The Nature of Truth
The Nature of Truth
The Nature of Truth
one thing is better than another, and those of us who are not experts may believe them because we
feel unqualified to question their opinions. In modern times some might challenge such arbitrary
choices by saying "It is true for you that Pavarotti is better but it is true for me that Elton John is
better." This leads to the idea that there are different "truths" for different people. This might be fine
for evaluating artists, but it gets us into big trouble when talk about the conservation of energy or
when the football game starts or whether there is a cement truck heading toward our car at high
speed. The problem of truth involving preferences is better resolved by saying that it is true that you
prefer Pavarotti and that I prefer Elton John (this is a hypothetical example by the way).
The problem of moral and ethical statements is similar in that there is no agreed upon rule for how to
determine whether they are true. The method above for truths involving preferences could be
employed, but it isn't very satisfactory. If we say "Stealing is wrong for you but it's not wrong for
me," people aren't going to be very happy. Many individual questions might be resolved if the
people debating the question agree on the ultimate purpose they want to achieve. For example,
virtually all moral and ethical systems agree that we should try to avoid killing people, so a debate
about which of two possible military actions is most ethical might be resolved by gathering and
analyzing evidence as to which would cause the fewest deaths.
Unfortunately, many of the most serious disputes such as abortion, sexual morality, and demands for
particular forms of religious worship cannot be addressed this way because they involve
fundamental differences in the definition of morality. By considering the basic nature of morality it
might be possible to make some progress on such issues; otherwise we might hope a rational
examination of how each of us arrived at our moral beliefs would help people realize that their own
basis is not guaranteed to be more valid than someone else's. This would hopefully reduce the
chances of bitter confrontations with people who make different moral assumptions.
The case of the mathematical statement is special because, unlike scientific statements, the truth of
such statements follows totally from the definition of terms and axioms, and not on any observation
of the real world. Generally truths involving the real world involve measurements that have some
degree of inaccuracy and generalizations for which exceptions may be found in the future. In
mathematics (which includes formal logic) it is reasonable to consider some statements to be
perfectly true and those which are not perfectly true to be utterly false. We should be careful to
recognize that real world statements tend to become useless if they are held to such an extreme
standard, since few things are totally true or totally false.
truck, it isn't valid for me to say "it was true for me that it was safe for him to cross the street." He
was depending on a kind of truth that is more than just a point of view.
Postmodernists' views seem more reasonable when applied to things like art and morality, where
there are no widely agreed on ways to determine what is true. Even in these areas, we can benefit by
gaining a better understanding so issues of truth are better defined. In traditional scientific areas,
postmodernists correctly point out that there is always an element of opinion and bias in scientific
work. While this is so, scientific methods are carefully designed to keep such biases to an absolute
minimum, which would not normally be the case when using emotional or political or religious
methods to reach conclusions.
Probability
We can consider all knowledge as having a probability associated with it. Do I know that the floor
of my house will support my weight, because it has in the past? I feel that is extremely probable, but
there is some tiny possibility that something has recently undermined it. I am very confident that the
world is roughly spherical. I am pretty sure that eating fatty foods increases my risk of heart attack.
We often think of probability as only applying to the future, but as long as we have some doubt
about the answer to a question, the concept of probability can apply to the past and present as well.
If we deal one card from a deck of playing cards to a friend, the probability of it being an ace would
be 4 in 52. As far as we are concerned, the fact that the card has already been determined does not
affect our judgment of the probabilities. If we then also deal a card to ourselves and see it is an ace,
the chances of our friend having an ace is now 3 in 51 (three out of the 51 cards we cannot see are
aces), while if we don't have an ace the probability would be 4 in 51. When we learn more about a
situation, the probabilities of certain facts change accordingly.