious; whites can be emotional and lustful. In other words, according to integrationist ideology, racists make the mistake of essentializing racial categories and believing that there is some necessary, intrinsic relationship between race and particular social characteristics. Integrationists are committed to the view that race makes no real difference between people, except as unfortunate historical vestiges of irrational discrimination. 22 In an extreme form of the integrationist picture, the hope is that when contact occurs between different groups in society, not only race, but all ethnic identity will become a thing of the past. 23

*772 B. Race, Universal Reason, and Liberal Progress Of course, this is a highly abstracted model of what I mean by the ideology of integrationism; I assume that these general ideas about race are so familiar that simply evoking them calls to mind the fuller meaning of integrationism in mainstream American culture. But at the same time it is important to grasp the integrationist worldview at this level of generality. Integrationists comprehend racism at a high level of abstraction in part because they wish to transcend the bias of particularity that they see as the root of racist consciousness. Integrationism, in short, links up with a broader set of liberal imagesimages that connect truth, universalism, and progress. A commitment to a form of universalism, and an association of universalism with truth and particularism with ignorance, forms the infrastructure of American integrationist consciousness. 24 This universalism is the common theme that connects the integrationist analytic distinctions between reason and prejudice, objectivity and bias, neutrality and discrimination, and integration and segregation. Each dichotomy envisions a realm of impersonality, understood as the transcendence of subjective bias and contrasted with an image of a realm of distortion where particularity and stereotype reign. Integrationist beliefs are organized around the familiar enlightenment story of progress as consisting of the movement from mere belief and superstition to knowledge and reason, from the particular and therefore parochial to the universal and therefore enlightened. 25

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

Within this frame for organizing social perception, controversy revolves around how to categorize particular social practices as either rational and neutral or irrational and biased. Liberals and conservatives can be distinguished by how far they believe the realms of either bias or neutrality extend. But conservatives' and liberals' basic comprehension *773 of racial justice has the same underlying structureto universalize institutional practices in order to efface the distortions of irrational factors like race, to make social life neutral to racial identity. To both liberals and conservatives, racism consists of a form of distortion that could be superseded by an aracial arena of social understanding. Once we remove prejudice, reason will take its place; once we remove discrimination, neutrality will take its place; and once we remove segregation, integration will take its place. 26 One way that this universalizing character of integrationism manifests itself in perception is that diverse social phenomena begin to appear the same because they are all viewed through the same analytic lens. From within this structure for cataloguing and organizing thinking about social life, racism becomes equivalent to other forms of prejudice and discrimination based on irrational stereotype. Social domination based on race, gender, sexual preference, religion, age, national origin, language, and physical disability or appearance, can all be categorized as the same phenomena because they all represent biasunderstood as a deviation from a neutral, rational standard. Similarly, the fact that relations between Anglos and African Americans, Asians, and Hispanics are all perceived as presenting the issues of discrimination against racial minorities in legal and political discourse reflects the same structure of abstraction. From this structure, it begins to appear that the social subordination of various groups does not have a complex, particular, and historical context, but rather is a formal, numeric problem of the relations of majorities to minorities, unified under the concept discrimination. Moreover, given this universalist dimension to integrationist thinking, it is plausible to conceive of a category of reverse racism, which is really not reverse at all. Since racism means a deviation from a universal norm of objectivity, it can be practiced by anyone, and anyone can be its victim, regardless of their particular historical circumstances or power relations. Thus, within the integrationist ideology, a black person who stereotypes whites is racist in the same way as a white person who harbors prejudice against blacks. And blacks who discriminate against whites are guilty of the same kind of racism as whites who discriminate against blacks. Anyone can engage in racism because we can identify racism from a vantage point of race neutrality, of not making someone's race count for anything. In short, the symmetry of the integrationist picture is rooted in the idea that racism consists of possessing a race consciousness *774 about the world, in thinking that race should make a difference in social relations. Finally, given the idea of immutability common to categories of discrimination, the story of the struggle against racism can be related in a way that follows the basic script of liberal progress more generally. Race consciousness is associated with status-based social coercion, where individuals are treated in a particular way because of the arbitrary fact of membership in a social group they did not choose. The transcendence of race consciousness represents a social movement toward the freedom of the individual to choose group identification. Like classical images of the common law, the vision underlying integrationist ideology is of American culture working itself pure by overcoming the distortions of various kinds of prejudice in favor of the increasing rationalization of institutional forms, which in turn provides greater individual liberty to choose, free of coercive social power. Freedom from racial discrimination is but one instance of the historical move from status to contract, from caste to individual liberty. 27 Individualism and universalism are thereby linked together. 28 The aims of racial integration seem self-evident because they are one part of a web of meaning that constitutes the dominant ideology of the nature of social progress itself. The meaning of race has been grafted onto other central cultural images of progress, so that the transition from segregation to integration and from race consciousness to race neutrality mirrors movements from myth to enlightenment, from ignorance to knowledge, from superstition to reason, from the primitive to the civilized, from religion to secularism, 29 and, most importantly, the historical self-understanding of liberal society as representing the movement from status to individual liberty. In other words, integrationist ideology comprehends the issue of racial domination

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

by viewing race relations through stock images about the nature of progress in liberal society and through the prism of a qualitative difference between liberal enlightenment and *775 feudal hierarchy. The struggle against racism thus appears natural and inevitable, as simply another part of the teleological progression toward the liberation of social life. 30

C. Integration and Legitimation This liberal integrationist approach to race has some real attractions. The image of universality, and its correlate aim of transcending racial consciousness, forms a large part of the deep appeal that the integrationism vision has for many of us. This vision seems to reflect, at the ideological level, the occasional glimpses we attain in personal relations of a deep shared identity as fellow human beings in what are often the very best moments of social life. The aspiration for racial integration confirms our sense of the possibility of true and authentic relations that transcend racial status and other forms of cultural distance and difference. And integrationism appeals to the utopian ideal that these moments could be translated into organized institutional practices because, at the core, we are all the same, regardless of race. But this universalism also marks the narrowing limits of integrationist ideology. Understanding this aspect of integrationism helps one to comprehend how well-intentioned people could view the manner in which racial integration has actually proceeded in American life as, without question, a progressive reform of race relations. As I have described it, integrationism is organized around an image of reason and neutrality that represents the transcendence of bias and prejudice. The liberal discourse of race represented by integrationism actually contains within itself two distinct ways to perceive social practices. On the one hand, the possibility of bias and prejudice constitutes a language of critique and reform that provides a framework to articulate what needs to be changed in society. On the other hand, this liberal discourse also constitutes a narrative of legitimation, a language for concluding that particular social practices are fair because they are objective and unbiased. This second aspect of liberal discourse embodies a conception of a realm of social life outside the influence of racial history and politics. *776 Take, for example, the debate about affirmative action. In this context, race consciousness is employed by those interested in race reform. The familiar dilemma that surrounds affirmative action is that it requires the use of race as a socially significant category, although the deepest aims of integrationist ideology point toward the transcendence of race consciousness. The dominant discourse about affirmative action reflects the core categories of the liberal theory of race that I described. The issues in the affirmative action debate are organized around the same structural opposition between reason and bias. Here, the category of merit represents the universal, impersonal side of integrationist perception. The use of race-conscious means to distribute social goods is problematic because it represents a deviation from the impersonality of merit. Thus, liberal support of affirmative action has always been defensive because its proponents themselves experience it, at least in part, as dissonant with their most fundamental convictions. Affirmative action has been characterized as merely an exceptional remedy for past injustice, rather than an affirmative right rooted in present social circumstances. It has been characterized as temporary and only necessary to achieve integration, at which time equal opportunity can take over. And affirmative action has been defended on the grounds that its beneficiaries have suffered from a deprived background, so that putting a thumb on the side of minorities in the scales of social decisionmaking helps even out the otherwise rationalized competition for social goods. 31 Alternatively, affirmative action has been defended on the grounds of promoting diversity, an approach that challenges the notion of merit as the sole basis on which to distribute social opportunities. According to this justification, merit is only one value to be vindicated in determining admission to various institutions. Alongside merit is the value of *777 having a racially diversified society, a justification that can be used to counterbalance merit as a criterion. 32

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

Whether articulated in terms of remedy or diversity, this discourse assumes that minority applicants are less qualified on neutral, impersonal, and objective criteria. Thus, to integrate institutions, we must compromise meritocratic standards either temporarilyin order to break the cycles of institutional life that racial domination entailedor permanently, by diffusing merit with other ends such as diversity. Today, conservative integrationists preach a principled commitment to color-blindness in institutional practices, even if it results in segregated institutions, and liberal integrationists advocate limited, effects-oriented race consciousness in order to ensure that some integration actually takes place. But from within the discourse through which they perceive the issues, both commit to the premise that the category of merit itself is neutral, impersonal, and somehow developed outside the economy of social power, with its significant currency of race, class, and gender, that marks American social life. 33 Given their view of the pervasive nature of American racism, at least in the recent past, it is conceivable that integrationists might have demanded a radical transformation of social practices before they assumed the existence of merit-based decisionmaking. But instead, integrationists assumed that fair, impersonal criteria simply would be what remained once the distortion of race consciousness was removed. One manifestation of this assumption was that the purportedly broad social transformation reflected in the national struggle against racism resulted in hardly any change in administrative personnel. The transformation from a Jim Crow to an integrationist racial regime was thought to require *778 only a change in the rules of social decisionmaking. The same whites who once carried out the formal program of American apartheid actually kept their jobs as the decisionmakers charged with evaluating merit in the employment offices of companies and in the admissions offices of schools in the post-segregation world. In institution after institution, progressive reformists have found themselves struggling over the implementation of racial integration with the former administrators of racial segregation, many of whom soon constituted an old guard concerned over the deterioration of standards. The point here is not to suggest that racism so permeated those who managed segregated institutions that the only solution was to purge them all. There can be no doubt that many people who kept their jobs should at least have been relieved of institutional authoritybut that is not my point. I want to suggest that the continuity of institutional authority symbolizes the limited nature of social reform that most integrationists associated with the achievement of racial justice. Even more dramatic than the continuity of personnel (since the particular people in power eventually age, retire and die), the same criteria that defined the standards during the period of explicit racism continue to be used, as long as they cannot be linked directly to racial factors. Within liberal integrationism, racism, seen to consist of a deviation from neutral, impersonal norms, focused on the exclusion of people of color, with the idea that all the rest of the cultural practices of formerly segregated institutions would stay the same. From within the integrationist ideology of neutral standards, no conceptual base existed from which integrationists could question whether standards, definitions of merit, and the other myriad features of the day-to-day aspects of institutional life constructed or maintained during segregation might have reflected deeper aspects of a culture within which the explicit exclusion of blacks seemed uncontroversial. And integrationists, organizing their perception of racial justice around images of objectivity, rationality, and neutrality, never considered whether this language for distinguishing the worthy from the unworthy itself might serve to help justify racial dominationif not to its victims, then at least to white beneficiaries who need to believe that their social positions are the result of something more than the brute fact of social power and racial domination. 34 *779 Liberal integrationist ideology is structured so that some social practices are taken out of the economy of race relations, and understood to be undistorted by racial power. To be sure, no analytically necessary point from within the terms of the integrationist view of race exists at which the line between racial discrimination and neutral meritocracy must be drawn. One can imagine that the very definition of what constitutes qualifications to attend law school, to work as a police officer, to own a home, to live in a particular neighborhood, or to have a particular income could be challenged as either directly rooted in

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

the distortions of race consciousness or more indirectly dependent on a rhetoric through which the powerful generally justify their share of the distribution of social benefits. And, in some contexts, reform within the integrationist tradition followed this path. But integrationism also labels the distribution of social goods as impersonal and neutral once we remove distortions like race consciousness. Integrationists tend to understand racism as a particular, identifiable deviation from an otherwise rational decisionmaking process that is not itself based in the history of social struggle between groups and worldviews. This narrow image of the domain of racial power characterizes the tendency of liberal integrationism to become part of a self-justifying ideology of privilege and status. The realm of neutral social practices from which to identify bias and deviation constitutes a whole realm of institutional characteristics removed from critical view as themselves historical, contingent and rooted in the particularities of culturea realm that is itself a manifestation of group power, of politics. This obscures the possibility that the very core values of liberal integrationiststhe ideals of objectivity, rationality, and neutralitywere historically constructed out of particular perspectives and as responses to specific historical situations rather than representing the transcendence of perspective itself.

D. Integrationism in Social Form: Public Schools To this point, I have described integrationism simply as a set of ideas that form a recognizable worldview about race. But the ideology that I am evoking does not simply exist in people's heads as a group of concepts. That is, although these beliefs do characterize recognizable social and legal philosophies, integrationist ideology and the liberal dualities that provide its context are more diffuse and in the background of our social world than the image of a philosophy suggests. We should see integrationism as one part of a more general cultural meaning system, *780 rather than as a worked-out theory. Integrationist assumptions do not manifest themselves solely in self-conscious legal and political argument about race, but instead provide the filter for how we experience, perceive, and construct a broad range of social relations and institutional practices. Seeing integrationism as the race component of a wider cultural ideology reflects the sense we have that a wide array of social practices and programs for reform hang togethernot as necessarily implicated by analytic necessity, but recognizable as a particular discourse in our culture nevertheless. Consider the program for reform of Southern public schools in which integrationism played a central part in the 1960s. Public education, at least in the South, embodied the most realized attempt to institutionalize the cultural assumptions of the liberal, enlightenment ideology underlying integrationism. Integrationists put tremendous energy and effort into the struggle over Southern schools. Here the universalism of liberal race ideology appeared as a commitment to centralism in institutional culture and a corresponding opposition to local control. And here the terms of the cultural compromise reflected in the national embrace of integrationism were clearest: In liberal education reform, the definition of what constitutes enlightened good sense was drawn in negative contrast to an image of the backward and ignorant whites who opposed racial integration of Southern public schools, and whose lack of enlightenment was further symbolized by their embrace of the mythologies of fundamentalist religion. Liberal integrationism entailed a trade-off of this redneck culture with African American culture; in consideration for the suppression of white Southern working class culture in schools, blacks were expected to accede to the suppression of African American culture as well. Instead, school life would be characterized by the particular culture of technocracy and professionalism, presented as the aracial, neutral face of quality in education, and as the transcendence of localism and particularity. Racial integration of Southern schools represented only one aspect of the liberal reform of public education. Roughly simultaneous with the constitutional prohibition of racial segregation in public education, school prayer was also declared an unconstitutional violation of the norm of state neutrality. 35 There was a deep link between these two major reforms. The logic of the joint rejection of school segregation and school *781 prayer was contained in the sense that each reform reflected a progressive move from ignorance and parochialism to enlightenment and equality, from the particular and biased to the universal and objective. 36 Just as school segregation represented the bias of the primitive beliefs of white supremacists, school prayer

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

10

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

represented the bias of local, primitive religious beliefs. Just as school segregation formed one manifestation of the social face of racial discrimination, compulsory school prayer was the social face of religious intolerance, of discrimination according to theology. And just as school integration substituted universal and neutral norms for the particularities of white supremacist myth, the ban on school prayer substituted a neutral, secular discourse for the particularities of religious belief. 37 The similarity in the way that segregation and prayer were understood is one manifestation of the deep connections between integrationism as an ideology and centralism as an institutional norm. Today's culture of public education is marked by a commitment in institutional life to the same kind of universalizing that integrationism reflects in ideological form. Along with the banning of the perceived local biases of segregationism and religion, a great centralization of curriculum and administration has occurred. The advanced degrees of administrators, the prevalent professional status of school board members, the implementation of standardized tests on a widespread basis, the exclusion of religion from schools, and the near-universal replacement of corporal punishment (paddling in the Southern vernacular) with therapeutic or contractual counseling approaches to student discipline, all reflect the attempt to substitute a standardized national culture of public school administration for the perceived repressionrooted in parochialismof the former institutional culture of Southern schools. There is no analytic reason for the simultaneous occurrence of all these changes in the culture of the public schools: Racial integration has been just one part of a more general sanitization of Southern public educationthe formerly maternal relationship between teacher and student has been replaced by the cool of professional distance. Graduate schools teaching expertly tested methods of instruction replaced traditional training of teachers through contact with older faculty. The decentralization of curriculum now exists only as a formality, as public education has, for all practical purposes *782 except funding, been nationalized. The standardized test and the cultural commitment to the No. 2 pencil are the lived, institutionalized rituals that reflect the commitment to impersonality and objectivity at the ideological level. 38 In educational discourse, professionalism plays the same symbolic role as merit, as a neutral alternative to irrational bias. Liberal reformers of public education in the late 1950s and 1960s associated professionalism with centralism, and understood that both provide a way to oppose local parochialism: The public interest is almost invariably better served by leaving professional questions to the professionals. 39 Likewise, local control results in the same kind of intellectual parochialism that characterizes schools in totalitarian countries. 40 Professionalism is the legitimating rhetoric of public school administration. Centralism and professionalism became responsive images to the liberal perception of the previous problems with public educationthe idea that localism and parochialism compromised neutrality and objectivity. And the underlying assumption was that once public education eradicated the influences of locality and bias, it would achieve a neutral, acultural form that, precisely because of its impersonality, would treat everyone alike. Localismlike race consciousnesshad to be resisted because it threatened the connection between universalism, individualism and truth with the particularism of culture, community and politics. Myron Lieberman argued that: National survival now requires educational policies which are not subject to local veto. . . . It is becoming increasingly clear that local control cannot in practice be reconciled with the ideals of a democratic society. . . . Local control is a major cause of the dull parochialism and attenuated totalitarianism that characterizes public education in operation. 41

Which brings us back to the Malcolm X quote that introduces this section. In his view, the problem with school segregation was not the failure to integrate black and white children, but rather the dynamics of power and control that formed the historical context of racial separation. Whereas liberals experienced integrationism as a progressive rejection of the bias and parochialism of the local in favor of the impersonality of centralized authority, Malcolm X asserted that the very goal of the struggle *783 against racism was to achieve local control, to liberate community institutions from outside, colonial rule. While the dominant

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

11

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

culture translated the demand for local control as the states' rights discourse of Southern racism and the religious dogma of Southern fundamentalists, Malcolm X associated local control with racial liberation. And while integrationists understood public school integration to be the institutional synonym for racial justice, Malcolm X asserted that integration was a manifestation of white supremacist ideology. To grasp how he could understand racial liberation in terms so diametrically opposed to the mainstream discourse of liberal integrationism, it makes sense to turn now to the alternative ideology of race developed by Malcolm X and other black nationalists.

II. THE BLACK NATIONALIST CRITIQUE Thus, within the black community there are two separate challenges to the traditional integration policy which long has constituted the major objective of established Negro leadership. There is the general skepticism that the Negro, even after having transformed himself into a white black-man, will enjoy full acceptance in American society; and there is the longer-range doubt that even should complete integration somehow be achieved, it would prove to be really desirable, for its price may be the total absorption and disappearance of the racea sort of painless genocide. Understandably, it is the black masses who have most vociferously articulated these dangers of assimilation, for they have watched with alarm as the more fortunate among their ranks have gradually risen to the top only to be promptly integrated off into the white communityabsorbed into another culture, often with undisguised contempt for all that had previously constituted their racial and cultural heritage. Also, it was the black masses who first perceived that integration actually increases the white community's control over the black one by destroying institutions, and by absorbing black leadership and coinciding its interests with those of the white community. . . . Such injurious, if unintended, side effects of integration have been felt in almost every layer of the black community. 42

Robert S. Browne, 1968 Like integrationism, black nationalism among African Americans has taken various forms and has been associated with divergent *784 worldviews. 43 The long tradition dates back to antebellum proposals by Martin Delany and others to colonize parts of Africa as a homeland for American blacks. 44 Some form of nationalism was manifest in Booker T. Washington's selfhelp and separatist ideas of black advancement. 45 Black nationalism in its modern, urban form can be traced among the *785 poor to the organizing efforts of Marcus Garvey in the 1930s, 46 and of the Black Muslims since, 47 and among the middle class to W.E.B. Du Bois' critique of the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People's (NAACP) policy of integrationism in the 1930s. 48 There is little doubt, however, that black nationalism had its most complete and sophisticated theoretical development, as well as its greatest mass appeal, during the 1960s and early 1970s, when it was articulated as an alternative worldview to integrationism and as part of a program of *786 radical social transformation by, among others, Malcolm X, 49 Eldridge Cleaver, 50 Stokely Carmichael, 51 Imamu Baraka, 52 Harold Cruse, 53 the Black Panthers, 54 and quickly-expanding factions of the Student Nonviolent Coordinating Committee (SNCC) and the Congress of Racial Equality (CORE). 55 I will discuss black nationalism with specific reference to the ways in which it was articulated in the late 1960s and early 1970s. My goal here is not to provide a complete social history or philosophical account, but instead to sketch out, in general form, the ways that nationalists opposed the understanding of race embodied by integrationist ideology.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

12

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

The controversy in the mid-1960s over the slogan Black Power exemplifies the contrast between integrationists and black nationalists. I begin the introduction to nationalism with a brief analysis of the issues at stake in the Black Power idea. I then discuss the nationalist critique of integration at an institutional level, focusing on public schools and the movement for community control. In the third Section, I describe ways in which nationalist intellectuals contested more general and abstract epistemological assumptions of liberal integrationism. I conclude this Part with a discussion of the systematic differences between integrationist and nationalist analyses of the meaning of racial domination and reform.

*787 A. Black Power The black nationalist position received its first modern wave of sustained mass exposure in 1966 when Willie Ricks and Stokely Carmichael began using the term Black Power during the March Against Fear in Mississippi. 56 Tension between integrationist and nationalist approaches had already erupted within and between various civil rights organizations. But the high-profile and polarized controversy over the term Black Power transformed what had been largely an underground conflict into a full-scale, highly-charged public debate over the fundamental direction and conception of the civil rights movement. 57 *788 The mainstream reactions to the idea of comprehending the civil rights movement as a struggle for Black Power reflect the discourse associated with the marginalization of nationalist race consciousness in the dominant cultural rhetoric. Both black and white integrationists equated Black Power with white supremacy. 58 Hubert Humphrey responded by reject ing calls for racism, whether they come from a throat that is *789 white or one that is black. 59 Roy Wilkins charged that no matter how endlessly they try to explain it, the term Black Power means anti-white power. He characterized Black Power as a reverse Mississippi, a reverse Hitler, a reverse Ku Klux Klan. 60 Time and Kenneth Clark each referred to Black Power as a racist philosophy, 61 and Crisis, the publication of the NAACP, called Black Power advocates black neo-segregationists and advocates of apartheid. 62 In fact, the virulent and extreme denunciation of Black Power symbolized the unity of what would quickly become the new center of American consciousness about race. 63 The integrationists saw two problems with Black Power. First, the concept assumed that power should be distributed on a racial basis, thereby assuming that American society should be thought of in terms of *790 separate white and black communities. Black Power thus violated both the integrationist principle to transcend race consciousness at the ideological level and the integrationist program to end the segregation of whites and blacks at the institutional and community level. Second, the Black Power concept troubled integrationists because it assumed that power determined the distribution of social resources and opportunities, rather than reason or merit. It was not simply the theory of Black Power that engendered the charged reaction, but rather the resistance to the reigning liberal idea of progress through reasoned discussion and deliberation that the Black Power movement, for a time, embodied. The clenched fist of the Black Power salute and the militaristic affectation of many black nationalist groups were the overt physical manifestations of this dimension of the movement. Through the ideological filters of integrationism, black nationalism and white supremacy appear essentially the same because both are rooted in race consciousness, in the idea that race matters to one's perception and experience of the world. Integrationists saw nationalists as regressive because, in the integrationist view, progress meant transcending race as a basis of social decisionmaking, and in the long term, replacing power with reason as the basis for the distribution of resources. With the centering of integrationism as the mainstream ideology of American good sense, nationalism became marginalized as an extremist and backward worldview, as the irrational correlate in the black community to the never-say-die segregationists of the white community.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

13

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

But the equation of black nationalists and white supremacists assumes a neutral standard from which to identify race consciousness as a deviation, and from which to link race inherently to prejudice and domination. When viewed in terms of the actual context of history and power relations between racial groups in America, however, white supremacy and black nationalism embodied very different understandings of race. The mainstream reactions to black nationalism were so vociferous not because the Black Power movement presented any real threat of racial domination by blacks, but rather because black nationalism embodied a profound rejection of the reigning ideology for understanding the distribution of power and privilege in American society. Just as integrationism became the mainstream discourse for racial justiceto the extent that it could be articulated in the terms of a deep cultural selfidentity of enlightenment-through-evolution toward rationality and objectivitythe nationalist analysis of racial justice became threatening, in part, because it challenged the universalist assumptions underlying these images of progress. These images were challenged as themselves elements of a particular ideology of power and of the particular culture of whites.

*791 B. Nationalism as a Critique of Universalism Integrationists by and large never comprehended the analysis of racial domination presented by black nationalists. From their universalist view of racism as a distortion of an otherwise aracial rationality, integrationists interpreted the race consciousness of black nationalists as the mark of racism and never considered the nationalist position as a competing, alternative, and systematic analysis of the meaning of racial domination. Thus, when black nationalists declared that integration was a subterfuge for white supremacy 64 and even represented a form of painless genocide, 65 integrationists literally could not understand what they were talking about. The nationalist worldview was based on a fundamentally different set of beliefs and perceptual categories through which reforms that looked progressive to integrationists looked regressive to nationalists. The contrast between the integrationist commitment to centralization and expertise in public education and Malcolm X's discourse of local, community control was only one manifestation of the deep and thoroughgoing opposition between integrationists and nationalists on the more basic issue of the meaning of race in America. Where integrationists understood race through the prism of universalismfrom within which race consciousness appeared arbitrary, irrational, and symmetrically evil whether practiced by whites or blacksnationalists viewed race in the particular context of American history, where racial identity was seen as a central basis for comprehending the significance of various social relations as they are actually lived and experienced, and within which the meaning of race was anything but symmetrical. The opposition between centralism and local control that distinguished integrationist and nationalist rhetoric about schools had its philosophical correlates in the opposition between timelessas opposed to historicistviews about identity and group consciousness, between the discourses of impersonal professionalism and ideas of organic community, and most generally between the assumptions of universalism and the assertions of qualitative cultural differences encompassed in the idea of nationalism. These basic differences are reflected in the very idea that African Americans comprise a nation. This starting point is commonly associated with separatism in general, and with the demand for a separate nation as a homeland for American blacks in particular. But while at least some geographic separation has often characterized nationalist programs, 66 *792 and while the idea of a formal nation-state has been advocated by several nationalist groups, 67 there is, as I see it, no necessary relation between nationalism as a way to understand race relations and a formal demand for geographic separation. 68 Instead, the image of African Americans as a nation within a nation 69 should be understood as a symbol of the core assertion that race consciousness constitutes African Americans as a distinct social community, in much the same way that national self-identity operates to establish the terms of recognition and identity in regular nations. 70 In contrast to the integrationist premise that blacks and whites are essentially the same, the idea of race as the organizing basis for group consciousness asserts

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

14

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

that blacks and whites are different, in the sense of coming from different communities, neighborhoods, churches, families, and histories, and of being in various ways foreigners to each other. 71 *793 And in contrast to the white supremacist ideology of natural, essential racial characteristics, the image of nationhood locates differences between whites and blacks in social history, in the temporal context in which all national identity must come into being. As Dr. C. Munford put it: It is different from other emergent nations only in that it consists of forcibly transplanted colonial subjects who have acquired cohesive identity in the course of centuries of struggle against enslavement, cultural alienation, and the spiritual cannibalism of white racism. This common history which the Black people of America share is manifested in a concrete national culture with a peculiar spiritual complexion, or psychological temperament. Though the Black nation expresses its thoughts, emotions, and aspirations in the same tongue as American whites, the different conditions of existence . . . have, from generation to generation, welded the bonds of a national experience as different from that of white existence as day is from night. And what differentiates nations from one another are dissimilar conditions of life. 72

The depth of identification of self and recognition of others implicit in the idea of nationhood based on generations of dissimilar conditions of life marks a vision of community that cannot be captured in the liberal dichotomies of either liberty and coercion, or reason and myth. The *794 public assertion of spiritual cohesion represented by black nationhood contested the liberal border between public objectivity and private sentiment underlying the link between universality and individualism. 73 Nationhood, understood as an historically created community, assumes that social bonds of identity, recognition, and solidarity can be liberating and fulfilling outside the family. In this way, nationalists articulated what might be seen as an historicized view of social relations. In opposition to the universal vantage point used by integrationists to identify bias and prejudice, nationalists presented the time-bound, messy, and inherently particular social relations between nations as the central ground from which to perceive race. In opposition to the essentializing of race engaged in by white supremacists, nationalists located the meaning of race in history, in the social structures that people rather than God or some objectified naturehave created. Again, the commitment to an historical view means that there is no objective or natural necessity to the way that groups, identities, and social meanings have been structured. Because the structure of race relations is a social creation, it could have been constructed differently in the past and could still be changed in the future. But the nationalist view contrasts with the liberal image of group identity either as an irrational status or as a matter of choicea voluntary, willed association. The idea of a nationalist base of social identity is that we are, in a sense, thrown into history, with aspects of social reality already structured to limit some possibilities, while making other ones available. Rather than imagining that people simply exist as autonomous individuals who create social relations out of acts of private will, C. Munford, for example, saw African Americans in terms of traditions and communities that provide the historical context for individual identity. From a nationalist perspective, the fact that African Americans compose a socially-created community, in terms of a contingent history, does not mean that the community that exists should be rejected because it represents either a distortion that must be transcended or the result of domination that must be erased. Against the liberal image that group identity and status are opposed to the possibility of individual freedom, the nationalist perspective sees in historical structures the very basis for social meaning. 74

*795 C. The Nationalist Interpretation of School Integration Integration as a goal speaks to the problem of blackness not only in an unrealistic way but also in a despicable way. It is based on complete acceptance of the fact that in order to have a decent house or education, black people must move into a white neighborhood, or send their children to a white school. This reinforces, among both black and white, the idea that white is

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

15

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

automatically superior and black is by definition inferior. For this reason, integration is a subterfuge for the maintenance of white supremacy. . . . The goal is not to take black children out of the black community and expose them to white middle-class values; the goal is to build and strengthen the black community. . . . Integration also means that black people must give up their identity, deny their heritage. . . . The fact is that integration, as traditionally articulated, would abolish the black community. The fact is that what must be abolished is not the black community but the dependent colonial status that has been inflicted on it. 75

Stokely Carmichael, 1967 The conception that African Americans created a concrete national culture and constitute an integral, historically created national community within the structure of American social relations is crucial to understanding the divergent ways that nationalists and integrationists understand racial domination. Compare, for example, the different ways that nationalists and integrationists interpreted public school integration. Nationalists believed that school integration was undesirable for two main reasons. First, integration of black and white schools entailed the abolition of one of the few organized institutions in the black community. School integration therefore contributed an even greater loss of social power: Blacks lost the ability to control and shape their children's education. As Malcolm X described community control, it was necessary in order to create the curriculum, textbooks, and general content of educational life in a way that would respond to the needs and wishes of the black community. By conceiving of African Americans in nationalist terms, black nationalists focused attention on the impact of race reform on the community as a whole and evaluated integration according to whether the black community was made stronger or weaker. 76 As Stokely Carmichael and Charles Hamilton stated, T he racial and cultural personality of the black community must be preserved and the community must win its freedom while preserving its cultural integrity . . . . *796 This is the essential difference between integration as it is currently practiced and the concept of Black Power. 77 Second, nationalists asserted that school integration meant the adaptation of blacks to white normsto quote Carmichael, integration entailed taking black children out of the black community and exposing them to white middle-class values. Of course, there was no analytically intrinsic content to the idea of integration that mandated that school integration proceed on the basis of white cultural normsjust as there was nothing intrinsic to the concept of integration that entailed Robert Browne's image of the Negro . . . transform [ing] himself into a white black-man. 78 But Carmichael and Browne highlighted an aspect of American racial integration buried in the mainstream ideology of neutrality and universalism, but central to the black nationalists' analysisa consideration of the cultural terms on which integration in social institutions would proceed. According to Harold Cruse, the commitment to integration embodied absorption into white culture through the failure to recognize the integrity of the black culture created in conditions of domination: [T]he Negro working class has been roped in and tied to the chariot of racial integration driven by the Negro middle class. In this drive for integration the Negro working class is being told in a thousand ways that it must give up its ethnicity and become human, universal, full fledged American. Within the context of this forced alliance of class claims there can be no room for Negro art . . . or art institutions . . . because all of this is self-segregation which hangs up our drive for integration. 79 In fact, [t]he integrationist philosophy sees Negro ghettos as products of racial segregation that should not even exist. Hence, nothing in the traditions of ghettos are worth preserving even when the ghettoes do exist in actuality. This is typical integrationist logic on all things social. 80

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

16

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

*797 In more general terms, this understanding of integrationism as based on a vision of a universal, full-fledged American underlies the sense expressed by Carmichael and Browne that integration entailed the abolition of the black community. Because integrationists had no conceptual category with which to comprehend African Americans as a separate national group, they, by and large, ignored the possibility of understanding racial justice in terms of the transfer of resources and power to the black community as an entity. Hence, rather than providing the material means for improving the housing, schools, cultural life, and economy of black neighborhoods, 81 nationalists saw mainstream race reform as entailing progress only through blacks moving into historically white neighborhoods, attending historically white schools, participating in white cultural activities, and working in white-owned and white-controlled economic enterprises. Even if such a program were possible, its result would be, not to develop the black community as a functional and honorable segment of the total society, with its own cultural identity, life patterns, and institutions, but to abolish itthe final solution to the Negro problem. 82 Accordingly, although there was nothing intrinsic to the liberal theory of integrationism that required public school integration to proceed by closing black schools, firing black teachers and administrators, and integrating black children into formerly white schools, 83 the mainstream discourse of school integration perceived implementation in terms of symmetry and quality, rather than in terms of the particular needs of the black community to use schools as a base of empowerment and unity for the community as a whole. Given the integrationist analysis *798 that racism stemmed from race consciousness, the issue of the effect of school reform on African Americans as a separate, integral community was categorically excluded from thinking about school reform. From the nationalist viewpoint, integration has meant the loss of local institutions in the African American community geared to the needs and aspirations of African Americans, but integrationists did not even notice this consequence of a reform like public school integration. For them, African Americans do not comprise a community at all, but rather are simply individuals who just happen to be black. Without the idea of racial difference, no space existed within integrationist ideology where one could conceive of African Americans as constituting a national community, as a group with common historical experience, cultural bonds, and aspirations for the future. The correlate of the nationalist critique, that school integration meant not only the loss of an important institution in the black community but also the assimilation of blacks into white cultural practices, likewise was invisible to integrationists. Just as integrationists translated the race consciousness of the nationalist focus on the need for black institutional life as a form of reverse prejudice, they also failed to comprehend the idea that racially integrated schools might manifest white culture. Instead, the images of expertise and professionalism that became the ideology of public education signified for integrationists the institutional face of the commitment to reason and impersonality at a philosophical level. In school integration, integrationists believed that black children would be integrated into the aracial culture of quality education. The clinical computer printouts, reflecting the cognitive achievement level gleaned from standardized tests in statistical, percentile terms, symbolized the impersonality and hence cultural neutrality of the liberal reform of public education. But where integrationists saw school integration in terms of transcending the bias at the root of segregation in favor of an objectively defined quality education, nationalists saw that process as assimilating black children to white middle class norms. The nationalist perspective characterized the norms that constituted the neutral, impersonal, aracial, professional character of school integration as particular cultural assumptions of a specific economic class of whites. The vision of integration as a form of painless genocide, then, stemmed from an analysis of integration as meaning, not the liberation of the black community from racial domination, but instead the transcendence of the black community itself in favor of neutral social practices that could only be identified as historically situated and culturally particular from the outside, by those *799 for whom their supposed universality is experienced as a particular form of otherness. 84

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

17

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

One can imagine a form of school integration that would have entailed consideration of the integrity of African American culture and recognition of the cultural assumptions of dominant public school practices. Nothing in the simple idea of racial integration necessitated that it be linked with universalist assumptions. But the nationalist analysis did correlate well with the ways that integrationism proceeded. The dismantling of dual school systems in reality meant closing black schools and integrating black children into white school systems. Moreover, for two reasons, the loss of black community control over the education process did not even result in integration. First, whites fled urban schools in favor of predominantly white private or suburban schools, a move that left urban education with the universalist ideology of centralized professionalism, a segregated student population, and an insufficient tax base. Perhaps more telling, in light of the nationalist critique of integration as a subterfuge for white supremacy, even where integration has been successful, it has largely meant resegregation within the walls of formally integrated schools. On the purported basis of intelligence rather than race, the process of tracking utilizes various objective tests to segregate school children according to cognitive ability. In school district after school district, the slower tracks are disproportionately comprised of black children and faster tracks are disproportionately comprised of whites. 85 The nationalist critique of integration highlights the ideological background against which this manner of conducting racial integration could seem plausible. Within the integrationist vision, once race consciousness (and other biases) are removed, neutral, objective social practices remain. Thus, the logic of conducting school integration by *800 closing black schools and firing black teachers and principals was premised on the ability to identify quality schools, teachers, and administrators in a neutral, objective way. In these neutral terms, black schools were closed because they were inferior as a result of discrimination between white and black institutions under segregation. Similarly, tracking supposedly measures an acultural, objective mental process called cognitive ability. Signifying the transcendence of race as a meaningful social category, integrationists rationalize the disproportionate representation of black children in decaying schools and slower educational tracks not as the manifestation of black inferiority, but instead as the result of povertyarticulated bureaucratically as low socioeconomic status or in the acronym, low SES. 86 Just as integrationists failed to recognize the cultural achievements of black schools, and saw them, as Harold Cruse noted, simply as products of racial segregation that should not even exist, 87 they also failed to recognize the cultural specificity of white schools, which were instead seen only as superior education. The intense reaction on the part of liberals to black nationalist movements for community control of schools and for the establishment of separate and autonomous Afro-American Studies Departments 88 reflected the depth of the challenge that nationalism posed to the dominant cultural ideology that linked rationality, enlightenment, and progress with racial integration. For a brief period in the late 1960s and early 1970s, issues of educational public policy crystallized the dramatic opposition between the nationalist ideology of cultural difference and organic community, and the integrationist ideology of universal reason and neutral institutions. In terms of community support and interest, nationalists produced their greatest organizational successes in the arenas of public schools and university politics. For low-income people of color, the nationalist approach to education unified popular movements for community control over schools in urban communities such as Harlem and Ocean Hill-Brownsville in New York City, and Adams-Morgan in Washington, D.C. In the middle class, nationalist activism took the form of demands for the establishment of Afro-American Studies Departments in predominantly white *801 colleges and universities across the country. 89 In each dimension, the movement toward community control is a profound rejection of the core of liberal ideology because liberal integrationism assumes that society is the aggregation of independent individuals, rather than an organic compact of groups. 90 Nationalists asserted that educational reform cannot be understood in terms of a quality education neutral as to race, but instead must be examined in terms of how schools serve the needs of an organic community held together by bonds of a particular racial culture and history. They therefore challenged the fundamental philosophical *802 ideology that knowledge itself represents some acultural achievement and that schools could be evaluated according to some aracial standard based on how well they impart the neutral educational commodity of knowledge

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

18

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

and reason. Rather, the word better can only be taken to mean better according to some secular standards, and it is precisely those standards that are now rejected. 91 The equation of integration with assimilationas drawn by Stokely Carmichael, Robert Browne, Harold Cruse, and many other nationalistsconstituted the most threatening aspect of the nationalist critique. Here the rejection of universalism took the form not only of an assertion that African Americans constitute a distinct community, a nation, but correspondingly that white Americans also constitute an historically identifiable group within the structure of American race relations. 92 Integrationists believed that the transcendence of white supremacy would be achieved by eliminating the exclusion of blacks from mainstream institutions, as if racism as a regime of domination and power consisted only of exclusion and did not inform the broader self-definition of white institutions. Nationalists sought to expose these limits of the integrationist vision and to focus critically on the manner in which white cultural assumptions extended to the everyday construction of institutional practices. 93

D. Nationalism as a Critique of Liberalism It is necessary for us to develop a new frame of reference which transcends the limits of white concepts. It is necessary for us to develop and maintain a total intellectual offensive against the false universality of white concepts, whether they are expressed by William Styron or Daniel Patrick Moynihan. By and large, reality has been conceptualized in terms of narrow point of view of the small minority of white men who live in Europe and North America. We must abandon the partial frame of reference of our oppressors and create new concepts which will release our reality, which is the reality of the overwhelming majority of men and women on this globe. We must say to the white world that there are things in the world that are not dreamt of in your history and your sociology and your philosophy. 94

Lerone Bennett, 1972 *803 The alternative nationalist worldview embodied in the critique of public school integration manifested itself not only in an analysis of particular institutional practices, but also in a critique of each component of the integrationist worldview. At a more general and abstract level of nationalist analysis, the repudiation of the dominant ideology of public education corresponded to a thoroughgoing critique of the epistemological assumptions of liberalism as a whole. Black nationalists depicted the ideas of rationality, neutrality, and objectivity that integrationists associated with the transcendence of bias and prejudice as the particular cultural rhetoric of the small minority of white men who live in Europe and North America. According to nationalists in the 1960s, these traditional categories of liberal and enlightenment thought do not constitute an aracial or culturally neutral standard that measures social progress in overcoming partiality, parochialism, and bias, but instead are simply parts of the dominant worldview of white elites. The rejection of prevailing scholarly standards and methodologies represented one dimension of the challenge to the philosophic assumptions underlying liberal integrationism. Black nationalist scholars in the field of sociology, for instance, began to critique the social science norms of objectivity and value neutrality, and to draw a link between those general assumptions about the nature of intellectual and academic inquiry and the particular concepts that justified racial domination. Nationalist sociologists argued that American scholarly norms constituted a form of academic colonialism in which the discourse of universality and neutrality embodied an assumption of the superiority of white cultural practices and the corresponding inferiority of African American culture. 95 According to one line of attack, the mind/body dichotomy implicit in the distinction between intellectual and manual work, and the tradition of distinguishing scholarship as a specialized activity in the mental realm, represented an

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

19

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

attempt at class rationalizationthe elevation of mental *804 activity symbolized the superior entitlement of the leisure class to the distribution of goods in society. 96 Black nationalist sociologists further criticized the idea of impartiality and the notion of a sharp dichotomy between the detachment that marks good research skills and the emotionalism that constitutes a form of bias. The sociologists contended that the research norms that require a lack of empathy and existential connection with the subjects of sociological studies reflect a particular value-orientation that ultimately helps to legitimate conditions of racial hierarchy. According to black nationalist academics, the relationship between the objective researcher and his research subject mirrors the relationship between dominant and suppressed cultural groups. The researcher represents, vis-a-vis the social groups under study, the same rhetoric of rationality and objectivity that the powerful use to justify their domination generally. 97 Many black sociologists also sought to demonstrate a systematic bias in the ways that mainstream sociological research was conducted, arguing that white culture represented the implicit standard in empirical research and that black cultural practices were represented as deviations. 98 Similarly, nationalist sociologists criticized the analytic categories of prejudice and discrimination as based on a false image of reason and neutrality that embodied white cultural norms and concluded that integration as understood in mainstream sociological analysis was premised *805 on the annihilation of black culture through assimilation into white American culture. 99 The nationalists did not limit their attack on the idea of an objective, impersonal reason to a critique of academic work. Eldridge Cleaver focused on the dominant image of rationality to launch a critique of white culture as manifesting a repression of sexuality which provided the psychological ground for a deep fear of blacks. Cleaver argued that the liberal contrast between reason and desire was part of a particular, historic language of power, within which dominant social groups differentiated themselves from those who are taken to be irrational, uncivilized, and ruled by myth. The white supremacist discourse that depicted whites as rational and civilized, and blacks as irrational and lustful was one manifestation of the reason/desire polarity. But, according to Cleaver, white supremacist ideology amounted to more than a failure to view the characteristics of reason and desire as symmetrically distributed among whites and blacks. Instead, the very definition and content of rationality itself represented an ideology rooted in the sexual politics of race. 100 Specifically, Cleaver argued that the manner of understanding reason in contrast to desire reflects the fear of black sexuality that formed the infrastructure of white self-identity. The notion of reason as asexual was part of a legitimating rhetoric that itself justified white rule over blacks by providing the conceptual categories within which whites represented the head and blacks the body; in Cleaver's depiction of white racism, whites became the bodiless Omnipotent Administrators and Ultrafeminines and blacks were mindless Supermasculine Menials and Black Amazons. 101 That is, the rhetoric of superior evolution that characterizes explicit white racism was reflected in the reason/desire dichotomy through the differentiation of whites as rational and blacks as ruled by passion. Such a filter in turn formed the basis for the projection of white male sexual anxiety through the image of unbridled black sexuality. In this description, reason was understood not as the universal, objective transcendence of bias, but rather as the particular discourse by which whites justified their status in the social structure of racial domination as based on their asserted superior evolution from primordial sexuality. *806 By denying reason to blacks, whites eroticized blacks as embodying the sexual license that whites denied to themselves as rational administratorsexplaining, Cleaver claimed, the fear and simultaneous attraction to blacks that form the psychological infrastructure of white sexuality. 102 In general, the radical critique launched by black nationalist sociologists and cultural critics claimed that objective reason or knowledge could not exist, because one's position in the social structure of race relations influenced what one would call knowledge or rationality. The cultural differences between blacks and whites could not be studied through a neutral frame of reference, because any frame of reference assumed the perspective of either the oppressed or the oppressor, either African

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

20

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

Americans or whites, either the sociologist or the subject. Cultural differences were not limited to particular social practices like religious activity or artistic production, but instead were infused more generally into how people perceived reality and experienced the world. There could be no neutral theory of knowledgeknowledge was itself a function of the ability of the powerful to impose their own views, to differentiate between knowledge and myth, reason and emotion, and objectivity and subjectivity. In the historicizing perspective of black nationalists, knowledge was necessarily a social construct. Understanding what society deemed worthy of calling knowledge depends on a prior inquiry into a social situation. 103 Culture precedes epistemology. This kind of generalized challenge to reigning cultural assumptions also characterized black nationalist perspectives on the debate about affirmative action. Rather than perceiving a conflict between objective merit and the goal of racial integration, the nationalist approach challenged the objectivity of the category of merit by viewing it in terms of the particular social practices by which whites historically distributed social *807 goods. From the nationalist worldview, integrationist debates about affirmative action are a subterfuge for white supremacy: The debates focus on white cultural mores, present them as universal and objective, and then utilize them to characterize blacks as not qualified. A contemporary example of this process can be found in legal education. In law schools throughout the country, admissions, hiring, and tenure debates proceed on the basis of standards of academic and scholarly merit that were constructed in an historical period when African Americans were excluded from mainstream law schools, and when the very law to be studied itself sanctioned white supremacism. The notion that racism was limited only to the exclusion of blacks from law schools, and was not a part of the infrastructure for thinking about and constructing qualifications is emblematic of the limiting assumptions that nationalists perceived as underlying integrationism. The concepts of merit and qualifications have a function only in relation to existing social practices; black nationalists insisted that the existing social practices should not be taken as the standard since those practices were created by a culture that considered it normal to exclude blacksthat is, a culture itself in need of transformation. 104 For example, imagine a legal challenge to the disproportionate racial impact of the LSAT test. The use of the LSAT test might be justified based on a functional correlation with performance in law school. But that functional defense views the status quo of legal education as the standard. Nationalists would argue that there is no intrinsic necessity to the current ways that law schools conduct legal education, and would emphasize the genealogy of existing law school practices in terms of their roots in white culture. To be sure, the status quo of legal education itself might be justified by a functional relation to existing legal practice, but that merely pushes the controversy to another levelthe nature of existing legal culture. And that is exactly what a challenge to the exclusionary aspects of the LSAT contests, the way that the legal profession is currently constituted as a reflection of white culture. In short, the nationalist approach emphasized and criticized the self-justifying character of meritocratic assumptions about qualifications. Once we consider the possibility that existing social practices might reflect the domination of particular racial groups, those practices can no longer provide a neutral ground from which to defend existing definitions of either qualifications or merit as functionally correlated with necessary social roles.

*808 E. Power, Subordination and Colonialism The assertion of nationhood on the part of African Americans also comprised a declaration of alien-nation between races, an assertion that white culture is experienced as other to blacks. Integrationists saw the transcendence of the structure of racism as replacing the same/other image of white supremacists with expansion of sameness to blacks; nationalists conceived of the relations as other to other. Integrationists located the roots of racism in consciousness, in the cognitive distortion of stereotype and prejudice. In contrast, the nationalist perception of whites and blacks as occupying different national spaces entailed a view of racial domination as

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

21

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

located in the particular power relations between black and white communities, in the exteriors of social life rather than the interiors of consciousness. And given the focus on social context rather than consciousness, the cure for racial domination could not be centered on education and interracial contact to dispel stereotypes, but instead depended on the transformation of power relations between black and white communities, or, in other words, on the achievement of Black Power. Similarly, since racism referred to the particular power relations between black and white communities, there was no center of comparison from which to equate racial identity with other forms of identity, nor to equate the domination of African Americans with discrimination against other groups. The significance of race in terms of social relations and the self-identity of people was seen by nationalists to have a particular weight and depth that could not be comprehended by abstracting from historical context and flattening out racial domination into one of many structurally equivalent forms of discrimination. And nationalists asserted that a group identity that centers around race was not structurally the same as the ethnic heritage that every American has, because, in our social history, race has acquired a particular significance and centrality that is qualitatively different than the differences, say, between Italian Americans and Polish Americans. 105 In contrast to the integrationist image of discrimination as the social practice of racism, the nationalist image was subordination, the hierarchy of the white community over the black community. Rather than conceive of race reform in terms of affirmative action aimed at integrating formerly white institutions, nationalists sought to strengthen and develop institutions in the black community that would serve African Americans. Thus, nationalists tended to see racial justice in terms of *809 reparations, 106 or foreign aid from developed countries to the third world. 107 And that is why Malcolm X distinguished segregation from racial separation. According to his analysis, segregation amounted to a form of racial domination, in which the black community was not only separate from the white, but also ruled by the white community. As he saw it, if the power relations were changed, the meaning of the separation would be dramatically different. In contrast to the integrationist image of segregation as a systematic form of racism, black nationalists developed an analysis that relied primarily on an image of whites and blacks constituting separate national communities. The systematic nature of American racism was described not as segregation, but as a form of colonialism. 108 According to Harold Cruse's description, domestic colonialism . . . instead of establishing a colonial empire in Africa, the United states brought the colonial system home and installed it in the Southern states . . . . Emancipation elevated the Negro only to the position of a semi-dependent man, not to that of *810 an equal or independent being. 109 In the nationalist analysis, African Americans exist in a neocolonial relationship with whitesas a colonized people dispersed throughout North America: Black Power must be viewed as a projection of sovereignty, an embryonic sovereignty that black people can focus on and through which they can make distinctions between themselves and others, between themselves and their enemiesin short, the white mother country of America and the black colony dispersed throughout the continent on absentee-owned land, making Afro America a decentralized colony. Black Power says to black people that it is possible to build a national organization on someone else's land. 110

Comprehending the relations between blacks and whites on a colonial model, 1960s nationalists asserted that even black control of the black community would be insufficient if it merely meant that blacks would administer the same structural power relations that previously existed between white and black communities. The metaphor of colonialism thus symbolically placed 1960s nationalists outside the parameters of the pluralist wing of integrationism by suggesting that the racial diversification of existing American institutions and social patterns might simply be another form of the colonial relationship. A radical transformation of the status quo institutional practices would be necessary before identifiable black and white communities could relate on a just basis. 111

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

22

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

The colonialism metaphor unified the nationalist analysis by capturing, in one image, the totalizing sense of alienation between whites and blacks that the rejection of common nationality represented, the depiction of structural and systematic power exercised by the white community, *811 and the conviction that group solidarity was necessary to change existing power relations. It also provided the rhetoric for a critical analysis of relations within the black community between economic classes. Nationalists deploying a neo-colonialism analysis accounted for opposition to the nationalist position in the black community as the effects of indirect rule, within which an elite was created among the colonized class, to administer and mediate on behalf of colonialist interests. According to many black nationalists, the black middle class played this role in America, and class differences with the black poor and working class accounted for the middle class support of integration. 112 This orientation around colonialism connected various projects in the 1960s and early 1970s, including movements for community control over schools; for black political, economic, and police control over black neighborhoods; for raceconscious economic cooperation among African Americans; for race-conscious reparations from the white community to African American communities; for the establishment and control of Afro-American Studies Departments in universities; for the preservation and transformation of black colleges and universities; and for cultural autonomy in arts, music, literature, and intellectual life.

III. DIFFERENT MANIFESTATIONS OF INTEGRATIONISM AND NATIONALISM To this point, I have described integrationism and nationalism as distinct and diametrically opposed ideologies about race. My goal was to highlight the philosophic and cultural context within which integrationism is situated and to describe black nationalism as a comprehensive analysis of racial power resting on a competing, interlocking set of ideas about what race means in American social life. Given the cultural dynamics *812 through which integrationism became the mainstream ideology of race and nationalism was marginalized as an extremist ideology, it is necessary to contrast the two ideologies in these oppositional and bipolar ways. Only then can we recover the integrity of the nationalist position as a liberating discourse about race and counter the deeply-held stereo-type that Malcolm X, Stokely Carmichael, the Black Panthers, and other nationalists were simply reverse racists or violent, militaristic extremists. But one of the difficulties in describing cultural ideologies is that they can never really be captured in their lived and complex forms. These descriptions thus tend to sound like worked-out theories rather than the more complicated and contradictory ways people in actual historic situations come to terms with social life. Although these polarized descriptions capture important differences between the two cultural stances, in actual social life no one experienced or articulated their commitment either to nationalism or to integrationism in the clean, philosophic manner in which I identified the worldviews. Before beginning an analysis of the cultural dynamics underlying the rejection of nationalism in the 1970s, I want first to discuss other ways that integrationism and nationalism might beand have beenunderstood.

A. Integrationism and Group Consciousness I have identified the structure of integrationist ideology as a cluster of ideas connecting belief in universalism, objectivity, and individualism, and I have suggested that integrationism consequently obscured consideration of the racial character of practices in institutions such as public schools. But this depiction itself tends to obscure the ways that the demand for racial integration has often been radically oppositional, spiritual, and communal. One important dimension of integrationism, as it manifested itself in American culture, was the manner in which the goal of racial integration helped generate an authentic community of people who understood themselves as profoundly committed to the

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

23

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

eradication of racial domination in American society. For them, the ideology of integrationism was not experienced as simply the working out of a liberal theory of enlightenment; instead, integrationism provided a frame for articulating their more deeply rooted, existential revulsion to racial domination. The flattening out of integrationism as a philosophy should not obscure the dramatic courage of its proponents, fueled by authentic spiritual connections between individuals and displayed by thousands of people in the civil rights movement. 113 Despite the cognitive dimension of integrationism *813 that reflected assumptions of individualism and universalism, the goal of racial integration spawned a social movement based, ironically, on a sense of group consciousness, communal support, and intersubjective recognition that transcended the ideological limits of integrationism as a theory. The religious imagery of broad-based spiritual communion was intertwined with the more rationalist political and legal rhetoric of civic equality that symbolized the civil rights movement for many years; the combination captured real aspirations for human freedom and social decency.

B. Martin Luther King, Jr. and Black Power The stark opposition between integrationism and nationalism that I have drawn also lends itself to an overly simplified categorization of particular movements that were, in fact, much more complex. For example, by viewing race relations issues as fundamentally organized around a clear opposition between nationalism and integrationism, one tends to associate Martin Luther King, Jr. with the integrationist, rights-oriented wing of the black liberation movement, and to associate Malcolm X with the nationalist faction. But whatever accuracy might exist in that depiction of Malcolm X, the King position was far more complicated and ambiguous. It is true that King's rhetoric was organized around universalist imagery of the Beloved Community, drawn from both Christianity and American liberal constitutionalism, and his articulated goals were the transcendence of race consciousness in favor of integration. 114 In addition, much of the King/SCLC discourse appeared integrationist insofar as it was framed as an appeal to morality and conscience as the framework for the achievement of racial justice, in contrast to the nationalist analysis that racial justice depended on achieving Black Power. King has become more of an integrationist in death, however, than he was in life. With the elevation of King to the status of a national hero, mainstream culture has focused exclusively on King's non-violent, universalist rhetoric. But if integrationism means a commitment to transcend race consciousness, or if integrationism is tied to the rejection of Black Power as a goal of mass organization, then King cannot properly be perceived as an integrationist. The domesticated, popularized image of King leaves out a critical aspect of King's work, an aspect that might *814 be interpreted as the more revolutionary dimension to his organizational strategy. In terms of community organizing, King accomplished a critical dimension of the nationalist project while speaking the language of integration. In a profound way, King represented the symbolic message that African Americans could conceive of themselves as an organic community bound together by a unique history, by a present whose power relations demanded solidarity and support, and by a shared future that demanded collective action. Thus, the civil rights movement under King's leadership assumed an important part of the nationalist worldview: the idea that African Americans could, as a community, self-consciously develop a strategy of social transformation through participation in politics on the basis of group power. This aspect of King's work is obscured when he is sharply distinguished from Black Power advocates; King's commitment to nonviolent means has come to signify the movement's goal as neutral reason and institutional impersonality rather than community power. 115 But, in contrast to the image of nonviolence, one of the most significant features of the civil rights movement under King's leadership was the manner in which civil rights activists actually transformed race relations in cities and towns across the South by exerting the power of African American community and acting in solidarity and through alliances with other groups, both within and outside of the particular locale, to force social change.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

24

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

*815 This power challenge to the status quo was manifested in an important way by the fact of black protest and resistance itself. Major portions of the white community, especially in the South, had resolved their own participation in racial domination through an ideological construction of African Americans as happy, smiling, and contented. 116 Whites imagined that these images were confirmed, at the micro-level of daily interaction within the hierarchies of race, by the (coerced) deference, gratitude, and loyalty that formed the social language of public contact between whites and blacks. One reflection of this dynamic was that many Southern whites saw black resistance as the work of outside agitators. King mobilized hundreds of thousands of blacks to declare their alienation from this social structure, to demonstrate that the peaceful, contented, and settled quality of race relations was a charade, to show that the social structure of race had invaded on a mass scale virtually every relation between blacks and whites, and to give notice that the black community en masse was prepared to assault the social structure through organized social power. The emphasis on nonviolence hides this power/ confrontation dimension of King's organizing, and tends to make invisible the threat to fundamental power relations manifest in the mass organizing of the black community during the civil rights movement. The image of King pleading with the conscience of white America on the grounds of morality leaves much out of the picture: King helped organize masses of black people to step out of the daily roles of accommodation or defeat, and to utilize racial solidarity to boycott buses, banks, and stores; to strike from jobs; to disrupt the business-as-usual *816 aspect of settled racial domination with small sit-ins as well as mass mobilizations; and to demonstrate the power of African Americans to reclaim and transform streets, institutions, and communities. To be sure, King's strategy clearly included a coalition with white liberals, moderates, and the federal governmentbut an important dimension of his organizing was implicit in the mass mobilization of blacks themselves. From the viewpoint of many whites, the formal fact of nonviolence was overwhelmed by the pervasive threat of the disintegration of the social structure of deference and subordination that black mobilization embodied. 117

C. Nationalism as an Influence Within Integrationist Practice An absolute association of integrationism with the discourse of universalism and individualism also obscures the ways that nationalist ideology might exert influence within the discourse of integrationism itself. The stereotypical conflicts among integrationistsover affirmative action, whether to identify racism in terms of intent or impact, the roles of diversity and merit in institutional decisionmaking, and whether to engage in race-conscious remediationcould represent a split between integrationist and nationalist interpretations of integrationism itself. In this view, the conservative side of the controversies within integrationism form a particularly universalist and individualist version of integrationism within which intent becomes critical because racism is seen as rooted in individual consciousness, in prejudice and bias. Here color-blindness is the goal; any deviation is suspect; and it is assumed that once we transcend intentional consciousness about race, we will be left with neutral, rational, and objective social practices and institutional forms. *817 On the other hand, the liberal discourseconsisting of support for affirmative action, an impact standard to identify racism, a de facto view of the equal protection clause, and diversity as a goal for institutional lifecan be interpreted in two ways. First, the liberal positions might simply represent a different means to the same normative end of integrationism; or second, they might constitute a more radical, nationalist-oriented challenge to the universalizing assumptions of integrationist ideology. In the first interpretation, the liberal wing of the integrationist argument appears as a tougher version of integrationism the demand for an impact standard can be understood to ensure more rigorously and cautiously that irrationality and bias have been eradicated. The racially identifiable results of a purportedly neutral selection procedure are simply taken as more reliable evidence of racial bias than the vague and subjective inquiry into intent. Affirmative action and the diversity commitment can be seen as empirically verifiable means to ensure that selection procedures are not biased, because through such special efforts proportionate numbers of racial minorities are chosen.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

25

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

On the other hand, the liberal wing of the integrationist conflict might be understood alternatively as a nationalist-oriented tendency within integrationism, or at least as an accommodation to the nationalist commitment that the focus of racial justice should be on the impact of social practices on the black community as a whole. The impact perspective accordingly would signify not the possibility of bias, but rather the qualitatively different view that civil rights means a transfer of opportunities and resources on a group basisa view comprehending that race marks a culturally significant group. Rather than accepting the central commitment of integrationisma desire to transcend race consciousnessthe progressive aspect of mainstream legal and political civil rights discourse might be interpreted as contesting the issue of race consciousness in the trenches of integrationist doctrine, as demanding that selection procedures, for example, be understood through their effect on the power of racially defined communities. Thus, liberal integrationist discourse can be understood as rejecting the individualist focus of the enlightenment assertion that race-consciousness is irrational, in favor of an interpretation of history through the prism of social groups. 118 Extending this wing of liberal integrationism, one can imagine a sophisticated vision of racial justice that would systematically replace the individualist focus of traditional integrationism with a focus on cultural communities, and simultaneously view institutional practices as a reflection *818 of particular manifestations of cultural power. Rather than comprehending identity in terms of the diluted practice of cultural pluralism, within which ethnic and racial difference become privatized to the home and marginalized to episodic public celebrations, this kind of ideology would interpret norms of diversity in terms of the creation of a creole institutional and public culture that would contain within itself the elements of composite cultures, rather than flatten out difference into an assumed universal and neutral set of public practices. 119

D. Black Nationalism as a Conservative Force Just as my description of integrationism as a universalizing ideology excluded its more complicated manifestations, so my description of nationalism as fundamentally historical in orientation obscures significant aspects of the social history of black nationalism. In fact, nationalism has often taken an extremely conservative stance with respect to the identity of the African American culture that forms the ground for community solidarity and intra-group recognition. The relatively rapid transformation in formal community self-description (colored, Negro, black, Afro-American, African American) indicates one facet of a deeper controversy over what actually makes up the concrete national culture that C. Munford evoked. Given that a structure of racial domination and oppression marks African American history, many nationalists, like integrationists, rejected the possibility of identifying with the particular culture that black people created in America on the ground that it reflects the pathologies of subordination and repression. Rather than view African Americans as constituting a particular and unique community whose culture has been deeply influenced by its formation in the context of American race relations, these nationalists define the community in terms of an earlier time of imagined purity, before the American experience. 120 In social life, this stance is reflected through an exclusive identification with African cultural symbols and a demand that community members Africanize according to some central, universal image of what an African heritage means. *819 One cultural manifestation of this dynamic occurred in the 1960s through the often repressive and authoritarian demand for conformity in African dress (e.g., dashikis) and natural hairstyles (Afros). But the Back to Africa consciousness was only one aspect of a continual tension within nationalist ideology between an historicized or essentialized understanding of the self-identity of the black community. 121 Another manifestation was the insistence by many 1960s black nationalists that male domination was a part of authentic black culture, thus making problematic the opportunity of black women to experience nationalism as liberating rather than repressive. The essentialized identification of black culture with patriarchy extended from the generally conservative ideology of the Nation of Islam to the otherwise countercultural mindset of radicals such as Stokely Carmichael. The same tension between an essentialist and historicist conception of group identity also underlay conflicts

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

26

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

between nationalists over whether to form coalitions with white groups. 122 The essentialists within the black nationalist movement tended to exaggerate the cultural separation of whites and blacks so that any influence of white norms on the development of black cultureas well as the reciprocal influence of black culture on the dominant American culturewas denied. Similarly, the association of black nationalism with an historicized view of social relations obscures how nationalists often essentialized not only the black community, but also the white community. The extreme manifestation of this tendency occurred in the rhetoric of mainstream Black Muslims, for example, which regarded the white community in monolithic and universal terms as the eternal white devil. 123 But the tendency toward reductionism also was reflected in more subtle ways by a conception of the white community as a unitary, timeless entity, rather than a complex group of subcommunities and subcultures, organized around and within histories of bitter conflict over issues of class, ethnicity, age, region, and sexuality. And, just as integrationism could be interpreted with a nationalist tilt, so, too, could nationalism also be interpreted to contain a distinctly integrationist influence. Thus, Black Power could be understood not as the challenge to the fundamental premises for the distribution of power *820 that I described, but rather as a call for African Americans to integrate either into electoral politics, by registering to vote and by becoming an interest group in a pluralist polity, 124 or into the economy by becoming entrepreneurs and capitalists. 125 Under this kind of interpretation, nationalism could become such a limited and non-threatening ideology that even Richard Nixon would call for black capitalism. 126 But even without a particular capitalist spin, it is difficult to distinguish this tendency within black nationalism from the pluralist, group-based interpretation of integrationism that demands the respectful coexistence of diverse cultural groups within the existing structure of social relations. 127 In addition, the nationalist position could overlap with integrationism to the extent that, in particular contexts, nationalists would conclude that integration was the best means to ensure community power. For example, a nationalist-oriented argument for school integration might advocate integration as the only way to guarantee that public education resources are actually distributed to the black community on an equitable basis. 128 The idea that black children must sit beside white children in order to prevent a maldistribution of resources does not in and of itself contradict the nationalist commitment to a race-conscious focus on the impact of social arrangements on the black community. Despite all the ways that nationalism and integrationism overlap and intersect, however, their opposition constitutes a critical frame through which to understand race relations in recent American history. Although a group-based integrationist perspective can accommodate nationalism, and a nationalist perspective can include integration to gain community power, the struggle over the issue of race consciousness symbolizes the cultural compromise underlying the institutionalization of the civil rights movement in the American cultural mainstream.

IV. THE CONFRONTATION OVER RACE IN THE 1960S As I have suggested, there was no analytically necessary reason that would require the identification of the social reform of racial integration *821 with cultural assimilation, individualist norms, or with the idea that race consciousness is evil. But racial integration, and its oppositional relation to black nationalism, have acquired this particular meaning within the last two decades. The ideology of integrationismwith its analytic components of prejudice, discrimination, and segregationforms the framework for American mainstream thinking about race. Black nationalismfocusing on race relations in terms of racial power, social subordination, and domestic colonialismhas been diffused to the social margins of the underclass, to the outposts of artistic production, and to the Nation of Islam. 129 To the extent that the integrity of African American culture and community is recognized as a commitment of mainstream American life, it has been safely absorbed into the pluralist respect for

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

27

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

everyone's cultural heritage or different voice. The rejection of black nationalism as reverse racism, with the corresponding idea that any race consciousness implies a form of domination and oppression, now forms part of the underlying structure of mainstream discourse about race in legal, political, and cultural spheres. When liberal positions within integrationist discourse (for instance, support for affirmative action or an impact standard for identifying discrimination) echo the remnants of race consciousness, they appear marginalized and inconsistent with the basic integrationist premise that race consciousness must be transcended. The borders of contemporary political and legal discourse about race formed in the cultural crisis that militant black nationalism engendered when it was first articulated on a mass scale in the late 1960s. Although there was nothing intrinsic in the concept of racial integration that demanded that it be understood according to the universalist ideology that I described, and although there was no reason why African American racial consciousness had to be equated with the racial consciousness of white supremacists, this way of thinking about race was produced in part to justify the rejection of black nationalism. On one level, the rejection of nationalism and the institutionalizing of integrationism as the official way to think about race relations can be accounted for as a philosophical choice: Integrationists rejected nationalism out of a commitment to the principle that race consciousness was a *822 deviant and distorted way to look at the world because it was irrational. The shared opposition to white supremacy and black nationalism accordingly reflected a commitment to objectivity, neutrality and reason, whose background image was the universalism of our shared humanity. But this kind of account takes the ideologies of integrationism and nationalism as being pre-defined philosophic options from which people choose. My sense is that the mainstream ways to think about race in America are both produced in, and help to produce, particular cultural conflicts and struggles. What I mean when I say that this ideology was produced is that we cannot understand the integrationist worldview simply as a philosophy or a set of concepts that themselves demanded that black nationalism be translated in a particular way. We should understand the dominance of integrationism as at least in part an effect, as well as a cause, of the marginalization of nationalismas a discourse that was created to justify the rejection of nationalism as well as a discourse that, simultaneously, informed the way that nationalism was perceived. 130 Integrationism was supported by a wide range of denouncers of the Black Power slogana coalition between black, predominantly middle class moderates, and white, predominantly middle and upper class liberals and progressives. Understanding themselves as specifically opposed to race consciousness, integrationists needed to reject black nationalists because of the threat that they posed to the cultural self-identity of both the black middle class moderates and the white upper class liberals. The commitment to a universalist vision of racial justice reflected the shared ambiguities that these two groups had about their own racial identities. The upshot of their implicit coalition was that they constructed and embraced a conservative race ideology that helped to contain the issue of racial liberationtogether with other disruptive challenges to the assumptions of everyday institutional life, such as the feminist movement by perceiving all of these challenges as part of a single discourse, unified around an idea of discrimination. This integrationist ideology served simultaneously to recognize racial power as a formal matter and yet to set boundaries for its critique. Without attempting a complete account of how and why this coalition formed in this particular manner, I want to recall briefly the cultural politics of that period and to speculate about the dynamics that enabled the present mainstream ideology about race to achieve its dominant status. *823 The clash between nationalism and integrationism extended from the period starting in 1966when the Black Power slogan first gained national prominenceand lasted until the marginalization of black nationalists was complete in the mid-1970s. This was, to say the least, a particularly intense and significant historical juncture for both black and white communities in America. The list of events, in no particular order, is staggering: The Black Panther Party was organized on a national scale; Martin Luther King, Jr. spoke out against the Vietnam War and began criticizing capitalism; King and Robert Kennedy were assassinated; African Americans rioted yearly in urban ghettos across the country; the Vietnam War galvanized

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

28

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

an increasingly radical white and black youth, who helped force a president out of office; Southern institutions had used up all deliberate speed and many were forced to desegregate; George Wallace mounted two national campaigns for the presidency on a white supremacist platform; the federal government was in the midst of civil rights enforcement; Nixon was twice elected by the silent majority; white middle-class women were organizing on feminist issues on a mass scale; the Woodstock Nation was born; and the sexual revolution and the counter-cultural movement of white and black youth were connected to anti-war and more general leftist projects in a large-scale rebellion of young against old. Against this intense background, in which it seemed that so much in American society was up for grabs, black nationalism achieved its most sophisticated articulation and its greatest mass appeal. As various ruptures of American society were resolved in favor of the integrationist/ discrimination ideology, black nationalism was pushed to the cultural margins. To understand the particular way that the conflict between nationalists and integrationists in the late 1960s and early 1970s constituted a pivotal, constitutive cultural moment for contemporary race discourse, it is important to comprehend what the conflict meant for the black and white communities. In this Section, I first trace the particular significance that 1960s nationalism had in the black community, arguing that 1960s nationalism for the first time in the 20th century shed its historic association with a conservative, accommodationist, and disgraced tradition. Moreover, this conflict within black communities had sharp class and generational dimensions. For many middle class and conservative blacks, the universalist interpretation of integrationism was crucial to understanding their own position as not implying group betrayal. In the next Section, I discuss what the black nationalist position meant in the white community, and contend that for many white liberals and progressives, understanding racial justice through a universalist prism was crucial *824 to avoiding deep-seated anxieties that they lacked the kind of rich culture and sense of community that the nationalists asserted for blacks and that, in a distorted way, was also attributed to blacks by white supremacist ideology.

A. The Transformed Meaning of Black Nationalism One important aspect of the confrontation between nationalism and integrationism in the 1960s was that after decades of marginality within the African American community, nationalism achieved mass appeal and arguably overtook integrationism as the dominant ideology of racial liberation. Black nationalism in the 1960s represented both the reappearance of a long tradition that began at least as early as Martin Delany in the 1850sa tradition that had been obscured by the unity created by integrationist-oriented leadership from the mid-1950s to the mid-1960sand also embodied a reinterpretation of the nationalist ideology. This reinterpretation dramatically severed the associations between nationalism and accommodationisma link dating back to the confluence, under Booker T. Washington's leadership, of separatist organizing and accommodationist relations with white domination. 1. The Continuity of the Civil Rights/Nationalism Opposition. According to Harold Cruse, American Negro history is basically a history of the conflict between integrationist and nationalist forces in politics, economics and culture, no matter what leaders are involved and what slogans are used. 131 This conflict has reappeared repeatedly; for *825 example, when Martin Delany articulated the formation of black colonies as a strategy for racial liberation in the mid-19th century, his proposals were opposed by Frederick Douglass' discourse of militant abolitionism, articulated in terms of American constitutional and civil rights. 132 The nationalist strain subsided during Reconstruction, but was rejuvenated in the post-Reconstruction world by the widely influential self-help and separatist ideas of Booker T. Washington, 133 which W.E.B. Du Bois challenged at the turn of the century. In the tradition of Douglass, Du Bois argued for political and legal equality as the proper vision of racial justice. From his influence, one can directly trace the origins of the NAACP in the early 20th century. 134 And just as the NAACP was consolidating its legal and political strategies in the 1930s and 1940s, nationalist organizing reached a new mass base in Northern urban centers through the leadership of Marcus Garvey. 135 Even in the late 1950s, when King galvanized the African

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

29

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

American community behind an integrationist vision fused with images of religious and moral transcendence, the Nation of Islamarticulating programs of economic cooperatives, cultural discipline, self-help and solidarity, and African American separation from the United States through a land grantcontinued to contest the integrationist program, and attracted significant support in urban centers and among the most economically deprived groups. 136 Moreover, the tensions between integrationist and nationalist ideologies were reflected within individuals as well as between political factions. Du Bois provided the most vivid example of this inner conflict. Initially, he publicly represented the integrationist/civil rights ideology in his critique of Booker T. Washington. In fact, to this day, he is probably the person most responsible for the popular image of Washington as a conservative accommodationist to Southern racial apartheid. 137 Du Bois edited the publication of the NAACP, Crisis, for several decades, but he *826 ultimately resigned his position, broke with the NAACP in the early 1940s in dramatic opposition to its policy of integrationism, and began to emphasize Pan-Africanism, the organization of economic cooperatives on a race-conscious basis, and voluntary self-segregation as the key ideas of black liberation. 138 And this invocation of the highly publicized tension between integrationism and nationalism among community leaders does not even begin to describe the tensions and ambiguities that have traditionally characterized the popular, day-today culture of African American life. The demands and fruits of community solidarity are in constant tension with the ambiguity of simultaneous hostility and attraction to the possibility of assimilation into the white world. 139 In short, the reappearance of nationalism in the 1960s reflected a long-standing conflict within the African American community that the brief unity around Martin Luther King's leadership temporarily obscured. But what made the struggle between black nationalists and black integrationists particularly significant in the 1960s was not its continuity, but its changed cultural meaning. Integrationism and nationalism traditionally have been the stark choices the African American community associated with racial politics, but that does not mean that the two ideologies were always understood in the same way. 2. The 1960s Transformation of Black Nationalism. In addition to the conflict over nationalist and integrationist conceptions of race, the issue of accommodationism versus resistance embodies another central dimension of African American racial discourse. 140 The degree of resistance and opposition associated with either integrationism or nationalism was an independently important cultural issuewith its own history of conflictin the perception of each stance. Although the black nationalist stance was unmistakably identified with a commitment to militancyand eventually violent revolutionby the late 1960s and early 1970s, there was no necessary historic or analytic connection between black nationalism and the desire to confront and resist the white power structure. To the contrary, virtually every other significant black nationalist movement in American history bore marks of accommodationism. Early 19th century colonization movements were framed in an historical context in which African American support for *827 Back-to-Africa programs was linked closely to white supremacists who supported colonization as a means to deport black people from North America. 141 In contrast to the colonists, the abolitionist/civil rights/integrationist rhetoric of, say, Frederick Douglass appeared far more militant and oppositionist. Similarly, Du Bois based his critique of the self-help, racial solidarity and separatism rhetoric of Booker T. Washington on the manner in which Washington's approach amounted to a submission and a surrender to the Jim Crow social structure, rather than a challenge to that structure. 142 Du Bois' differences with Garvey centered on the same issue, although Garvey was clearly more militant and confrontational than Washington. 143 By the time that the integrationists' momentum increased in the 1940s and 1950s, black nationalismrepresented mainly by teh socially and religiously conservative dogma of the Nation of Islam had achieved the role of a kind of traditionalism. Thus, in the early years of the civil rights movement, nationalist approaches organized in the cultural margins of the black communityseemed to many civil rights activists to imply an accommodation to the racial apartheid structure of white society through a retreat to the isolation of the black community. 144 In generational terms, this *828 meant that nationalist appeals to young civil rights workers were likely experienced as the conservative voice

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

30

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

of an older generation saying don't make waves and stick with your own people, in contrast to the sense within the civil rights movement of building a drive for resistance to and confrontation with the white power structure. This symbolic association of nationalism with accomodationism, and integrationism with resistance in the cultural perception of the basic choices helps account for how King could simultaneously represent the militant, confrontation-oriented aspirations of black activists, while speaking in the rhetoric of integrationism, moralism, and civil rights. 145 When King began in Montgomery, one could divide civil rights activists and groups according to whether they supported a legalist, litigation-oriented strategy of race reform or the approach of direct action and confrontation. As an early leader of mass direct action, King began his career representing the militant, non-accommodationist wing of the civil rights movement, a faction whose strategies embodied the nationalist belief that racial solidarity and assertions of group power were the means to attain racial liberation. 146 That is even while nationalist ideology was most marginalized in the black community during the 1950s and early 1960sone can detect aspects of nationalism within the integrationist civil rights movement itself. The historic opposition between nationalism and integrationism was reproduced in the conflict between the legalistic and direct-action factions of the civil rights movement. Prior to the resurgence of nationalist ideology in the mid-1960s, this tension within the civil rights movement was understood to encompass only the strategic question of the degree of militancy. The decision to turn back the marchers at the Petus Bridge in Selma became the cultural symbol of a split between black activists over how far to extend confrontational organizing. 147 But, in retrospect, this argument over tactics can be seen to have contained the seeds of the later, more explicit opposition between nationalism and integrationism. For a time in the early 1960s, in fact, the two tendencies merged in cultural perception. Militant, confrontational integrationists like Robert Williams who advocated armed self-defense became associated with militant, confrontational *829 nationalists like Malcolm X. 148 It was possible to perceive as similar individuals and groups with such ultimately opposing and inconsistent ideologies because the issue of militancy versus accommodation embodied central cultural significance in ways that both transcended, and eventually subsumed, the split between nationalist and integrationist positions. 149 It is therefore no coincidence that the most direct action-oriented groups within the civil rights umbrella, SNCC and CORE, would eventually renounce the civil rights analytics of prejudice, discrimination, and segregation in favor of the nationalist analytics of power, subordination, and colonialism. 150 In short, black nationalism in the 1960s embodied two important African American traditionson the one hand, the long tradition of explicit nationalist ideology, and, on the other hand, the long tradition of resistance by blacks to racial domination. Given the different roles that integrationism and nationalism played in relation to this separate conflict between resistance and accommodation, it would be a mistake to limit the historical antecedents of the nationalist presence in the mid- to late-1960s to groups, such as the Nation of Islam, that embraced black nationalism as a formal ideology. In addition to roots in movements such as the Nation of Islam, Pan-Africanism, and Garveyism, an important historical antecedent for 1960s black nationalism was the split among *830 integrationists in the 1950s and early 1960s between those who advocated direct action and those who advocated legal and civil remedies for racial discrimination. 151 The widespread invocation of the colonialism model to describe race relations 152 symbolized how 1960s black nationalist linked nationalism and social struggle, and thus symbolically broke the traditional association of separatism with accomodationism. Previous nationalist movements, even militant Garveyism, 153 always could be associated with the degradation of accommodationism to the extent that they seemed to accept American racial segregation. Rather than oppose the power dynamics between white and black communities in the United States, the separatist proposals for a return to Africa (Delany and Garvey), the creation of a separate land base in the United States (the Nation of Islam, the Republic of New Africa), or the various proposals for the creation of a separate black economic base (Du Bois, the Nation of Islam, Washington), all carried a sense of retreat from mainstream American life into isolation and nonconfrontation. In contrast, the articulation of the

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

31

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

relations between blacks and whites as neo-colonialist served as a bridge between the aspirations for community power that were always at least implicit in the nationalist ideology of racial solidarity and self-help, and the militancy an confrontationism that had been the province of direct action integrationists. Rather than representing a fantasy of separation or isolation from whites, the colonialism metaphor presented nationalists as engaged in the struggle for power in the United Statesit posed the problem facing African Americans as the form of relations between white and black communities, instead of the fact that there were relations at all. And the colonialist analysis located the solution not in a retreat from the United States, but rather as a struggle to transform relations of subordination within America. Unlike the conservative aspects of earlier manifestations of black nationalism, the colonialist analysis comprehended the imposition of an external power structure on the African American community, and accordingly provided a symbolic mediation of the tendency for self-blame that a nationalist emphasis on selfhelp and personal discipline might otherwise imply. *831 In the 1960s, black nationalists began to conceive of their project not as geographic separation from whites, but rather as the dismantling of the power relations between white and black communities. Instead of the choices appearing as either integration and assimilation on the one hand, or total geographic separation on the other, 1960s nationalists, led most notably by Malcolm X, developed a third way that combined militant engagement with the white power structure with the racial solidarity and anti-assimilationism traditionally associated with nationalism. 154 In short, after embodying the opposite associations for most of the 20th century, nationalism became associated with resistance and militancy in the 1960s, and integrationism appeared as the more accommodationist and conservative position. Early in the decade, Malcolm X symbolized this dimension of 1960s nationalism. By the mid-1960s, this reinterpretation of the black nationalist tradition that Malcolm X began (and that helps explain his eventual break with the Nation of Islam) 155 was embodied by Black Power movement, the explicit symbolic conjunction of the two traditions of nationalism and confrontation. 156 In this new context, nationalist activism both reproduced the class splits that historically characterized the opposition between integrationism and nationalism, and for the first time appeared poised to transcend *832 those splits in favor of nationalism rather than integration. 157 In rough terms, prior to King's leadership, integrationism was the central ideology of the black middle class, and the nationalist ideology primarily received support only from the black poor and working class. Part of King's significance as a political leader was his ability to unite African Americans around integrationism across class lines for the first time in the 20th century. 158 Yet even during the period of King's greatest mass appeal, membership in Muslim temples continued to grow, and Malcolm X's militant nationalist appeals became popular in Northern urban centers. And as King started to lose black support, it was the urban poor who most substantially challenged his leadership. By the late 1950s, King had united virtually the entire black community behind a program of confrontational direct action aimed at the achievement of integration, but the situation had changed by the late 1960s. Nationalists claimed the symbolic ground of militancy. They developed a sophisticated critique of dominant American culture and power relations that at least rhetorically connected African Americans to the Africans and Asians who were achieving independence from colonial rule, and they utilized a class-based neo-colonialist analysis to identify black integrationists with moderate and assimilationist middle-class accommodation to the white power structure. A dramatic example of the differences is the respective reactions of integrationists and nationalists to urban riots in the mid-and late 1960s. In contrast to the attempt of those in the mainstream to interpret urban riots as the unfortunate and irrational frustration with the slow pace of civil rights reform, 159 nationalists identified with and tended to support riots as decolonizing revolts *833 against the white power and property structure. 160 These contrasting positions with respect to the hot issue of urban disruption were only one face of more thoroughgoing ruptures of the consensus that King had achieved. Nationalists also contested the class unity that King had achieved, so that by the mid-1960s, integrationism again bore the mark of the black middle class and seemed to have little to offer the poor or working class. Furthermore, significant portions of the relatively small black middle class, represented most strongly by black students,

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

32

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

repudiated integrationism. Integrationists were on the defensive within the black community, and all the momentum seemed to be moving toward the nationalist position. 161 The explicit ideological changes within organizations evidenced the sense of nationalist momentum. In the mid- to late 1960s, both SNCC and CORE, which previously had been direct action-oriented civil rights groups advocating integration, adopted explicit nationalist positions. 162 In addition, the power of the nationalist drift was evident within the SCLC itself. King's decision finally to oppose the Vietnam War publicly in 1967, and the SCLC's shift in focus both from civil to economic rights and from the South to Northern ghettos shortly before King's assassination, were arguably in response to the sense that King and the SCLC were quickly losing the support of both black youth in general and the urban poor in particular. 163 The conflict between these two groups soon became acute: Nationalists developed a rhetoric within which any association with whites was seen to be the sign of race treachery, captured by the epithet of oreo; integrationists developed a rhetoric in which the nationalists represented a form of extremism akin to that of white supremacists and other hate groups. And, in fact, the polarization of the discourse between black integrationists and nationalists was a manifestation of the ways that each group threatened the other. Nationalism upset the confidence that the black middle class had held since the turn of the century in the achievement of civil rights and integration into dominant American institutionsa goal which to them *834 had appeared a real possibility. Nationalist ideology threatened the self-identity of the middle class as the elite of black society, who symbolized the achievement possible when blacks are accorded opportunity. Nationalists also undermined the black middle class' conception that their role in racial liberation was to help the brothers and sisters left behind to escape the ghetto and join mainstream institutions. In the nationalist analysis, the very success of the black middle class in American society might undermine individual identity and betray the aspirations of the black community because it reflected gains granted by a white power structure in exchange for black administration of white interests. This rhetoric called to mind the shame of the long history of accomodationism by black middle class leaders and thus generated a kind of group anxiety. Integrationismin the particular, universalist form that it took in the 1960sresponded to this anxiety by denying that the world to which the black middle class aspired was racially identifiable as a particularly white world, rather than a realm of universal, culturally-neutral social practices. Similarly, the very predominance and strength of the integrationist/civil rights tradition engendered a correlate anxiety for nationalists, an anxiety that extreme and polar expressions of black separatism helped resolve. According to Harold Cruse, the particular violence and hateful rhetoric that came to characterize black nationalist discourse by the end of the 1960s was rooted in a psychological attempt to overcome the ways that blacks had been conditioned historically to depend on whites in the realm of political action. In order to overcome the deeply ingrained interracialism that had characterized progressive coalitions for several decades, Cruse asserted that black nationalists had to muster hatred to avoid the necessity of apologizing to whites for excluding them. 164 Thus, just as black integrationists gravitated toward a particularly universalist interpretation of racial justice to help resolve anxiety that nationalists raised about their self-identity, so black nationalists gravitated toward particularly extreme interpretations in order to overcome their anxiety about their own relation to whites. And, in this cultural posture, each group tended to confirm the suspicions of the other. The more universalist the integrationist ideology, the more nationalists saw an apologetic for assimilation into the white world and a corresponding betrayal of the black community. The more hateful the nationalist ideology became, the more integrationists saw the same bitterness and parochialism that they saw in white supremacists.

*835 B. Black Nationalism and Whites

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

33

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

The ultimate marginalization of black nationalists from mainstream discourse reflects several historical factors. One important feature was the State repression that groups like the Black Panthers faced. Another was the way in which the increasingly extremist and revolutionary rhetoric and social actions on the part of both the black and the white Left began to appear more and more fantastic as time went on. 165 Furthermore, limitations in ideology often led to a rigid other-worldly revolutionary dogma gleaned from a conglomeration of Marx, Lenin, Mao, Fanon, and othersa dogma that took on an extremist, righteous tone that began to associate with the white power structure anyone who had a job. This approach alienated masses of African Americans and others who were not prepared to engage in an armed guerrilla campaign in America. 166 In addition, just as the economic health of black communities deteriorated during the early 1970s recession and the associated cutback in federal spending, the black middle class expanded with the advent of integrationism as a national policy and, by and large, abandoned traditionally black neighborhoods. 167 By the mid-1970s, successes in struggles for political influence in or control of many cities, combined with the national commitment to cultural diversity, began to echo features of the nationalist program as American mainstream institutions seemed to accommodate a diffused and limited version of black race consciousnessdevelopments that all tended to obscure the nationalist position as a sharp alternative to integration. Whatever else caused the decline of nationalism, however, there can be no question that its near-total rejection by whites played a critical factor in its exclusion from mainstream American discourse. As indicated above, the overt analytic framework for this reaction was the identification of race consciousness with the evil of racism and the consequent perception of black nationalists as racists. In this Section, I now want to speculate about what led whites to the adoption of this view of race and to the mistranslation of black nationalism as the black equivalent of white supremacy. *836 Various factors partially explain why white liberals and progressives in particular rejected nationalism as a way to analyze race relations. First, unlike the long tradition of progressive black nationalism in African American communities, the only whites who explicitly perceived race as a significant feature of group identity were white supremacistsa group historically comprised of a loose cultural coalition of Southern well-to-do whites and major segments of the white working class across the country. In their congruence of race and nationalism, race consciousness was tied to an interest in racial domination specifically the perpetuation of white dominationand, in more recent years, the exaggerated fears of black domination should African Americans achieve significant social power in American society. One factor that led to the failure of white liberals and progressives to comprehend black nationalism as a liberating rather than repressive movement was that race consciousness had been historically associated with precisely the segments of the white community from whom enlightened whites wished to distinguish themselves for their own self-respect. 168 Moreover, because black nationalism before the 1960s was largely separatist and isolationist, almost by definition whites had little or no contact with the different tradition of race consciousness among African Americans. In terms of their perception of the black nationalist position, *837 most white liberals and progressives were influenced by the conventional understanding of the racial separatism advocated by Booker T. Washington as black accommodationism to segregation. Like most black activists, white civil rights supporters in the early 1960s took the confrontation-oriented direct action wing of civil rights protest as the very definition of committed struggle. They perceived that the choices were between moderation and activism, or between legalism and street action coupled with community organizing, and that these choices defined the parameters of political and ideological issues posed by race. Prior to the 1960s, whites who were serious about race reform worked with, supported, and often directed the legalist strategies of the NAACP and the direct action integrationism of groups like the SCLC, the Urban League, SNCC, and CORE. 169 This decades-long civil rights tradition carried on by white liberals and progressives, with longer roots to 19th century abolitionists, defined racial enlightenment in relation to the staunch and often violent opposition of white supremacists. By the mid-1960s, when black nationalism reached its height of popularity within the black community, white liberals and progressives still

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

34

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

understood the issue as a choice between militancy in support of immediate integration as opposed to the conservative stance of foot-dragging. While black integrationists with any connections to the black community simply could not avoid confronting the black nationalist analysis of race in the 1960s, it is striking that, except for some relatively isolated leftist factions, whites as a group never considered the possibility that race consciousness might have a liberating, rather than repressive, meaning. Against this historical background of nonengagement with, and ignorance of, the black nationalist tradition, black nationalism confronted white integrationists in the 1960s through the militant rhetoric first of Malcolm X, and then of Black Power proponents. Although the particular form that nationalist rhetoric took in the 1960s was largely responsive to the struggle between integrationists and nationalists within the black community, an obviously significant factor in the white response was the rejection and repudiation that whites experienced from black nationalists. One important episode that marked the white response to 1960s nationalists was the expulsion and exclusion of whites from civil rights organizations like SNCC and CORE when the organizations took a nationalist turn in the mid-1960s. 170 The rageful rhetoric of hate against *838 whites adopted by many nationalist groups and leaders seemed to confirm to whites the idea that black nationalism and white supremacy were identical manifestations of irrational and indiscriminate hate. As the nationalists began to achieve power within the former direct action wing of the civil rights movement, liberal and progressive whites who had participated in the movement either withdrew from racial politics altogether or made alliances with moderate and mostly middle-class blacks around the commitment to integrationism, understood as the transcendence of race consciousness. 171 But the image that whites were simply repelled by black nationalists does not fully account for the ways that white liberals and progressives reacted to nationalism as an ideology of race reform. Their embrace of integrationism in the particular universalist form that it took in the 1960s *839 was more subtly related to anxieties of their own cultural self-identity than can be accounted for solely by the pain of exclusion and rejection by blacks. For this group of whites, the nationalist assertion of the particularities of black culture brought to the surface unresolved anxieties that nonracist whites had about their own feelings about both blacks and themselves. With respect to blacks, the nationalist assertion of difference, and the location of that difference in terms of the particularities of culture, simultaneously connected to two key issues for whites: First, whites committed to nonracism had expended energy and concentrated on overcoming the teachings of a society permeated with racist ideology that black difference specifically inferiorityjustified racial hierarchy. Second, to the extent that a residue of racist dogma remained in white liberal consciousness, it existed as a vague sense of envy that blacks were different from whites specifically because blacks possessed a rich and spiritual culturefilled with music, dance, religion, and passionate sexuality that whites experienced most strongly as lacking in the dominant white American culture. In other words, for white liberals and progressives, the nationalist assertion of a particular African American culture immediately brought to the surface white anxiety that, in fact, the nationalists were rightblacks had the kind of cohesive and rich culture that whites felt they themselves lackedand simultaneously created feelings of guilt about believing such a thing, since that kind of attribution of characteristics to blacks seemed just like the racist ideology that these whites had worked so hard to overcome. More specifically, the culture whites secretly feared that blacks possessed tended toward the same symbolic structure as white supremacist ideologyhaving a particular culture was like being a primitive and having a folklife, a spirituality and a sexuality, which stood in opposition to rationalism, objectivity and civilization. Black nationalism, particularly in the machismo and Africanist forms that it took in the late 1960s, specifically exposed the deepest inner anxieties that whites as a cultural group possessedanxieties that white liberals and progressives had worked hard to repress. Integrationism, understood as the transcendence of race consciousness, provided a vehicle for resolving the anxiety that nationalists raised by denying that blacks or whites as such had any identifiable culture at all. People happen to be black or happen to be white. In the integrationist mindset that white liberals and progressives adopted, it made no sense to think about institutional practices in racial/cultural terms, because there were no cultures tied to racial identity, anyway. And so it came to be, paradoxically, that for whites, integrationism actually constituted an indirect defense of status quo social and

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

35

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

institutional practices to the extent that *840 integrationist ideology was constructed to foreclose consideration of the cultural manifestations of racial power. Seen in this way, the psychological identity issues engendered by black nationalists were in some ways similar for both black and white integrationists. The otherwise paradoxical coalition between black moderates and conservatives, and white liberals and progressives, had its roots in the way that universalism helped resolve the identity anxieties of each group. Black integrationists could identify with a commitment to an objective, aracial set of social norms, rather than perceive themselves as assimilating into the white world. And white integrationists could understand themselves as advocating the equal distribution of opportunity rather than asserting the superiority of white social norms or acknowledging their more deep-sated fears about black passion, culture, and sexuality. In short, enlightened whites helped construct and deploy a liberal understanding of racial justice that incorporated universalist and objectivist assumptions. This understanding rejected race consciousness as a categorical matter, in part as a way to avoid issues of white cultural identity that black nationalism brought to the fore. The near universal rejection of a nationalist understanding of race was not required in order for whites to oppose white supremacists, nor was it based on simply a philosophical commitment to integrationism, since the repudiation of racial domination could have taken many other forms. Instead, the particular view of race embraced during the 1960s reflected a cultural response on the part of white liberals and progressives, not only to white supremacists, but also to black nationalists. To be sure, the embrace of integrationism did not represent the only way that the broad avoidance of white racial identity took place. Although the mainstream white response was to denounce black nationalists as reverse racists, significant elements of the white liberal and progressive community attempted to embrace nationalists as allies. A roughly identifiable group of Northeastern liberal elites, depicted in Tom Wolfe's account of this cultural phenomenon in Radical Chic & Mau-Mauing the Flak Catchers, 172 sympathized with nationalist groups and personalities, but their comprehension of the issues did not extend to the actual substantive programs or theoretical commitments of the nationalists. Instead, they perceived black nationalists from a civil liberties standpoint within which nationalists appeared as militant and aggressive civil rights groups who were wrongfully repressed by the State. *841 On the other hand, radical white groups such as the Students for a Democratic Society (SDS) did embrace the nationalist critique of existing American cultural forms as well as the critique of the conservative underside of liberal integrationism. In fact, during the 1960s there was a great degree of reciprocal influence between the developing social analysis that came to be known as the New Left and the developing black nationalist approaches. But relations between white radicals and black nationalists in the 1960s and early 1970s tended to have a distorted and pathological dynamic: White radicals approached nationalists as representing an oppressed group that possessed, by virtue of their oppression, the unique insight and entitlement to determine how the social struggle should proceed, as well as to decide virtually any other issue that arose. Lacking success with the traditional Left constituencythe working classwhite radicals began to substitute a third worldism for an economic analysis. Black nationalists, in turn, approached white radicals as representatives of historic white power. The relationship was repetitive in nature: Black radicals made more and more demands for control of white groups as evidence of white commitment, and white radicals continually deferred to blacks as acts of white atonement. The more general cultural manifestation of this stance of white radicals was the constant tendency to make blacks the paradigms of political and cultural insight. In interracial contexts in radical circles, this tendency led to the development of a dynamic of black self-assertion and racial critique, and white submission and deference colloquially known as white self-flagellationthat came to define race relations among radicals.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

36

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

These predominant relations to black nationalism 173 linked together manifestations of a central dynamic that characterized the liberal and progressive white communitythe inability to come to terms with white self-identity. The virulence with which white liberals denounced black nationalism as reverse racism, the patronizing tolerance of Northeastern liberal elites, and the self-effacing submission that characterized many white radicals who engaged nationalists, reflected a similar cultural position among nonracist whites during the 1960s. In fact, the widespread embrace of integrationism and the idea that racial enlightenment consisted *842 of transcending race consciousness was only the reigning ideological face of a more diffuse and widespread cultural avoidance that seemed to include measures of guilt, desires for atonement, and needs for absolution. 174 This discomfort with whiteness has led to a kind of self-negation. One manifestation is the attempt to construct racially neutral settings for example, public educationwhere the problem of interracialism is imagined to be resolved by effacing any culture at all. Another manifestation is the attempt to embrace black culture by making it one's own; that is, by talking and acting according to how whites think blacks act. At the individual level, this flight from racial identification appears as the exaggerated need for acceptance from blacks on the ground that one is not like the rest of the whites, that one is not really white. And the broad-scale ideological dimension is a commitment to integrationism in the particular form that has characterized mainstream race discourse for the last two decadesintegrationism understood as the transcendence of race consciousness. Black nationalism caused great anxiety and turmoil for whites, in part because of the violence that nationalists symbolized, but also in part because nationalism represented whites as constituting a community with particular cultural norms. As whites articulated their rejection of black nationalists, they complained of reverse racism because they experienced the nationalist depiction of a white culture as the same kind of essentializing and stereotyping that white racists utilized in describing black culture. And, to be sure, much of nationalist rhetoric was reductionist with respect to the complexity of group relations within the white community. But through the identification of racial identity and group consciousness as central to the structure of American social relations, the black nationalists of the 1960s also identified the particular aspect of avoidance and denial that white support of black liberation assumed the commitment by whites to deny the centrality of race as an historically constructed, and powerful, factor in the social structure of American life. Understanding racism as a form of discrimination from an *843 assumed neutral norm was the cognitive face of a widespread cultural flight from white self-identity. The resurgence of ethnic group consciousness on the part of whites during the 1970s, although in part a liberating attempt to reclaim cultural authenticity in the face of the mainstream culture of neutrality, was also in part a reflection of this same dynamic. Being Polish, Italian, or Irish meant, to a degree, not being simply white. The upshot of this cultural situation is that, despite the fact that race has worked as such a powerful element of the economy and culture of social relationships, no group of whites has formed who could identify themselves with the white community without also associating whiteness with either paralyzing guilt or interest in racial domination. Explicit white racial identification was left to lower class, ignorant whites; the implicit racial identification was left to the universalizing aspirations of the culturally dominant white upper middle class. The broadscale effect of this particular resolution of the race issue within mainstream discourse was that the very whites who might otherwise have been allies of black nationalists during the 1960s were motivated, in terms of their own cultural identity, to avoid racial identification altogether. Without the development of white race consciousness, no significant group of whites either understood themselves as struggling to transform the white community itself in terms of race relations or as supporting African Americans as a people, a nation. In terms of national policy, tremendous energy was committed to the centralized policy of integration, but little attention was paid to the integrity and health of black neighborhoods and institutions. Integration of dominant institutions, rather than reparations from one community to another, became the paradigm for racial enlightenment. The kind of cultural dynamic that I describe here is not presented as the basis for white guilt. We can be empathetic with the particular historical and cultural situation within which whites rejected African American race consciousness, and yet also

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

37

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

recognize that it had powerful, self-serving effects in insulating a wide range of social practices from cultural critique. Moreover, we can recognize the reductionist ways that 1960s nationalists described the white community without thereby completely repressing the fundamental ways that the economy of race has historically constructed our social identities and relationsin complex and often contradictory ways, but central to American life nonetheless and irreducible to class or to various forms of discrimination. And just as membership in the African American community does not exhaust the social bases upon which blacks self-identify, a recognition of membership in a white community that we did not construct, but of which we are historically a part, does not exclude the various other ways that we self- *844 identifyas Jews, Italian Americans, men and women, straights and gays, working class and middle class, and so on.

V. CONCLUSION I have argued that the basic assumptions of contemporary race discourseof what passes for common sense among the educated and enlightened where issues of race are concernedshould be understood to reflect a particular ideology rather than the necessary and transcendent meaning of progress itself. The commitment to integration as the ultimate goal of race reform, like the understanding of Brown v. Board of Education 175 as the exemplar of progressive jurisprudence, is connected in our social context to a whole range of images about the nature of truth, progress, and enlightenment within which race consciousness appears arbitrary, subjective, primitive, and backward. But this particular ideology about race was not simply chosen because it conformed with traditional liberal ideas about epistemology, historical progress, or social justice; it was constructed in this universalist form in part because the myth of universalism helped resolve at the ideological level the psycho-cultural anxieties about group and self-identity that both black moderates and white liberals and progressives experienced when militant nationalists such as Malcolm X, Stokely Carmichael, and the Black Panthers revitalized the tradition of black nationalism in the 1960s. The embrace of integrationism as the dominant ethos of race discourse is the symbolic face of the new cultural center that was created in the context of the various ruptures of American society in the 1960s. Relative to this center, black militants and white rednecks were defined together as extremists; comprehending racism as a form of discrimination meant that race could be understood as just another example of the range of arbitrary social characteristicslike gender, physical handicap or sexual preferencethat right-thinking people should learn to ignore. For the cultural centrists, the concept of overcoming bias became the way to comprehend all the various challenges to mainstream culture in the 1960smovements by women, the poor, gays and lesbians, blacks, and young anti-war and leftist counter-culturistsas together representing the basic idea that bias should be overcome in favor of objectivity and neutrality. From the outside, it was apparent that this reasonable and enlightened cultural center had a distinctly white, upper-middle class and Protestant flavora correlate in the cultural sphere to what Unitarianism, or maybe Presbyterianism, represents in the religious sphere. The *845 culture that seemed to descend upon public schools throughout the South in the late 1960s and 1970s, for example, constituted more than the new policy of racial integration or a stricter separation of church and state. Its norms of professionalism, impersonality, and centralism were experienced in the Southby both blacks and whitesas imposed from the outside, vaguely from the upper-middle class, white Northeast. But that character of the center was invisible from within it; instead, for the whites who embraced integrationism, the realm of social practices and attitudes they associated with racially integrated institutions were taken as culturally neutral and objective. The fact that everyday public school culture in integrated schools was essentially a white culture never really occurred to a whole range of otherwise decent and committed white liberals. And for the middle class black moderates who aligned with whites in constructing and supporting the integrationist ideology, the racial character of integrated institutions must have been more apparent, and yet its very obviousness made the embrace of universalist imagery all the more important to their self-respect.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

38

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

Whatever the intentions and psycho-cultural needs of black and white integrationists in the past, it should now be apparent that the exclusion of a nationalist approach to racial justice from mainstream discourse has been a cultural and political mistake that has constrained the boundaries of racial politics. Instead of comprehending racial justice in terms of the relations of distinct, historically-defined communities, the embrace of integrationism has signified the broad cultural attempt not to think in terms of race at all. Integrationists filter discussion of the wide disparities between African American and white communities through the nonracial language of poverty and class, and avoid altogether any consideration of the racial implications of the institutional practices of integrated arenas of social life. Moreover, the construction of race reform as being concerned with overcoming bias at the level of consciousness, overcoming discrimination at the practice level, and achieving integration at the institutional level has meant that tremendous social resources and personal energy have been expended on integrating formerly white schools, workplaces, neighborhoods, and attitudes. This program, such as it is, has had some success in improving the lives of specific people and in transforming the climate of overt racial domination that pervaded American society thirty years ago. But it has been pursued to the exclusion of a commitment to the vitality of the black community as a whole and to the economic and cultural health of black neighborhoods, schools, economic enterprises, and individuals. *846 It is frustrating to reconsider the long history of American race relations from this perspective. One gets the sense that if, at any number of points in American history, a nationalist program of race reform had been adopted, African Americans in virtually every urban center would not be concentrated into disintegrating housing, would not be sending their children to underfunded and overcrowded schools to learn a nationally-prescribed curriculum, would not be sending them to play in parks and on streets alongside drug dealers and gang warriors, and would not be working at the bottom of the economic hierarchy (if they are lucky enough to have a job at all). If community-to-community reparations had been made (as promised), if there had actually been a massive transfer of economic resources from the white to the black community in the 1940s, then the kind of black economic cooperatives and black-run schools, newspapers and cultural institutions advocated by Du Bois would likely exist today as foundations for healthy African American neighborhoods. Or, if a similar program had been adopted in the 1960s, one can imagine that black neighborhoods would be by and large healthy, cosmopolitan parts of the urban scene rather than ghettos of hopelessness and frustration. But, in the integrationist ideology, as Harold Cruse observed, black communities should not even exist because they are vestiges of segregation; it was therefore inconceivable to devote resources to their health rather than to programs like urban renewal plans of the late 1960s premised on their destruction. I do not mean to suggest that black nationalists in the 1960s, or at any other point in our history, had the perfect plan for social transformation, nor that they pursued the best strategies for acquiring political power and mass support. To the contrary, black nationalism is not a monolithic tradition; it has taken various forms, with its own internal dynamics and a wide range of external relations with white and black integrationists. In particular, the tendency towards essentializing black identity around centrally prescribed images of authentic black culture has been a recurring and regressive undercurrent of the nationalist presence that at times generated its own forms of craziness and oppression. But the dominant image, especially among whites, that black nationalism is simply a form of reverse racism, or that it manifests frustration with the pace of mainstream civil rights reform, and is therefore merely an emotional reaction on the part of some blacks, is just plain wrong. In terms of intellectual and philosophical sophistication, the historicizing and anti-universalist assumptions of black nationalist views about culture and identity represent a profound critique of the liberal presuppositions of integrationisma critique that extends from social theory to epistemology. *847 And, if support for nationalism can be accounted for in terms of group emotions, so too can the embrace of integrationism. The assumptions of integrationism have become so deeply ingrained in the dominant culture of educated Americans that it is easy to forget that a sharp and dramatic alternative exists for a progressive and liberating way to think about, and effectuate, race reform. The reappearance of race consciousness in the scholarly work of critical race theorists in part reflects an attempt to

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

39

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

reopen a political discourse that was closed off in the 1960s. It should be the occasion for whites to reconsider our position in the cultural compromise that defined the discourse of race and reform for the past few decades. We should, I think, reinterpret our role in race relations so that we might self-consciously understand ourselves as whites, as having a particular identity that was historically constructed through the economy of race relations. This kind of identification need not mean an interest in racial domination, nor must it mean a paralyzing guilt and self-flagellation. Rather than despise what reveals one as white, and engage in neurotic self-improvement to remove such biases, a precondition to meaningful negotiation of the terms of our social spaceswhether they are separate or sharedis to recognize that racial cultures form a significant element of what goes into the construction of our social relations. And, finally, such a historicist notion of identity also, of course, means the simultaneous recognition first, that there are other important dimensions to our self-identity and group life that are not captured by race; and second, that the meaning of race itself will necessarily change with time. An embrace of a nationalist perspective on race does not mean comprehending nationalism in the specific form that it took in the 1960s or at any other time. It means utilizing race consciousness to approach our social relations in the context of where we are right now, in the 1990s. The historicized view of nationalism, in short, means that new programs for race reform will make sense in the circumstances of today's world, where some institutions and neighborhoods do in fact represent space that is shared by blacks and whites.

Footnotes a Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center. B.A. 1977, Emory; J.D. 1980, Harvard.
I wish to thank Kimberl Crenshaw, Duncan Kennedy, Neil Gotanda, Gerald Torres, William Eskridge, Girardeau Spann, David Trubek, Nancy Ehrenreich, Theresa Miller, Amy Hill, Rina Rosenberg, and Alan Freeman for their helpful comments on this essay. This Essay is dedicated to Lowell Dickerson, whose courage in struggle and clarity of vision have inspired and informed this work.

1 2

MALCOLM X, MALCOLM X SPEAKS 31 (G. Breitman ed. 1965) [hereinafter MALCOLM X SPEAKS]. Critical Race Theory is the name of an informally organized group of scholars writing in the area of race law and theory; the group held its first conference in Madison, Wisconsin in July 1989. For a brief overview of the group's goals and perspectives, see Crenshaw, A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Law and Politics, in THE POLITICS OF LAW 195 (D. Kairys 2d ed. 1990). Matsuda, Looking to the Bottom: Critical Legal Studies and Reparations, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 323 (1987). Crenshaw, Race, Reform and Retrenchment: Transformation and Legitimation in Antidiscrimination Law, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1331, 1379-80 (1988) [hereinafter Crenshaw, Race, Reform and Retrenchment] (discussing the white norm . . . as a statement of the positive social norm, legitimating the continuing domination of those who do not meet it); Crenshaw, Foreword: Toward a RaceConscious Pedagogy in Legal Education, 11 NAT'L BLACK L.J. 1, 2 (1989) [hereinafter Crenshaw, Foreword] (discussing the dayto-day culture of law schools as embodying a false assumption of perspectivelessness). Torres & Milun, Translating Yonnondio by Precedent and Evidence: The Mashpee Indian Case, 1990 DUKE L.J. 625. See Delgado, Storytelling for Oppositionists and Others: A Plea for Narrative, 87 MICH. L. REV. 2411 (1989); Delgado, When a Story is Just a Story: Does Voice Really Matter?, 76 VA. L. REV. 95 (1990); Delgado, The Imperial Scholar: Reflections on a Review of Civil Rights Literature, 132 U. PA. L. REV. 561, 566-73 (1984) [hereinafter Delgado, The Imperial Scholar]. I have referred only to a few of the writers in the emerging Critical Race Theory approach. Others who utilize a race conscious perspective in their work include Derrick Bell, see D. BELL, AND WE ARE NOT SAVED: THE ELUSIVE QUEST FOR RACIAL JUSTICE (1987) [hereinafter D. BELL, AND WE ARE NOT SAVED]; John Calmore, see Calmore, Fair Housing vs. Fairhousing: The Problems with Providing Increased Housing Opportunities through Spatial Deconcentration, 14 CLEARINGHOUSE REV. 7 (1980) [hereinafter Calmore, Fair Housing]; Calmore, Exploring the Significance of Race and Class in Representing the Black Poor, 61 OR. L. REV. 201 (1982); Harlon Dalton, see Dalton, The Clouded Prism, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 435 (1987); Neil Gotanda, see N. Gotanda, A Critique of Our Constitution is Colorblind: Racial Categories and White Supremacy (unpublished manuscript) (available from author); Angela Harris, see Harris, Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory, 42 STAN. L. REV. 581 (1990); Charles Lawrence, see Lawrence, The Id, the Ego and Equal Protection: Reckoning With Unconscious Racism, 39 STAN. L. REV.

3 4

5 6

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

40

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 317 (1987); Theresa Miller, see T. Miller, An Anti-Integrationist's Critique of School Desegregation: Making the Case for Black Colleges (unpublished manuscript) (available from author); Patricia Williams, see Williams, Alchemical Notes: Reconstructing Ideals from Deconstructed Rights, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 401 (1987); Williams, The Obliging Shell: An Informal Essay on Formal Equal Opportunity, 87 MICH. L. REV. 2128 (1989) [hereinafter Williams, The Obliging Shell]; Robert Williams, see Williams, Taking Rights Aggressively: The Perils and Promise of Critical Legal Theory for Peoples of Color, 5 LAW & INEQUALITY 103 (1987); Williams, The Algebra of Federal Indian Law: The Hard Trail of Decolonizing and Americanizing the White Man's Indian Jurisprudence, 1986 WIS. L. REV. 219. Race consciousness in the work of Critical Race Theorists has been noted and criticized by Randall Kennedy in R. Kennedy, Racial Critiques of Legal Academia, 102 HARV. L. REV. 1745 (1989).

7 8 9

See R. Kennedy, supra note 6, at 1786-1807. For example, the institutionalization of Black History Month as an element of official American culture. I am thinking, for example, about the public school culture created in part to reform previously racist schools. See infra notes 35-41 and accompanying text. See, e.g., City of Richmond v. Croson, 488 U.S. 469, 521 (1989) (Scalia, J., concurring) (only a social emergency rising to the level of life and limb . . . can justify an exception to the principle embodied in the Fourteenth Amendment that our Constitution is colorblind. . . .) (quoting Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting)). MALCOLM X, BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY: SPEECHES, INTERVIEWS AND A LETTER 16-17 (G. Breitman ed. 1970) [hereinafter MALCOLM X, BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY]. For examples of opposition to affirmative action among academics, see A. BICKEL, THE MORALITY OF CONSENT 133-34 (1975) (affirmative action divides society, reduces productivity and promotes inequality); T. SOWELL, CIVIL RIGHTS: RHETORIC OR REALITY 13-48, 109-16 (1984); Abram, Affirmative Action: Fair Shakers and Social Engineers, 99 HARV. L. REV. 1312 (1986); Posner, The DeFunis Case and the Constitutionality of Preferential Treatment of Racial Minorities, 1974 SUP. CT. REV. 1 (1974); Schiff, Reverse Discrimination Re-Defined as Equal Protection: The Orwellian Nightmare in the Enforcement of Civil Rights Laws, 8 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 627 (1985); Van Alstyne, Rites of Passage: Race, the Supreme Court, and the Constitution, 46 U. CHI. L. REV. 775 (1979). For examples of academics supporting affirmative action, see Bell, Bakke, Minority Admissions and the Usual Price of Racial Remedies, 67 CALIF. L. REV. 3 (1979); Brest, Foreword: In Defense of the Antidiscrimination Principle, 90 HARV. L. REV. 1 (1976); Delgado, The Imperial Scholar, supra note 6, at 566-73; Ely, The Constitutionality of Reverse Racial Discrimination, 41 U. CHI. L. REV. 723 (1974); Fallon & Weiler, Firefighters v. Stotts: Conflicting Models of Racial Justice, 1984 SUP. CT. REV. 1; Fiss, Groups and the Equal Protection Clause, 5 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 107, 147-70 (1976); Freeman, Racism, Rights and the Quest for Equality of Opportunity: A Critical Legal Essay, 23 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 295, 362-85 (1988); Karst & Horowitz, Affirmative Action and Equal Protection, 60 VA. L. REV. 955 (1974); R. Kennedy, Persuasion and Distrust: A Comment on the Affirmative Action Debate, 99 HARV. L. REV. 1327 (1986); Wasserstrom, Racism, Sexism and Preferential Treatment: An Approach to the Topics, 24 UCLA L. REV. 581 (1977). For examples of the Supreme Court's reactions to affirmative action plans, see Croson, 488 U.S. at 498-99 (affirmative action by municipality in awarding contracts not justified by general societal discrimination); Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Educ., 476 U.S. 267 (1986) (affirmative action hiring plans in consent decrees cannot impinge on whites' seniority rights for layoff purposes absent showing that the blacks to be laid off were themselves victims of discrimination). Cf. United Steelworkers v. Weber, 433 U.S. 193 (1979) (broad statistical disparity between workforce and population sufficient predicate for affirmative action provision in collective bargaining agreement); Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 311-17 (1978) (race as a factor in an admissions plan may be upheld on the basis of medical school interest in diversity). Compare Ward's Cove Packing Co. v. Atonio, 109 S.Ct. 2115 (1989) (plaintiffs in Title VII suits must demonstrate how particular invidious employment practices caused discriminatory results to shift burden of production to the defendants) and Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976) (holding that a racially discriminatory purpose must be proved to make out a claim under the equal protection clause) with Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.S. 424 (1971) (disparate impact of facially neutral employment practices makes out a prima facie Title VII claim, subject to showing of business necessity) and White v. Register, 412 U.S. 755 (1973) (inhibiting effect of redistricting on minority political participation sufficient for prima facie violation of equal protection clause).

10

11

12

13

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

41

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 Academic defenses of at least some form of the intent requirement include Brest, Palmer v. Thompson: An Approach to the Problem of Unconstitutional Legislative Motivation, 1971 SUP. CT. REV. 95; Ely, Legislative and Administrative Motivation Constitutional Law, 79 YALE L.J. 1205 (1970). Criticisms of the doctrine include Fiss, Groups and the Equal Protection Clause, supra note 12; Lawrence, supra note 6; Strauss, Discriminatory Intent and the Taming of Brown, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 935 (1989); Note, Discriminatory Purpose and Mens Rea: The Tortured Argument of Invidious Intent, 93 YALE L.J. 111 (1983). See generally Freeman, Legitimating Racial Discrimination Through Antidiscrimination Law: A Critical Review of Supreme Court Doctrine, 62 MINN. L. REV. 1049 (1978) (arguing that the intent/impact controversy is one element of a more general ideological struggle between victim and perpetrator perspectives within antidiscrimination law). For general discussions of the constitutional issues, see Brest, supra note 12; Eisenberg, Disproportionate Impact and Illicit Motive: Theories of Constitutional Adjudication, 52 N.Y.U. L. REV. 36 (1977).

14

Compare Keyes v. School Dist., 413 U.S. 189, 198-203 (1973) (finding of de jure discrimination in one part of city justifies presumption that actual segregative results in other parts of the city are also the effect of de jure intent) and Swann v. CharlotteMecklenburg Bd. of Educ., 402 U.S. 1, 16-18 (1970) (clarifying broad remedial powers of federal courts to remedy school segregation) and Green v. County School Bd., 391 U.S. 430 (1967) (striking down freedom of choice desegregation plans because of a concern with achievement of a certain result) and Fiss, The Fate of an Idea Whose Time Has Come: Antidiscrimination Law in the Second Decade After Brown v. Board of Education, 41 U. CHI. L. REV. 742 (1974) (calling for consideration of result-oriented rather than process-oriented antidiscrimination remedies) with Dayton Bd. of Educ. v. Brinkman, 443 U.S. 526, 542-44 (1978) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (arguing that only de jure segregation is remediable under Constitution) and Columbus Bd. of Educ. v. Penick, 443 U.S. 449, 492-508 (1978) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (same) and Pasadena City Bd. of Educ. v. Spangler, 427 U.S. 424 (1975) (suggesting that once effects of de jure segregation are overcome, there is no more obligation to achieve actual racial integration) and Milliken v. Bradley, 418 U.S. 717 (1974) (reversing order for interdistrict remedy for school desegregation since de jure violation proven in only one of the districts) and Keyes, 413 U.S. at 258 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (there is no affirmative duty to integrate, only an obligation not to engage in de jure racial discrimination) and Kitch, The Return of Color-Consciousness to the Constitution: Weber, Dayton, and Columbus, 1979 SUP. CT. REV. 1. For a general overview, see Goodman, De Facto School Segregation: A Constitutional and Empirical Analysis, 60 CALIF. L. REV. 275 (1972); Note, Reading the Mind of the School Board: Segregative Intent and the De Jure/De Facto Distinction, 86 YALE L.J. 317 (1976). There is now a substantial body of work describing the early years of the direct action civil rights movement. I have found most useful R. BLUMBERG, CIVIL RIGHTS: THE 1960s FREEDOM STRUGGLE (1984); T. BRANCH, PARTING THE WATERS: AMERICA IN THE KING YEARS, 1954-1963 (1988) (focusing on King and the Southern Christian Legal Conference (SCLC)); R. BRISBANE, BLACK ACTIVISM: RACIAL REVOLUTION IN THE UNITED STATES, 1954-1970 (1974); T. BROOKS, WALLS COME TUMBLING DOWN: A HISTORY OF THE CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT, 1940-1970 (1974); C. CARSON, IN STRUGGLE: SNCC AND THE BLACK AWAKENING OF THE 1960's (1981); D. GARROW, BEARING THE CROSS: MARTIN LUTHER KING, JR., AND THE SOUTHERN CHRISTIAN LEADERSHIP CONFERENCE (1986); A. MEIER & E. RUDWICK, C.O.R.E., A STUDY OF THE CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT, 1942-1968 (1973); A. MORRIS, THE ORIGINS OF THE CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT: BLACK COMMUNITIES ORGANIZING FOR CHANGE (1984); B. MUSE, THE AMERICAN NEGRO REVOLUTION: FROM NONVIOLENCE TO BLACK POWER (1968); H. SITKOFF, STRUGGLE FOR BLACK EQUALITY, 1954-1980 (1981); E. STOPER, THE STUDENT NON-VIOLENT COORDINATING COMMITTEE: THE GROWTH OF RADICALISM IN A CIVIL RIGHTS ORGANIZATION (1989); R. WEISBROT, FREEDOM BOUND: A HISTORY OF AMERICA'S CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT (1990); H. ZINN, SNCC: THE NEW ABOLITIONISTS (1965); Colaiaco, Martin Luther King, Jr., and the Paradox of Nonviolent Direct Action, 47 PHYLON 16 (1986). The classic text embodying this perspective is G. ALLPORT, THE NATURE OF PREJUDICE (1954). The comprehension of racism as embodied in the idea of prejudice has had wide influence in academic study. See R. BLAUNER, RACIAL OPPRESSION IN AMERICA 19 (1972) (The analysis of race by social scientists has been shaped by an underlying assumption that the concern with color in human society is ultimately irrational or nonrational.). For works employing this concept of prejudice, see O. COX, RACE RELATIONS: ELEMENTS AND SOCIAL DYNAMICS 21-40, 226-41 (1976); T. CROSS, THE BLACK POWER IMPERATIVE: RACIAL INEQUALITY AND THE POLITICS OF NONVIOLENCE 83-136 (1984); R. DANIELS & H. KITANO, AMERICAN RACISM: EXPLORATION OF THE NATURE OF PREJUDICE (1970); J. JONES, PREJUDICE AND RACISM (1972); G.

15

16

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

42

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 MYRDAL, AN AMERICAN DILEMMA: THE NEGRO PROBLEM AND MODERN DEMOCRACY 106-12 (1944); R. PARK, RACE AND CULTURE 231-43 (1950); RACISM: A CASEBOOK (F. Lapides & D. Burrous eds. 1971); Blumer, Race Prejudice as a Sense of Group Position, PAC. SOC. REV., Spring 1958, at 1; Lusky, The Stereotype: The Hard Core of Racism, 13 BUFFALO L. REV. 450 (1964). This view of racism as based in prejudice was embodied in the REPORT OF THE NATIONAL ADVISORY COMMISSION ON CIVIL DISORDERS (Bantam ed. 1968) [hereinafter COMMISSION REPORT]; for criticisms of this vision in the Commission's report, see Marx, Two Cheers for the National Riot Commission, in BLACK AMERICA 78 (J. Szwed ed. 1970); Tabb, Race Relations Models and Social Change, 18 SOC. PROBS. 431-34 (1971). For general critiques of the way social scientists have comprehended race through the images of irrationality and bias, see L. BENNETT, THE CHALLENGE OF BLACKNESS 121 (1972) (discussing the vision of racism as a mental error); R. BLAUNER, supra, at 2-11; W. WILSON, POWER, RACISM, AND PRIVILEGE: RACE RELATIONS IN THEORETICAL AND SOCIOHISTORICAL PERSPECTIVES 29-68 (1973). For a recent work presupposing this prejudice/stereotype model as the definition of racism, see R. Kennedy, supra note 6, at 1787-1807.

17

See M. CASSITY, LEGACY OF FEAR: AMERICAN RACE RELATIONS TO 1900, at 32-63 (1985); S. DRAKE, BLACK FOLK: HERE AND THERE 28-30 (1987) (explaining the origin and perpetuation of the stereotype of the Negro); G. FREDRICKSON, THE BLACK IMAGE IN THE WHITE MIND: THE DEBATE IN AFRO-AMERICAN CHARACTER AND DESTINY, 1817-1914, at 53-58, 275-82 (1972); R. HORSMAN, RACE AND MANIFEST DESTINY: THE ORIGINS OF AMERICAN RACIAL ANGLO-SAXONISM 43-61, 116-57 (1981); W. JORDAN, WHITE OVER BLACK: AMERICAN ATTITUDES TOWARD THE NEGRO, 1550-1812 (1968); I, NEWBY, JIM CROW'S DEFENSE: ANTI-NEGRO THOUGHT IN AMERICA 1900-1930 (1968); C. VANN WOODWARD, THE STRANGE CAREER OF JIM CROW 56-95 (1958); Crenshaw, Race, Reform, and Retrenchment, supra note 4, at 1373-76. See G. FREDRICKSON, WHITE SUPREMACY (1981); C. VANN WOODWARD, supra note 17. The classic study is J. DOLLARD, CASTE AND CLASS IN A SOUTHERN TOWN (1949). See generally Alkalimat, The Ideology of Black Social Science, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY 173, 175 (J. Ladner ed. 1973) [hereinafter THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY] (linking prejudice, discrimination, and segregation as key elements of restrictive white ideology about racism). See Fein, Community Schools and Social Theory: The Limits of Universalism, in COMMUNITY CONTROL OF SCHOOLS 76, 91 (H. Levin ed. 1970). According to Leonard Fein, [T]he central tenet of liberals, when dealing with race, has been to assert its irrelevance. The argument has been that color is an accidental characteristic, which, in the truly rational, liberated, social order, ceases to have any empirical correlates. . . . The main thrust of the civil rights movement has been, therefore, in the direction of persuading white America to become color-blind. The corollary of the liberal ethic that white people ought not to pay attention to the blackness of Negroes was the proposition that Negroes ought not to pay attention to their own blackness. James Farmer tells a story indicating the extreme manifestation of the colorblindness affliction, at least among some whites. A 20 year-old white CORE worker was mugged in her apartment. She described the assailant with great detail to the police, including height, weight, eyes, teeth, and clothing, but she didn't mention that fact that he was black for fear of indicating prejudice. J. FARMER, FREEDOMWHEN? 85 (1965). As Farmer makes clear, this analysis of racism and prejudice was extremely individualistic; the error of prejudice was taken to be reaching conclusions about people on the basis of any group association at all. See also R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 2-50 (describing the focus of sociologists of race on prejudice, stereotype, and assimilation and linking such a frame with individualist norms); H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL 6-8 (1967) (describing integrationist link to individualist mythology of merit); Miller, Farewell to Liberals, in BLACK PROTEST THOUGHT IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY 379 (A. Meier, E. Rudwick & F. Broderick eds. 1971) (liberals individualize racism and look toward the elimination of all race distinction, failing to recognize race as a group status). The equality of opportunity or formal equality ideology underlying this basic vision of racism is discussed in Crenshaw, Race, Reform and Retrenchment, supra note 4, at 1336-49; Fallon, To Each According to His Ability, From None According to His Race: The Concept of Merit in the Law of Antidiscrimination, 60 B.U.L. REV. 815 (1980); Freeman, supra note 12, at 354-85; Williams, The Obliging Shell, supra note 6, at 2142. See also Malcolm X & Farmer, Separation or Integration: A Debate, DIALOGUE, May 1962, at 14, reprinted in BLACK PROTEST THOUGHT IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY 387, 404 (A. Meier, E. Rudwick & F. Broderick eds. 1971) [hereinafter Separation or Integration] (according to Farmer, integration means that each individual [is] to be accepted

18

19

20

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

43

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 on basis of his merit and not on the basis of his color); Rustin, Separate is not Equal, in BLACK PROTEST THOUGHT IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, supra, at 622 (after graduation [black students] will have to engage in free and open competition for jobs in a marketplace where standards are universal); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at xiii (A basic assumption of liberalism in the 1960s was that equal protection of constitutional rights would afford all Americans, regardless of color, an equal chance to amass wealth, influence, and stature.).

21

See T. CROSS, supra note 16, at 609-10. According to Cross, Integration is indispensable to shattering racial stereotypes. . . . Only in day-to-day contact with blacks will whites learn that blacks are not less intelligent, less honest, or less human than whites. Through time, integrated living and integrated education are the most forceful weapons for breaking the stubborn and enduring mental habit of defining people's traits according to their race. See also Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 177 (investing in education is a major integrationist policy because racism is seen to be based in ignorance); Malcolm X & Farmer, supra note 20, at 17 (According to Farmer, [i]t is segregation that produces prejudice, as much as prejudice produces segregation.); Fein, supra note 19, at 90 (liberals have seen the public schools as society's best hope for achieving comprehensive integration). The roots of the idea that overcoming racism would mean integration, understood as assimilation, can be found in academic thought in the widely influential study by Robert Park, see R. PARK, RACE AND CULTURE, supra note 16 (describing a structure of race-relations based on distinct stages of contact, competition, accommodation, and assimilation). Park's basic model was somewhat refined by Wirth, The Problem of Minority Groups, in THE SCIENCE OF MAN IN THE WORLD CRISIS (R. Linton ed. 1945); see also N. GLAZER & D. MOYNIHAN, BEYOND THE MELTING POT (1963); M. GORDON, ASSIMILATION IN AMERICAN LIFE 62-64 (1964) (discussing Park's definition of assimilation). For discussions of the influence of Park's basic model, see R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 5-12; Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 173-81. For a description of this perspective at the level of everyday culture among civil rights activists in the 1950s and early 1960s, see J. FARMER, supra note 19, at 53-128; Epps, The Integrationists, in THROUGH DIFFERENT EYES: BLACK AND WHITE PERSPECTIVES ON AMERICAN RACE RELATIONS (P. Rose, S. Rothman & W. Wilson eds. 1973). See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 266-68; Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 177-82; J. FARMER, supra note 19, at 85-86; Fein, supra note 19, at 89-93. Although integrationism rejected the essentialism of white supremacy ideology, it constituted its own form of essentialism by assuming that the categories of description themselves were outside the social economy of racethat is, the assumption that the division of the world between the rational and the emotional, or the pious and the lustful, was not itself part and parcel of a rhetoric of domination. According to integrationists, racism consists only in the failure to recognize the distribution of these characteristics across racial lines, rather than in the ideological structure that conceives of the mind and the body, reason and desire, and intelligence and ignorance as the natural categories to organize social perception. See infra notes 94-103 and accompanying text. T. SHIBUTANI & K. KWAN, ETHNIC STRATIFICATION: A COMPARATIVE APPROACH 589 (1965). Shibutani and Kwan argue that: Human beings throughout the world are fundamentally alike. . . . Hence, whenever social distance is reduced, individuals recognize their resemblances. The basic differences between ethnic groups are cultural, and conventional norms serve as masks to cover the similarities. Whenever men interact informally, the common human nature comes through. It would appear, then, that it is only a matter of time before a more enlightened citizenry will realize this. Then, there will be a realignment of group loyalties, and ethnic identity will become a thing of the past. See Fein, supra note 19, at 87-94 (describing the centrality of the idea of universalism to liberal integrationists). For other writers linking integrationism with a commitment to universalism, see R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 266-67; L. BENNETT, supra note 16, at 35-36; R. STAPLES, INTRODUCTION TO BLACK SOCIOLOGY 260-61 (1976); Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 188. See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 266-67 (The liberal wants to judge a man in terms of his individual uniqueness and his universal humanity, not in terms of accidental features like skin color. Universalism thus goes hand in hand with individualism, and in the area of race the two join in the ideal of color blindness.). For descriptions of the centrality of these distinctions to Enlightenment thought generally, see M. HORKHEIMER & T. ADORNO, DIALECTIC OF ENLIGHTENMENT (J. Cumming trans. 1972); H. MARCUSE, REASON AND REVOLUTION: HEGEL AND THE RISE OF SOCIAL THEORY (1955).

22

23

24

25

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

44

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 For discussions of the polarities of reason and desire as central to the liberal theories of justice, embodied in the distinction between law and politics, see R. UNGER, KNOWLEDGE AND POLITICS 1-103 (1975); Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133 U. PA. L. REV. 685 (1985); Peller, The Metaphysics of American Law, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 1151 (1985).

26

See Fein, supra note 19, at 87 (The liberal commitment, in education as in other spheres, is to universalism. We approach liberal salvation as we move from the sacred to the secular . . . from tradition through charisma to rational bureaucracy.). R. NISBET, COMMUNITY AND POWER (1962). Robert Nisbet describes the liberal vision of progress as a move toward increasing secularization: The demands of freedom appeared to be in the direction of the release of large numbers of individuals from the statuses and identities that had been forged in them by the dead hand of the past. A free society would be one in which individuals were morally and socially as well as politically free, free from groups and classes. . . . Freedom would arise from the individual's release from all the inherited personal interdependencies of traditional community, and from his existence in an impersonal, natural, economic order. Id. at 22. For other discussions of the general secularization associated with liberal visions of progress, see generally M. HORKHEIMER & T. ADORNO, supra note 25; R. UNGER, LAW IN MODERN SOCIETY: TOWARD A CRITICISM OF SOCIAL THEORY (1976). See supra note 25. See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 19-21 (linking repudiation of race consciousness with similar images of religiosity and other forms of primordial belief). The link between images of universalism and progress in liberal ideology are well summarized by Robert Nisbet: To regard all evil as a persistence or revival of the past has been a favorite conceit of liberals nourished by the idea of Progress. . . . Present evils could safely be regarded as regrettable evidences of incomplete emancipation from the pastfrom tribalism, from agrarianism, religion, localism, and the like. In one form or another, the theory of cultural lag has been the secular approach to the problem of evil. R. NISBET, supra note 27, at 214. See C. JENCKS, INEQUALITY: A REASSESSMENT OF THE EFFECT OF FAMILY AND SCHOOLING IN AMERICA 253-65 (1972); Fiss, supra note 12, at 154-55. The cultural deprivation analysis was especially prevalent in the 1960s. See, e.g., N. GLAZER & D. MOYNIHAN, supra note 21, at 53 (arguing that lower-class problems are so great and the line dividing lower from middle class so thin that the middle-class Negro cannot deal with them); E. LIEBOW, TALLY'S CORNER: A STUDY OF NEGRO STREETCORNER MEN 208-22 (1966) (concluding that black male street culture is not distinct from white culture but is merely a shadow system of values); C. SILBERMAN, CRISIS IN BLACK AND WHITE 249-307 (1964) (arguing that an overall poverty of environment accounts for the problems in slum schools and the poor educational performance of Negro children). Silberman later repudiated the position in C. SILBERMAN, CRISIS IN THE CLASSROOM: THE REMAKING OF AMERICAN EDUCATION 81 (1970). For one of many criticisms of the cultural deprivation approach as racist, see K. CLARK, DARK GHETTO: DILEMMAS OF POWER 129-53 (1965). See Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 311-15 (1978) (finding the goal of a diverse student body to be a compelling justification for affirmative action admissions); R. DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 301-03 (1985) (Places in medical schools are scarce resources and must be used to provide what . . . society most needs. . . . Racial justice is now a special need.); Letter from Robert Lack to the Editors, N.Y. Times, Mar. 9, 1981, at A22, col. 3 (defending affirmative action plan for Harvard Law Review based on the need for diversity). I don't mean to suggest that the ideology of merit has never been questioned within the mainstream discourse. See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 20 (merit is but one value which competes and conflicts with other values); Wasserstrom, supra note 12, at 619 (arguing that no normative justification can be found for meritocracy). Conventional discourse, however, has contained the critique of meritocracy to low-level, blue collar positions; the assumption has been that higher-level jobs are truly based on merit. See Bartholet, Application of Title VII to Jobs in High Places, 95 HARV. L. REV. 945 (1982). For a particularly telling example of this elitism, see the sharp reaction that the usually liberal New York Times editors expressed in opposing the adoption of an affirmative action program

27

28 29

30

31

32

33

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

45

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 for membership on the Harvard Law Review. Drawing Distinctions at Harvard Law, N.Y. Times, Mar. 3, 1981, at A18, col. 1 (characterizing selection procedures as a fixed standard of [absolute] merit). For an extended analysis of the link between the ideology of meritocracy and issues of race, see Freeman, supra note 12, at 295, 362-85.

34

See R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 260-61. Robert Staples linked the origin of the theory that whites and blacks are identical to the ideology of universalism: The theory that no important differences exist between Blacks and Whites in America either biologically or culturallyis of recent origin. It gained prominence at precisely the time when Blacks began to insist they did have distinctive attitudes, values, and lifestyles and began to question the validity and relevance of White culture. At the same time that Whites wanted to be color-blind, Blacks were demanding separate admissions standards to schools and jobs. Thus the ideology of universalism must be viewed in proper context. It is mostly an attempt by Whites to maintain institutional arrangements which embody the residual results of past overt racism. See Abington School Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 223-25 (1963) (prohibiting public school children from reciting verses of the Bible and the Lord's Prayer does not establish a religion of secularism but instead allows the government to maintain strict neutrality vis-a-vis religion); Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421 (1962) (declaring unconstitutional state-sponsored, non-denominational prayer in schools). See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 19 (linking social science view of religious belief as irrational with similar view about race consciousness). The link between integration and the ban on school prayer was made explicit by both George Wallace and Martin Luther King, Jr. See M. L. KING, JR., A TESTAMENT OF HOPE: THE ESSENTIAL WRITINGS OF MARTIN LUTHER KING, JR. 374 (J. Washington ed. 1986) [hereinafter M. L. KING, A TESTAMENT OF HOPE]; see also Fein, supra note 19, at 87 (linking secularism and integrationism). See Freeman, supra note 12, at 375-85. For a general description of the cultural and political clash reflected in the reform of Southern schools, see Peller, Creation, Evolution and the New South, TIKKUN, Nov.-Dec. 1987, at 72. M. LIEBERMAN, THE FUTURE OF PUBLIC EDUCATION 60 (1960). Id. at 38. For a more general discussion of the link between professionalism, centralism and progress in liberal attitudes toward public education, see Fein, supra note 19, at 87. M. LIEBERMAN, supra note 39, at 34. Browne, A Case for Separation, in SEPARATISM OR INTEGRATION: WHICH WAY FOR AMERICA: A DIALOGUE 7-15 (R. Browne & B. Rustin eds. 1968). Browne, then a professor of economics at Fairleigh Dickinson University, advocated partitioning the United States into two separate and independent nations at the Conference on Black Power held in Newark, New Jersey in July, 1967. T. DRAPER, THE REDISCOVERY OF BLACK NATIONALISM 136-37 (1969). See Browne, The Case for Black Separatism, RAMPARTS, Dec. 1967, at 50. For the best general histories of black nationalism, see R. ALLEN, A GUIDE TO BLACK POWER IN AMERICA: AN HISTORICAL ANALYSIS (1970); R. CARLISLE, THE ROOTS OF BLACK NATIONALISM (1975); H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION? 48-97, 193-258 (1968); T. DRAPER, supra note 42; W. MOSES, THE GOLDEN AGE OF BLACK NATIONALISM, 1850-1925 (1978); A. PINKNEY, RED, BLACK AND GREEN: BLACK NATIONALISM IN THE UNITED STATES (1976); BLACK NATIONALISM IN AMERICA (J. Bracey, Jr., A. Meier & E. Rudwick eds. 1970) (a documentary history). Although I utilize different frames of reference, my analysis of competing African American traditions has been influenced by Cornel West's excellent study; see C. WEST, PROPHESY DELIVERANCE!: AN AFRO-AMERICAN REVOLUTIONARY CHRISTIANITY (1982). For Delany's views of American race relations, see M. DELANY, THE CONDITION, ELEVATION, EMIGRATION AND DESTINY OF THE COLORED PEOPLE OF THE UNITED STATES 159-73 (1852) ([T]hat there are circumstances under which emigration is absolutely necessary to [our] political elevation cannot be disputed. . . . We desire the civilization and enlightenment of Africa.). Recently, a body of scholarly work has considered Delany's significance in terms of the black nationalist tradition. See

35

36

37

38

39 40

41 42

43

44

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

46

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 21-41; C. GRIFFITH, THE AFRICAN DREAM: MARTIN R. DELANY AND THE EMERGENCE OF PAN-AFRICAN THOUGHT (1975); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 23-27; V. ULLMAN, MARTIN R. DELANY: THE BEGINNINGS OF BLACK NATIONALISM (1971). Prior to Delany, Paul Cuffe had called for repatriation of blacks to Africa, petitioned Congress for assistance in 1814, and actually resettled 38 blacks to Sierra Leone in 1815. See also S. HARRIS, PAUL CUFFE: BLACK AMERICA AND THE AFRICAN RETURN 62-65 (1972); W. ALEXANDER, MEMOIR OF CAPTAIN PAUL CUFFEE, A MAN OF COLOUR: TO WHICH IS SUBJOINED THE EPISTLE OF THE SOCIETY OF SIERRA LEONE, IN AFRICA &C. (1811). Congress funded the American Colonization Society, founded by whites to resettle free blacks to Africa, in 1819. The Society purchased land on the west coast of Africa and began what became, in 1847, the country of Liberia. The Society had an explicit white supremacist ideology and was opposed by most African Americans, although it claimed to have resettled 13,000 blacks prior to the Civil War. Delany, among other black leaders, refused to cooperate with the American Colonization Society, denouncing its leaders as arrant hypocrites. E. REDKEY, BLACK EXODUS 18-21 (1969). See R. CARLISLE, supra note 43 (summaries of antebellum emigration proposals and efforts); T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 14-33; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 19-23. Delany's nationalism was explicitly opposed to the ideology of constitutional civil rights, and he and Frederick Douglass had public disagreements. See Delany, I Have No Hopes in this Country, quoted in T. WAGSTAFF, BLACK POWER: THE RADICAL RESPONSE TO WHITE AMERICA 43 (1969). An important advocate of emigration to Africa during the late 19th and early 20th century was Bishop Henry Turner. See T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 43-47; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 28-36; M. PONTON, THE LIFE AND TIMES OF HENRY M. TURNER (1970).

45

According to Harold Cruse, Booker T. Washington is a central figure in the tradition of black nationalism in the United States. Black Power is militant Booker T.-ism. H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 201. For Washington's analysis of racial progress, including his philosophy of economic self-improvement, see B. WASHINGTON, FUTURE OF THE AMERICAN NEGRO (1899); B. WASHINGTON, UP FROM SLAVERY (1901); see also A. MEIER, NEGRO THOUGHT IN AMERICA, 1880-1915: RACIAL IDEOLOGIES IN THE AGE OF BOOKER T. WASHINGTON (1963). The leading biography of Washington is the two-volume work by Louis Harlan, L. HARLAN, BOOKER T. WASHINGTON: THE MAKING OF A BLACK LEADER, 1865-1901 (1972); L. HARLAN, BOOKER T. WASHINGTON: THE WIZARD OF TUSKEGEE, 1901-1915 (1983). Documents concerning Washington are exhaustively collected in THE BOOKER T. WASHINGTON PAPERS (L. Harlan & R. Smock eds. 1972-89) (14 vols.). The most effective early 20th century black nationalist leader, Marcus Garvey, a Jamaican emigrant to the United States, founded the Universal Negro Improvement Association (UNIA). The UNIA advocated black unity, a mass migration to Africa and the liberation and unification of Africa as a homeland for all black people. Garvey urged the immediate organization of all-black businesses and established UNIA operated cooperatives, including the Black Star Line steamship company. Garvey also started Negro World. Critical of the NAACP's focus on politics and civil rights and disparaging of its intellectual leader, W.E.B. Du Bois, Garvey attacked NAACP activists as race traitors. The UNIA attracted a half-million people at its height in the 1920s, almost entirely from the poor of the urban ghettoes, with chapters in cities across the United States and abroad. For the best studies of Garvey, see E. CRONON, BLACK MOSES: THE STORY OF MARCUS GARVEY AND THE UNIVERSAL NEGRO IMPROVEMENT ASSOCIATION (1955) (focusing on Garvey's shortcomings as a leader); A. GARVEY, GARVEY AND GARVEYISM (1970) (a description of Garvey and the movement by his widow); T. MARTIN, RACE FIRST: THE IDEOLOGICAL AND ORGANIZATIONAL STRUGGLES OF MARCUS GARVEY AND THE NEGRO IMPROVEMENT ASSOCIATION (1976) (arguing that Garvey was a revolutionary and the greatest black figure of the century); T. VINCENT, BLACK POWER AND THE GARVEY MOVEMENT (1971) (contending that Garvey was the direct forerunner of 1960s nationalists). The religious component of Garveyism is analyzed in R. BURKETT, GARVEYISM AS A CIVIL RELIGIOUS MOVEMENT: THE INSTITUTIONALIZATION OF A BLACK CIVIL RELIGION (1978). For a collection of Garvey's pre-1925 views, see PHILOSOPHY AND OPINIONS OF MARCUS GARVEY (A. Garvey ed. 1968) (two volumes); see also MARCUS GARVEY AND UNIVERSAL NEGRO IMPROVEMENT ASSOCIATION (R. Hill ed. 1983) (two volumes) (collection of documents relating to the Garvey movement). For diverse views of the Muslims, see E. ESSIEN-UDOM, BLACK NATIONALISM: A SEARCH FOR AN IDENTITY IN AMERICA (1962); C. LINCOLN, THE BLACK MUSLIMS IN AMERICA (1962); E. MUHAMMAD, MESSAGE TO THE BLACK MAN IN AMERICA (1965); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 155-64. For an analysis that connects the Nation of Islam to Booker T. Washington, see H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 211. Cruse writes that:

46

47

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

47

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 [The] Nation of Islam was nothing but a form of Booker T. Washington's economic self-help, black unity, bourgeois hard work, law abiding, vocational training, stay-out-of-the-civil-rights-struggle agitation, separate-from-the-white-man, etc., etc., morality. The only difference was that Elijah Muhammad added the potent factor of the Muslim religion to a race, economic, and social philosophy of which the first prophet was none other than Booker T. Washington. Elijah also added an element of hate Whitey ideology which Washington, of course, would never have accepted.

48

See Du Bois, Postcript: The N.A.A.C.P. and Race Segregation, 41 CRISIS 52, 53 (1934); W.E.B. DU BOIS, DUSK OF DAWN AUTOBIOGRAPHY 193, 199 (1940). For a discussion of the significance of Du Bois' shift in ideology, see H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL: A CRITICAL STUDY OF BLACKS AND MINORITIES AND AMERICA'S PLURAL SOCIETY 80-101 (1987) [hereinafter H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL]; H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 175-77, 330-36, 558-65; M. MARABLE, W.E.B. DU BOIS: BLACK RADICAL DEMOCRAT 140-42 (1986); J. WHITE, BLACK LEADERSHIP IN AMERICA, 1895-1968, at 52-61 (1985). See MALCOLM X, THE AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF MALCOLM X (A. Haley ed. 1965); MALCOLM X, BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY, supra note 11; MALCOLM X SPEAKS, supra note 1; P. GOLDMAN, THE DEATH AND LIFE OF MALCOLM X (1973). See E. CLEAVER, POST-PRISON WRITINGS AND SPEECHES (R. Scheer ed. 1969); E. CLEAVER, SOUL ON ICE (1968). See S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, BLACK POWER: THE POLITICS OF LIBERATION IN AMERICA (1967) (Carmichael, a former chairperson of SNCC, is now known as Kwame Toure). See Baraka, The Pan-African Party and the Black Nation, BLACK SCHOLAR, Mar. 1971, at 24; I. BARAKA, RAISE, RACE, RAYS, RAZE (1971). See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43. See THE BLACK PANTHERS SPEAK (P. Foner ed. 1970); H. RAP BROWN, DIE NIGGER DIE! (1969); G. JACKSON, SOLEDAD BROTHER: THE PRISON LETTERS OF GEORGE JACKSON (1970); G. MARINE, THE BLACK PANTHERS (1969); H. NEWTON, TO DIE FOR THE PEOPLE: THE WRITINGS OF HUEY P. NEWTON (1972); B. SEALE, SEIZE THE TIME: THE STORY OF THE BLACK PANTHER PARTY AND HUEY P. NEWTON (1970). The founding platform and program of the Black Panther Party is reprinted in BLACK LIBERATION POLITICS: A READER 380-82 (E. Greer ed. 1971) [hereinafter BLACK LIBERATION POLITICS]. See C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 50-55, 66-71 (describing the nationalist turn within SNCC); A. MEIER & E. RUDWICK, supra note 15, at 431 (describing the nationalist turn within CORE). For general histories of black nationalism in the 1960s, see R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 18-74, 108-239; T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 86-167; H. HAINES, BLACK RADICALS AND THE CIVIL RIGHTS MAINSTREAM: 1954-1970, at 57-76 (1988); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 76-219; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 222-61; Turner, Black Nationalism: The Inevitable Response, BLACK WORLD, Jan. 1971, at 4. The March Against Fear was begun as a solitary march across Mississippi by James Meredith to protest the slaying of Medgar Evers. After Meredith was shot by a would-be assassin, the leaders of SCLC, SNCC, CORE, the NAACP, and the Urban League got together in Memphis to plan to continue the march symbolically on Meredith's behalf. The Urban League and the NAACP eventually refused to participate in opposition to the manner in which the March's manifesto sharply criticized the slow pace of civil rights reform of the federal government. See D. GARROW, supra note 15, at 475-97; V. HARDING, THE OTHER AMERICAN REVOLUTION 185-87 (1980); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 193-221; J. WHITE, supra note 48, at 139-43. The term Black Power first gained publicity when Richard Wright so entitled his autobiographical reflections on Africa. R. WRIGHT, BLACK POWER: A RECORD OF REACTIONS IN A LAND OF PATHOS (1954). It initially was used as a political slogan, without much notoriety, by Representative Adam Clayton Powell in 1966, during Howard University commencement exercises. See H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 207. But it was not until Ricks and Carmichael

49

50 51

52

53

54

55

56

57

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

48

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 began using the slogan during the March Against Fear that it gained mass appeal. The slogan originated as part of the competition between the King/SCLC faction and the SNCC faction of the March's organizers. Tension between the civil rights groups dated back at least to the 1961 Albany campaign, where SNCC organizers attempted to mobilize the black community en masse to resist the racial structure of the city as a whole, and where disagreements arose between SNCC organizers and the SCLC as to the militancy of nonviolent tactics, whether to violate federal court orders against marches, and more generally whether the civil rights campaign should be focused on building community strength or on persuading the federal government to grant civil rights. See C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 56-65, 83-95; A. MORRIS, supra note 15, at 239-50; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 30-38, 130-43. By the 1963 March on Washington, the ideology of the groups had substantially diverged, with the SCLC leadership supporting the passage of the civil rights bill and cooperation with the Kennedy Administration and John Lewis of SNCC prepared to deliver a scathing attack on the government and on the slow pace of race reform, including opposition to the Civil Rights Act as too little, too late. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 20-21; T. BRANCH, supra note 15, at 869-70, 873-74, 878-80; D. GARROW, supra note 15, at 281-83; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 76-83. At the March Against Fear, the rift opened around the question of nonviolence, and, reflecting the beginnings of nationalist sentiment among the SNCC/CORE organizers, around the issue of whether to permit white participation in the March. Symbolically, the positions were represented by competing crowd chants, with the SCLC organizers trying to get the crowd to chant Freedom Now while the SNCC organizers were challenging with Black Power. For descriptions of this context of the march, see C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 209-10; D. GARROW, supra note 15, at 475-97; M. L. KING, WHERE DO WE GO FROM HERE: CHAOS OR COMMUNITY 31-32 (1967); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, 193-221. To be sure, the slogan Black Power did not itself have a necessary nationalist meaning; in fact, a virtual cottage industry was created around attempts to define its meaning, and many of its exponents were clearly integrationist. For examples of the substantial writing devoted to defining and evaluating Black Power, see S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51; E. PEEKS, THE LONG STRUGGLE FOR BLACK POWER (1971); THE RHETORIC OF BLACK POWER (R. Scott & W. Brockriede eds. 1969) [hereinafter RHETORIC]; N. WRIGHT, BLACK POWER AND URBAN UNREST: CREATIVE POSSIBILITIES (1967); THE BLACK POWER REVOLT (F. Barbour ed. 1968); Bennett, Of Time, Space, and Revolution, EBONY, Aug. 1969, at 24, 31-44; Black Power: A Discussion, PARTISAN REV., Spring 1968, at 195 (symposium) [hereinafter Black Power: A Discussion]; Bloice, Black Labor is Black Power, BLACK SCHOLAR, Oct. 1970, at 2; Lasch, The Trouble with Black Power, 10 N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Feb. 29, 1968, at 10; Onwachi, Identity and Black Power, NEGRO DIG., Mar. 1967, at 16; Relyea, Black Power as an Urban Ideology, EDUC. DIG., Feb. 1970, at 35, 46-49; Symposium on Black Power, NEW SOUTH, Summer 1966. For general commentaries on the Black Power controversy, see R. ALLEN, supra note 43; T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 118-31; H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 57-70; V. HARDING, supra note 56, at 177-200; B. MUSE, supra note 15, at 243-44; F. POWLEDGE, BLACK POWER, WHITE RESISTANCE: NOTES ON THE NEW CIVIL WAR (1967). The Black Power Conference called by Adam Clayton Powell and held in Newark in 1967 reflected the broad disagreements among those characterizing themselves as Black Power activists. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 132-61; V. HARDING, supra note 56, at 194-95; Stone, The National Conference on Black Power, in THE BLACK POWER REVOLT, supra, at 189. Further evidence of the elasticity of the slogan is produced by a recent book by Theodore Cross, supra note 16, who uses the concept of Black Power as an organizing idea for a clearly integrationist-oriented, anti-nationalist argument. Nevertheless, it is clear that for most, the Black Power slogan represented the beginning of repudiation of integrationist/civil rights ideology in favor of some form of nationalism. See A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 64 (The introduction of the concept of black power was the beginning of the current spread of nationalist sentiment among Afro-Americans, and signalled the decline of integration as the dominant thrust of the black movement.); T. WAGSTAFF, BLACK POWER: THE RADICAL RESPONSE TO WHITE AMERICA 103 (1969) (The Black Power Movement is a conscious attempt to harness the emotional power of Black Nationalism to a practical program for the elimination of racial oppression in America.); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 169-70, 236-56.

58

For discussions of the mainstream reactions to the slogan Black Power from which these examples are drawn, and from which my analysis proceeds, see R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 66-67; C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 153-243; J. FARMER, supra note 19, at 91-93; Marable, Black Nationalism in the 1970s: Through the Prism of Race and Class, SOCIALIST REV., Mar.-June 1980, at 66-72. For empirical research on white and black reactions to the term Black Power, see Aberbach & Walker, The Meanings of Black Power: A Comparison of White and Black Interpretations of a Political Slogan, 64 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 367, 370 (1970) (interviewed 855 whites and blacks in Detroit asking, What do the words black power mean to you? The largest percentage of whites said that the words meant black rules white, while about 65% of blacks said the words meant nothing or a fair share for black people or racial unity). For discussions of the reactions to Black Power as reverse racism, see Duberman, Black Power

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

49

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 in America, PARTISAN REV., Winter 1968, at 34-48 (ambiguity in the phrase Black Power derives from a failure in clarity or frankness on the part of its advocates; the dangers of black racism in Black Power are real and not the invention of frightened white liberals); Feldman, How the Cry for Black Power Began, 13 DISSENT 472 (1966) (reactions to Black Power include thoughts of racial war, racism in reverse and actual withdrawal of support from the civil rights movement); see also C. FAGER, WHITE REFLECTIONS ON BLACK POWER 41-63, 83-96 (1967); F. POWLEDGE, supra note 57; Scott & Brockreide, The Rhetoric of Black Power: Order and Disorder in the Future, in RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 194, 204.

59 60

Address by Hubert Humphrey, 57th Annual NAACP Convention (July 6, 1966), reprinted in RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 65, 71. Wilkins, Whither Black Power?, 73 CRISIS 353-54 (1966) (excerpts from keynote address delivered at the NAACP 57th Annual Convention, July 5, 1966), reprinted in BLACK PROTEST THOUGHT IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, supra note 19, at 596-98. C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 22. The Black Neo-Segregationists, 74 CRISI 439-40 (1967) (editorial), reprinted in BLACK PROTEST THOUGHT IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, supra note 19, at 598-604. For further examples of writers identifying Black Power as racism, see O. COX, supra note 16, at 210-18, 298-302; Cook, The Tragic Myth of Black Power, NEW SOUTH, Summer 1966, at 58 ([T]he slogan Black Power does have, when words, context, shorn of pretensions, hypocrisy and intellectual dishonesty and program are combined, a generic or core meaning, and that meaning is racist.); Weschler, Killers of the Dream, PROGRESSIVE, Dec. 1966, at 12. For a more complicated association of Black Power with racial domination that locates Black Power proponents on the dominated side of the relationship, see COMMISSION REPORT, supra note 16, at 235 (Black Power advocates . . . function as an accommodation to white racism . . . reminiscent of Booker T. Washington.). Several moderate black leaders, including Roy Wilkins, Whitney Young, Jr., Bayard Rustin, Bishop Carey Gibbs (leader of the AME Church), Dorothy Height (president of the National Council of Negro Women), and Marion Bryant (president of the National Association of Negro Business and Professional Women's Clubs) issued a statement which appeared in an advertisement in the New York Times and black-owned newspapers across the country denouncing any strategies of violence, reprisal or vigilantism and rejecting the way of separatism, either moral or spatial. The statement declared that blacks fighting and dying in Vietnam were more representative of the black community than those blacks who were rioting in the streets. N.Y. Times, Oct. 14, 1966, at 35, col. 3 (advertisement), reprinted in Crisis and Commitment, 73 CRISIS 474 (1966); see also Johnson, Negro Leaders Issue a Statement of Principles Repudiating Black Power Concepts, N.Y. Times, Oct. 14, 1966, at 27, col. 2. Interestingly, Martin Luther King's response was more ambiguous. To the extent the Black Power slogan was associated with a renunciation of the principle of nonviolence or with separatism and withdrawal from the struggle for equality, he was clearly opposed; however, he saw positive aspects to the concept in terms of building race pride and solidarity in political and economic struggles. See M.L. KING, supra note 57, at 23-66. See also D. GARROW, supra note 15, at 475-574; Scott, Black Power Bends Martin Luther King, in RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 166 (describing King's utilization of Black Power imagery in speech to Tenth Anniversary Convention of the SCLC shortly before he was assassinated). For a critique of the Black Power/nationalist turn from the viewpoint of a black socialist who saw the issue as fundamentally strategic, see Rustin, Black Power and Coalition Politics, COMMENTARY, Sept. 1966, at 35. S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 54. Browne, supra note 42 at 7. See supra notes 44 & 46 and infra note 67. This program characterized the early colonization efforts, as well as Garvey's Back to Africa movement and the Black Muslims' program. See supra note 46. See also the Republic of New Africa movement's proposal that the states of Mississippi, Louisiana, Alabama, Georgia, and South Carolina be ceded by the U.S. government for the creation of an independent black nation, along with the payment of $200 billion in reparations. R. BRISBANE, supra note 15, at 183-85; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 125-26; Sherrill, Birth of a (Black) Nation, ESQUIRE, Jan. 1969, at 70, 72.

61 62

63

64 65 66 67

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

50

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

68

Theodore Draper complains that a nationalist ideology is incoherent without geographic separation rooted in sovereignty over land. T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 120-25, 131-47, 168-81. I believe that Draper has an overly formalistic and traditional view of nationhood and sovereignty. All that Draper proves is that the language of nationhood does not precisely match the way that nations were recognized in a particular world order that, at least in the 1960s, was explicitly linked to the African American situation through an analysis centering around the concept of colonialism. See infra text accompanying notes 152-54. See, e.g., R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 1-14; S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 3-32 (discussing the colonial situation in America under which policies are based on subordinating a racial group and maintaining control); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 3-13; R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 13-14, 300-10. The phrase originated with Martin Delany. M. DELANY, supra note 44, at 203. Delany has been called the first major Negro nationalist, see L. BENNETT, BEFORE THE MAYFLOWER: A HISTORY OF THE NEGRO IN AMERICA, 1619-1966, at 137 (1966), but Draper argues that Delany's black nationalism was based on unrequited love on rejection by whites. T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 24. For more inspiring views of Delany, see R. CARLISLE, supra note 43, at 67-84; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 23. [T]he central significance of Black Nationalism is the emergence of Black group-consciousness, self-assertion and cultural identity. Turner, supra note 55, at 8. The idea that African Americans have created a distinct culture that is not reducible to class or Americanism has been a controversial notion in the fields of sociology and anthropology. For example, it was long the dominant view that African Americans have no ethnic culture, but instead the Negro is only an American and nothing else. He has no values and culture to guard and protect. N. GLAZER & D. MOYNIHAN, supra note 21, at 53. For other writers articulating the same idea, see E. FRAZIER, THE NEGRO IN THE UNITED STATES 680-81 (rev. ed. 1957); G. MYRDAL, supra note 16, at 928 (In practically all of its divergencies, American Negro culture is not something independent of general American culture. It is a distorted development, or a pathological condition of American culture.); R. PARK, supra note 16; K. STAMPP, THE PECULIAR INSTITUTION: SLAVERY IN THE ANTI-BELLUM SOUTH vii (1956) (slaves were merely ordinary human beings . . . innately Negroes are, after all, only white men with black skins, nothing more, nothing less). For criticism of this tradition in social science, see R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 124-55; R. Ellison, An American Dilemma: A Review, in SHADOW AND ACT 303-17 (1964); R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 6-9; W. WILSON, supra note 16, at 143; Alkalimat, supra note 18; Ladner, Introduction, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at xxiii. For discussions of the need to analyze a unique African American culture, see L. BENNETT, supra note 16, at 1-43, 293-312; THE BLACK AESTHETIC (A. Gayle ed. 1971); BLACK LITERATURE AND LITERARY THEORY (H. Gates ed. 1984); J. BLACKWELL, THE BLACK COMMUNITY: DIVERSITY AND UNITY (1985); J. HALE-BENSON, BLACK CHILDREN: THEIR ROOTS, CULTURE, AND LEARNING STYLES (1982); C. KEIL, URBAN BLUES (1966); T. KOCHMAN, BLACK AND WHITE STYLES IN CONFLICT (1982); J. LADNER, TOMORROW'S TOMORROW: THE BLACK WOMAN (1971); A. PINKNEY, BLACK AMERICANS (1969); R. STAPLES, supra note 24; Baraka, A Black Value System, BLACK SCHOLAR, Nov. 1969, at 54-60; Foster, Toward a Definition of Black Referents, in BEYOND BLACK AND WHITE (A. Dixon & B. Foster eds. 1971); Jones, The Need for a Cultural Base to CivilRites and Bpower Mooments, in BARBOUR, THE BLACK POWER REVOLT 119 (1968) [hereinafter Jones, The Need for a Cultural Base]. Black nationalist descriptions of the character of African American culture have roughly divided between an emphasis on African roots in the Pan-Africanism tradition, see, e.g., Baraka, supra, and the description of a unique Afro-American culture and community, see, e.g., H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 48-138. See generally AFRO-AMERICAN ANTHROPOLOGY: CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES (N. Whitten & J. Szwed eds. 1970); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 127-50. For a critique of the cultural distinctiveness thesis, see R. Kennedy, supra note 6, at 1778-1818. Turner, supra note 55, at 7-8 (quoting Address by C. Munford, Black National Revolution in America, Utah State University (May 1970)). Liberals associate the phenomenon of nationalism in general with irrationality, danger, and regression. The invocation of organic communities are identified with status-based feudalism and group irrationality; emotional patriotism to country is the mark of backwardness.

69

70

71

72

73

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

51

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

74

Along with C. Munford and James Turner, Harold Cruse's conception of black nationalism exemplifies the historicist perspective that I believe marked the intellectual and theoretical advances made in the black nationalist position in the 1960s. See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 20-44, 544-65; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 48-138, 193-258 (1968); Cruse, The Fire This Time?, N.Y. REV. OF BOOKS, May 8, 1969, at 13-18. S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 54-55. See H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL, supra note 48, at 1-52, 192-202, 244-60; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 51-65. S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 55. Id. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 283. Id. at 234. For further examples of the association of integration with assimilation to white norms, see D. BELL, AND WE ARE NOT SAVED, supra note 6, at 110, discussing R. RIST, THE INVISIBLE CHILDREN: SCHOOL INTEGRATION IN AMERICAN SOCIETY (1978) and stating that, Rist . . . followed . . . a group of young black children bused to an upper-class, mainly white school. The principal's policy was to treat all the kids just alike. This evenhanded policy meantin practicethat the handful of black children from the ghetto were expected to perform and behave no differently than did the white children from comfortable suburbs in this mainly white school where the curriculum, texts, and teaching approaches were designed for the middle-class white kids. As you can imagine, the results of this evenhanded integration were disastrous. See also H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 48-125; H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 7-9, 64-95, 240-52; see, e.g., R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 101; R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 35-36, 251-54, 301 (public schools an important site for the transmission of the white majority's worldview); Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 175-183; Browne, supra note 42; Chrisman, The Formation of a Revolutionary Black Culture, BLACK SCHOLAR, June 1970, at 2 (analyzes integrationism as the co-optation of the black middle class to white culture accomplished through the clash between race and class interests); Ladner, Introduction, supra note 18, at xxiii (blacks have been considered to be a deviation from an ambiguous white middle-class model); Poussaint, The Negro American: His Self-Image and Integration, 58 J. NAT'L MED. A. 419 (1966). See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 64-95; Calmore, Fair Housing, supra note 6 (discussing impact of integrationist housing policy on African American communities). S. CARMICHAEL, STOKELY SPEAKS 39 (1971); see also H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 72 (the trend toward integrationism has favored the eradication of the Negro community as a symbol of segregation); id. at 33-67 (criticizing integrationism in the arts as entailing destruction of African American cultural forms in favor of an already despiritualized and deadened European tradition). See D. BELL, The Chronicle of the Sacrificed Black Schoolchildren, in AND WE ARE NOT SAVED, supra note 6, at 102, 109 (citing amicus curiae brief for the National Educational Association, United States v. Georgia, 445 F.2d 303 (5th Cir. 1971) (No. 30,338) (for empirical data on burden borne by black teachers, administrators and students by school integration)); H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL, supra note 48, at 20-24 (public school integration resulted in loss of traditional black educator class); J. BLACKWELL, supra note 71, at 107-10 (same). See, e.g., Crenshaw, Foreword, supra note 4, at 2-6 (describing typical law school classes as assuming white perspective under the guise of perspectivelessness); Davidson, The Furious Passage of the Black Graduate Student, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at 23 (describing graduate education as based on white norms); Hamilton, An Advocate of Black Power Defines It, in RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 190-91 (discussing ways that black-controlled schools would be reorganized to reflect the culture of the black community); T. Miller, supra note 6 (describing the cultural alienation of black students from predominantly white colleges).

75 76

77 78 79 80

81

82

83

84

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

52

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 For more general discussions of the idea that dominant images of neutrality and objectivity reflect white, European culture, see Jones, The Need for a Cultural Base, supra note 71; Chrisman, supra note 80, at 2-6; M. GORDON, supra note 21, at 9 (the central images of American culture are the expressions of white Anglo-Saxon Protestant ethnic consciousness).

85

For discussions of the racial impact of student classification schemes, see T. CROSS, supra note 16, at 488-95, 668; J. OAKES, KEEPING TRACK: HOW SCHOOLS STRUCTURE INEQUALITY (1985); Kirp, Schools as Sorters: The Constitutional and Policy Implications of Student Classifications, 121 U. PA. L. REV. 705 (1973). See R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 36-38 (poverty has come to replace race as explanation for disparate black performance in schools); Peller, supra note 38, at 74-75 (same). H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 283. See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 288-94 (discussing white liberal faculty opposition to black studies programs); N. LEVINE & R. COHEN, OCEAN HILL-BROWNSVILLE: SCHOOLS IN CRISIS, A CASE HISTORY 39, 56 (1969) (describing liberal opposition to community control movements as implemented by the New York Board of Education). The most well-known movement for community control occurred in the Ocean Hill-Brownsville area of Brooklyn, New York, where the City agreed to the establishment of an experimental school district over which local parents would have authority; when the local committee requested the transfer of several teachers to schools outside their neighborhood, the teachers' union went on strike city-wide, and relations in New Yorkin particular between Jews and African Americansreached high levels of hostility. For an account of the Ocean Hill-Brownsville movement, see Mayer, The Full and Sometimes Very Surprising Story of Ocean Hill, the Teachers' Union and the Teacher Strikes of 1968, N.Y. Times, Feb. 2, 1969, 6 (magazine), at 18; see also H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL, supra note 48 at 246-48; N. LEVINE & R. COHEN, supra note 88; CONFRONTATION AT OCEAN HILL-BROWNSVILLE (M. Berube & M. Gittell eds. 1969); R. BENDINER, THE POLITICS OF SCHOOLS: A CRISIS IN SELFGOVERNMENT (1969); O. COX, supra note 16, at 182-88; Brooks, Tragedy at Ocean Hill, 16 DISSENT 28 (1969); Fein, supra note 19; Maynard, Black Nationalism and Community Schools, in COMMUNITY CONTROL OF SCHOOLS, (H. Levin ed. 1970); McCoy, The Formation of a Community-Controlled School District, in COMMUNITY CONTROL OF SCHOOLS (Levin ed. 1970). The Ocean Hill-Brownsville movement was the best known of several community control of schools movements influenced by the Black Power movement. For accounts of other movements, see also Lauter, The Short, Happy Life of the Adams-Morgan Community School Project, 38 HARV. EDUC. REV. 235 (1968) (detailing the origin of the Adams-Morgan project in Washington, D.C. and the ensuing difficulties inherent in such projects); Epstein, The Politics of School Decentralization, 10 N.Y. REV. BOOKS, June 1968, at 26-32 (describing movements in Washington, D.C. and East Harlem). On the movement for the creation of Afro-American Studies, see R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 215-20; A. PINKNEY, supra note 71, at 177-198; Fischer, Ghetto and Gown: The Birth of Black Studies, 57 CURRENT HIST. 290 (1969); Lythcott, The Case for Black Studies, 29 ANTIOCH REV. 149 (1969); Turner, Black Students and their Changing Perspective, EBONY, Aug. 1969, at 135; see also A. BALLARD, THE EDUCATION OF BLACK FOLK: THE AFRO-AMERICAN STRUGGLE FOR KNOWLEDGE IN WHITE AMERICA (1973); BLACK STUDIES IN THE UNIVERSITY (A. Robinson, C. Foster & D. Ogilvie eds. 1969); BLACK POWER AND STUDENT REBELLION (J. McEvoy & A. Miller ed. 1969); H. EDWARDS, BLACK STUDENTS (1970). The most notorious movement for a Black Studies curriculum occurred at Cornell University in 1968-69, when African American students demanded an autonomous Afro-American Studies Department and separate living quarters. During the course of the movement, there were several confrontations, including the seizure of the student union building during Parents' Weekend, April 1969. After several attempts by white students to evict them, the African American students acquired guns, and when they finally gave up the occupation, they left in military formation, bearing arms, a scene that was plastered on the front page of newspapers across the country. For various descriptions, see A. BLOOM, THE CLOSING OF THE AMERICAN MIND 91-97, 315-18, 347-56 (1987); DIVIDED WE STAND: REFLECTIONS ON THE CRISIS AT CORNELL (C. Strout & D. Grossvogel eds. 1970); T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 151-62; H. EDWARDS, supra, at 158-83; A. PINKNEY, supra note 71, at 182-83; T. SOWELL, BLACK EDUCATION: MYTHS AND TRAGEDIES 112-18; 192-99 (1972); Friedland & Edwards, Confrontation at Cornell, TRANS-ACTION, June 1969, at 29. Fein, supra note 19, at 92. Id. at 94.

86

87 88

89

90 91

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

53

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

92

See R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 267 (The liberal is uncomfortable with the consciousness of color. Again, unlike the conservative, particularly the Southern breed, the liberal does not like to think of himself as white . . . .); Sobran, Plural But Equal: Blacks and Minorities in America's Plural Society (Book Review), NAT'L REV., Sept. 11, 1987, at 64 (For most [whites,] liberal or conservative, race is an embarrassing residual category, something we should have gotten beyond by now.). See R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 260-61; Delgado, The Imperial Scholar, supra note 6. L. BENNETT, supra note 16, at 35-36. See Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 188 (criticizing conventional social science assumption that society evolves to a higher level based on more universalistic rational standards of operation); Davidson, supra note 84, at 27-42; Hare, The Challenge of a Black Scholar, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at 67-78; Forsythe, Radical Sociology and Blacks, in id. at 213 (criticizing mainstream sociology's ideology of objectivity). See also Cruse, Black and White: Outlines of the Next Stage, BLACK WORLD, Jan. 1971, at 19 (emphasizing the centrality of culture as a unifying concept for black studies and arguing that black studies should mean the construction of new interpretative paradigms related to black culture, rather than simply focusing existing scholarly assumptions on black subjects); Cruse, Part 2: Black and White: Outlines of the Next Stage, BLACK WORLD, March 1971, at 4, 13 (criticizing the liberal consensus of mainstream scholarship for reflecting a universalist stance in interpretation). Hare, supra note 95, at 68-69 (citing T. VEBLEN, THE THEORY OF THE LEISURE CLASS (1934)). See Ladner, Tomorrow's Tomorrow: The Black Woman, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at 414, 420-21. Ladner writes that: [T]he relationship between the researcher and his subjects . . . resembles that of the oppressor and the oppressed, because it is the oppressor who defines the problem, the nature of the research, and to some extent, the quality of the interaction between him and his subjects. . . . [White sociologists'] inability to understand the nature and effects of neo-colonialism in the same manner as black people is rooted in the inherent bias of the social sciences. The basic concepts and tools of white Western society are permeated by this partiality to the conceptual framework of the oppressor. . . . Simply put, the slave and his master do not view and respond to the world in the same way. . . . George Washington and George Washington's slaves lived different realities. And if we extend that insight to all the dimensions of white American history we will realize that blacks lived at a different time and a different reality in this country. And the terrifying implications of all this is that there is another time, another reality, another America. Id. (quoting L. BENNETT, supra note 16, at 39). For more general discussions of the links between epistemology and power, see J. HABERMAS, KNOWLEDGE AND HUMAN INTERESTS (J. Shapiro trans. 1971); K. MANNHEIM, IDEOLOGY AND UTOPIA: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE (1936); M. FOUCAULT, Truth and Power, in POWER/KNOWLEDGE (C. Gordon ed. 1980); Gouldner, AntiMinotaur: The Myth of a Value-Free Sociology, 9 SOC. PROBS. 199 (1961). Murray, White Norms, Black Deviation, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at 96. Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 175-81. E. CLEAVER, SOUL ON ICE, supra note 50, at 145-73; see also Pacion, Still Soul on Ice, 15 DISSENT 310, 313-15 (1969) (discussing Cleaver's mind/body and sexual frame for analyzing racial relations); Mailer, in Black Power: A Discussion, supra note 57, at 218 (discussing challenge of black power as a critique of dominant white culture marked by the elevation of the head and the repression of the body); Peller, Reason and the Mob: The Politics of Representation, TIKKUN, July-Aug. 1987, at 28 (arguing that the reason/desire dichotomy is the language of a particular technique of power and subordination). E. CLEAVER, SOUL ON ICE, supra note 50, at 145-73. Id. Hare, supra note 95, at 74. Hare concluded that the black scholar has a different mission than that of the white scholar: The challenge facing the black scholar is to cleanse his mind and the minds of his people of the white colonial attitudes toward scholarship and people as well. This includes the icons of objectivity, amoral knowledge and its methodology, and the total demolition of the antisocial

93 94 95

96 97

98 99 100

101 102 103

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

54

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 attitudes of Ivory-Towerism. Id. at 78. See also Staples, What is Black Sociology? Toward a Sociology of Black Liberation, in THE DEATH OF WHITE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 18, at 163-68. Robert Staples argues that prevalent structuralist-functionalist model of sociological inquiry is oriented toward the assumption of stability in social structure, whereas black sociologists should be oriented toward the transformation of the social order. [I]f white sociology is the science of oppression, Black sociology must be the science of liberation. Id. at 168. For a general exposition of the idea that social position structures perception and experience of the world so that there can be no universal category of knowledge, see G. LUKCS, Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat, in HISTORY AND CLASS CONSCIOUSNESS: STUDIES IN MARXIST DIALECTICS 83 (R. Livingstone trans. 1971) (focusing on economic class).

104 105

See R. STAPLES, supra note 24. See H. CRUSE, PLURAL BUT EQUAL, supra note 48, at 53-58, 280-86, 362-70 (criticizing the conjunction of racial status with gender, immigrant and minority status). For descriptions of the movements for reparations in the late 1960s and 1970s, see BLACK MANIFESTO: RELIGION, RACISM, AND REPARATIONS 1-2 (R. Lecky & H. Wright eds. 1969) (collection of views from the religious community on the reparations controversy); D. BELL, AND WE ARE NOT SAVED, supra note 6, at 123-39 (hypothetical discussion of the broad social changes that serious racial reparations might have effected); R. BRISBANE, supra note 15, at 186-90 (discussing James Forman's Black Manifesto movement for reparations). For a recent work linking race consciousness and a program of reparations, see Matsuda, supra note 3. For analyses of the legal dimensions of black nationalist demands for reparations, see B. BITTKER, THE CASE FOR BLACK REPARATIONS (1973); Hughes, Reparations for Blacks?, 43 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1063 (1968). H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 91. The term was first used in a comprehensive analysis of the situation of African Americans by Cruse, Revolutionary Nationalism and the Afro-American, 2 STUDIES ON THE LEFT 12-13 (1962). See also H. CRUSE, An Afro-American's Cultural Views, in REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 48-67 (first published in PRESENCE AFRICAINE, Dec. 1957-Jan. 1958, at 31); Cruse, Negro Nationalism's New Wave, NEW LEADER, Mar. 19, 1962, at 16. By the mid-1960s, the neocolonial analogy was widely used by black nationalists. See, e.g., Alkalimat, supra note 18, at 183-188; R. ALLEN, BLACK AWAKENING IN CAPITALIST AMERICA: AN ANALYTIC HISTORY 5-17 (1969); J. BLACKWELL, supra note 71, at 12-14; J. BOGGS & G. BOGGS, REVOLUTION AND EVOLUTION IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY (1974); S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 2-56; E. CLEAVER, POST-PRISON WRITINGS AND SPEECHES, supra note 50, at 57-72; H. NEWTON, ESSAYS FROM THE MINISTER OF DEFENSE HUEY NEWTON 2-10 (1968); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 8-13; R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 13-14; W. TABB, THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF THE BLACK GHETTO (1970); The Black Panther Party Platform and Program, in BLACK LIBERATION POLITICS, supra note 54. See also O'Dell, A Special Variety of Colonialism, FREEDOMWAYS, Winter 1967, at 1. Robert Blauner summarizes the analysis of black communities through the colonialist metaphor by focusing on four elements of colonization: (1) the colonized subjects enter the system involuntarily; (2) the subjects' indigenous culture is transformed or destroyed; (3) the subjects are managed or controlled by those outside their own ethnic status; and (4) racism prevails or the group is oppressed psychologically and socially by an outside group that conceives of itself as superior. Black communities are an example of the colonization process in that they are controlled politically, economically, and administratively from the outside, distinguishing them from the voluntary ethnic business and social communities of the Poles, Jews, Italians and Irish. R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 83-89. H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 76. E. CLEAVER, POST-PRISON WRITINGS AND SPEECHES, supra note 50, at 57-72. See Chrisman, supra note 80; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43. Nationalists speaking in terms of colonialism tended to cite F. FANON, STUDIES IN A DYING COLONIALISM (1965); F. FANON, THE WRETCHED OF THE EARTH (C. Farrington, trans. 1965); F. FANON, BLACK SKIN, WHITE MASKS (C. Markmann trans. 1967); A. MEMMI, THE COLONIZER AND THE COLONIZED (H. Greenfeld, trans. 1967). Stokely Carmichael pointed to the colonialist relationship as an explanation of the apparent similarity between the material conditions of African Americans in diverse cities:

106

107 108

109 110 111

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

55

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 The American city, in essence, is going to be populated by the peoples of the Third World, while the white middle classes will flee to the suburbs. Now the black people do not control, nor do we own, the resourceswe do not control the land, the houses or the stores. These are all owned by whites who live outside the community. These are very real colonies, in the sense that they are capital and cheap labor exploited by those who live outside the cities. . . . It does not seem that the men who control the power and resources of the United States ever sat down and designed those black enclaves, and formally articulated the terms of their dependent and colonial status. . . . Indeed, if the ghettos had been formally and deliberately planned instead of growing spontaneously and inevitably from the racist functionings of the various institutions that combine to make the society, it would be somehow less frighteningone could understand their similarity as being artificially and consciously imposed, rather than the result of identical patterns of white racism which repeat themselves in cities as far apart as Boston and Watts . . . . S. CARMICHAEL, supra note 82, at 86-87.

112

As Cruse saw it, the black middle class was frightened of the masses, dependent on the white power structure, and ambivalent about their own identity; consequently, the installation of the black bourgeoisie as administrators of the black community did not necessarily serve the community's interests: The tragedy of the black bourgeoisie in America is not that it simply sells out, since all bourgeois classes are prone to compromise their sovereignty during a crisis. It is rather that no class the world over sells out so cheaply as the American black bourgeoisie, whose nation, the richest in the world, wastes billion overseas buying the fickle friendship of unworthy allies. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 91. See also R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 205. Robert Staples notes the structurally different interests of the black middle class and predicts, [T]he emergence of a class of Black petty bourgeoisie who will undertake the exploitation of the Black masses that is now done directly by the White colonial power structure. Hence, we shall witness large numbers of Blacks being elected to public office, programs created to develop a Black capitalist class, and Black functionaries replacing Whites in the role of colonial mediating positions such as teachers, social workers, policemen, etc. Id. (citing Cleaver, The Crisis of the Black Bourgeoisie, BLACK SCHOLAR, Jan. 1973, at 2-11). For descriptions of this dimension of the civil rights movement, see supra note 15. Perhaps the best known testament to this is Martin Luther King's I have a dream speech: I have a dream that one day on the red hills of Georgia, sons of former slaves and sons of former slave owners will be able to sit down together at the table of brotherhood . . . . I have a dream my four little children will one day live in a nation where they will not be judged by the color of their skin but by the content of their character. M. L. King, I Have a Dream, reprinted in A TESTAMENT OF HOPE, supra note 37, at 219. This dimension of King's work might help explain why, for example, Thurgood Marshall (now Justice Marshall) initially opposed mass organizing to achieve school integration in favor of litigation. See T. BRANCH, supra note 15, at 190 (describing Marshall's hostility to the idea of utilizing tactics developed in the Montgomery Bus Boycott to achieve school integration). For a more general discussion about the cautionary attitude of many black leaders towards direct action protest, see L. LOMAX, THE NEGRO REVOLT 167-68, 209 (1962); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 30-44. The difference between the movement that King led and the position represented by Marshall mirrors the contrast that I have drawn between nationalism and integrationism more generally. In the legalist conception, racial justice was to be achieved, in a sense, through reason, by mastering the elite discourse of the white power structure in order to integrate that power structure. In King's direct action conception, racial justice was infused with the particular cadences of African American spiritualism. The roots of the civil rights movement in the black church symbolized the fundamental difference between integrationism as it became institutionalized in American discourse through the imagery of a secular reason and the vision of integration articulated by King. See generally A. MORRIS, supra note 15. For most white integrationists, and for many black ones as well, the connection between the civil rights movement and black churches was a source of background dissonance because it clashed with their comprehension of religion as representing irrationality and backwardness. Secular liberals soon came up with mediations for this incongruity. They attempted to translate the Christian character of King's discourse into a secular ethics, and to explain the prevalence of ministers among black civil rights leaders and central role of the black church in the movement as merely a functional result of the lack of other organized black institutions. See B. DOYLE, THE ETIQUETTE OF RACE RELATIONS IN THE SOUTH: A STUDY IN SOCIAL CONTROL (1937) (describing the way that the social protocol developed during slavery continued during segregation); Boyle, Inside a Segregationist,

113 114

115

116

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

56

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 in WHITE ON BLACK: THE VIEWS OF TWENTY-TWO WHITE AMERICANS ON THE NEGRO 48 (E. Thompson & H. Nipson eds. 1963) (Good Negroes and Bad Negroes distinguished by former's good humor, cheerfulness, contentment, and gratitude; the latter were conceived as dangerous, and sub-human); Killian, White Southerners, in THROUGH DIFFERENT EYES: BLACK AND WHITE PERSPECTIVES ON AMERICAN RACE RELATIONS 89, 96-101 (P. Rose, S. Rothman & W. Wilson eds. 1973) (describing the Southern image of the courteous, patient domestics . . . so willing, so loving and so happy. . . . The worst indignity inflicted on black Southerners was that they were forced to act as accomplices in preserving the indifference of their oppressors.); Quinn, The Transmission of Racial Attitudes Among White Southerners, 33 SOC. FORCES 41 (1954) (discussing the subtle and pervasive way that the social protocol of race relations was transmitted among whites so that issues of race never reached the level of conscious choice or decision). See also T. SHIBUTANI & K. KWAN, supra note 23, at 318-21 (describing symbolic social rituals signifying hierarchies between blacks and whites in Southern society); C. HERNTON, SEX AND RACISM IN AMERICA 127-29 (1965) (describing white sexual exploitation of black women and taboos on contact between black men and white women). Cf. Sheatsley, White Attitudes Toward the Negro, in THE NEGRO AMERICAN 303, 317 (T. Parsons & K. Clark eds. 1966) (concluding that survey data of the civil rights movement demonstrates that white attitudes have changed to recognize integration is correct).

117

See H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 29-41 (describing King-led direct action integrationism as a radical and disruptive force in the context of the late 1950s and early 1960s); V. HARDING, supra note 56, at 194-95 (describing King's view of protest as not counting on government goodwill but serv[ing] instead to compel unwilling authporities [sic] to yield to the mandates of justice); A. MORRIS, supra note 15, at 37-119 (describing the direct action activities of the SCLC as confrontational as compared with the legalistic strategy of the NAACP); RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 166-77 (describing King as a black power proponent before his death); Colaiaco, supra note 15, at 16-28 (emphasizing disruptive quality of direct action tactics despite their nonviolence); Killian, supra note 116, at 102 (describing white Southern sense of a radical disruption of social order in the Montgomery bus boycott); id. at 69-75, 106-11 (nonviolent direct action was not designed for test cases, but was a strategy to coerce negotiation, a strategy of power, not persuasion. . . . While the apostles of nonviolence have spoken a language of love and reconciliation, their actions have moved steadily in the direction of a naked display of power.); M. L. KING, The Burning Truth in the South, in A TESTAMENT OF HOPE, supra note 37, at 97 (relating nonviolent tactic to the necessity of creating discord to alter established community patterns); see also W. WILSON, supra note 16, at 131, 137 ([T]he technique of nonviolence was in reality an aggressive manifestation of pressure.). In this way, the transformation in liberal discourse from a belief in colorblindness in the 1960s, see R. BLAUNER, supra note 16, at 267, to a commitment to diversity and pluralism in the 1970s and 80s can be seen as a partial accommodation to the nationalist position. See, e.g., D. Kennedy, Radical Intellectuals in American Culture and Politics, or My Talk at the Gramsci Institute, RETHINKING MARXISM, Fall 1988, at 121 (describing such a creole culture as a utopian possibility immanent in American life) For Duncan Kennedy's description of a liberating form of cultural pluralism see D. Kennedy, A Cultural Pluralist Case for Affirmative Action in Legal Academia, 1990 DUKE L.J. 705. See H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 48-49. For the analogous controversy in American feminism, see the discussion between Catherine MacKinnon, Carol Gilligan, Ellen Du Bois, and Carrie J. Menkel-Meadow, Feminist Discourse: Moral Values and the LawA Conversation, 34 BUFFALO L. REV. 11, 73-75 (1985). See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 333-34. That is, the intensity about barring white participation in SNCC, see C. CARSON, supra note 15, or the general hate whitey rhetoric of some nationalists, might have reflected the attempt to purify the black community from white influences. Harold Cruse and Eldridge Cleaver argued that such a posture reflected the cultural insecurity of middle class black nationalists who had formerly been committed to integrationism. See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 363-65; T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 110. See supra note 47. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 246-50; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 93-97.

118

119

120

121 122

123 124

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

57

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

125 126 127

See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 212-38; T. CROSS, supra note 16. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 230. Stokely Carmichael described Black Power as entailing group solidarity [in order to] operate from a bargaining position of strength in a pluralist society, S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 44. This provided the basis for Robert Allen's critique that Stokely Carmichael's Black Power amounted to reformism. R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 246-53. According to Judge Robert Carter, this is what the NAACP lawyers thought was being accomplished through the litigation strategy in Brown v. Board of Education. Carter, A Reassessment of Brown v. Board, in SHADES OF BROWN: NEW PERSPECTIVES ON SCHOOL DESEGREGATION 21 (D. Bell ed. 1980). The plausibility of the range of cognizable arguments about racial reform being limited to the basic question of intent or impact, the rhetorical ground for the controversy over affirmative action, and the common sense of understanding calls for Black Power as reverse racism, are connected together around the unifying cultural commitment to make race consciousness the very definition of racial oppression, and thereby to relegate black nationalism to an area outside the realm of serious possibility. For a description of the demise of black nationalism as an organized community presence, see Poinsett, Where are the Revolutionaries?, EBONY, Feb. 1976, at 84; Marable, supra note 58, at 50-51, 57-108 (1980). On this view of the dialectic character of ideologies as discourses of power, see M. FOUCAULT, supra note 97. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 564. Not surprisingly, there is a historiographic controversy about this point that correlates with the position of the historian on the integration/nationalism issue. Integrationistoriented commentators tend to see nationalism as a discontinuous tradition in African American history, arising only as a movement of despair and frustration when hopes for civic equality and integration have been raised and then frustrated. See, e.g., Meier & Rudwick, Introduction, in BLACK NATIONALISM IN AMERICA, supra note 43, at liii-lvi (arguing that black nationalism is simply a form of ethnic solidarity akin to that of American Jews, and a response to worsening social conditions). For other writers contending that black nationalism reflects disappointment with the pace of integration, see J. BLACKWELL, supra note 71, at 287 (describing blacks' efforts during Vietnam period to make the military more responsive to their needs, i.e., black literature at the post exchanges, rakes for Afro hair and barbers who could style black people's hair); O. COX, supra note 16, at 226-41; T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 180; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 223; W. WILSON, supra note 16, at 136, 139; COMMISSION REPORT, supra note 16, at 206-19. On the other hand, nationalist-oriented commentators tend to see the nationalist tradition as continuous and roughly independent of the opportunity for integration. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 75-98 ([N]ationalism, and overt separatism, are ever-present undercurrents in the collective black psyche which . . . in times of crisis, rise to the surface to become major themes; most whites do not notice this ever-present belief because they communicate only with middle-class, college-educated African Americans, who in most historical periods are the least likely to be nationalist in orientation); BLACK NATIONALISM IN AMERICA, supra note 43, at lvi-lx (John Braceydissenting from the views of his fellow editorsargues that black nationalism is an ideol ogy that has been fairly continuous among blacks throughout American history and has never been regarded as an extremist ideology among American blacks); A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 76-219; Turner, supra note 55, at 7-8. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 4-10. See supra note 45. For descriptions of Du Bois' opposition to Washington, and his influence on the Niagara Movement and its successor, the NAACP, see M. MARABLE, supra note 48, at 46-98; J. WHITE, supra note 48, at 44-57. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 100-01. A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at 62. For the view that the nationalist/integrationist split has traditionally had a class dimension in the black community, see R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 75-98; L. BENNETT, supra note 16, at 57-65; H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 202-84; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 165-70.

128

129

130 131

132 133 134

135 136

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

58

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758

137 138

See W.E.B. DU BOIS, THE SOULS OF BLACK FOLK 41-59 (1903). See Du Bois, A Negro Nation within the Nation, CURRENT HIST., June 1935, at 265-70; 3 WRITINGS BY W.E.B. DU BOIS IN PERIODICALS EDITED BY OTHERS 1-6 (H. Aptheker ed. 1982). See M. GORDON, supra note 21, at 113. For discussion of the centrality of the idea of accommodationism in black politics, see Chrisman, supra note 80; G. MYRDAL, supra note 16, at 721-27; Huggins, Afro-Americans, in ETHNIC LEADERSHIP IN AMERICA 93-98 (J. Higham ed. 1978); E. LADD, NEGRO POLITICAL LEADERSHIP IN THE SOUTH (1966). An early colonization effort was undertaken by Paul Cuffe in 1815, who arranged for a small expedition of black colonists to Africa, which inspired the creation of the American Colonization Society, a white-controlled group whose purpose was to relocate free blacks to Africa because they were a dangerous and useless part of the community. 1 A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE NEGRO PEOPLE IN THE UNITED STATES 71 (H. Aptheker ed. 1951). See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 76-77. For a general description of white deportationists, and an analysis of the ideological failure of colonization focused on its associations with racist whites, see R. CARLISLE, supra note 43, at 10-12, 24-30. In criticizing Washington's famous Atlanta Compromise, where Washington advocated that [i]n all things purely social we can be as separate as the five fingers, and yet one as the hand in all things essential to mutual progress, W.E.B. DU BOIS, supra note 137, at 42, Du Bois concluded that Mr. Washington represents in Negro thought the old attitude of adjustment and submission . . . [which] practically accepts the alleged inferiority of the Negro races. Id. at 50. See generally id. at 41-59. See T. MARTIN, supra note 46, at 297-99 (describing Du Bois' attempt to link Garvey with the accommodationism of Washington). While this was Du Bois' interpretation of Garveyism, Garvey painted the opposite picture. See J. WHITE, supra note 48, at 61, 89-95; T. MARTIN, supra note 46, at 297-99; H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 86 (The rise of Garvey nationalism meant that the NAACP became the accommodationists, and the nationalists became the militants.). See, e.g., J. JOHNSON, NEGRO AMERICANS, WHAT NOW? 35-40 (1934) ( [T]he outcome of voluntary isolation would be a permanent secondary status . . . I do not believe we should ever be willing to pay such a price for security and peace.); Bunche, A Critical Analysis of the Tactics and Programs of Minority Groups, 4 J. NEGRO EDUC. 308, 312 (1935) (Because of the seeming hopelessness of the fight to win equal rights for many minority racial groups, some of the leadership of such groups has often espoused a defeatist philosophy, which takes the form of racial separatism.); Farmer, We Cannot Destroy Segregation with a Weapon of Segregation, EQUALITY, Nov. 1944, at 2 (editorial) (Garveyism [and other nationalisms] . . . are not liberating the Negro people; they are further enslaving their minds under the yoke of caste.); White, Segregation: A Symposium, 41 CRISIS 80, 81 (1934) (responding to Du Bois' calls for voluntary self-segregation, White, then executive secretary of the NAACP, argued that no Negro who respects himself and his race can accept these segregated systems without at least some inward protest.); R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 301 ([Garveyism] was an escapist philosophy); id. at 302 (Muslims did not engage in political action and insulated themselves from both the culture and everyday life of the Black community.) (footnote omitted); R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 31 (direct actionists advised by elders to be cautious). See H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 30-32, 44, 75; see also supra text accompanying note 117. See supra text accompanying note 117. See R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 30-38, 132-43, 204-70. The confluence of these two issuesmilitancy versus accommodation and nationalism versus integrationhelps explain what otherwise appears to be confusion on the part of the 1960s nationalists about their historical antecedents and heroes. Harold Cruse criticizes 1960s nationalists for their lack of historical comprehension of the nationalist tradition, since they looked to Robert Williams and Frederick Douglass as heroes. Williams was the NAACP Chapter head in Monroe, North Carolina who advocated and began to act upon the use of violence to achieve civil rights. See R. WILLIAMS, NEGROES WITH GUNS 39 (1962). For a description of Williams' role in Monroe, his subsequent expulsion from the NAACP, his exile to Cuba and the People's Republic of China,

139 140

141

142

143

144

145 146 147 148

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

59

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 see Poinsett, supra note 129. As Cruse points out, while Williams and Douglass employed militant rhetoric and activism, both were committed to the ideology of integrationism. Similarly, Cruse argues that the ideological confusion of 1960s nationalists was confirmed by their adoption of Marcus Garvey as a hero but their failure to recognize Booker T. Washington as in many ways the founder of black nationalism among African Americans, instead making Booker T.-ism a synonym for assimilationism. See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 347-401, 544-65. But whatever merit there might be to Cruse's criticism in general, it leaves out of the analysis the fact that the ability of 1960s nationalists to combine black nationalism with a confrontationalists commitment was an independently significant historical development. They valorized both nationalist and militant integrationist figures because they sought to link nationalism with militancy.

149 150

See infra note 150. The community-organizing militancy of the direct action factions of the civil rights movement in the 1950s and early 1960s, and the later critique of nonviolence as a means to achieve integration, can be seen to have reflected a submerged form of nationalist ideology itself, to be made explicit by the mid-1960s when CORE and SNCC adopted formal nationalist programs and when, in 1967, Rap Brown, Stokely Carmichael, and James Foreman joined the Black Panthers. See C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 196-207; H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 57-75; A. MEIER & E. RUDICK, supra note 15, at 17-18. For an analysis of the early years of the civil rights movement centered on the ideological and cultural differences between legalist and direct action ideologies, see A. MORRIS, supra note 15; H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 29-46; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 30-38; Killian, supra note 116, at 69-75. See also supra note 15 (describing differences between direct action and legalist approaches to civil rights reform). See supra text accompanying note 108. It is ironic that Harold Cruse misses the changed meaning of nationalism symbolized by the colonialism analysis, since he was one of the first to set it forth in a comprehensive way. See supra note 108. See supra note 46. See R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 291-93; Turner, supra note 55, at 7-8; RHETORIC, supra note 57, at 4-5. See MALCOLM X, THE AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF MALCOLM X, supra note 49, at 294. According to Malcolm X, it was precisely the Muslim policy of not engaging in conflict with the white power structure that led to his frustration and eventual break with the Nation of Islam: [O]ur Nation of Islam could be an even greater force in the American black man's overall struggleif we engaged in more action. [W]e should have amended or relaxed our general non-engagement policy. I felt that, whenever black people committed themselves, in the Little Rocks and Birminghams . . . militantly disciplined Muslims should be there also. Id. Robert Staples explores the simultaneous oppositional and nationalist meaning of Black Power: Black power ideology . . . evolved into different nationalist expressions, but it gave rise to the modern-day Black Nationalist movement . . . . Millions of Black people were inspired by the concept that they should develop the political power to take control over their political, economic and social fortunes. This new Black consciousness was seen in the ghetto rebellions of the 1960s. It was also expressed in the increased support among Afro-Americans for the liberation struggles in the colonial world, in the protests by Black high school and college students, and in the development of militancy and organization by Black workers and professionals. It probably had more influence on Black cultural change than any other social movement. In the short period of five years it had revolutionized Black cultural lifestyles. It most eloquently symbolizes the idea whose time has arrived. R. STAPLES, supra note 24, at 290-92. See also Turner, supra note 55, at 7-8 (nationalism usually politically conservative until the 1960s). But see Gershman, Black Nationalism and Conservative Politics, 17 DISSENT 10, 11 (1970) (arguing black nationalism is a conservative movement); K. CLARK, supra note 31, at 612 (black power is accommodationism); COMMISSION REPORT, supra note 16, at 235 (same). See H. EDWARDS, supra note 89 (noting that the radicalization of black students during the 1960s brought collaboration between black bourgeoisie and poorer classes). Manning Marable states that,

151

152

153 154 155

156

157

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

60

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 [b]y the late months of 1966 . . . the young nationalists had succeeded in creating a broadbased wave of support, touching virtually every segment of the black population. . . . By the end of the decade the Old Guard seemed to be fighting a losing battle . . . . It is difficult to find an appropriate parallel to any previous stage of black American struggle. . . . By 1971, the Old Guard leadership appeared to be thoroughly discredited. Marable, supra note 58, at 20-21.

158

Most (integrationist) commentators have interpreted black nationalism simply as an ideology of frustration when integration does not seem to work. See supra note 131. But at least in the 20th century, such a diagnosis at most accounts for the cultural position of a segment of the black middle class. See H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 175-248; J. FARMER, supra note 19, at 92-93; R. WEISBROT, supra note 15, at 169-70; Kilson, The New Black Intellectuals, 16 DISSENT 304 (1969). Among poorer African Americans, a nationalist political and cultural stance has had a more continuous presence. R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 75-98. See COMMISSION REPORT, supra note 16, at 205-38 (interpreting the rise of Black Power ideology and the increased militancy of ghetto youth as a reflection of frustration with the slow pace of civil rights reform). See H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 55-76. See id. at 46-74; Marable, supra note 58, at 20-21; A. PINKNEY, supra note 43, at ix (in 1970, there seemed to be little doubt that black nationalism was the dominant ethos of the black movement). See H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 35-36 (noting the rapid shift in SNCC ideology), 46-76 (chronology of the momentum towards Black Power and black separatism in the late 1960s, and how sense of radicalism shifted from direct action integrationism in the late 1950s and early 1960s to black nationalism in the mid- to late-1960s). For a description of the sense within the SCLC and on the part of King himself that he was losing support, see D. GARROW, supra note 15, at 431-547. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 364. For example, plans by various splinter groups to engage the police in urban guerrilla war, to assassinate political figures, etc. See Poinsett, supra note 129. See Cruse, The Fire This Time?, supra note 74 (criticizing simplistic social theories of 1960s nationalists); see also H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 347-401 (criticizing as unrealistic and romanticizing the 1960s nationalists' invocation of images of armed revolution). See W. WILSON, THE DECLINING SIGNIFICANCE OF RACE: BLACKS AND CHANGING AMERICAN INSTITUTIONS 142-43 (1978). The only significant nondeportationist white support for nationalism as a way to comprehend race relations prior to the 1960s was the formal position of the American Communist Party. From 1928 to 1959, the Communist Party argued that the black belt in the South should be recognized as a sovereign entity of African Americans. In 1959, the Communists changed their position to a call for immediate integration and an end to racial discrimination, and even during the period in which Communists formally supported black nationalism, their support and understanding were deduced from theoretical postulates of Marxism-Leninism, rather than from any engagement with the black nationalist tradition in the United States. See W. FOSTER, THE NEGRO PEOPLE IN AMERICAN HISTORY 461 (1954) (including the text of the 1928 resolution). For a full analysis of the Communist Party's position on black nationalism, see H. CRUSE, REBELLION OR REVOLUTION?, supra note 43, at 78-94; for more general analysis of the relation of Marxists to black nationalism, see id. at 139-55 (analyzing Trotskyist racial ideology); id. at 193-258 (analyzing limitations of Marxist analysis more generally). In any event, the Communists spent their organizing energies on antidiscrimination efforts and attempts to establish interracial trade union and farm worker organizations. See R. ALLEN, supra note 43, at 85-90. In the Left more generally, the tendency was to see the race issue as subordinate to the more fundamental analytic of economic class; accordingly, the reigning image of racial liberation for most American leftists was the creation of an integrated working class movement that would overthrow capitalism and thereby

159

160 161

162

163

164 165

166

167

168

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

61

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 remove the cause of exploitation of all workers, whether black or white. The sorry record of organized labor on race issues is a source of great embarrassment for the traditional Left. To be sure, there are many historic examples of courageous leftist support for civil rights, and there have been many occasions in the history of American race relations when white leftists were the only dependable allies of African Americans; the point here is that, in the Left tradition, integrationism was integrated into the class analysis under the general assumption that the structure of racial domination was subsidiary to and comprehended by the structure of capitalist domination.

169 170

C. SILBERMAN, supra note 31, at 212. See S. CARMICHAEL & C. HAMILTON, supra note 51, at 58-84; C. CARSON, supra note 15, at 229-43; H. HAINES, supra note 55, at 57-70. As Stokely Carmichael stated the nationalist position on white participation, How can you, as the youth in this country, move to start carrying those things out? Move into the white community. We have developed a movement in the black community. The white activist has miserably failed to develop the movement inside of his community. Will white people have the courage to go into white communities and start organizing them? That's the question for the white activist. S. CARMICHAEL, supra note 82, at 57. This conflict helps account for what seems in retrospect the particular and often seemingly gratuitous extremism of middle class black nationalists during the 1960s. It is possible that the extreme militancy that many others experienced as posturing played a defensive role in helping to repress the actual cultural ambiguity that has historically marked the black middle class self-identity. See supra note 111. See also F. POWLEDGE, supra note 57; C. FAGER, supra note 58, at 89-96. While many black nationalist groups and individuals adopted the hate whitey rhetoric that had historically characterized the Nation of Islam ideology, other black nationalists analyzed the dynamic as part of a pathology rooted in the historic commitment to interracialism on the part of the black middle class. According to Eldridge Cleaver, who on behalf of the Black Panthers actively advocated and organized coalitions with radical whites, the expulsion of whites from SNCC resulted from a paranoid fear of white domination rooted in the fact that SNCC nationalists had to wrest control over SNCC from whites, a situation the Panthers never faced. T. DRAPER, supra note 42, at 110. According to Cruse, hatred of whites on the part of new nationalists resulted from the particular ideology of interracialism that had become inculcated into the Negro's mind. Even before the average Negro attempts to undertake any action himself, he assumes, almost involuntarily, that he must not, cannot, dare not exclude whites, because he cannot succeed without them. He has been so conditioned that he cannot separate personal and individual associations with individual whites . . . from that interior business that is the specific concern of his group's existence. . . . But with LeRoi Jones and his young Afro-American nationalists, anti-interracialism was equated not only with anti-whiteness, but with hatred of whiteness. In other words, Negroes had become so deeply mired in an institutionalized form of political interracialism that they could not break with it unless sufficient hatred were mustered to avoid the necessity of apologizing to whites for excluding them. That this was a paranoia-producing rationalization was not understood. If Negroes were actually thinking and functioning on a mature political level, then the exclusion of whitesorganizationally and politicallyshould be based not on hatred but on strategy. It would be much like the tradition that no one outside one's immediate family is ever admitted into a discussion of intimate family problems. It is, therefore, an unfortunate development in Negro life that political interracialism has become so doctrinaire that certain nationalistic Negroes have been forced to resort to race hate in order to block out the negative effect of interracialism on ethnic consciousness. H. CRUSE, THE CRISIS OF THE NEGRO INTELLECTUAL, supra note 19, at 363-65. T. WOLFE, RADICAL CHIC & MAU-MAUING THE FLAK CATCHERS (1970). Of course, this is not the whole story of white radical response to nationalism. Many white activists took seriously the black nationalist analysis that suggested the need for black leadership and mass participation in the black liberation struggle, and that pointed to the reform of the white community as the best role for whites to play. The mass struggle against the Vietnam War soon came to pervade virtually all aspects of politics within the white community, and many such activists were quickly absorbed in antiwar issues. Others went to poor white communities, such as Appalachia, where they tended more quickly to experience a sense of being outsiders. See C. FAGER, supra note 58, at 89-91. This dynamic of white cultural identification also manifested itself in small, everyday ways. At the micro-level of social intercourse, the dynamic appeared in the cultural politics of interracial relations. One example was the familiar phenomenon of whites beginning to talk black, using what they conceived of as black vernacular and slang when in the presence of blacks, or adopting black musical

171

172 173

174

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

62

Brooks, Hannah 1/10/2014 For Educational Use Only

RACE CONSCIOUSNESS, 1990 Duke L.J. 758 tastes. The flip side of this cultural phenomenon, reflecting the same discomfort with one's own culture, is the sense of awkwardness that whites sometimes experience in interracial contexts concerning any aspect of their lifestyle that might reflect whitenessthe sense that indications of white culture are signs of bias, leading to the aspiration for a culture of neutrality in interracial settings and a corresponding compulsion to integrate social and institutional arenas to demonstrate their aracial character.

175

347 U.S. 483 (1954).

1990 DUKELJ 758


End of Document 2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

2014 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works.

63

You might also like