06 Crowell
06 Crowell
STEVEN CROWELL
We are still far from pondering the essence of action decisively enough.
We view action only as causing an effect.1 Of action, praxis, Aristotle
noted that it is something which is itself its end and thus cannot be
understood as a cause that brings something about.2 Of course, action
does bring things about, but that does not exhaust its meaning. It can be
hard to find a way to talk about that meaning without falling into the
language of causing and producing, but unless we do we will miss Hei-
deggers contribution to the philosophical elucidation of practical reason.
For that contribution does not lie in explaining what makes an action
rational, what it is to act according to reason; rather it lies in clarifying,
phenomenologically, what it is to be an agent. For this reason, if we wish
to determine where morality fits in to Heideggers ontology we should
look not to the quality of character (virtue) or to the maxim of acts
(duty) but to the nature of agency.
The concept of practical reason has roots in Aristotles concept of
phronesis. In contrast to that sort of reason episteme, theoria that has to
do with what is not even capable of being otherwise (as in mathem-
atics or metaphysics), phronesis concerns what is capable of being other-
wise above all, human affairs, ethics and politics (NE 1139b, 1140b).
While this way of distinguishing practical from theoretical reason has its
uses, it is too bound up with the details of Aristotles metaphysics to be
1 Heidegger, Letter on Humanism, in Basic Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell (Har-
3 For Heideggers own discussion of this distinction, see Martin Heidegger, Platon:
Sophistes, Gesamtausgabe Bd. 19, ed. Ingeborg Schler (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1992),
21-60.
4 Heidegger, Letter on Humanism, 217.
5 Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New
York: Harper & Row, 1962), 32 (H 12). Henceforth cited in the text as BT with English
pagination first, followed by the German pagination in the Niemeyer edition e.g., (BT
32/12).
6 Arguments for this claim can be found in Steven Galt Crowell, Hussserl, Heidegger,
and the Space of Meaning: Paths Toward Transcendental Phenomenology (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 2001).
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 51
7 Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, tr., Mary Gregor (Cambridge, UK: Cam-
In Sein und Zeit Heidegger breaks with the intellectualistic and Cartesian
understanding of the subject, according to which the intelligibility of
action is a function of thinking of reflecting, planning, and representing
to oneself. Thus Hubert Dreyfus once approvingly described the every-
day coping skills of Dasein as mindless.11 In a debate with Dreyfus,
John McDowell argued that even when there is no spontaneity, no ex-
plicit reflection and thought, our behavior is not mindless coping but is
minded, that is, infused with the intelligibility that will subsequently
serve as the basis for explicit thinking.12 There are real issues at stake in
this dispute, but others are merely terminological. For both McDowell
and Dreyfus, action is worldly in Heideggers sense that is, possible
gerian phronimos (p. 271). The crux of our disagreement lies in the fact that Dreyfuss
reading fails to appreciate the role Kant plays in Division II.
11 Hubert Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heideggers Being and Time, Di-
The work belongs to this relevance totality but it does not exhaust it;
what the work is supposed to be refers back to that for the sake of which all
these actions are being carried out. Heidegger writes: But this totality of
relevance itself goes back ultimately to a towards which in which there
is no further relevance... The primary towards which is a for-the-sake-
of-which. But the for-the-sake-of always pertains to the being of Da-
sein, for which, in its being, that very being is essentially an issue (BT
116-17/84). In other words, what is being made is determined by what I
am doing. And what I am doing, in turn, is in an important sense deter-
mined by what I am trying to do.13 The standards that govern the as-
structure of equipment derive from such trying. Making is minded be-
cause in exercising a particular ability or skill I understand myself as up
to something. In understanding a context of relations... Dasein has as-
signed itself to an in-order-to, and it has done so in terms of a potential-
ity-for-being [Seinknnen] for the sake of which it itself is (BT 119/86).
To understand, in Heideggers existential sense, is to try to be some-
thing, and in this I can succeed or fail. On this basis I will hazard the
following thesis: For Heidegger, the Worumwillen or for the sake of is
the ultimate source of all particular norms.
The Umwillen is a possibility of Daseins being, where possibility
is not something I represent to myself but something I am in the sense
of something I am able to do. Possibility is an ability to be (Seinknnen),
whose modal character derives from the fact that it is only in being an
issue for me something I can succeed or fail at being in trying to be it.
Being a lawyer, being a carpenter, being a father, teacher, lover, or friend:
all of these are possibilities, that is, things that I am up to, capable of;
roles and practices I engage in more or less ably. I join these boards in
order to make a house, but it is for the sake of being a carpenter that I
do it in just the way I do. Of course, I make the house in order to live in
it, but that is not why I exercise myself in just the way I do; rather, it is
because I am trying to be a carpenter, I am trying (and so perhaps failing)
to live up to what the practice requires, acknowledging the claims they
make on me. Only so do those requirements take on normative force (i.e.,
actually govern my behavior). Thus, to understand myself as suspended
between success and failure to exist in a normative space is possible
only because my being is Care. Here I will posit a second thesis: all
normative force depends on Care.
Making (poiesis) rests upon this sort of existential possibility. Doing
something in just the way I do exhibits my skill, my know-how. I know
how a table is made; that is, I am able to make one. Such know-how is
not necessarily something I can articulate theoretically, but it is not whol-
ly mechanical either; it is techne or art. What distinguishes a carpenter
from a carpenter ant is art, a kind of mindedness that stems from the way
I understand myself in trying to be a carpenter. Carpenter ants can suc-
ceed or fail at making something, but only the carpenter can succeed or
fail at what he is trying to be. The carpenters skill or techne is an intellectual
virtue, not mere instinct, because to try to be a carpenter is to act in light
of the norms that govern the practice. The intelligibility of making, then,
depends on norms that govern not only the product but the process,
norms that govern what it is to be whatever Dasein is able be.
This shows that Heideggers analysis of everyday Dasein includes not
only the principles of making but the principles of acting (praxis) as well.
For being a father or a friend is an Umwillen, but no one least of all
Heidegger will confuse these with modes of making something. Being
a good friend is not just knowing how to write a congratulatory letter but
knowing when to write it, in what sort of medium, the character of the
one to whom it is addressed, and so on. I may be able to write a congrat-
ulatory letter, but if I do so too late, or by email, or with rhetorical flour-
ishes when its recipient dislikes verbosity, then, even if I have succeeded
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 57
For the most part, I am absorbed in the world; praxis is, for the most
part, simply going with the flow. But it often happens that my projects
are disturbed by glitches and snags that disrupt the flow, major or minor
breakdowns that make it difficult for me to go on. At such times I am
forced to take stock of my situation, to reflect, to consider what should
be done. At such times, I am forced to deliberate.
Heidegger says very little about deliberation. This has led one com-
mentator to hold that Heidegger banishes reason from human exis-
tence and to deny that there is, in Sein und Zeit, anything remotely
14 To speak of acting in light of norms does not entail that these norms are formul-
ated anywhere; they are not rules. Thus acting immediately (i.e., without explicit delib-
eration) is not incompatible with acting in light of norms and not merely in accord with
them.
58 Steven Crowell
it without caring (say, because it is my duty), I will still not fulfill the
normative demands of being a father. I will fail to be a good father be-
cause good fathers care about being fathers and so feel the normative
force of the reasons stemming from their practical identities. They do
not merely recognize such norms but are beholden to them, committed.
Thus interpreted, Korsgaards concept of practical identity tracks
Heideggers Worumwillen and allows us to see that his account of deliber-
ation need not be limited to the sort of instrumental reasoning charac-
teristic of making. For if practical identities provide me with reasons for
acting in a certain way, so too do Heideggerian projects. This sort of
reason is not well expressed as an in-order-to; I do not attend the violin
recital in order to be a good father but for the sake of being one. Phron-
esis has to do with this sort of reason, a sort to which the phronemos is
especially attuned. The importance of this distinction becomes clear if we
look into what Aristotle says about choice.
Choice (prohairesis) is the origin of action its efficient, not its final
cause; and the origin of choice, in turn, is desire and reasoning with
a view to an end that is, desire and deliberation. Hence choice can-
not exist either without reason and intellect or without a moral state
(NE 1139a). More specifically, minded agency requires reason and intel-
lect because it does not merely tend toward an end through desire but
chooses it; that is, acts in light of that which tends to attain what is good
(NE 1142b), the sorts of things that conduce to the good life in gener-
al, the things that are good and bad for man (NE 1140a). To see the
end in light of the good is itself a specific sort of practice, one whose ex-
cellence, Aristotle says, is a kind of correctness other than the correc-
tness of knowledge and opinion that is, other than the kind of cor-
rectness pertinent to formulated judgments and propositions. This prac-
tice is deliberation or, as Aristotle says, thinking, and practical wisdom
(phronesis) is correctness in thinking (NE 1142b).19
19 Dreyfus, What Could be More Intelligible, 268, is thus right to emphasize that
phronesis (cultural expertise) is not ratiocination but rather an immediate response to
each situation. But given Aristotles distinction between correctness in thinking and the
correctness of explicitly formulated propositions, such immediacy does not exclude del-
iberation or thinking and can thus be an instance of acting in light of norms rather than
merely in accord with them. See footnote 14 above.
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 61
20 There are several interrelated senses in which the phrase what one does may be
understood among them: (1) a sociological, third-person sense; the statistical norm;
what is normally done; (2) a psychological, first-person sense: roughly, my assumptions
about what the sociologically normal is; (3) an ontological sense, which I take to be
Heideggers, which involves the philosophically relevant ambiguity between what one
really ought to do and what one does in sense (2).
62 Steven Crowell
identities and the norms that govern them. I can try to be a father in my
own way, but if in so doing I cannot at all be recognized by others as
trying to be a father, then I am not doing anything at all. I can transgress
some of the norms that everyone knows to govern fatherhood (for
instance, being the breadwinner) and still succeed in being a father; I
may even reshape the norms to some extent.21 But one cannot simply
decide that fatherhood will henceforth mean, say, what we now mean
by baseball player. If I transgress too many of the current norms of
being a father, I can neither succeed or fail at being one. To try in the
existential sense is not a matter of what I think I am doing. For even if I
think that in pitching and batting I am trying to conform to the norms of
fatherhood, that does not mean that I am failing at being a father. It just
means that Im crazy.
Thus we may add a third thesis to those posited in the previous sec-
tion: One always deliberates from within some practical identity or other,
or some combination of them. They alone give me justifying reasons to
do X rather than Y. All practical reasoning including moral reasoning
thus remains within the scope of current public norms. If, as Heidegger
says, the one itself articulates the referential context of significance
that is, world (BT 167/129) it is the one-self (das Man-selbst) who
reasons and deliberates. Indeed, deliberation is nothing but the think-
ing part of ones practical identity. And since phronesis is the virtue or
excellence of deliberation, phronesis too will always be tied to some prac-
tical identity, without which it could have no purchase on what that
good is. This is the basis for Aristotles claim that it is impossible to
be practically wise without being good (NE 11144a). One must be a
21 This is what is importantly correct in Dreyfuss claim (What Could be More Intel-
ligible, 272) that Heideggers move beyond Aristotle lies in recognizing the possibility of
a cultural master who can disclose new worlds. One need not hold that such cre-
ative transformation is an ability toto caelo distinct from the expertise of the phronemos,
however; Dreyfus himself acknowledges that disclosing new worlds happens when the
master takes up a marginal practice from its cultural heritage and uses it to transform
the present. The point is that the world cannot be altogether transformed; the new norms,
and intelligibility, cannot arise out of whole cloth. But whether there is a radical distinc-
tion between expert and master is finally irrelevant, since the systematic role of the
analysis of authenticity does not lie in a further development of the skills and practices
focus of Division I but in an account of what, beyond practical abilities, I must be in order
to be beholden to norms, to act in light of them.
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 63
22 Some interesting, though very different, starts in this direction have been made by
Frederick Olafson, Heidegger and the Ground of Ethics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 1998); Werner Marx, Is there a Measure on Earth: Foundations for a Non-Metaphysic-
al Ethics, tr. Thomas Nenon and Reginald Lilly (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1987); Joanna Hodge, Heidegger and Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1995); Lawrence Hatab,
Ethics and Finitude: Heideggerian Contributions to Moral Philosopy (Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield, 2000); Frank Schalow, The Renewal of the Kant-Heidegger Dialogue (Albany: SUNY
Press, 1992).
23 How then should we explain Heideggers claim (Platon: Sophistes, 56), noted above,
that [d]ie phronesis is nichts anderes als das in Bewegung gesetzte Gewissen, das eine
Handlung durchsichtig macht? The key point is that conscience and phronesis are not
equated; phronesis is conscience set in motion. To set conscience in motion is, as I will
argue in this section, to take over the essential consciencelessness of action. To make
action transparent in this sense is to act in light of ones responsibility for the norm-
ative character (force) of those norms in light of which one acts. Gewissen itself, however,
belongs to the existential condition in which I grasp myself as responsible in this way; it is
a mode of self-awareness that is possible only when I do not act.
66 Steven Crowell
it as a property but to try to be it, that is, to act in light of its norms. If to
be a carpenter, for instance, involves taking-action as a carpenter does,
then to be a good carpenter is to accomplish, in taking action, an exem-
plary instance of what it means to be a carpenter. According to Heideg-
ger, then, being-good at anything will involve a certain consciencelessness.
But what is conscience, such that taking action and being-good essential-
ly exclude it?
The passages about consciencelessness appear among a series of ont-
ological equations in which Heidegger summarizes the phenomenology
of conscience that he had provided earlier in the chapter (BT 334/288).
Consience is a call, a mode of discourse, and thus something heard.
To hear discourse is to understand. To understand, in the existential sense, is
not to grasp thematically but to be able-to-be, to exercise an ability. Thus
to hear is to do something: Understanding the call is choosing. But it is
not a choosing of conscience, which as such cannot be chosen. One
cannot choose when to have the call call: it comes from me and yet
from beyond me and over me (BT 320/275). Instead, what is chosen is
having-a-conscience as being-free for ones ownmost being-guilty. Under-
standing the appeal means wanting-to-have-a-conscience. And it is precisely
this wanting-to-have-a-conscience that becomes the taking-over of that
essential consciencelessness within which all taking-action, all praxis,
and so also any existentiell possibility of being-good subsists.
What does it mean to take over the essential consciencelessness
of praxis? In taking over that is, in the choice that constitutes Daseins
understanding the call Dasein lets its ownmost self take action in itself
in terms of that potentiality-for-being which it has chosen (BT 334/288).
Taking-over is thus a kind of doubling of action: the potentiality-for-
being which [Dasein] has chosen is nothing other than the practical
identity as which it is engaged in a conscienceless way. Let us call this
choice1. In hearing the call this is subtended by another doing un-
derstanding the call is choosing in which Dasein lets its ownmost
self (that is, its most primordial potentiality-for-being) take action...
in terms of choice1. Let us call this choice2. But Daseins most primor-
dial potentiality for being is being-guilty [schuldig] (BT 334/288).
Wanting-to-have-a-conscience thus transforms everyday praxis (choice1)
by taking over its essential consciencelessness in light of my being-guilty
(choice2). Thus, everything depends on what being-guilty, in the phenom-
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 67
24 For more, see my Conscience and Reason: Heidegger and the Grounds of Inten-
tionality, in Transcendental Heidegger, ed. Steven Crowell and Jeff Malpas (Stanford: Stan-
ford University Press, 2007), 43-62.
25 See my Subjectivity: Locating the First-Person in Being and Time, Inquiry 44
(2001), 433-54.
68 Steven Crowell
26 The crux of my disagreement with Dreyfus is found here, for his interpretation de-
pends on seeing two kinds of anxiety in Division II, and so two levels of authenticity. I
can find no textual justification for this reading. According to Dreyfus (What Could be
More Intelligible, 271), the phronemos possesses the anxiety of guilt i.e., the sense
that the everyday social norms of its society are thrown rather than grounded and so have
no final authority but is not yet fully authentic because he does not face the anxiety
of death i.e., that Dasein has to be ready at all times to give up its identity and its
world altogether. The sort of distinction Dreyfus draws between two kinds of anxiety is
phenomenologically intelligible in existentiell terms. Heidegger, however, does not sever
the meaning of guilt and death in this way, because the point of his analysis is to un-
cover the ontological condition for what makes praxis any praxis, not just some special
form possible, namely, my ability to be I-myself.
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 69
for it, does not possess its thrownness, its inclinations, as an apple pos-
sesses its color. Rather, Dasein is this thrown ground... only in that it
projects itself upon possibilities into which it has been thrown. This is
what it means that Dasein must take over being-a-ground.
Heidegger continues: In being thrown, Dasein has been released from
its ground, not through itself but to itself, so as to be as this ground. Self-
hood, being a self, is to be the being of its ground, a ground that is
never anything but the ground for an entity whose being has to take over
being-a-ground (BT 330-31/285). Taking over being-a-ground cannot
mean that I create myself; my inclinations are not mine to create. Rather
to take over the ground into which I am thrown is to see my inclinations
in a normative light, that is, as possible rather than inevitable grounds of
my behavior; it is to see them as potentially justifying reasons. In taking
them over I become responsible for them either by making them my rea-
sons or refusing to do so. Only by understanding the call in this sense
can Dasein be responsible [verantwortlich] (BT 334/228).27
We are now in a position to understand the concept of authenticity as
anticipatory resoluteness (BT 349/302). One might think of it this way:
Aristotle has a one-level conception of action prohairesis is choice in the
sense of choice1 above. Phronesis is excellence in such choices. Heideg-
gers notion of authentic choice, on the other hand, is two-tiered: the
practical identity in light of which I act (choice1) is accompanied by a
choosing to choose (choice2): to be resolute is to act as I-myself, that
is, in anticipation of the possibility of breakdown. More specifically,
it is to act in light of what is revealed in breakdown, namely, my responsib-
28 From this point of view we can see that Dreyfuss interpretation in What Could
be More Intelligible sets the bar of authenticity too high, since authenticity is ascribed
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 71
only to the phronemos or the fully authentic cultural master. But while these (rare) indiv-
iduals may be authentic, surely Heideggers concept is not limited to them.
29 John Drummond develops a phenomenological version of this sort of Aristotelian-
ism on the basis of what he calls transcendental goods. See Drummond, Respect as a
Moral Emotion: A Phenomenological Approach, Husserl Studies 22 (2006): 127. Kors-
gaard argues for something like this from a Kantian perspective in Sources of Normativity
(123), where she presents a transcendental argument to the effect that valuing ones
humanity is a condition for valuing oneself under any other practical identity.
30 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, tr. H. J. Paton (New York:
32 Martin Heidegger, Vom Wesen der Menschlichen Freiheit: Einleitung in die Philosophie.
Gesamtausgabe Bd. 31, ed. Hartmut Tietjen (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1982), 139-298.
33 Kant, Groundwork, 80.
34 Summing up his argument in the Second Part of Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit
(303), Heidegger writes: Freiheit is die Bedingung der Mglichkeit der Offenbarkeit des
Seins von Seienden, des Seinsverstndnis. But if that is so, then freedom cannot be
thought in terms of causality. Eine Seinsbestimmung unter anderen aber ist die Kausali-
tt. Kausalitt grndet in der Freiheit. Das Problem der Kausalitt ist ein Problem der
Freiheit und nicht umgekehrt.
Heidegger on Practical Reasoning 73
in light of, and not merely in accord with, reasons namely, Daseins es-
sential being-guilty. Though it yields no test for the morality of ones
maxim, it does yield something like a moral (that is to say, universal) ob-
ligation.
To have Care as ones being to be an issue for oneself means to
see things in normative terms, to understand ones factic inclinations in
relation to the very idea of what is best (as Plato would say), of better
and worse. This is to treat them as only potentially my reasons that is, to
treat them as normative reasons rather than causes. But Dasein is essent-
ially Mitsein, and thus to be responsible is equiprimordially to be answerable
(ver-antwort-lich) to others, accountable to them. The constitutive hori-
zon of responsibility in which alone I can be I-myself thus includes
among its references every other Dasein, all those to whom I am ac-
countable, i.e., all those who may call upon me to justify or give an ac-
count of myself. Thus to be I-myself is to be under an obligation to offer
reasons to others for what I do. My nature as Care entails a moral ob-
ligation insofar as taking-over-being-a-ground obliges me to take up the
practice of giving and asking for reasons, a kind of meta-practice that be-
longs among the norms of all particular practical identities.
Phronesis always remain tied to concrete practical identities, since these
alone provide the necessary ends or standards of success or failure.
And on Heideggers view, morally practical reasoning is also tied to such
identities, since moral responsibility cannot be defined in terms of reason
or law as the criterion for a concrete, but identity-transcending, universal
good. Because Dasein is always an issue for itself, such goods are also al-
ways at issue. Thus, ontologically considered, practical rationality is es-
sentially practical reasoning that is, the dialogical practice of offering rea-
sons to others for what I do and demanding the same from them. What
such reasoning should find to be the right thing to do cannot be det-
ermined in advance by any theory but depends on actual argumentation.35
What it means to be a good father, friend, or carpenter and so also
what it means to be a good person, morally good is always the sub-
stance of the conversation that we ourselves are. Nevertheless, we do
Rice University
Houston, Texas
USA