Radical Painting
Radical Painting
henry staten
CLEMENT GREENBERG,
RADICAL PAINTING,
AND THE LOGIC OF
MODERNISM
viable in the contemporary crisis, a painting had
to defeat or suspend its own [literal] objecthood by the assertion of pictorial shape (ibid.).
In the introduction to the collected work Fried
updates, but fundamentally reaffirms, the judgments about contemporary art at which he had
arrived when he wrote the earlier work, and notes
that he stopped writing art criticism in the 1970s
because he was out of sympathy with the direction art had taken and saw no point in continuing to reiterate his opposition.
Just as Art and Objecthood appeared,
however, Artforum (Sept. 1998) carried a review
by Fried of monochrome paintings by the New
York painter Joseph Marioni. In this remarkable
document Fried declared, against all expectation,
that Marionis monochromes were paintings in
ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/02/010073-16 2002 Taylor & Francis Ltd and the Editors of Angelaki
DOI: 10.1080/0969725022014206 5
73
radical painting
the fullest and most exalted sense of the word,
and went on to this conclusion:
I consider Marioni to be one of the foremost
painters at work anywhere at the present, and
the great and thought-provoking surprise his
work has given me is not only that it transcends the previous limitations of the monochrome but also that it is the first body of work
I have seen that suggests that the Minimalist
intervention might have had productive consequences for painting of the highest ambition.
Simply put, the Minimalist hypostatization of
objecthood seems to have led in Marionis
art to a new, more deeply founded integration
of color, amateriality, and support, which is to
say to an affirmation of the continued vitality
of painting that has something of the character
of a new beginning. (149)
74
staten
de duves interpretation of greenberg
Greenbergs narrative about modernism has
recently been massively re-examined and recontextualized by Thierry De Duve.3 De Duve has
heightened the philosophical stakes in this discussion by extensive analysis of the conflicting
Kantian elements in Greenbergs problematic
the fact that for Greenberg the beauty of a painting always had to be evaluated by a Kantian judgment of taste, while on the other hand the logic
of modernism that Greenberg equally derived
from (his reading of) Kant implied that judgments
of taste were no longer necessary. Greenberg
wrote in his 1960 essay Modernist Painting that
the essence of Modernism, as observable in
Kant, the first real Modernist, lay in the use of
characteristic methods of a discipline to criticize
the discipline itself, not in order to subvert it but
in order to entrench it more firmly in its area of
competence (85).4 Hence modernism in art
meant that each art was concerned with all that
was unique in the nature of its medium, and the
task of self-criticism became to eliminate from the
specific effects of each art any and every effect
that might conceivably be borrowed from or by
the medium of any other art. Thus would each art
be rendered pure (86). The quest for purity,
in the case of painting, yielded the reduction to
mere flatness:
It was the stressing of the ineluctable flatness
of the surface that remained more fundamental than anything else to the processes by
which pictorial art criticized and defined itself
under Modernism. For flatness alone was
unique and exclusive to pictorial art. The
enclosing shape of the picture was a limiting
condition, or norm, that was shared with the
art of the theater; color was a norm and a
means shared not only with the theater, but
also with sculpture. [F]latness was the
only condition painting shared with no other
art (87)
The logic of this famous argument is considerably less than compelling. Leaving aside its questionable relation to Kants project, its shakiest
assumption is this: that if there is to be an
essence of painting, that essence must be
absolutely singular, there must be one character-
75
istic that is the essence and this one characteristic cannot be shared with any other art. By parity
of argument, one would have to conclude that
sound is inessential to poetry because it is shared
with music, and the history of modernist poetry,
with its recurrent tendency toward pure musicality, would be an unaccountable mistake.
In any case, this was the conclusion at which
Greenberg arrived, a conclusion that, on De
Duves account, led him into an intolerable
contradiction. For if mere flatness is the essence
of the art of painting, then, as Greenberg
remarked in 1962 in After Abstract
Expressionism, a stretched, unpainted canvas
could be experienced as a painting or, in the
slightly weasally term that he actually used, a
picture, though not necessarily as a successful
one.5 According to De Duve (and I was
surprised to find this out), no one ever presented
a mere unpainted canvas as a painting; monochrome or quasi-monochrome was thus the closest thing to the limit-condition of the art of
painting at which modernism in fact arrived, the
zero degree of painting (217). But when
Greenberg saw monochrome paintings, rather
than thinking that they had arrived at the
essence, he dismissed them as familiar and
slick. Monochrome, he judged, had become
almost overnight another taming convention
that automatically declared itself to be art (De
Duve 251).
If a work automatically declares itself to be
art, then no act of aesthetic judgment is required
from the viewer; yet Greenberg was irrevocably
committed to the necessity of aesthetic judgment.
De Duve comments:
Once an unpainted canvas can be called a
picture or a painting, then it is automatically
called art. With the dismissal of the very
last expendable convention of modernist
painting that the canvas be painted at all
the specific [i.e., the art of painting] surrenders to the generic [art in general]. The
consequences branch out into two possibilities. Either the making and appreciation of
art require nothing but a mere identification
predicated on the conceptual logic of
modernism, and aesthetic judgment is no
longer necessary; or aesthetic judgment is
radical painting
still necessary. But the pressure that the
conventions of painting had put on its practice
is now nil (De Duve 222)
On De Duves reading, then, if there is a reductive logic of modernism, it follows that, once
the reduction is complete, there will no longer be
any room for judgments regarding the beauty of
the work, either on the part of the viewer or on
the part of the artist as he creates his work; or,
conversely, if there is to be aesthetic judgment,
purism or reductivism is no longer tenable
(ibid.). Hence, Greenbergs choice in favor of
aesthetic judgment meant that he had to abandon
modernism with its progressive paring away of
nonessentials from the medium.
De Duves account, which skillfully exploits
the weaknesses in Greenbergs own formulations
(importing, however, these same weaknesses into
his own argument as we will see), gains its plausibility not only from its elegant formulation but
from the historical sequel, the Greenbergian
anti-Greenbergianism of Donald Judd and
Joseph Kosuth that developed the terms of
Greenbergs logic uncompromisingly away from
the specificity of the art of painting and toward
the negation of aesthetic judgment. Looking at
Stellas black paintings in 1962 with Greenbergs
doctrine in mind, Judd and his generation of
artists had no alternative other than to pursue
the modernist tradition even beyond the literal
monochrome where it actually meets its end
(231). Stellas paintings, which seemed to mark
the limit to which the modernist reduction could
be pushed, were interpreted by Judd as really
more like objects than paintings. [M]ost of the
works, Judd wrote, suggest slabs, since they
project more than usual (cited in De Duve 236).
But Judd argued that three-dimensional actual
space is intrinsically more powerful and
specific than painting on a flat surface.
Because the nature of three dimensions isnt set,
given beforehand, something credible can be
made, almost anything (in De Duve 235). As
these remarks indicate, Judd was still awkwardly
trying to work with Greenbergs idea of specificity while loosening the traditional constraints
to which Greenberg had bound it: Judds new
three-dimensionality in order to open its unlim-
76
staten
the basis of Stellas early work, which teetered on
the edge of the minimalist reduction; more
puzzling is how De Duve can praise Ryman as a
great painter but quickly assimilate his work,
because it acknowledge[s] the readymade, to
the tradition of Duchamp (277). For Rymans
work in fact exploits to an unparalleled degree
the pressure that the conventions of painting put
on its practice.
Ryman has made an entire career out of paintings that are nominally white, yet each of which
is a distinctive exploration of the immense variety of effects of texture, color, and reflectivity
that can be achieved within the limits of what
language labels univocally (and quite inadequately) as white; of the interaction of paint
with the immense variety of surfaces to which it
can be applied (linen, plastic, paper, metal, etc.);
and of the thematization, as part of the formal
whole, of the other, previously merely substructural elements, such as the stretcher, the size of
the brush and the amount of paint it will hold,
the means of attachment to the wall (a very rich
element for Ryman, who has used tape, bolts of
various sorts, tacks, and so forth, exposing them
and making them part of the composition of the
painting) and even the wall itself, which
Ryman also calculates as an integral part of the
aesthetic structure of the painting. De Duve
appears to leap from the fact that brushes, bolts,
and so forth are manufactured objects to his
conclusion that Rymans art is properly to be
understood as an acknowledgment of the readymade. There is some interest in linking Ryman
in this way to the tradition of Duchamp; but the
artistic goal at which Ryman aims could scarcely
be more distant from Duchamps. The thematization of readymade elements in Rymans work
is subordinate to a more comprehensive logic of
making than that of the readymade a logic,
older than modernism, that, before it involves
their manufactured character, involves acknowledging, and drawing out the consequences
of, the materiality of the artworks component
materials.
The characteristically modern critical awareness that there is no pure, raw materiality, that
the materials of art come to us already worked
over by a long cultural history, becomes for many
77
radical painting
the modernist idea of the specific medium. I will
say more about this at the conclusion of this
essay.)
Now, Ryman is often praised for his pragmatic, non-theoretical stance toward his work; yet
in his terse way he has situated himself very
precisely as working within the selfsame logic
that was more fully theorized in the 1980s by
Marioni and Umberg in their jointly authored
account of the nature of Radical Painting.7 There
are, Ryman says, three kinds of painting procedure: representation, abstraction, and his own,
which has been called by various names, none of
them very satisfactory: Theres been
concrete, its been called absolute, nonobjective, and its even been called abstraction
(a list to which we can now add radical).
Ryman prefers to call it realism, because,
unlike the first two procedures, this type of work
involves no picture, no illusion, only the perceptual reality of the painting itself.
It is much harder to achieve freedom from
representation than one might think. The very
fact that realism has been confused with
abstraction (a concept that retains the notion
of something represented, only abstractly)
shows that even the idea of purely non-representational painting is not easy to grasp. The notion
of a paintings having no picture at all (not even
one that is abstractly gestured at), is deceptively
simple to state, yet the radical extirpation of
representation requires a thinking-through of
every conventional and material element of the
art of painting a thinking-through that
produces a new logic of form. Realism, says
Ryman, uses all the devices that are used by
abstraction and representation such as composition and color complexity, and surface and light,
and line and so on, and yet all these terms are
transformed when their logic is reconfigured
from scratch without the relation to figure.
Consider an element as simple and fundamental
as line: if line is still to be found in the realist
or radical painting, it cannot be drawn, because
drawing is a function classically, for Aristotle
as much as for Kant8 the defining function, of
the procedure of representation. Hence: I would
not actually paint a line, I would paint an area of
paint and stop. And then at the edge of the paint
78
staten
The difference between Rymans work and
Marionis, and then again between either of theirs
and that of Umberg, shows how vast is the range
of possibility of this fundamental or radical or
realist exploration of painting. Like the work of
the others, Umbergs has evolved through a
number of transformations, but in the 1980s
when he was collaborating with Marioni he
painted intensely black-looking paintings on thin
sheets of aluminum, made of dry particles of
graphite or ivory black, which he brushed dry
onto moist dammar, horizontally and vertically,
thirty or forty layers, building up a porous
texture that registers the disciplined lines of the
brush strokes in the strikingly dry painted
surface. This texture is extremely fragile: the
merest touch will destroy it. This fragility,
together with the thinness of the support which
makes the painting seem at first to be part of the
wall creates a sort of attenuation of materiality,
at least in the sense of withdrawal from threedimensionality. Yet the paint, with its delicately
refined yet charcoal-like texture, remains
intensely material, and in the absence of any
figure, shape, or line, the eye can only perceive
the color as bound to this materiality. Black is
actualized in a specific painting-medium, and this
actualization can only be judged aesthetically in
the context of the specific history of aesthetic
exploration out of which it comes, the context of
fundamental, concrete, absolute, realist, or radical painting.
The increasingly articulate consciousness of
the (historically, contextually significant) materiality of painting, the nature of the pressure it
exerts on the quest for aesthetic form, and the
means by which that pressure can be put to
aesthetic account that painters in this tradition
have developed, give the lie to Greenbergs own
belief that painters had never been, and could not
be, explicitly aware of the logic that had been
guiding their practice throughout the history of
modernism. 9 Yet this increased awareness actually has the opposite effect from that inferred by
De Duve, moving the art of monochrome farther
than ever away from any possibility of producing
a painting by mere deduction from a logic.
De Duve creates his dichotomy between
aesthetic judgment and conceptual deduction by
79
Yet De Duve renders the reference to the inspiration the painter receives from the medium
itself effectively meaningless when, endorsing
Greenbergs narrowest interpretation of the logic
of modernism, he sublates the materiality of the
medium into the idea of convention. In the
context of this sublation, it is easy to conceive
monochrome as a bodiless zero degree of painting that can provide no further inspiration (only
concoctions that are produced automatically). And the judgment of quality must now
hover in the thin air of a generalized or generic
art that has no palpable relation to the specificity of a given medium, because this relation, if
conceived as a logic, would result in the automaticity that renders aesthetic judgment irrelevant. One should pay careful attention to the
sleight of hand with the word medium that is
required for the logic of this argument:
Between content and form, between the
generic value-judgment and the specific selfcriticism of the particular medium, there has
to be a mediation, but one that doesnt allow
for a deduction. If it did, it would mean that
content aesthetic value could be inferred
from the state of the medium. Conversely, it
would mean that the medium could be deliberately manipulated so as to produce content
or quality, thus allowing for what Greenberg
called concocted art. (213)
radical painting
been given an essential impetus by Greenbergs
logic, it is not a problem that is intrinsic to the
notion of modernism as specific self-criticism, if
that notion is going to be construed not in the
odd and indefensible form of its reductio in a
blank canvas but in the most expansive terms
terms that look to Greenbergs critical practice,
which was, as Fried notes, separated by a gulf
from his theory and to the history of the
modernist reduction since 1962.
80
staten
De Duve passes lightly over this praise of Still,
Rothko, and Newman, taking it as somehow
restoring Greenbergs confidence in the thesis of
flatness and thus as leading up to the remark
about a bare canvas; Fried more acutely notes
that Greenbergs remarks on color are ironically
at odds with the remark about the bare canvas,
but argues that the reductionist logic of
Greenbergs theory of modernism meant that
color or indeed openness in recent painting
could not assume the constitutive or essentialist
significance of flatness and the delimitation of
flatness (39). And it is true that Greenberg
now suggests the old logic has expended its impetus as Still, Rothko, and Newman have opened a
second phase in the self-criticism of
modernism. In this new phase, the delimitation
of flatness is replaced as the central question by
that of the ultimate source of quality in art
(Greenberg 132) a source that Greenberg identifies as conception, in the quite traditional
sense of inspiration. But this proclamation of a
new phase does not erase from the record the
previous remark in which he marks out color and
openness as the exclusive formal pathway to the
future of painting precisely the role he had
formerly assigned to the problematic of flatness
(of which, properly conceived, the questions of
color and openness are aspects as I will argue
below).
The statement about a new phase confusedly
implies both that the old formalist logic is no
longer relevant as painting turns from questions
of form to questions of aesthetic quality an
implication contradicted by the declaration
concerning color and openness; and that the
question of quality in painting was not formerly
a problem for modernism as it pursued its quest
for flatness an implication that is contradicted
by Greenbergs own earlier critical practice, in
which he insisted on the distinction between
formal means and aesthetic quality. In 1959, for
instance, in The Case for Abstract Art
Greenberg had written that Abstract painting
may be a purer, more quintessential form of
pictorial art than the representational kind, but
this does not of itself confer quality upon an
abstract picture (82).10
It is clear, despite Greenbergs muddled
81
radical painting
of figuration, the physical and perceptual qualities of painted color, and the flatness of the nonillusionistic painted surface.
could easily have called the telos of the paintingobject or object-that-is-a-painting, which irreducibly involves being painted.11 Unlike, say, a
wall that one paints, the painting-support is
created purely in view of this function.
(Greenberg ignored this fact and thus curiously
gave way to literal literalism when he started to
think of the flatness of the support in abstraction
from the purpose for which painting-supports are
made.) The function of the whole painting, in
turn, is to be perceived as a painting, to give
human beings the perceptual experience that is
the experience of looking-at-a-painting, where the
painting, and not the illusion of space or the
figure of something in the world, is indeed what
is looked at and where, of course, this entire
complex of function, artifact, and experience is
constituted conventionally by a given society
with a given history. The functions of the physical support and its qualities, including flatness,
are definable only with reference to the function
of the full perceptual unity that is defined by this
history, or by a certain appropriation of it, as the
finished painting; and the form or essence of the
finished painting is the color-image that it
constitutes. In the final analysis, the objectness
of the painting is color (ibid.); all the physical
parts of which the painting is made are brought
into their unity of aesthetic form by their subordination to the color. This does not mean that
they are effaced, as was the tendency in representational painting. On the contrary, color is a
dimension of materiality and the radical painter is
not trying to detach it from materiality. Aristotle
defines color as the limit of the translucent in a
determinately bounded body. This is a superb
definition for the painter. It locates color within a
material (even though it is, in Aristotles concept,
the outermost part of a thing) and it implies the
limitation of its form as material (24). The color
of a painting, if it gives the rule to the physical
constituents, is itself bound to or determined by
their materiality (first of all, that of the paint) as
this materiality has historically evolved in relation
to the evolving function of painting. But the size
and shape and texture and absorptiveness of the
support, the relation to the wall, and so forth,
must co-operate in an overall perception, the decisive or ruling factor of which is color. Color is the
82
staten
essence of the painting in much the way that for
Aristotle the soul is the essence or form of the
body. Even though the form is in perception
detached from the material, substance or ousia is
embodied form; and the radical painting is ousia
as embodied color.
How can color be a form? A form is by definition bounded or what gives boundary; Aristotle
himself in the Poetics used the drawn line as a
paradigm of form, but the drawn line is one of
the remnants of representation that the radical
painter eschews in his search for openness. But
color becomes, or can become, a form when it
finds the absolutely specific, bounded body that
it reciprocally determines and is determined by.
There is no notional answer to the question of
how color can function as form, only the historical fact that certain painters have worked out an
aesthetic and a painting-practice that treats it as
such, and the proof is in the experience of their
work (or not).
83
radical painting
work that has been produced either on the basis
of this thesis or in a way that supports it, then one
can in principle have an aesthetic experience that
stands up to the experience one has had of the
aesthetic objects that have formed ones sense of
optimal aesthetic experience; but it is only as a
quite specific experience that one can have it.
Contrary to De Duve, it is not only not necessary
to judge this is art before one can judge this is
a painting, and a good one; it is necessary not to
do so (though one might go on to the generic
judgment afterwards, recognizing that one is now
switching language-games in so doing).
As in any other question of aesthetic experience, the judgment of quality in front of a radical painting is not a matter of deduction and it is
not compulsory. But Radical Painting has the
earmarks of a well-grounded and valid aesthetic
movement, and forces a reconsideration of questions that had seemed to be closed when it looked
as though the modernist logic had hit a dead end.
What all this betokens regarding the larger questions of the culture wars is a further question
that I will touch on below; for now what I want
to stress is that, if we are going to use modernism
as an example of anything on the way to a larger
argument, we should address it in its fullness as
a historically evolving phenomenon, along with
the most resourceful statement of its rationale or
theory; and this involves criticizing and rejecting Greenbergs own dogmatic theses and De
Duves interpretation of them.
Nevertheless, I want to pay tribute to the
scope and seriousness of Kant after Duchamp,
particularly because of the framework of sociopolitical reflection that gives point to De Duves
genealogical reconsideration of modernist
painting. My remarks here have focused on
narrowly aesthetic issues, and I recognize that
these issues may appear trivial compared to
the question of the cultural and political mission
of the artist, in the context of the great upheavals
of the twentieth century, which De Duve tries
to understand. I am especially troubled by the
problem of the esoteric nature of the
modernistformalist aesthetic I have defended
here, its seemingly elitist adherence to a refinement of aesthetic taste that can perhaps only ever
be the possession of a privileged few. I have no
84
staten
trouble keeping consistently in view in spite of
the modernist intervention. The continuing
significance of the thesis of specificity is for me
grounded in the indissociability it suggests of the
labor of the artist from the specific nature of his
medium in its complex, socially conditioned
materiality which is the same as the indissociability of art from its craft-aspect. The generic
judgment this is art is no doubt necessary in
the language-game that has developed around art
that intentionally wanders away from the
constraints of established, specific art-forms. As
I have tried to show in this essay, however, this
development does not mean that some generic
judgment of value has now superseded, wholly
and in all contexts, the modernist logic of specificity. Moreover, De Duves arguments that a
picture must be judged to be art before it can be
judged to be a picture, and that the judgment
this is beautiful is identical with the judgment
this is art, strike me as no friendlier to a
democratization of art and the creative process
than they are to the vacuous cult of art-fetishism
of which we already see signs in Kants almost
helpless awe before the inexplicability of genius,
and of which the only slightly more foolish
descendant is the contemporary worship of the
art-superstar. 13
In this essay I can only indicate the outlines
of the full theorization that Radical Painting
invites, and to which the current notion of the
conventionality of art practices is so inadequate.
The convergence once more at this late date in
history of the notions of art and craft requires a
rethinking of the entire history of the concept of
art as this history has been configured by the
evolutionary narrative of its emergence more
than once; in ancient Greece and again in the late
Middle Ages in its purity from a more generalized notion of making. Modernism is
commonly and rightly understood as the
final step in the emergence of the pure concept
of art, and Greenbergs ideas about the specificity of the individual arts are an important
chapter in the history of this emergence. Hence
the notion that Radical Painting is a continuation of the logic of modernism, yet an overcoming of the distinction between art and craft,
might seem paradoxical.
85
radical painting
pleasures of postmodern cultural aesthetics.
Nevertheless, there is something specific to the
painters, sculptors, musicians practice that
is also autotelic, or which might be so conceived,
and as so conceived made the basis of that practice, and to which justice can be done only by a
critical discourse that does not auto-authorize
itself but binds itself as tightly as possible to that
practice in the fullness of its conventional materiality.
Here I can only sketch the outlines of the full,
historically articulated account of human praxis
as a whole that would constitute a more adequate
account of artistic convention as grounded in
what I have been calling conventional materiality.16 Such an account would take as its fundamental reference points, on the one hand,
Aristotles analysis of the teleology of human
practices and, on the other hand, Marxs analysis
of human productive activity, that is human
labor as the foundational fact of social existence.
A fully articulated theory of conventional
materiality would begin with the beginnings of
human culture in order to excavate the residue of
fatality, the unpredictable system of limits, that
arises at the point of intersection of multiple acts
of individual exertion that are carried on within
a social context and leave their residue on the
physical world, long before the emergence of
even the most rudimentary arts and crafts, and
even before the advent of language. The most
primordial inscriptions on the world of these
residues are the rubbing clear of the ground
where a group of humans or proto-humans sits to
rest or lies down to sleep, of pathways where one
walks after the other, of trees stripped bare of
fruit around these inscribed areas so that the
people are constrained to move along, fraying
new paths and making new clearings. Here is the
beginning of history as the simple deposit of
accumulated acts within the context of sociality,
and the landscape is the incipiently socialized
materiality that serves as the support of this
inscription. Later on in history, as Marx observes
in The German Ideology, there will no longer be
any nature left; it will all have been absorbed into
the network of cultural inscription; in this earlier
period there is as yet nothing that can be called
a convention, and nevertheless there is already
86
staten
notes
1 The movement was formally baptized in the
public eye by a special issue of Kunstforum
International (Mar.Apr. 1987), edited by Amione
Haase, that focused on Radikale Malerei. Among
the pieces included in this issue are my Joseph
Marioni: Malerei Jenseits Narrativitt and articles
on Umberg and other German radical painters
who have continued to figure significantly: Ullrich
Wellman, Ingo Meller, and Peter Tollens.
2 See the essay on Umberg by Hannelore
Kersting, Painting as Articulated Paint, in the
catalogue to the exhibition Gunter Umberg,
Stdelsches Kunstinstitut Frankfurt, 1985.
3 Thierry De Duve, Kant after Duchamp
(Cambridge: MIT P, 1996). All citations of De
Duve refer to this volume.
4 All citations of Greenberg are to Clement
Greenberg: The Collected Essays and Criticism, vol. 4,
Modernism with a Vengeance (Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 1993).
5 Painting and picture are normally synonymous in
art-critical talk, and I wont object to this usage.
However, the idea that there can be an unpainted
picture seems to me to dissimulate an absurdity
that is patent in the phrase unpainted painting.
This absurdity that Greenberg created is exploited
at great length by De Duve, who buys into it
because it serves his purposes admirably.
6 Stedelijk Museum Catalog, 1975; quoted by
Sauer in Christel Sauer and Urs Rausmller (eds.),
Robert Ryman, catalog for Ryman exhibition in the
Espace dArt Contemporain, 1991, 31.
7 Joseph Marioni and Gnther Umberg, Outside the
Cartouche: Zur Frage des Betrachters in der Radikalen
Malerei. English and German; German trans.
Nikolaus Hoffmann and Rolf Taschen (Munich:
Neue Kunst, 1986). Umbergs work in the 1990s
took new directions; in this essay I refer only to
the period of his collaboration with Marioni.
8 Aristotle remarks in the Poetics, chapter 10, that
in a painting the most beautiful pigments smeared
on at random will not give as much pleasure as a
black-and-white outline picture. Aristotle, Poetics,
trans. Gerald Else (Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P)
28. And Kant comments in the Third Critique that
delineation is the essential thing in all the formative arts (61), and painting is the foremost of
these arts because as the art of delineation it lies
87
radical painting
never presented flatness and the inclosing of flatness as criteria of quality (66).
11 The conclusion that a painting must be painted,
obvious from the ordinary persons standpoint,
and which I am thus slightly embarrassed to draw,
has to be argued in the face of De Duves argument, which keeps alive Greenbergs suggestion
that a painting (or picture) need not be painted
(see n. 5 above).
12 See Graham Chester, Baudelaire and the Poetics
of Craft (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1988).
13 I say almost helpless because Kant does
choose the primacy of rules over mere undisciplined genius.
14 Yet another, deconstruction-based, development of the logic of specificity is that by Rosalind
Krauss, who in her reading of Marcel Broodthaers
argues that the specificity of mediums, even
modernist ones, must be understood as differential, self-differing, and thus as a layering of conventions never simply collapsed into the physicality of
their support. A Voyage on the North Sea: Art in
the Age of the Post-Medium Condition (New York:
Thames, 1999) 53. Although the artist she
discusses, and the theory she elaborates, are very
distant from Radical Painting, her essay, like mine,
rejects the vulgar idea of the medium as a layering of conventions simply collapsed into the
physicality of their support.
15 A Voyage on the North Sea 56.
16 The earliest stimulus to the interpretation
of Radical Painting, and the following reflections
on praxis, that I present here was a fascinating
essay by Lothar Romain on Analytical Painting,
a movement which I interpret as a precursor
of Radical Painting. See Lothar Romain, The
Artistic Truth of Things that Exist: Reflections
Pertaining to (the Theory of) Analytical Painting,
trans. Antony de Nardini and Paul Angus
in A Proposito della Pittura/Bettrefende Het
Schilderen/Concerning Painting, catalogue Museum
Van BommelVan Dam Venlo/Stedelijk Museum
Schiedam/Hedenaagse Kunst Utrecht 197576,
2732.
17 Georg Lukcs, The Ontology of Social Being:
Labour (London: Merlin, 1980) 3. This volume is a
translation of the first chapter of Part Two of the
larger work.
Henry Staten
Department of English
University of Washington
Box 35436
Seattle, WA 98195
USA
E-mail: [email protected]
He jotted down this thought, if it can be called that, on a loose sheet of paper, hoping to use it later,
perhaps in some pondered statement about the mystery of writing which will probably culminate, following the definitive lessons of the poet, in the precise and sober declaration that the mystery of writing lies in the absence of any mystery whatsoever, which if accepted, might lead us to the conclusion
that if there is no mystery about writing, neither can there be any mystery about the writer.
89