Moral Philosophy and Social Work Policy

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 14
At a glance
Powered by AI
The key takeaways are that moral philosophies like Paternalism, Consequentialism, and Deontology influence social policies and views on individual responsibility and social control. Paternalism focuses on protecting individuals, Consequentialism considers outcomes of actions, and Deontology judges actions themselves.

Paternalism believes society should protect those who cannot make good decisions themselves. Consequentialism judges actions based on their outcomes/consequences. Deontology believes people should be judged based on their actions themselves, not outcomes. They differ on when and how much society can control individuals.

Soft Paternalism in US policies only overrides individual rights when people are incompetent or coerced, like in situations of coerced treatment evaluation. Paternalism is also applied under assumptions of intervener knowledge and preventing harm to self/others.

J Soc Work Values Ethics. Author manuscript; available in PMC Oct 1, 2010.

Published in final edited form as:


J Soc Work Values Ethics. Oct 1, 2009; 6(3): 136.
PMCID: PMC2859451
NIHMSID: NIHMS143625

Moral Philosophy and Social Work Policy


Amanda Reiman, MSW PhD
Author information Copyright and License information

Abstract
Go to:
1. Introduction
In all categories of policy- making, morality plays a role. Environmental policy, tax policy and social
policies all develop with a backdrop of moral philosophy. Beliefs about responsibility and personal rights
often weave their way into legislation. In social welfare, this link can be blatant and far- reaching. When
decisions are being made concerning policies and programs for human beings, the fact that people can
play a role in their own destiny sparks the debate about the size and power of that role. Some, such as
John Stuart Mill, feel that individuals should remain in complete control of their lives and the paths they
choose to take based on individual circumstances. Others believe that it is the job of those with strong
moral beliefs to guide and protect those who have lost their way (Reid, 1981). An argument further
exists as to when others should step in and try to change a persons desired behavior against their will.
These discussions often occur as a reaction to deviant behavior committed by an individual or group.
Three moral philosophies, Paternalist, Consequentialist and Deontological, provide theories of the role of
the will of man and social control in the evolution of society. At the heart of these philosophies are
differing beliefs about under what conditions society should demand a man relinquish his free will for the
good of the people and whether he should be judged by the consequences of his actions, or the actions
themselves.
Go to:
2. The Regulation of Deviant Behavior: Paternalism, Consequentialism and Deontology
Behavior that exists outside the norms of a society is often subject to regulation. Which behaviors are
chosen and how they are regulated can be influenced by the moral philosophies held by society. Three
philosophies that often contribute to the identification and regulation of deviant behaviors in the United
States are Paternalism, Consequentialism and Deontology.
Theories of Paternalism state that individuals are responsible for preventing others from harming
themselves or other people. The word paternalism comes from the word paternal for father. Indeed,
Aristotle described Paternalism as an extension of a family. In this way, Paternalism can be viewed much

as a parent-child relationship. A parent is responsible for ensuring that their child does not harm
themselves. Furthermore, if a child harms another person, it is the parent who is ultimately responsible
(New, 1999). Another aspect of Paternalism states that the intervener is logically more adept,
knowledgeable and a better judge of welfare than the person being Paternalized (Leonerd, Goldfarb and
Suranovic, 2000). Many social policies in the United States contain a type of Paternalism called Soft
Paternalism. In this view, a persons rights should only be overlooked when they are incompetent,
incapacitated or coerced (Leonard, Goldfarb and Suranovic, 2000). This view of Paternalism complicates
social welfare issues such as coerced treatment, when a persons competence might be subjective. In this
case, the question of whether to force some one into treatment might be evaluated in either a
Consequentialist or Deontological nature, which will be discussed later. As far as situations where
Paternalism is warranted, consideration is sometimes given to the role of the intervener (New, 1999).
Paternalism assumes that the paternalized person is unable to make a healthy decision and that intervener
is capable of making a better decision.New (1999) provides three situations in which a person might not
be able to make as sound a decision as the intervener. First, when the individual faces a weakness of
will, meaning that temptation might prevent an individual from making a decision in their best interest.
This situation is the most subjective. Secondly, in situations when the person making the decision has
little first hand information to aid them in arriving at a decision. Third, complicated situations in which
the intervener can provide specific and specialized knowledge.
While Paternalism focuses on the right of those with knowledge, power and ability to interfere in the lives
of those deemed to be harming themselves or others, Consequentialist and Deontological Theories center
around whether the decision to interfere should be based on the persons actions or the consequences of
their actions. Therefore, both Consequentialist and Deontological Theories can be carried out
Paternalistically.
Consequentialist policies are concerned with the consequences of the behavior in question, rather than the
behavior itself. The term for this is agent-neutral. Consider, as an example, the act of driving drunk and
hitting a neighbors mailbox. A Consequentialist would argue that the only crime committed was
destruction of property. In this case, the action of drinking and driving is neutral in deciding the outcome.
Rather, it is the consequence of hitting the mailbox that calls for punishment (Louise, 2004).
Consequentialist theory can be described as focusing on the consequences of a persons actions when
deciding whether to intervene. Two questions arise when considering this theory: 1) consequences for
whom? and 2) what kinds of consequences? Part of Consequentialism considers who benefits or suffers
from the consequences. To this end, there are two competing theories. Egoism states that decisions should
be made based on the consequences for the individual, regardless of the consequences to others. By
contrast, Utilitarianism contends that decisions should be made based on the consequences for society,
regardless of personal sacrifice. Both of these theories are considered Consequentialist because they focus
on the consequences of actions, rather than on the actions themselves (Scheffler, 1994). A second aspect
of Consequentialism examines what kind of consequences result from a decision. Arguments exist within
Consequentialism as to what consequences are the ultimate aims. Hedonic Consequentialism claims net
pleasure to be the ultimate consequence. A variation on this is Eudaimonic Consequentialism, which has
the stated goal of happiness. Some Consequentialist theories have the goals of material equality or
personal liberty (such as John Stuart Mill). In these cases, actions are taken to achieve these goals,
regardless of other, less important consequences (Scheffler, 1988). An example of current

Consequentialist policies in the U.S. is gun laws. It is not illegal to own a gun, as long as the
consequences of that ownership do not involve crime. It is not the action of owning a gun or firing a gun
that is illegal, rather it is the consequence of shooting some one or something or committing a crime with
a gun that breaks the law.
In contrast to Consequentialist Theory, Deontological Theory focuses on the innate morality of the actions
themselves, regardless of the consequences. In Deontological Theory, lying is wrong, even if it is done to
bring about good consequences. As previously mentioned, Consequentialist Theory is agent-neutral while
Deontological Theory is agent-relative. That is, in Deontological Theory, it is the action of the agent that
is important, rather than the consequence of that action (Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2004). Consider
again the example of drunken driving policy. This policy is Deontological in nature because it is not only
the consequences of drunk driving that are illegal, but also the act of driving drunk itself, on the premise
that it is an inherently wrong, agent-centered action. One of the biggest proponents of Deontological
Theory is Immanuel Kant. Kant introduced the idea of the categorical imperative. This idea maintains that
a persons motives for their actions should be acceptable as universal law. That is, people should act on
motives that can be used by everyone in a moral society (Darwell, 2002). For example, a persons motive
for going to work should be such that if everyone adopted that same motive it would be acceptable in
society. Therefore, if a persons motive for going to work is to provide for their family, it would be an
acceptable motive for everyone to have. On the other hand, if a persons motive for going to work is to
steal from the company, even if it is justified in that particular case, it does not matter because it is not an
acceptable motive for everyone in the work force to have.
Deontological theorists believe that having the correct motive and action is preferable over achieving the
desired outcome. However, this notion of an acceptable motive lends itself to judgment and subjectivity.
Furthermore, deontology leaves little room for adjusting the action to fit the situation. One criticism of
Deontological policy-making is the power to decide what is inherently right. Deontological theories often
find their way into so-called victimless crime policies. These policies, revolving around unacceptable
private behavior only consider the behavior itself, regardless of the consequences. If a person uses drugs,
even if the only negative consequence is to them, deontics would view the drug use as inherently wrong
and would therefore encourage policies prohibiting drug use. Sodomy laws are another example of
Deontological policies. The private behavior of consenting adults is prohibited due to the belief that the
behavior is inherently wrong.
Another aspect of Deontological policy is that the context in which the behavior occurs is not taken into
consideration. This rule often softens even the most rigid Deontic believers in extreme situations. For
example, although Deontological Theory holds that killing an innocent person is inherently wrong,
modern Deontological theorists maintain that killing an innocent person might be acceptable if it is in the
context of preventing a catastrophe. Furthermore, Deontological theorists recognize that moral obligations
have a ranking order, even among several inherently right options, in the context of the situation
(Haydar, 2002). To this end, Consequentialist and Deontological Theories disagree as to the best method
of making a decision. Consequentialist Theory dictates that to make a decision, all the alternatives are laid
out and the decision that leads to the intended consequence is chosen. In Deontological Theory, there is an
innate right answer for any decision, so laying out alternatives is not necessary (Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, 2004).

At the heart of the differences in moral philosophy is the argument about whether it is the consequence or
the action that is most important. Consequentialists maintain that it is the consequence that should be
considered when making a decision. This can be a consequence for an individual (egoism) or a
consequence for society (utilitarianism). The consequence can also be psychological in nature, such as
happiness, or principled in nature, such as personal liberty. Consequentialist policies, such as gun control,
often develop laws based on the consequences of actions, not the actions themselves. On the opposite end,
Deontological theorists insist that it is the action itself that should be the focus. Furthermore, deontics
believe that each action is inherently good or bad, although modern deontics allow some exceptions based
on the magnitude of the situation and the order of importance among competing moral values. One major
criticism of this is, again, that it is up to those in power to decide what is inherently right or wrong and
legislate accordingly, often criminalizing private, consensual behavior on the grounds of morality and a
societal or political definition of deviance. Each of these theories can be carried out in a Paternalistic way.
That is, both Consequentialist and Deontological policies can incorporate different levels of intervention
and different levels of coercion within the intervention. The second part of this paper will focus on how
these philosophies play out across three areas of social policy around deviant behavior: welfare, drugs,
and sexual behavior.
Go to:
3. Social Policy
Social policy development encompasses problem identification and definition, and policy design and
implementation. Before considering how moral philosophy plays into the development of social policies,
it is important to differentiate between two ways of defining social policy. Social policies can be activities
of Federal and local governments, such as laws or programs that are aimed at improving the well being of
members of society (Jansson, 1999). Sometimes social policies are aimed at the general population, such
as drug laws, and sometimes they are designed for a particular segment of the population, such as
disability insurance. The population for which the policy is intended can influence the philosophy on
which the policy is based and the level of paternalism with which the policy or program is carried out.
This influence is the second part of defining social policy. Social policies can also refer to the
authoritative distribution of values. How a social problem is defined and what determines the success of
a social policy is often determined by the values of those in power that design and implement the policy.
Therefore, social policies are both legislative actions and reflections of the values and morals of those
who design the policy. For example, welfare policies are legislative acts of government. However,
stipulations for receiving aid and the funds allocated to ensure the quality and success of welfare
programs reflect the ideas of right living held by those who created the policies: ie. marriage, stable
employment, owning a house, and no drug use. Furthermore, the lack of program funding and strong
paternalistic nature of these policies speaks to the underlying idea that vulnerable members of society do
not deserve as much as the rest of society and are applicable to the enactment of soft paternalism, even
though they might be adults of sound mind and body (Leonard, Goldfarb and Suranovic, 2000). Indeed,
how social problems are identified and operationalized is also influenced by underlying moral
philosophies. Why is drug use ok if a doctor prescribes it and not if a person decides to use it on their
own? There is a commonly held belief that drug use is dangerous, doctors are experts, and dangerous
activities should only be done under the watch of an expert. This situation would fall under News
(1999) criteria for the use of Paternalism. However, if this is true, then why is alcohol ok to use without a

doctors note, when it too is dangerous? This example shows that within social policies lie conflicting
messages about right and wrong. This conflict stems from the influence of moral philosophy on the
identification and definition of social problems. If laws concerning the use of drugs were based solely on
the scientific research concerning their harm to the user and society, they would look very different than
the laws that exist today.
Regardless of how a social problem is defined, the subsequent policy has elements designed to ensure
compliance. These elements can be normative or coercive. Moral philosophy can influence which type of
compliance tool is used. When a policy is designed to encourage behavior deemed desirable by those in
power, normative compliance tools are used, which reward the individual for engaging the desired
behavior. Examples would be tax credits for being married and having children, and access to the carpool
lane for hybrid vehicles. When a policy is designed to discourage behaviors deemed unacceptable by
those in power, coercive, and therefore paternalistic, elements are used. For example, those who receive
public housing can lose it if they are caught using drugs, and students can lose their college funding if
they incur a drug conviction. The act of rewarding those who engage in desirable behaviors, and
punishing and controlling those who engage in undesirable behaviors, and rely on the government for
aid, reflects the influence of moral philosophies in controlling behavior.
Go to:
4. Moral Philosophy in the Development of Social Policies that Address Deviant Behavior
Now that Paternalism, Consequentialism and Deontological Theory have been discussed in relation to
their definitions and role in social policy; and the issues surrounding the definitions of social problems
and the development of such policies have been explored, the next section of the paper looks at three
specific and often controversial issues in social welfare dealing with perceived deviant behavior. These
issues are examined with respect to how current policies reflect the moral philosophies discussed in the
first section. The three areas are: welfare policy, drug policy and sexual policies.
The Deontological basis for welfare policy can be traced back to the idea of the deserving poor. This
idea maintains that certain people deserve aid due to physical, emotional or psychological impairment.
Those deemed unimpaired are expected to be able to pull themselves up and succeed without extra
assistance. This ideal has prevailed in current welfare policy. Those who apply for public aid but are not
on disability are labeled as lazy and irresponsible. Welfare to work programs are a way of asking that
population to prove their worth by fulfilling work and other welfare-related requirements. These
requirements send a message to recipients that society will not support them unless they pay a penalty.
What is commonly overlooked is the idea that many welfare recipients cannot hold stable employment
due to family status, completely unrelated to responsibility and laziness (Reamer, 1982; Rainford,
2004). Rainford (2004) conducted a qualitative study (n=30) looking at the barriers that exist for welfare
recipients that keep them from completing work requirements. The barriers identified included domestic
violence, lack of education, health issues, lack of child care/transportation, no case - worker and
communication disconnect. Furthermore, the sanctions put in place after failure to complete work
requirements did not have an effect on future requirements. In this case, a Deontological approach is
expressed in a punitive and retributive manner, enforcing the agent-relative status of the policy.

The barriers mentioned above are all considered consequences of both poverty and system involvement.
If sanctions are imposed for agent-relative behavior (ie: completing work requirements, staying sober,
making meetings, etc.) while ignoring the consequences, then the policies are directed at punishing and
changing personal behavior, in a coercive way, by an agent of change deemed more adept than the
recipient. Current welfare policy can be described as Deontological, its provision Paternalistic in nature.
In 1996, welfare reform brought about work and time requirements as motives for recipients to get off
welfare and enter the working world within a certain amount of time (Fellowes and Rowe, 2004). This
illustrates the belief that not working is a deviant behavior that is not allowed in this society. Moral
philosophy has informed welfare policy at both an organizational and individual level. Paternalism, in the
philosophical sense, is defined by a non-consensual intervention in which the intent is to stop harmful
behavior and the intervener is deemed more adept than the subject of the intervention. However, when
discussing welfare policy, Paternalism is defined as social policies aimed at the poor that attempt to
reduce poverty and other social problems by directive and supervisory means (Mead, 1997, 2). It is these
directive and supervisory means that take on a Paternalistic tone. As previously mentioned, a policy can
be either Consequentialist or Deontological and be carried out Paternalistically (although Deontological
policies often lend themselves more easily to Paternalistic provision). In the case of welfare policy, the
requirements set forth by the government in exchange for public assistance are Paternalistic in nature. The
intervention may, however, be viewed as consensual, since the welfare recipient agrees to these
requirements. But, if fulfilling the requirements is the only means by which aid can be received, then the
agreement cannot be recognized as fully consensual. If current welfare policy IS intended to be
Deontological in nature, as many suggest (Kaplow and Shavell, 2004; Wilson, Stoker and McGrath,
1999; Rainford, 2004; Fellowes and Rowe, 2004 andReamer, 1982) does the Paternalistic provision
overshadow the moral intent? One criticism of an over-reaching Paternalistic welfare system is that too
many requirements lead to the disruption of the moral message intended by a Deontological policy. The
assertion is that the time spent between welfare recipients and case- workers filling out forms distracts
from the ability of the caseworker to act as a moral role model, if that is indeed their intended role.
Supposing that welfare case workers ARE proposed moral leaders as suggested by Wilson et al (1999),
the Paternalistic requirements associated with welfare policy distract workers from providing guidance
and knowledge, one of the requirements of a Paternalistic intervention.
Fellowes and Howe (2004) provide a thought provoking discussion on the possible ways that individual
states can adopt either Consequentialist or Deontological policies regarding aid distribution. These
theories are all acted out in a Paternalistic manner, as described above. First Fellowes and Howe discuss
the reproductive behavior of recipients and its effect on aid distribution. If reproductive behavior,
operationalized by the number of unwed births, increases in a state, the state can react Deontologically
and restrict aid and increase requirements to send a message that the immoral behavior of having a child
out of wedlock will be punished. However, reproductive behavior can also result in a Consequentialist
situation in which, in response to rising out of wedlock births, the state increases aid and relaxes
requirements as to address the consequence of having a greater number of children in the system. This
moral crossroads can also be seen in relation to a states level of welfare dependency. Like reproduction,
dependency can lead to the reduction of benefits to punish the increase in immoral behavior, or an
increase in benefits to deal with the consequences of greater dependency (Soss, Schram, Vartarian and

OBrien, 2001). In addition to welfare policies, drug policies in the United States are also derived from
the legislation of morality.
The War on Drugs has been the motivation for drug policies developed during the past 40 years. This
punitive approach calls for the imprisonment of drug users and long, mandatory sentences for drug
sellers. Furthermore, drug users are portrayed as deviants by the media and the government and the
normalization of drug use is forbidden (Duster, 1970). U.S. drug policy is heavily Deontological and is
presented within a Paternalistic framework. The punishments for drug use often disregard the
consequences of that use when deciding the punishment. This is not the same thing as the punishment for
a car accident increasing in severity if drugs are involved, but rather the punishment for using the drug
itself. If a person is walking erratically in a park and is stopped and searched by police, the discovery of
drugs would likely lead to an arrest, even if the consequence for using the drugs has yet to be determined.
Rather, the agent-relative act of drug use and possession is the crime. This follows a Deontological
perspective. A Consequentialist policy would not place the person under arrest unless the consequence of
the drug use infringed on the rights of others. In the example given above, a Consequentialist policy
would allow the person to possess drugs and walk erratically in the park. However, if the person
destroyed anothers property or assaulted someone, that would be grounds for arrest, again, not because of
the role of the drugs, but rather the consequence of the situation. Today, drug policy seeks to legislate the
moral behavior of individuals by imposing illegality on the consumption of certain substances and not
others, rather than legislating negative consequences, no matter what the antecedent.
After a person is arrested for drug use, the system takes on a paternalistic role. The authorities offer the
offender choices concerning their punishment, sometimes offering a deal for information, sometimes
offering treatment. In each case, the assumption is that the offender needs the help of the authorities and
that the authorities know what is best for the offender. Even though the threat of jail prevents the
cooperation of individuals and authorities from being consensual, soft Paternalists would argue that a
drug addicted person is not capable of making decisions in their best interest, therefore it is alright for the
authorities to intervene in a non-consensual manner. Many drug-related paternalistic policies intersect
with social welfare. Stipulations for receiving food stamps, public aid, public housing and employment
involve a person being free of drug related charges and not using drugs. This paternalistic design ensures
that in order to receive an intervention from the system, the recipient must follow the rules set forth
concerning drug use. This is also Deontological in that it is up to the agent (agent-relative) to behave
appropriately, rather than up to the system (agent-neutral) to help the agent identify choices for achieving
the desired consequence. If this were the case, drug use would only become an issue if it stood in the way
from the agent following through on what has been identified as the best course of action, therefore
putting the desired consequence in jeopardy.
Those involved in researching and constructing drug policy often differ on where the intervention should
occur. The current drug control strategy focuses on intervening at the agent level, by prohibiting use,
intercepting drug shipments and making a drug free life a stipulation for receiving many benefits from the
Federal government. In 2001, 55% of Federal inmates were incarcerated on drug charges. In state prisons,
20.4% of all inmates were drug offenders (Harrison and Beck, 2003). This process is, by definition,
Deontological, due to the focus on the actions of the agent, rather than the consequences of those actions.
The other group of researchers, policy makers and scholars in the drug arena seek to intervene in a
Consequentialist manner, by focusing their interventions around harm reduction and treatment. Harm

reduction, the act of minimizing the harmful consequences of a behavior, exists outside of the realm of
drug policy. Wearing a seatbelt, a helmet or a condom are all harm reduction strategies, aimed at
minimizing the potential harm of a car accident, bike accident, or sexual experience. Similarly, services
such a needle exchange centers and Ecstasy testing at raves seek to minimize the harm that might result
from drug use. The common reaction from Deontologists when faced with harm reduction strategies is
that they send the wrong message. This insinuates that by accepting that people are going to use drugs
and trying to minimize harmful consequences, it sends the moral message that drug use is OK, which
strongly contradicts their Deontological message about the innate wrong or mala in se of drug use.
One scholar who supports this notion of Deonotological drug policy is Jerome Skolnick. Skolnick
(1992) presents the two sides of drug policy presented above in terms of mala in se, drug use as a
natural or moral wrong and mala prohibitum a regulatory issue. Skolnick argues that the current drug
control strategy in the U.S. is based on the principle of mala in se. To support this idea, he refers to the
first National Drug Control Strategy, written in 1989, in which then President George Bush referred to
drug use as a sign of deficient moral character and a weakness of will. Furthermore, the strategy called for
an increase of $1.5 billion dollars for both the enforcement and interdiction arms of drug control, but only
$321 million for treatment and $250 million for education. Again, this puts the emphasis on punishing the
personal decision to use drugs, rather than attempt to lessen the negative consequences of drug use.
Skolnick suggests that a Consequentialist drug policy would look very different, relying on a more
evidence-based approach, in which great care would be taken to determine the most effective method for
addressing the negative societal consequences of drug use, rather than trying to control individual
behavior with the threat of imprisonment or the denial of Federal aid.
Another framework in this area suggests that although those in favor of harsh penalties for drug use often
cite morality, they cannot be ruled out as Consequentialists. MacCoun and Reuter (2001) explore this idea
by looking at the full arguments of typically deontological policy makers and scholars, such as former
Drug Czar William Bennett and author James Q. Wilson. While both Bennett and Wilson have cited moral
repugnance for drug use, they often provide Consequentialist reasons for their feelings, such as the affect
that drug abuse has on the family and the community. However, MacCoun and Reuter conclude that even
though some moral anti-drug arguments are backed with the inherent consequences of drug use, the
policies surrounding drugs and their use in society still come from a place of personal morality and
responsibility. It is my belief that if Bennett and Wilson truly believe that the negative consequences of
drug use should be the primary rationale for their legal status, there would not be as much support for
punishing users and sellers, rather funding would be channeled to programs and policies directed at
reducing the negative consequences of drug use on the family and community and the rigorous and
constant evaluation of their effectiveness.
Similarly to drug policies, the inherent question concerning sexual policies surrounds the legislation of an
act that is consensual based on its view by some as immoral. Deviance from the traditional structure of
a monogamous marriage between a man and a woman has elicited a backlash from religious groups and
many Republicans, including President Bush, who favors a Constitutional amendment to prevent
deviant sexual behavior. Legislation against homosexuality, gay marriage and prostitution are based in
the Deontological argument that sexual acts of this manner are mala in se, natural wrongs. Sexual
behavior is another arena where harm reduction has played a role in attempting to inject some
Consequentialist programs into a Deontological policy. Other countries have embraced the role of harm

reduction in their sexual policies. Countries such as Amsterdam provide services for prostitutes such as
AIDS testing and condoms in the hopes of preventing disease and unplanned pregnancy. Again, in the
United States, services such as condom distribution are seen as sending the wrong message. Just as with
drugs, the stance is that addressing the consequences of sexual actions rather than the decision to engage
in the act is somehow saying to society that the act is ok. This is an argument often heard in respect to
giving teens access to condoms. A Deontologist would argue that premarital sex is morally wrong, and to
give out condoms is saying otherwise. A Consequentialist would note that if unplanned pregnancy or
disease is a possible consequence of sexual activity, addressing and trying to prevent those consequences
through means proven effective (condoms) is the best course of action for the good of society. Legislation
and policies surrounding sexual behavior bring up issues about privacy and the role of a Paternalistic
system.
As previously mentioned, in a Paternalistic policy there exists an unequal relationship between those in
power and those who need to be helped. Soft Paternalists qualify the need to be helped as someone who is
a minor, weak willed or otherwise unable to make their own decisions. The premarital sex issue speaks to
this because of the involvement of minors. However, the issue becomes cloudier when dealing with
consensual acts between adults, such as homosexuality or prostitution. First, a note, it is in no way my
intention to equate prostitution with homosexuality or to insinuate that they are similar acts, rather, they
are both examples of sexual acts with differing and subjective measures of consensuality.
The notion of Paternalism that the agent is somehow weak willed and in need of intervention is held up
by the claim that homosexuality is a choice and not an innate quality. For those who believe the choice
model, it is easy to justify why a Paternalistic intervention might be necessary. For those who support the
notion that one is born homosexual, it is difficult to understand the rationale for legislating private
behavior between two consenting adults who are more than capable of making their own decisions.
Similarly to homosexuality, the Paternalistic nature of legislation against prostitution assumes that the
prostitute is weak willed and unable to decide for themselves what is right. This follows directly with the
Deontological argument that prostitution is mala in se and the very fact that a woman chooses to engage
in prostitution shows her incompetence and therefore calls for an intervention by the system. Another
aspect of Paternalism is using misinformation or withholding information as long as it supports the
message of the Paternalist. In his book, The Legislation of Morality, Duster (1970), refers to a TV movie
entitled Never on Sunday, which was banned many places in the United States. This was not due to
sexually explicit content; rather, it was banned because of its portrayal of a prostitute as a compassionate
person with feelings and morals. To show a prostitute with character would have violated both the
Deontological idea that someone cannot be a moral person if they engage in what is considered an
immoral act and the Paternalistic notion that prostitutes are capable of making strong willed, informed
decisions about their well being without professional intervention.
Go to:
5. Implications for Social Work
Moral philosophy plays a role in policy formation, but how does moral philosophy intersect with the
profession of social work? Social work often addresses societys deviant behaviors and seeks to integrate
those classified as deviant by society into healthy, happy lifestyles. On the macro level, moral

philosophy helps shape social work as a profession. On the micro level, moral philosophy connects with
social work practice around specific issues, such as coercion. While the client side of social welfare
focuses more on avoiding negative consequences and generating viable alternatives, the professional side
of social work is more ambiguous as to whether the appropriate course of action is agent-relative or
agent-neutral.
The profession of social work follows both Deontological and Consequentialist philosophies. Reamer
(1982)identifies three questions that guide the social work profession and its associated ethics:
authoritative, distributive and substantive. These three areas can come into conflict with one another,
presenting ethical dilemmas for social workers. The authoritative question asks how social workers know
when and how to intervene in a clients life. Reamer points out that there are many reasons why a social
worker might intervene. There are three classifications of factors that might influence the decision to
intervene: technical, empirical and ethical. The technical reasons are highly Consequentialist, such as a
successful consequence with another client in a similar situation, or specific knowledge about the
effectiveness of a particular intervention. The empirical reasons for intervention are also Consequentialist
and based on research and program evaluation. Ethical reasons for intervention are Deontological, such as
a disagreement with the morals and practices of a client. Reamer claims that a social worker cannot rely
on any one way to make the decision to intervene. Rather, the contribution of each type of decision should
be weighed and looked at in terms of its effect on the client. For example, social work research may show
that condom distribution in schools lowers the pregnancy and disease rates of sexually active teens.
However, this contribution of empiricism might be overlooked if the school counselor insists on an
abstinence only program, due to his/her personal beliefs. The distributive question focuses on two issues.
First, whose interests should social workers concern themselves with? This question brings about the
issue of paternalism. If society is truly paternalistic, then it is the moral responsibility of citizens who are
doing well in life to intervene and aid those who are down on their luck. Under the current welfare
structure, the system takes responsibility for providing aid to those who need help. However, the
Deontological underpinnings of the welfare system put moral requirements on those who wish to receive
aid. As Reamer points out, the beginnings of social works Charity Organization Societies greatly
revolved around the Christian principle of helping those who have lost their way see the light. The second
part of the distributive question concerns how goods and services should be distributed. Consequentialists
such as Hume and Bentham argue that goods should be distributed based on what will provide the best
consequences for larger society. Aristotle believed that goods should be distributed according to virtue;
while Marx felt that need were the most important criteria. The question of service distribution can also
be affected by the professionals moral philosophy. For example, if a social worker receives a charitable
donation and must decide how to distribute the money, a Deontological social worker might give the
money to a program that subscribes to their own idea of morality, such as Planned Parenthood if the
worker believes strongly in a womans right to choose. A Consequentialist social worker might research
the effectiveness of various programs when making their decision. Or, they might find a way to distribute
the money that would help the greatest number of programs, therefore increasing the over positive
consequence for society. The substantive question asks which actions, goods and services are regarded as
helpful and worthwhile, and why. This question revolves around the idea of morality. The evaluation of
actions calls for the determination of its innate right or wrong. When evaluating goods and services, the
question becomes whether that program is morally good or bad. For example, is the action of breaking
confidentiality morally right or wrong? Similarly, is the service of needle exchange morally good or bad?

A Deontic would argue that the answers to these questions are the same in every situation and should be
based on whether the action in question could be committed by anyone in society and deemed acceptable.
A Consequentialist would interject that rather the consequence of any action or program should be the
primary focus in determining its worth. This conflict is addresses by Rosss (1930) idea of the difference
between a prima facieduty and an actual duty. A prima facie duty is one that the social worker should
perform, all other things being equal. The prima facie duty lends itself well to a Deontological argument,
since it ignores the other circumstances of a situation in favor of deciding what is innately right and
moral. An actual duty is what the social worker ends up doing, once the circumstances and intended
consequences of the situation have been established. For example, confidentiality is a prima facie duty of
social work. It is consider an innate right of the profession to keep client information confidential. A
Deontologist would claim that this virtue should be followed, no matter what the circumstance. However,
if a client tells the social worker that he/she is going to harm a co-worker, breaking confidentiality
becomes the actual duty; the decision that is considered morally right once the circumstances and
consequences are considered.
The morality of social work as a profession continues down through the general code of ethics and into
specific practice situations. One of those situations is coercion. While the decision to intervene has ties to
both Deontology and Consequentialism, how that intervention takes place falls in line with the idea of
Paternalism.
Go to:
6. Social Work Practice: The issue of coercive care
The Paternalistic relationship assumes two things, a power differential and the necessity of intervention to
prevent harm. Although, as previously discussed, the current welfare system is Paternalistic in nature, the
limits of that Paternalism, especially in the area of coercive treatment, have been important to the
profession of social work.Hutchinson (1992) claims that the question is not whether social workers have
the obligation to intervene and use their authority to prevent harm, but rather when and to what
degree that intervention should take place. Furthermore, it should be expected that issues such as coercion
will be met with competing moral values, and the importance lies in establishing guidelines that recognize
this moral struggle. Hutchinson suggests that careful attention should be paid to the clients level of selfdetermination (a prima facie) when deciding if involuntary treatment is necessary. Another suggestion is
that if coercion is deemed necessary, the social worker should explain to the client what competing values
are at stake and why involuntary treatment has been chosen as the most viable option. Even though
Hutchinson supports coercion, she notes that this only applies to two specific situations: if the coercion is
to fulfill a contract between the client and agency or state (such as mandatory treatment for batterers) or if
the client is in danger of harming themselves or others.
Concerning the paternalistic nature of the mental health system, Breeze (1998) points out that the prima
facie duty of empowerment is in conflict with Paternalism due to the emphasis on autonomous client
decisions. The role of Paternalism in mental health care, specifically around coercion is brought into
question due to the Paternalistic assumption of incompetence. As Breeze points out, competence can be a
subjective and value laden term. Both Deontologists and Consequentialists speak of the importance of
autonomy. Deontology protects autonomy with the belief that autonomy enables a person to follow a

universally accepted moral code. Consequentialists protect autonomy so that people can make choices
that result in the most good for themselves and/or society. However, both sides agree that Paternalism is
alright in the absence of rationality. The problem becomes, as previously mentioned; the assessment of
rationality can be subjective, especially around issues such as cultural and socioeconomic differences.
Go to:
7. Conclusion
The very nature of social policy and social work call for morally based decisions about how to address
deviant behavior. Creating policies and programs aimed at aiding people deemed to have a weakness by
the rest of society brings up issues of self determination, innate morality and the limits of systemic
intervention. Deontology approaches this area with a built in set of expected moral behaviors. While this
approach might be the most straightforward, with rights and wrongs spanning situational and personal
differences, it is unrealistic in that it assumes the ability to prevent undesired behaviors to the point that
dealing with their consequences is not necessary. A more realistic approach is Consequentialism, which
accepts that undesirable behaviors are a given, and resources are better spent focusing on preventing
harmful consequences and improving outcomes for society. Consequentialism recognizes that different
people and circumstances call for various approaches. Furthermore, Consequentialism accepts the
contribution of client input, evaluation and empiricism when deciding on the best alternative.
Whether policies or programs are Deontological or Consequentialist in nature, they can be carried out
paternalistically. That is, the person in power intervenes on behalf of a person deemed incompetent with
the primary goal or preventing harm or ensuring benefit. As previously discussed, two problems with
Paternalism are the subjective and relative nature of incompetence and the conflict between Paternalism
and the prima facie obligations of social welfare empowerment and self-determination.
Policies surrounding welfare, drugs, sexual activity and other deviant-related issues are morally charged
and based on Deontological views of how people should behave and what they should be able to achieve.
The profession of social work itself struggles with the incorporation of morality and rationality. Fostering
discussions of ethical and moral practices might be one way to bring this issue into the spotlight of social
work practice. The fact that social work deals with the delicate balance of good and harm around
vulnerable populations calls for a careful examination of the morals, consequences and objectives held by
the profession.
Go to:
Footnotes
Policies in the United States regarding personal responsibility and deviant behavior often follow an underlying moral
philosophy. This paper examines the philosophies in American social policy, and how beliefs about personal
responsibility, definitions of deviance and the role of the social welfare system shape current policies.

Go to:
References
1. Breeze J. Can paternalism be justified in mental health care? Journal of Advanced
Nursing.1998;28:2605. [PubMed]

2. Darwell S. Deontology. Blackwell Publishing; Oxford: 2002.


3. Duster T. The Legislation of Morality: Law, drugs and moral judgment. Free Press; New York:
1970.
4. Deontological Ethics. Macmillan Publishing; New York: 2004. Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
5. Fellowes M, Rowe M. Politics and the new American welfare states. American Journal of
Political Science. 2004;48:36273.
6. Harrison P, Beck A. Bureau of Justice Statistics, Prisoners in 2002. Washington D.C.:
Government Printing Office; 2003.
7. Haydar B. Forced supererogation and deontological restrictions. The Journal of Value
Inquiry.2002;36:44554.
8. Hutchinson E. Competing moral values and use of social work authority with involuntary
clients. In: Reid P, Popple P, editors. The Moral Purposes of Social Work. Nelson Hall;
Chicago: 1992. pp. 120136.
9. Jansson B. Becoming an Effective Policy Advocate: From policy practice to social
justice. Brooks/Cole; Pacific Grove, CA: 1999.
10. Kaplow L, Shavell S. Fairness versus Welfare. Harvard University Press; Cambridge, MA:
2002.
11. Kaplow L, Shavell S. Reply to Ripstein: Notes on Welfarist vs. Deontological
Principles. Economics and Philosophy. 2004;20:20915.
12. Leonard T, Goldfarb R, Suranovic S. New on Paternalism and public policy. Economics and
Philosophy.2000;16:32331.
13. Louise J. Relativity of value and the Consequentialist umbrella. The Philosophical
Quarterly.2004;54:51836.
14. MacCoun R, Reuter P. Drug War Heresies: Learning from other vices, times and
places. Cambridge University Press; Cambridge, UK: 2001.
15. Mead L. The Rise of Paternalism. In: Mead L, editor. The New Paternalism: Supervisory
Approaches to Poverty. Brookings Institution; Washington D.C.: 1997. pp. 138.
16. New B. Paternalism and pubic policy. Economic and Philosophy. 1999;15:6383.

17. Rainford W. Paternalistic regulation of women: Exploring punitive sanctions in Temporary


Assistance to Needy Families. AFFILIA. 2004;19:289304.
18. Reamer F. Ethical Dilemmas in Social Services. Columbia University Press; New York: 1982.
19. Reid C. Choice and Action. Macmillan Publishing; New York: 1981.
20. Ross WD. The Right and the Good. Clarendon Press; Oxford: 1930.
21. Scheffler S. Consequentialism and its Critics. Oxford University Press; Oxford: 1988.
22. Scheffler S. The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the
Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions. Oxford University Press; Oxford: 1994.
23. Skolnick J. Rethinking the drug problem. Journal of the Academy of Arts and
Sciences. 1992:13357.
24. Soss J, Schram S, Vartarian T, OBrien E. Setting the terms of relief: Explaining state policy
choices in the Devolution Revolution. American Journal of Political Science. 2001;45:37895.
25. Wilson L, Stoker R, McGrath D. Welfare bureaus as moral tutors: What do clients learn from
Paternalistic welfare? Social Science Quarterly. 1999;80:47387.

You might also like