Horky, Persian Cosmos and Greek Philosophy
Horky, Persian Cosmos and Greek Philosophy
Horky, Persian Cosmos and Greek Philosophy
OXFORD STUDIES
I N A NC I E NT
PHI LOSOPHY
EDITOR: BRAD INWOOD
VOLUME XXXVII
winter 2009
2009
48
49
50
51
52
53
centuries bce oer fragmentary and sometimes conicting representations of the Persian magoi.19 If a single concept of magism is
to be posited, we must recognize that it functions for us heuristically
in order that we may speak more eciently about ancient Greek and
Persian cultures. In this sense, magism must remain a term that
refers to a complex of cultural positions informed by so-called exotopic narratives, and its semantic range must be exible enough to
account for the variety of positions that inform it.20 One approach
that can account for this variety is, broadly speaking, historical, and
it accounts for the development of concepts such as magism by
foreign observers. An eective recent advocate of this approach to
studying the Greek reception, interpretation, and appropriation of
the magoi has been Matthew Dickie, whose analysis of the formation
of the Greek concept of magic focuses especially on the earliest
representation of magoi in a fragment attributed to Heraclitus of
Ephesus (late sixth century bce). As Dickie demonstrates, Heraclitus attack on the magoi and other persons who practised initiations
into the mysteries of Dionysus is signicant evidence. Here, in the
earliest surviving Greek reference to magoi, they are associated
though, notably, not simply identiedwith peoples who practised
the mystic rites of Dionysus: speaking of night-wanderers (), Bacchants (, 1), and initiates ('), Heraclitus claims that the sacred rites practised among men are celebrated in an unholy manner (2 ) %
3 +).21 In the context of such censure, we should be
suspicious that Heraclitus association of magoi with initiates into
the cult of Dionysus may include elisions of type that cannot be
carefully assessed because of his critical bias. Still, the association
is telling, although this evidence in and of itself does not necessarily warrant Dickies claim that the magoi and followers of Dionysus
19 Jan Bremmer acutely notices that, among the Greek sources, we can divide the
responses into legitimate and dubious in accordance with genres: positive responses
paint a picture of legitimate hereditary technologists of the sacred (Birth, 239) in
history and philosophy, whereas negative appraisals are more frequent in tragedy,
comedy, and medical texts. I would add that these latter genres also tend to represent
philosophy and philosophers in a negative light.
20 Compare Vasunias discussion of Mikhail Bakhtins creative understanding
in cultural ideology (Zarathushtra, 1516).
21 22 B 14 DK = Clem. Protr. 22 (no. 543), trans. Kirk, Raven, and Schoeld.
Some scholars have expressed doubt about the authenticity and precise wording
of this fragment. For a recent listing of the positions taken, see Bremmer, Birth,
236 with n. 9.
54
were oering initiation into the mysteries to other people.22 Importantly, Dickie here assumes that initiation into the mysteries
that the magoi and followers of Dionysus practised was available
to political agentsparticularly people who sought private initiations in place of civic cultwhose ethnic or political aliation was
other than their own.23 In order for this claim to be substantiated,
however, we are required to contextualize its contents with later accounts of magoi that derive from the end of the fth century bce and
later, where it appears that some magoi, at any rate, were interested
in incorporating followers from other groups.24 Moreover, Heraclitus fragment raises further concerns: what distinguishes the magoi
to whom Heraclitus refers from (a) the followers of Dionysus and
(b) other kinds of people labelled magoi in the sixth and early fth
centuries bce? For that matter, does any evidence existespecially
evidence from both Greek and Persian sourcesthat could provide
for us a cross-section of information about Persian magoi not only
as they were represented by Greeks but also as they were portrayed
by Persians themselves?
As we have indicated, Heraclitus of Ephesus marks the oldest surviving occurrence of magoi in Greek traditions, around the time of
the Ionian Revolts (end of the sixth century bce). This association
of magoi with other followers of the god Dionysus represents the
earliest example of a correlation that would come to be inuential
over philosophers, especially Plato, in the mid-fourth century bce,
as I shall discuss below. For now, however, it is important to note
that the evidence illustrated by Heraclitus criticism derives from
his experiences in western Asia Minor at the end of the sixth century bce, and that, based on the fact that Ephesus had been under
Persian suzerainty for around forty years (after 547 bce), it is possible that Heraclitus is referring either to true magoi as priests of
22 Dickie, Magic, 29 (emphasis added).
23 Late evidence (Philostratus, VS 1. 10. 1, no. 144) exists for the idea that the
Persian magoi did not give instruction to anyone except Persians, unless the King
allowed it.
24 The earliest evidence that suggests that magoi attempted to initiate Greeks
comes from the Derveni Papyrus (text c.400 bce), on which see below. The only
other direct references to anything involving the public activities of magoi in Greece
during the 5th cent. bce, viz. Gorg. Hel. 10 (no. 173), Soph. OT 3958 (no. 174),
and Eur. Or. 14909 (no. 175), and perhaps the Hippocratic DMS 2 (no. 176), make
absolutely no mention of initiations. Instead, the focus is on charlatanism and the
acquisition of money by means of deception. For historical accounts of magism in
the 5th and 4th cents. bce (Herodotus, Ctesias, Xenophon, and Dinon), see below.
55
Mar. 2009]. Scholars of the history of magic (e.g. F. Graf, Magic in the Ancient
World [Magic] (Cambridge, Mass., 1997), 21) have glanced in passing at the Persian
source material but have not fully explored its signicance.
29 All citations and translations (with minor changes) of the Old Persian text of
the Bisitun Inscription are from R. Schmitt, The Bisitun Inscriptions of Darius the
Great: Old Persian Text (London, 1991).
56
programme in the fullest senses of these terms. For instance, fragmentary copies of the Bisitun Inscription were not only found in
Babylon (inscribed in basalt and translated into Babylonian), but
also in Elephantine/Jeb in Egypt (papyrus fragment in Aramaic and
datable to c.420 bce).30 This evidence suggests that the Bisitun Inscription was translated and copied (and recopied)31 until the latter
part of the fth century bce in areas of Persian inuence, in keeping
with Ahuramazdas express wish that the inscription, composed on
clay tablets and parchment, would be sent o everywhere in the
provinces.32 One of those provinces, of course, would have been
Ephesus.33
It would be impossible to summarize, in a few sentences (or in a
single article), the characteristics of the Kingly ideology, a project
that has required book-length treatments by both Bruce Lincoln
and, in a slightly dierent tenor, Margaret Cool Root.34 What these
studies have demonstrated is the recurrence of, as Root calls them,
conceptual patterns that demonstrate the ocial programmatic
eort on a grand and universal scale in Persian written documents
and artistic representation.35 I shall attempt to shed light on those
30 Texts of the fragments of the Aramaic copy of the Bisitun Inscription, originally
published in A. Cowley, Aramaic Papyri of the Fifth Century B.C. (Oxford, 1923),
are also available in J. C. Greeneld and B. Porten, The Bisitun Inscription of Darius
the Great: Aramaic Version (London, 1982).
31 Cf. Schmitt and Luschey, Bsotun.
57
58
59
60
for other magoi: after all, each of the other defeated individual gures in the relief sculpture stands in as a representative for his own
unique rebellious tribe. It is thus clear that before Heraclitus declared his censure of magoi and other mystic practitionersnotably
those associated with the worship of Dionysusthe negative appraisal of a certain representative magu#s from the Persian Empire
was being distributed in imperial Persian propaganda that drew
centre and periphery into a relationship of unanimity against the
Lie and its advocates. Moreover, the publication and distribution of the account of the coercion, concealment, and deception of
the magu#s Gaumata were themselves gured as a sacred act, willed
by Ahuramazda himself, that provided stability and integration
to the region that comprised the peoples of the Persian Empire.
It is tempting to see Heraclitus criticism of the magoi and other
initiateswho, by denition, engaged in private rituals whose activities were practised in secretin the light of the censure of the
magu#s Gaumata and his tribe in the Bisitun Inscription. After all,
the story of the magu#s Gaumata inuenced the characterization of
the magoi in the accounts of other fth-century bce Greeks, including both Ctesias of Cnidus and Herodotus of Halicarnassus. Ctesias, whose historical information was probably obtained via oral
transmission, clearly knew the story of the deception of the magu#s
Gaumata (whom he calls Sphendadates) as well as the subsequent
slaughter of the magoi that took place following Darius ascension
to the throne.50 Moreover, the account of the magoi as preserved
by Herodotus features such remarkable similarities to the narrative
as recounted on the Bisitun Inscription that we can have little, if
any, doubt that Herodotus inherited the discourse about magism
that had been propagated nearly a century earlier by the King of
Kings himself, Darius the Great. It is to this account, and to other
accounts of magism that originate in areas inuenced by Persian
governance, that we now turn.
50 Cf. FGrHist 688 F 13 ( = Phot. Bibl. 72. 37 a40 a, nos. 130 and 261). Ctesias
account is interestingly dierent from those of Herodotus or Justin (who agrees
with Herodotus). This is signicant because it suggests that Ctesias account is not
derived from Herodotus, but is probably from another oral tradition. For Ctesias,
see Briant, History, 6 and 989.
61
62
. . . prayers and sacrices appease the souls, while the incantation [[]
of the magoi is able to drive away the daimones who are hindering; hindering daimones are vengeful souls (or: hostile to souls). This is why the
magoi perform the sacrice, as if they are paying a retribution. And on
the oerings they pour water and milk, from which they also make the
libations to the dead. Innumerable and many-knobbed are the cakes they
sacrice, because the souls too are innumerable. Mystai make the preliminary sacrice to the Eumenides in the same way the magoi do; for the
Eumenides are souls. On their account anyone who is going to sacrice to
the gods must rst [sacrice] a bird . . . and the . . . and they are . . . this
and as many [fem.] as . . .55
This passage is important for our understanding of the relationship between magoi, as they are described here, and initiates within
an OrphicDionysiac tradition that was practised by the Derveni
commentator. Given the fragmentary state of the text, it is dicult
to assess clearly how the magoi and the OrphicDionysiac mystai
relate to one another,56 and scholars have taken various positions on
this relationship.57 The evidence from Heraclitus discussed above
would seem to suggest that these various ritual communities could
55 Derveni Papyrus col. vi (no. 531), trans. Tsantsanoglou and Parassoglou,
slightly modied.
56 The initiation of Menippus in Lucians Menippus 68 (no. 155) provides an
excellent point of comparison. In it, a magos named Mithrobarzanes initially bathes
Menippus in the Euphrates while addressing the sun in a long speech (81
2 !) that was mouthed in a voluble and unintelligible fashion (
3 4 !), which the speaker takes to be an invocation of daimones.
Subsequently, the magos and Menippus eat (fruit, milk, honey, water from the
Chaospes) together, and the speaker is taken to the Tigris and cleansed while the
magos mutters an incantation (9 #9 :'), a process which may be
similar to his later prayer (at Menippus 9) to Hecate and Persephone in which were
intermingled some barbaric and meaningless words of many syllables (;
< 3 = > 3 '). Once Menippus has been
made into a magos (') himself, the senior magos walks around him to
prevent harm from the phantoms (:, ( ) and they travel home. Finally,
the speaker receives the proper clothing and is told no longer to say that his name
was Menippus but that he was Heracles or Odysseus or Orpheus. In this case,
the adoption of a new name signies the advanced status as hero, but it still marks
the taking of a name that was not originally ones own.
57 A useful summary of scholars views on the problem can be found in The
Derveni Papyrus, ed. and comm. T. Kouremenos, G. M. Parassoglou, and K.
Tsantsanoglou [Derveni] (Florence, 2006), 1668. I disagree with their procedure
in determining that charlatans is the probable intended meaning here (cf. also
pp. 501) because I do not think that we ought to privilege either the Hippocratic
author of On the Sacred Disease or Plato with regard to the information preserved
in the Derveni Papyrus. Concerning the former, his understanding of magoi derives
from the Heraclitean negative tradition, and concerning the latter, Plato inherited
the discourse surrounding these issues and did not himself invent it. We should
63
be associated with one another, although, if the Derveni commentator himself were an initiate of the OrphicDionysiac mysteries, it
would not be surprising for him to distinguish his own caste from
other ritual communities (even though there is no direct or indirect
censure of the activities of the magoi). Regardless, the emphasis
here is on what dierentiates mystai and magoi from one another in
a ritual performance: as Walter Burkert has noted, the mystai, like
the magoi, participate in the preliminary sacrice, but their imitation of the magoi in the ceremony apparently ends there. There is no
mention, for instance, of the mystai joining the magoi in singing the
hymn.58 Later evidence, preserved in Lucians Menippus (second
century ce), gives us a sense of the roles that the magos and the
mystes could play in the OrphicDionysiac initiation: there, it is
clear that the magos sings, while the mystes does not, and, moreover,
that the mystes cannot understand the barbaric utterances of the
songs.59 Roles in the OrphicDionysiac initiatory performance are,
in this case, distinguished both by status and by ethnicity. Since
the songs of the magoi represent an element that establishes the
otherness that magism presents to Greek culture, we might want
to examine it also as a locus of cultural dierence.60 What are we to
make of the proposition that the mystai do not apparently sing the
song with the magoi in the Derveni Papyrus?
In order to contextualize the question, we might consider ways
in which the evidence presented in the Bisitun Inscription, the
fragments of Heraclitus, and the Derveni Papyrus could help to
construct a paradigm by which to understand cross-cultural relationships between OrphicDionysiac and Persian ritual performers. Tsantsanoglou and Burkert, for instance, have pointed to the
correlation between the magoi whom the Derveni Author is describing and the Persian magoi described by Herodotus, whose Histories
therefore be wary of according his opinionsmuch less those of non-authoritative
speakers such as Adeimantus in the Republictoo much weight.
58 Burkert, Eastern, 11721. Or perhaps, if we accept the supplement 7[,
the sacrice itself. If so, we would have to assume that the mystai produce the
sacricial oerings of cake (and perhaps poultry), but do not proceed to pour out
the wineless . See Derveni, 16870, and K. Tsantsanoglou, The First Columns
of the Derveni Papyrus and their Religious Signicance [Columns], in A. Laks
and G. W. Most (eds.), Studies on the Derveni Papyus (Oxford, 1997), 93128 at 111.
As De Jong notes (Traditions, 11112), Greek libations prepared and concluded the
sacrice, whereas, for the Persians, libation rituals and sacrice of animals could
be performed separately.
59 See n. 56.
60 Cf. Bremmer, Birth, 246 with n. 61.
64
65
66
But the fragmentary representation of the magoi in the Derveni Papyrus and the more comprehensive illustration in Herodotus Histories lack some of the fundamental characteristics that are present
in the surviving incantations that Persian magoi sang in Avestan: there is no mention of the standard duality between Truth/
Cosmic Order (a#sa) and the Lie (drux#s) that underlies the cosmic ideology of both the Bisitun Inscription and the Old Avestan
texts of the Ya#sna, or, for that matter, of the cosmological principle
of Good Mind (vohu manah) and its model representative Ahuramazda (either as Zeus or as the Intelligent Lord).70 Herodotus
understanding of the ritual practitioners he called magoi is supercial, but it is also unlikely that his Persian sources possessed a
knowledge more extensive than his. Regarding the Derveni commentator, the case is less clear-cut: he appears to have had some
experience in the ritual performance as presided over by magoi, but
the fragmentary nature of the text does not allow us to deduce whether those fundamental elements that characterized legitimate magism in Persian traditions were available to the OrphicDionysiac
exegete.71
67
68
69
few critics have attempted to parse the dierences between the bad
and the good magoi in Platos dialogues within a larger context of
the discourse concerning magism, which, as we have seen, takes
on both political and cosmological valences. Indeed, the discourse
of magism as discussed by Plato nds a common ground between
politics and cosmology in the concept of universal justice, which is
promoted by the good magos and subverted by the bad magos.
Plato appears to refer twice to such bad magoi: rst, in the Republic Socrates speaks of the clever magoi and tyrant-makers (B 3
3 ) who, when a young man is in the process
of being reared, appear on the scene and attempt to inculcate an
insatiable desire in his soul and lead him to a tyrannical way of living.82 In this case, the clever magoi and tyrant-makers as itinerant
practitioners of wisdom resemble the mendicant priests and seers
(' 3 ) to whom Adeimantus had referred earlier in
the dialogue; the association of magos with agurtes and mantis was
known to Sophocles before, and there is no reason to assume that
Plato for his part did not countenance some interchangeability between the terms.83 These mendicant priests and seers appear at
a wealthy familys house and try to persuade the rich that they
have the power to eradicate past wrongs through the employment
of their sacrices and songs ( 3 #A) .84 Indeed, for
a price, these charlatans will produce Orphic texts as a means to
purify both individuals and entire cities from injustices:
They produce a hubbub of books of Musaeus and Orpheus, ospring of
Selena and the Muses, so they say, according to which they perform their
sacrices, persuading not only private citizens but even cities that there are
modes of deliverance and purications for injustices by means of silly sorts
of pleasures both for those who are still alive and even for those who are
defunct [], which they call functions []; they deliver us
from evils there [in the world of the dead], but terrible things await those
who do not sacrice. (Plato, Rep. 364 e 3365 a 3)85
While their activities are not precisely the same, these itinerant
practitioners of wisdom share in common the threat that they pose
82 Plato, Rep. 572 e 45. D. Scott documents the similarities and dierences between the eros of the future philosopher-king and that of the future tyrant (Eros,
Philosophy, and Tyranny, in id. (ed.), Maieusis: Essays on Ancient Philosophy in
Honour of Myles Burnyeat (Oxford, 2008), 13653 at 1416).
83 Soph. OT 38790 (no. 174): :3 , '
. . . . . . 3 !) !, + ; 5 ; Cf. Graf, Magic, 212.
84 Plato, Rep. 364 b 5c 5.
85 On this passage see Dickie, Magic, 62.
70
71
here is more positive than what Plato had illustrated in the Republic. Here, Socrates, in discussing many dierent methods of rearing,
tells Alcibiades about the royal tutors ( ) of the
son of the Persian King who undertake the future heirs education
at the age of fourteen. Four tutors are selected from among the
best men: the wisest, the most just, the most temperate, and the
most courageous.90 The wisest man (%) is expected to teach
the boy the Magian lore [] of Zoroaster, son of Horomazes,
which Socrates explains is comprised of two elements: the worship
of the gods (( ) and the royal things (2 ).91
Alcibiades by Nicholas Denyer, Ancient Philosophy, 24/2 (Fall, 2004), 4614 at 461;
and C. Rowe, Book Notes: Plato and Socrates, Phronesis, 48/3 (2002), 287308 at
301); contra M. Joyal, Review of Nicholas Denyer (ed.), Plato: Alcibiades, Bryn
Mawr Classical Review, 2003.01.28 <http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/bmcr/2003/2003-0128.html> [accessed 7 Mar. 2009], although some scholars (e.g. G. Betegh, Review of
J.-F. Pradeau (ed.) and C. Marbuf (tr.), Platon: Alcibiade (Paris, 1999) and Denyer,
Nicholas (ed.), Plato: Alcibiades (Cambridge, 2001), Classical World, 99/2 (Winter
2006), 1857) do not take a position on the authenticity of Alcibiades I. Interestingly,
Denyer prefers a dating nearer to the early 350s bce, following signicant changes
in Platos political theory and approval of Persian customs. This is not the place
to discuss the appearance of the magos Gobryes in the pseudo-Platonic Axiochus
(371 a 1372 a 4; no. 205), which would require a study all to itself. I shall oer
only a few comments: (a) even if the Axiochus were to be considered spurious, it
could still, at least theoretically, derive from the early Academy. But, as M. Joyal has
pointed out (Socrates as , in the Axiochus, in K. Doring, M. Erler, and S.
Schorn (eds.), Pseudoplatonica (Stuttgart, 2005), 97118 at 97 n. 3), the Axiochus is
an eclectic dialogue that features Platonic, Epicurean, Stoic, and Cynic elements; as
such, it is unlikely to have been composed before the 3rd cent. bce. Still, it is worth
mentioning (b) that the eschatological myth there preserves the theme of universal
justice (familiar from the judgement myths of the Republic and the Gorgias) in a
Persianized form: according to the bronze tablets that Gobryes father saw during
the reign of Xerxes, a person who has died travels through the underworld and
arrives at the plain of truth ( ; cf. Plato, Phdr. 248 b 6), where he will
be judged by Minos and Rhadymanthus; that person is not allowed to tell lies in
the presence of the judges.
90 The most temperate (!) Persian is expected to instruct the boy
how to rule over pleasure and to be truly free as a king should. This Persian instructor
is antithetical to the crafty magoi and tyrant-makers to whom Socrates referred in
the Republic; here, a good Persian educator teaches how to become a true king,
rather than a corrupt tyrant. Such an interest in preventing the corruption of a
future monarch into a tyrant appears in reference to the Spartans and Lycurgus
reforms in Platos Laws as well. The tutor () is referred to alongside the
Orphotelest () in Philodemus On Poems (P. Herc. 1074 F 30; 181.
1 . Janko = Bernabe 655).
91 Plato, Alc. I 121 e 4122 a 8 (no. 282). Cf. Sancisi-Weerdenburg, Political,
1501. In their zeal to show the historical inaccuracy of Alcibiades I, scholars have
unfortunately overlooked the fact that while Zoroaster is not the literal son of
Horomazes, the term father () in Greek philosophical circles (especially those
72
73
74
Thus Diogenes begins a historical assessment of the origins of philosophy, in which he disputes the point of view that he attributes
to Aristotle and Sotion. For Diogenes, philosophy begins with the
Greeks and possesses a twofold origin, in the schools of Pythagoras
in Italy and Anaximander in Ionia. The others who hold that philosophy received its origins among barbarians are a remarkable collection of gures: in addition to Aristotle (38422 bce) and Sotion
of Alexandria ( . c.200170 bce), Diogenes refers to the Egyptians, the Platonist Hermodorus of Syracuse (fourth century bce),
and the historian Xanthus of Lydia ( . mid-fth century bce).100
As is well known and has been recently investigated by James Rives,
the fragments of Aristotles lost works Magikos (if indeed it was by
Aristotle) and On Philosophy contained information about the magoi
and about Zoroastrian thought as it related to Aristotles philosophical systems. Indeed, Diogenes interest in the origins () of
philosophy as a problem of historiography responds to Aristotles
documentation of rst principles () of the systems of thought
of other philosophers and practitioners of wisdom, demonstrated
most famously in Metaphysics , but also preserved in the fragmen99 The attribution to Sotions twenty-third book is surely a mistake, and it should
be corrected to the thirteenth book. Generally, for a useful discussion of the problems
involved in using this passage as evidence for Aristotle, see Rives, Aristotle, 458,
and J. Mejer, Diogenes Laertius and his Hellenistic Background (Wiesbaden, 1978),
41 with n. 84.
100 For the activities and project of Xanthus, see Kingsley, Magi, 17391.
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
of the universe as preserved in Dercylides description of Hermodorus metaphysics and the gods in the writings of authority
[B] as employed by Plutarch could occur only if Horomazes and
Areimanius were considered to be among sensible objects; amazingly, they are: Horomazes and Areimanius are especially among
objects of perception ( ( (), a description that ts
adequately with Platos illustration of the astral gods in Timaeus,
who, among other things, are the craftsmen of good and bad things
(( 3 ( ) of a second ontological and causational stratum who work with Mind (2 +).161 As perceivable
beings, then, Horomazes and Areimanius as described by authority
[B] occupy a position in the cosmos that adapts and expands upon
Platos descriptions of the astral gods in Timaeus and the second
class of beings in the Philebus.
But there is a problem with the hypothesis that Hermodorus is
identical with authority [B] in Plutarchs On Isis and Osiris. On
the one hand, source [B] suggests that Horomazes and Areimanius assume two oppositional poles on the indenite spectrum, and
that Mithres occupies the middle as the mean (!) between
them.162 On the other hand, in the short fragment of Hermodorus
On Sciences, there is no explicit reference to a mediating gure
associates the creator (, +) with the cause (,
), although his suggestion
that despite Platos distinction in the Philebus between Limit itself and the cause
of the mixture, that the creative principle may reasonably be held to do its own
mixing cannot be demonstrated in this fragment of Hermodorus. In the passage
attributed to authority [B] and preserved by Plutarch, there is reference to the
mixing of good and bad things, but sadly a lacuna prevents us from knowing what
the subject of this sentence was.
161 Plato, Tim. 46 e 36 and 92 a 59, the end of the dialogue, where the cosmos
is called the image of the Intelligent, a perceptible god (* + + ,
). Note too that the astral gods, like other accessory causes (), eect
the universe by, among other things, cooling and heating (' 3 ).
Cf. Taran, Academica, 82 with n. 86.
162 This passage shares many features with the cosmology attributed by Eudemus
of Rhodes to Epimenides (F 150 Wehrli = Damasc. Princ. 124, no. 215), in which
Aer and Night, the two rst principles, give birth to Tartarus, the third principle,
which is in turn called the intelligent mean (G 9 ). Their mingling also
apparently produces the egg, from which other ospring come forward. As G. S.
Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schoeld note, however (The Presocratic Philosophers,
2nd edn. (Cambridge, 1983), 27), it is dicult to distinguish the passages that
refer genuinely to Epimenides cosmology (pre-414 bce) from additions that could
have been made either by Eudemus or by later Neoplatonist commentators. On
the subject of what Damascius borrowed, however, Betegh (Eudemus, 3479) has
persuasively demonstrated that Damascius tends to let Eudemus account speak for
itself, even if it runs counter to his own purposes.
89
90
91
92
93
He was the rst to set up the statue of Aphrodite Anaitis in Babylon and
ordered such worship from the Susians, Egbatanians, Persians, Bactrians,
and those from Damascus and Sardis. (FGrHist 680 F 11 = Clem. Al.
Protr. 5. 65. 2, no. 217)
As Briant has noted, the text here is derived from an ocial source,
which is indicated by the patrimony and the list of peoples who are
ordered by Artaxerxes II to worship statues.176 What this edict of
Artaxerxes II tells us is that a new policy of worshiping statues for
the gods was in place in Persia since the rst or second quarter of the
fourth century bce in the Persian Empire, even as far away as Sardis.
Dinon of Colophon, another historian who apparently travelled
to Persia with Alexander the Great, conrms that the Persians
considered the statues of their gods to be water and re, although
this account raises more questions than it provides answers.177 Still,
it is clear from Greek and Babylonian eyewitness testimonies of the
third quarter of the fourth century bce that the Persians honoured
their gods in the form of statues, and if Hermodorus was privy
to this sort of knowledge about Zoroastrian customs, we might
wish to entertain the possibility that, by referring (in an abstracted
philosophical sense) to Horomazes and Areimanius as phenomena
that could be perceived by the senses, he was referring to the images
of the gods in statue form.
94
Zoroaster which may have involved the story of a magos who circumnavigated Africa
and arrived at Gelons court in Syracuse. Of course, this story provides an interesting
parallel to Platos journey to the court of Dionysius II in 361 bce, although further
investigation on these lines would be speculative. Cf. H. B. Gottschalk, Heraclides
of Pontus [Heraclides] (Oxford, 1980), 11012.
181 Cf. K. Gaiser, Philodems Academica: Die Berichte u ber Platon und die Alte
Akademie in zwei herkulanensischen Papyri [Berichte] (Stuttgart, 1988), 1089, a
position that is strengthened by the presence in the margins of a summary of what
Neanthes says. Neanthes appears to have been active during the last quarter of the
4th cent. bce, as recently demonstrated by S. Schorn, Periegetische Biographie
Historische Biographie: Neanthes von Kyzikos (FgrHist 84) als Biograph, in M.
Erler and S. Schorn (eds.), Die griechische Biographie in hellenistischer Zeit: Akten
des internationalen Kongresses vom 26.29. Juli 2006 in Wurzburg (Berlin and New
York, 2007), 11556.
95
96
( = Posidonius F 49 EdelsteinKidd, no. 76). For Heraclides belief that the music and
ethnic virtues were coextensive, see F 114 ( = Ath. 14. 1921, 624 c626 a), F 115a
( = Philod. Mus. 4 col. 49. 120 Delattre), and F 115b Schutrumpf
( = Philod. Mus.
cols. 137. 27138. 9 Delattre), on which see Gottschalk, Heraclides, 1349. Of course,
Aristotle too thought that the practice of music, as performed by peoples of dierent
ethnic backgrounds, disposes people to virtues (e.g. Arist. Pol. 1339a11b10).
189 The Athenian Stranger (Laws 669 d 25) warns that poets who make music improperly do so irrationally (2 + ! 3 ( ),
gesturing towards their inability to perform dialectics.
190 Plato, Rep. 400 b 1c 4, where Socrates cites the music theory of Damon.
Aristoxenus of Tarentum (El. rhythm. F 30 Pearson), the famous Peripatetic/
Pythagorean musicologist and biographer, also understood the dactylic to be the
foot with the equal ratio (
# #). See M. L. West, Ancient Greek Music (Oxford, 1992), 2434.
97
In referring to the Pythagoreans here, Socrates is most likely recalling the theories of musical motion of the mathematical Pythagorean
Archytas of Tarentum.192 What is interesting about the account of
the Chaldaean Stranger in the Index, then, is that Philip of Opus
follows his teacher and the Pythagoreans by understanding motion to be a central element in his discussion of music, but, even
more interesting, he puts these words in the mouth of a Stranger
from barbarian land.193 Was the Chaldaean Stranger proposing
to emend the Platonic theory of motiona point of contention between Plato and the mathematical Pythagoreans in the Republicin
the larger scheme of Platonic physics? And what are we to do with
the apparent interrelationship between Pythagorean and barbarian, a topic that has been problematic for scholars of the history
of ancient philosophy? While it has been in fashion for some time
to take seriously the inuence of the Pythagoreansespecially the
mathematical group which involved itself in empirical studies of
the universeon the more famous associates of Plato (Speusippus,
Xenocrates, Hermodorus, Heraclides, Eudoxus, Aristotle, Philip
191 Cf. Tim. 47 d 2e 2 (G 4 [, A 7 2 A GA 1 1
. . .), 80 a 3b 8.
192 Cf. Human, Archytas, 3989.
193 Contrast Socrates position when speaking to the Pythagorean students of
Philolaus in the Phaedo (78 a 19), where Socrates half-seriously suggests that one
can nd people who understand how to sing charms in order to dispel fears among
both Greeks and barbarians.
98
99
B I B L I O GR A P HY
Barker, A., The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece (Cambridge, 2007).
Barney, R., Names and Nature in Platos Cratylus [Names] (New York,
2001).
Barr-Sharrar, B., The Derveni Krater: Masterpiece of Classical Greek Metalwork (Princeton, 2008).
Betegh, G., The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation
[Derveni] (Cambridge, 2004).
On Eudemus Fr. 150 (Wehrli) [Eudemus], in I. Bodnar and W. W.
Fortenbaugh (eds.), Eudemus of Rhodes (New Brunswick and London,
2002), 33757.
Review of J.-F. Pradeau (ed.) and C. Marbuf (tr.), Platon: Alcibiade
(Paris, 1999) and Denyer, Nicholas (ed.), Plato: Alcibiades (Cambridge,
2001), Classical World, 99/2 (Winter 2006), 1857.
Bidez, J., Eos ou Platon et lOrient (Brussels, 1945).
and Cumont, F., Les Mages hellenises: Zoroastre, Ostanes et Hystaspe
dapres la tradition grecque (1938; repr. New York, 1975).
Bollansee, J., Hermippos of Smyrna and his Biographical Writings: A Reappraisal (Leuven, 1999).
Boyce, M., A History of Zoroastrianism, ii. Under the Achaemenians (Leiden, 1982).
with F. Grenet, A History of Zoroastrianism, iii. Zoroastrianism under
Macedonian and Roman Rule [Macedonian] (Leiden, 1991).
Bremmer, J., The Birth of the Term Magic [Birth], in id., Greek
Religion and Culture, the Bible and the Ancient Near East (Leiden, 2008),
23548.
Briant, P., From Cyrus to Alexander: A History of the Persian Empire, trans.
P. T. Daniels [History] (Winona Lake, 2002).
Gaumata, in Encyclopedia Iranica <http://www.iranica.com/newsite/>
[accessed 7 Mar. 2009].
Brisson, L., Le M^eme et lAutre dans la structure ontologique du Timee de
Platon: un commentaire systematique du Timee de Platon (Paris, 1974).
Burkert, W., Babylon, Memphis, Persepolis: Eastern Contexts of Greek Culture [Eastern] (Cambridge, Mass., 2004).
Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism, trans. E. L. Minar, Jr.
(Cambridge, Mass., 1972).
The Orientalizing Revolution: Near Eastern Inuence on Greek Culture in the Early Archaic Age, trans. M. E. Pinder and W. Burkert (Cambridge, Mass., 1992).
Carastro, M., La Cite des mages: penser la magie en Grece ancienne [Cite]
(Grenoble, 2006).
100
101
102
Rives, J. B., Aristotle, Antisthenes of Rhodes, and the Magikos [Aristotle], Rheinisches Museum, 147/1 (2004), 3554.
Root, M. C., The King and Kingship in Achaemenid Art: Essays on the
Creation of an Iconography of Empire [King and Kingship] (Leiden, 1979).
Rowe, C., Book Notes: Plato and Socrates, Phronesis, 48/3 (2002), 287
308.
Russell, J. R., The Magi in the Derveni Papyrus, Name-ye Iran-e Bastan,
1/1 (Spring 2001), 4959.
Sancisi-Weerdenburg, H., Political Concepts in Old-Persian Royal Inscriptions [Political], in K. Raaaub (ed.), Anfange politischen Denkens
in der Antike: Die nahostlichen Kulturen und die Griechen (Munich, 1993),
14564.
Schibli, H. S., Xenocrates Daemons and the Irrational Soul [Daemons],
CQ, ns 43/1 (1993), 14367.
Schmitt, R., The Bisitun Inscriptions of Darius the Great: Old Persian Text
(London, 1991).
Iranische Personennamen bei Aristoteles, in S. Adhami (ed.), Paitimana: Essays in Iranian, Indo-European, and Indian Studies in Honor of
Hanns-Peter Schmidt, 2 vols. (Costa Mesa, Calif., 2003), 27599.
Onomastica Iranica Platonica, in C. Mueller-Goldingen and K. Sier
(eds.), L^enaika: Festschrift fur Carl Werner Muller (Stuttgart and Leipzig, 1996), 81102.
and Luschey, H., Bsotun,
in Encyclopaedia Iranica <http://www.
103