A priori knowledge is knowledge that is independent of experience, such as logical and mathematical truths. It can be known just through reason alone without needing to observe the world. A posteriori knowledge is dependent on experience, such as facts learned through the senses. The document discusses the history of these terms and their relationship to other philosophical concepts like analytic vs synthetic propositions and necessary vs contingent truths. It provides examples to illustrate a priori and a posteriori knowledge and explores how philosophers like Kant and Kripke have analyzed and distinguished these epistemological concepts.
A priori knowledge is knowledge that is independent of experience, such as logical and mathematical truths. It can be known just through reason alone without needing to observe the world. A posteriori knowledge is dependent on experience, such as facts learned through the senses. The document discusses the history of these terms and their relationship to other philosophical concepts like analytic vs synthetic propositions and necessary vs contingent truths. It provides examples to illustrate a priori and a posteriori knowledge and explores how philosophers like Kant and Kripke have analyzed and distinguished these epistemological concepts.
A priori knowledge is knowledge that is independent of experience, such as logical and mathematical truths. It can be known just through reason alone without needing to observe the world. A posteriori knowledge is dependent on experience, such as facts learned through the senses. The document discusses the history of these terms and their relationship to other philosophical concepts like analytic vs synthetic propositions and necessary vs contingent truths. It provides examples to illustrate a priori and a posteriori knowledge and explores how philosophers like Kant and Kripke have analyzed and distinguished these epistemological concepts.
A priori knowledge is knowledge that is independent of experience, such as logical and mathematical truths. It can be known just through reason alone without needing to observe the world. A posteriori knowledge is dependent on experience, such as facts learned through the senses. The document discusses the history of these terms and their relationship to other philosophical concepts like analytic vs synthetic propositions and necessary vs contingent truths. It provides examples to illustrate a priori and a posteriori knowledge and explores how philosophers like Kant and Kripke have analyzed and distinguished these epistemological concepts.
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4
A priori and a posteriori
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
For other uses, see a priori (disambiguation) and a posteriori (disambiguation). The terms a priori ("from the earlier") and a posteriori ("from the later") are used inphilosophy (epistemology) to distinguish two types of knowledge, justification, orargument: A priori knowledge or justification is independent of experience (for example "All bachelors are unmarried"). Galen Strawson has stated that an a priori argument is one in which "you can see that it is true just lying on your couch. You don't have to get up off your couch and go outside and examine the way things are in the physical world. You don't have to do any science." [1] "Knowledge" that is independent of confirmation by experience may not be true. The acceptance of a logical proposition that is not confirmed by experience can lead to the use of logic to give an illusion of truth to things that have no basis in reality whatsoever. Bertrand Russell's empirical version of the correspondence theory of truth, addresses this problem. Logical propositions must be perceivable to be valid before using them to derive "truth". The whole system must correspond to reality. And this correspondence needs to be confirmable. A posteriori knowledge or justification is dependent on experience or empirical evidence (for example "Some bachelors I have met are very happy"). There are many points of view on these two types of knowledge, and their relationship is one of the oldest problems in modern philosophy. The terms a priori and a posteriori are primarily used as adjectives to modify thenoun "knowledge" (for example, "a priori knowledge"). However, "a priori" is sometimes used to modify other nouns, such as "truth". Philosophers also may use "apriority" and "aprioricity" as nouns to refer (approximately) to the quality of being "a priori". [2][not in citation given]
Although definitions and use of the terms have varied in the history of philosophy, they have consistently labelled two separate epistemological notions. See also the related distinctions: deductive/inductive, analytic/synthetic, necessary/contingent. Contents [hide] 1 Examples 2 Analyticity and necessity o 2.1 Relation to the analytic-synthetic o 2.2 Relation to the necessary/contingent 3 History o 3.1 Early uses o 3.2 Immanuel Kant o 3.3 Johann Fichte 4 See also 5 Notes 6 Footnotes 7 References 8 Further reading 9 External links Examples[edit] The intuitive distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge (or justification) is best seen in examples.
A priori Consider the proposition, "If George V reigned for at least four days, then he reigned for more than three days." This is something that one knows a priori, because it expresses a statement that one can derive by reason alone. One doesn't actually "know" what is derived by reason alone. "A priori" knowledge is not a tautology. It is an hypothesis, yet to be confirmed. A posteriori Compare this with the proposition expressed by the sentence, "George V reigned from 1910 to 1936." This is something that (if true) one must come to know a posteriori, because it expresses an empirical fact unknowable by reason alone. Analyticity and necessity[edit] Relation to the analytic-synthetic[edit] For more details on this topic, see Analytic-synthetic distinction. Several philosophers reacting to Kant sought to explain a priori knowledge without appealing to, as Paul Boghossian (MD) explains, "a special faculty ... that has never been described in satisfactory terms." [3] One theory, popular among the logical positivists of the early 20th century, is what Boghossian calls the "analytic explanation of the a priori." [3] The distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions was first introduced by Kant. While Kant's original distinction was primarily drawn in terms of conceptual containment, the contemporary version of the distinction primarily involves, as the American philosopher W. V. O. Quine put it, the notions of "true by virtue of meanings and independently of fact." [4] Analytic propositions are thought to be true in virtue of their meaning alone, while a priori synthetic propositions are thought to be true in virtue of their meaning and certain facts about the world. According to the analytic explanation of the a priori, all a priori knowledge is analytic; so a priori knowledge need not require a special faculty of pure intuition, since it can be accounted for simply by one's ability to understand the meaning of the proposition in question. In short, proponents of this explanation claimed to have reduced a dubious metaphysical faculty of pure reason to a legitimate linguistic notion of analyticity. However, the analytic explanation of a priori knowledge has undergone several criticisms. Most notably, Quine argued that the analyticsynthetic distinction is illegitimate. Quine states: "But for all its a priori reasonableness, a boundary between analytic and synthetic statements simply has not been drawn. That there is such a distinction to be drawn at all is an unempirical dogma of empiricists, a metaphysical article of faith." [5] While the soundness of Quine's critique is highly disputed, it had a powerful effect on the project of explaining the a priori in terms of the analytic. Relation to the necessary/contingent[edit] The metaphysical distinction between necessary and contingent truths has also been related to a priori and a posteriori knowledge. A proposition that is necessarily true is one whose negation is self- contradictory (thus, it is said to be true in every possible world). Consider the proposition that all bachelors are unmarried. Its negation, the proposition that some bachelors are married, is incoherent, because the concept of being unmarried (or the meaning of the word "unmarried") is part of the concept of being a bachelor (or part of the definition of the word "bachelor"). To the extent that contradictions are impossible, self-contradictory propositions are necessarily false, because it is impossible for them to be true. Thus, the negation of a self-contradictory proposition is supposed to be necessarily true. By contrast, a proposition that is contingently true is one whose negation is not self-contradictory (thus, it is said that it is not true in every possible world). As Jason Baehr states, it seems plausible that all necessary propositions are known a priori, because "[s]ense experience can tell us only about the actual world and hence about what is the case; it can say nothing about what must or must not be the case." [6]
Following Kant, some philosophers have considered the relationship between aprioricity, analyticity, and necessity to be extremely close. According to Jerry Fodor, "Positivism, in particular, took it for granted that a priori truths must be necessary...." [7] However, since Kant, the distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions had slightly changed. Analytic propositions were largely taken to be "true by virtue of meanings and independently of fact", [4] while synthetic propositions were not one must conduct some sort of empirical investigation, looking to the world, to determine the truth- value of synthetic propositions. Aprioricity, analyticity, and necessity have since been more clearly separated from each other. The American philosopher Saul Kripke (1972), for example, provided strong arguments against this position. Kripke argued that there are necessary a posteriori truths, such as the proposition that water is H 2 O (if it is true). According to Kripke, this statement is necessarily true (since water and H 2 O are the same thing, they are identical in every possible world, and truths of identity are logically necessary) and a posteriori (since it is known only through empirical investigation). Following such considerations of Kripke and others (such as Hilary Putnam), philosophers tend to distinguish more clearly the notion of aprioricity from that of necessity and analyticity. Kripke's definitions of these terms, however, diverge in subtle ways from those of Kant. Taking these differences into account, Kripke's controversial analysis of naming as contingent and a priori would best fit into Kant's epistemological framework by calling it "analytic a posteriori". [nb 1]
Thus, the relationship between aprioricity, necessity, and analyticity is not easy to discern. However, most philosophers at least seem to agree that while the various distinctions may overlap, the notions are clearly not identical: the a priori/a posterioridistinction is epistemological, the analytic/synthetic distinction is linguistic, and the necessary/contingent distinction is metaphysical. [9]
History[edit] Early uses[edit] The phrases "a priori" and "a posteriori" are Latin for "from what comes before" and "from what comes later" (or, less literally, "[from first principles, but] before experience" and "after experience"). They appear in Latin translations of Euclid'sElements, a work widely considered during the early European modern period as the model for precise thinking. An early philosophical use of what might be considered a notion of a priori knowledge (though not called by that name) is Plato's theory of recollection, related in the dialogue Meno (380 B.C.), according to which something like a priori knowledge is knowledge inherent, intrinsic in the human mind. Albert of Saxony, a 14th-century logician wrote on the both a priori and a posteriori. [10] George Berkeley, the Irish divine and philosopher outlined the distinction in A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge of 1710, though the terms were already well known by that time. Immanuel Kant[edit] The 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1781) advocated a blend ofrationalist and empiricist theories. Kant states, "although all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it arises from experience" [11] According to Kant, a priori knowledge is transcendental, or based on the form of all possible experience, while a posteriori knowledge is empirical, based on the content of experience. Kant states, "... it is quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound of that which we receive through impressions, and that which the faculty of cognition supplies from itself (sensuous impressions giving merely the occasion)." [11] Thus, unlike the empiricists, Kant thinks that a priori knowledge is independent of the content of experience; moreover, unlike the rationalists, Kant thinks that a prioriknowledge, in its pure form, that is without the admixture of any empirical content, is knowledge limited to the deduction of the conditions of possible experience. These a priori, or transcendental conditions, are seated in one's cognitive faculties, and are not provided by experience in general or any experience in particular. Kant nominated and explored the possibility of a transcendental logic with which to consider the deduction of the a priori in its pure form. Concepts such as time andcause are counted among the list of pure a priori forms. Kant reasoned that the purea priori forms are established via his transcendental aesthetic and transcendental logic. He claimed that the human subject would not have the kind of experience that it has were these a priori forms not in some way constitutive of him as a human subject. For instance, he would not experience the world as an orderly, rule-governed place unless time and cause were operative in his cognitive faculties. The claim is more formally known as Kant's transcendental deduction and it is the central argument of his major work, the Critique of Pure Reason. The transcendental deduction does not avoid the fact or objectivity of time and cause, but does, in its consideration of a possible logic of the a priori, attempt to make the case for the fact of subjectivity, what constitutes subjectivity and what relation it holds with objectivity and the empirical. Johann Fichte[edit] After Kant's death, a number of philosophers saw themselves as correcting and expanding his philosophy, leading to the various forms of German Idealism. One of these philosophers was Johann Fichte. His student (and critic), Arthur Schopenhauer, accused him of rejecting the distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge: ... Fichte who, because the thing-in-itself had just been discredited, at once prepared a system without any thing-in-itself. Consequently, he rejected the assumption of anything that was not through and through merely our representation, and therefore let the knowing subject be all in all or at any rate produce everything from its own resources. For this purpose, he at once did away with the essential and most meritorious part of the Kantian doctrine, the distinction between a priori and a posteriori and thus that between the phenomenon and the thing-in-itself. For he declared everything to be a priori, naturally without any evidence for such a monstrous assertion; instead of these, he gave sophisms and even crazy sham demonstrations whose absurdity was concealed under the mask of profundity and of the incomprehensibility ostensibly arising therefrom. Moreover, he appealed boldly and openly to intellectualintuition, that is, really to inspiration. Schopenhauer, Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. I, 13 See also[edit]
Philosophy portal Abductive reasoning A priori probability Contingency (philosophy) Deductive reasoning Inductive reasoning Tabula rasa Notes[edit] 1. Jump up^ In this pair of articles, Palmquist demonstrates that the context often determines how a particular proposition should be classified. A proposition that is synthetic a posteriori in one context might be analytic a priori in another. [8]
Essence The Metaphysical Ground of Logic and Language: A Reason For The Bankruptcy of Logic, The Stultification of Reason and The Meaninglessness of All Views
Reflections On The Education of Gifted and Talented Students in The Twentieth Century Milestones in The Development of Talent and Gifts in Young People