Stanford Law Review Stanford Law Review: This Content Downloaded From 14.139.209.68 On Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
Stanford Law Review Stanford Law Review: This Content Downloaded From 14.139.209.68 On Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
Stanford Law Review Stanford Law Review: This Content Downloaded From 14.139.209.68 On Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Stanford Law Review is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Stanford Law
Review
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Julius Stone, Professor of Law at the University of Sydney, is a disciple of the late Roscoe Pound who is generally acclaimed as the founder
of having adopted the terms "nomostatic" and "nomodynamic"-as characteristics of two different
characterized the part of the doctrine dealing with the problems of the validity of the State-Order
as a legal order (Geltung der Staatsordnung) as Statik (p. 93) and the part dealing with the problems of the creation of the State-Order (Erzeugung der Staatsordnung) as Dynamik (p. 227); and
in the first edition of my Reine Rechtslehre (1934) I spoke of 'eine dynamische zum Unterschied
von einer statischen Theorie des Rechts.' 'Statik' and 'Dynamik' are terms generally used to indicate a system in the state of rest in contradistinction to a system in motion. The terms 'nomostatic'
and 'nomodynamic,' which are used in my General Theory of Law and State (1945), designate this
difference with respect to systems of norms. When I made this distinction I did not know a work
of John Henry Wigmore (not Henry Wigmore) in which these terms are used. Only after I read
Professor Stone's statement did I examine Wigmore's writings and found in his Panorama of the
World's Legal Systems (1936) on pages 1120, 1121 the terms 'Nomology,' 'Nomoscopy,' 'Nomothetics,' 'Nomogenetics,' but not the terms 'nomostatic' and 'nomodynamic.' When Professor Stone
was asked with reference to his above-quoted statement where the terms 'nomostatic' and 'nomodynamic' can be found in Wigmore's writings, he did not refer to Wigmore's writings but to Albert
Kocourek, An Introduction to the Science of Law (1930). There Kocourek says on pp. 63-64:
'Dean Wigmore has created a new classification of materials of legal science'; and-without quoting
any writing of Wigmore-Kocourek presents a terminology of this new classification. Under the
heading 'Nomology' he mentions sixteen compound terms whose first part is 'nomo' (from vouoc:
1128
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
* Dr. Jur. 1928, Vienna; J.D. 1941, University of Chicago; LL.M. 1942,
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ence between legal and moral norms, and that I maintained that the
specific difference is that the legal norms are norms prescribing a certain
human behavior by attaching to the contrary behavior a coercive act as
a sanction. According to the Pure Theory of Law the internal characteristic of the legal norm is that it stipulates a coercive act.' In my Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre9 I designated the sanctions of punishment
and civil execution as the characteristic elements of the norms of national
law. Professor Stone may not agree with this doctrine, but he has no
reason to object that the Pure Theory of Law does not indicate the specific difference between legal and other norms. Besides, Professor Stone
quotes a sentence of one of my writings in which I define the concept
of law "as a coercive order, that is to say as an order prescribing coercive
acts as sanctions."'0 And in open contradiction to his statement that the
Pure Theory of Law does not refer to any internal characteristic of each
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
the legal science whose object is legal norms. Already in my Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre (i9ii) I distinguished between the law,
i.e., norms whose essence is to stipulate that something ought to be done,
and the science of law whose object is norms.'6 Professor Stone says that
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
of Law "bind" the judge "in the way in which legal norm
proper role." And he adds: "It has taken a long time for W
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ence of law describes its object, the legal norms. I said: "These statements, by means of which the science of law represents law, must not be
confused with the norms created by the law-making authorities."" And
in the following section, under the title "Rule of Law and Law of Nature," I said: "The rule of law, the term used in a descriptive sense, is a
hypothetical judgment attaching certain consequences to certain conditions."34 In this sentence I referred expressly to the descriptive statements
about legal norms, and not to the prescriptive legal norms which must
be distinguished from the former. I compared the "rules of law," that is,
the hypothetical judgments by which the science of law describes its object, the legal norms, with the hypothetical judgments, the so-called laws
of nature, by which the science of nature describes its object,35 in order
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
59. REINE REcHrsLEHRE 10-15, 48-51, 78, 82, 91-93, 208, 212, 215-21, 279-80 (2d ed.
1960).
60. Id. at 215.
61. Id.at 82.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
one." I have never declared that I can tell nothing about the
origin of the basic norm. About no other problem have I sa
as about the basic norm. In the "Index" of my General Th
and State I refer to more than twenty different pages and i
constitution in the sense of positive law that the basic norm refe
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
from all that is said before about the basic norm as "th
86. DAS PROBLEM DER SOUVERXNITXT UND DIE THEORIE DES V6LKERREC
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
103. GENERAL THEORY OF LAW AND STATE 114 (1945). (Emphasis added.)
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The static and the dynamic principle are contained in one and
of positive norms, if the presupposed basic norm, according
principle, only authorizes a norm-creating authority, and if t
the authorities instituted by it establish not only norms whi
norm-creating authorities but also norms prescribing a defi
individuals subjected to the norms.'05
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
112. Id.at124-25.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
to be presupposed. Each of these different basic norms refers to a different positive constitution. What is common to all these basic norms is that
they refer to a positive legal constitution on the basis of which a positive
normative coercive order is established which is by and large effective.
All this stands to reason and has been questioned only by Professor Stone,
norms. "113
5. What does Kelsen mean by calling the "basic norm" a "hypothesis" or "a
hypothetical norm"? Are these the same thing? Or are they only related but
not identical notions? Or the same notion applied to different entities? Or
both of these?"14
There cannot be the slightest doubt about my view that the basic norm
-if presupposed to be valid-refers to the norms of a legal order and
113. Id. at 108.
114. Id.at125.
115. Ibid.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
opinion that the positive legal norms are "not the conce
prudent or lawyer," I am forced to doubt the objectiv
cism. This doubt is confirmed also by other passages in P
"pure" refers to the theory of law, not to the law; the law is not "pure," only
be "pure." That the Kelsenite system, as Professor Stone interprets Bustamante
moves to the point when even legal norms strictu sensu "seem to be exclud
and ideological," LEGAL SYSTEM AND LAWYERS' REASONINGS 109 (1964), is in
fact that I again and again emphasize that the Pure Theory of Law is a theor
mante's sentence: "Only the contentless content of formal juridical logic is fre
stigma and can be pure." Whether this is correct is here of no importance. Pro
it, gives the impression that Bustamante's attitude towards the Pure Theory
his-Stone's-rejection of this theory. This, however, is not true. Bustamante
with the greatest respect. See, eg., De Bustamante y Montoro, supra at 50.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
to a "tertium quid" which I-as he says-"ruled out as 'logically impossible.'" "This tertium quid is that, as between the international legal
order and a particular national order, primacy may simply be determined
by the legal order which has the question before it."'' But Professor
Stone ignores the fact that if a national legal order presents itself as sovereign it cannot recognize the other national legal orders as sovereign,
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
that State and law are identical, characterizing the State as a specific
legal order.'30 On page 289, I said under the heading, "The Identity of
State and Law":
In order to be a State the legal order must have the character of an organization
in the specific sense of this term, that is to say: it must institute special organs
for the creation and application of the norms which form this order; it must
exhibit a certain degree of centralization. The State is a relatively centralized
legal order.
of labor; and this normative order constituting this community is the legal
order, which, in contradistinction to the international legal order, is called national legal order.
On page go:
If we say that a certain community is constituted by a normative order regulating the mutual behavior of individuals we must be aware that order and
community are not two different objects but one and the same object, that the
community is nothing else but this order; and that what is common to the
individuals of which we say that they form, or belong to, a community, is
nothing else but the normative order regulating their mutual behavior.
nity and corporation, and which shows that there is no essential differ129. Id. at 118.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
132. Ibid.
133. Id. at'107.
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
legal order constituting the State," the relation of "the State legal order" to a
corporate person is different from its relation "to human individuals upon
whom it imposes duties and confers rights." The former is a relation of "a
total to a partial legal order," corporate by-laws being a case of delegation.'39
It is clear that the last statement, "it is a case of delegation," refers only
to the relationship between the law of the State and the bylaws of the
corporation. In case of a juristic person the law of the State delegates
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 14.139.209.68 on Wed, 07 Sep 2016 18:41:24 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms