Higher Superstition - Gross & Levitt (1994)
Higher Superstition - Gross & Levitt (1994)
Higher Superstition - Gross & Levitt (1994)
Gross, Paul R.
Higher superstition: the academic left and its quarrels with
science / Paul R. Gross, Norman Levitt.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-8018-4766-4 (alk. paper)
1. ScienceSocial aspects. 2. Humanities. I. Levitt, N.
(Norman), 1943 II. Title.
Q1755G757 1944
500dc20 93-32914
ISBN 0-8018-5707-4 (pbk.)
Contents
Sources of Indignation
Insularities
Distinctions
Designing a Rejoinder
Fresh from the horrors of the Thirty Years War, late seventeenth-
century Europe produced a generation of intellectual giants whose
collective accomplishment was to set in motion an epistemological
enterprise that has continued to flourish over the past three hundred
years, an effort that accelerates and expands continually in its scope,
precision, and reliability. The true scientific revolution instituted by
Galileo, Kepler, Newton, Halley, Harvey, Boyle, Leibniz, and others is
to be found, not in their particular discoveries about the world,
stupendous as these were, but rather in the creation, almost in passing,
of a methodology and a worldview capable of expanding, modifying
and generalizing these discoveries indefinitely. It was, moreover, a
methodology that almost unwittingly set aside the metaphysical
assumptions of a dozen centuries, under which a description of the
physical world would have been incomprehensible had it stood apart
from a vision of transcendent divine order on the Christian model. That
Newton, say, or Leibniz sought in all sincerity to affirm some version
of this divine order through his scientific work is almost beside the
point. The implicit logic of their work turned out to be of immensely
greater importance than the explicit pious intentions of those who
achieved it.
In its ineluctable dynamic, the science of the turn of the eighteenth
century could not be contained within the shell of any theological
system. It was, in important ways, already fully modern. Open-
endedness is the vital principle at stake here. It constitutes the lifeblood
of ongoing science. Newton said it best: an ocean of truth lies
undiscovered before us. Unless we are unlucky, this always will be the
case.
Having escaped most of the constraints of systematic theology, the
new science was hardly to be contained within the ideological matrix of
the society and political system within which it arose. The birth of
Western science as a powerful, systematic, and ever-expanding set of
interlinked disciplines very nearly coincides with the birth of its
prestige as a uniquely reliable and accurate way of describing the
phenomenal world. Consequently, philosophers and political thinkers
of all shades of opinion attempted eagerly to conscript that prestige on
behalf of their own favored ideas. Newton, along with his contemporary
Locke, is often thought of as the tutelary figure of the Glorious
Revolution and of the gentlemanly class, devoted equally to the pursuit
of mercantile wealth and to an Anglican faith forever irreconcilable
with Catholicism, that forged this constitutional and dynastic upheaval
this despite Newtons own peculiarly heterodox Protestantism. A
faction within the Established Church came to be called Newtonian
for its stout insistence that, just as Newtons singularly English genius
revealed the eternal regularity of Gods law made manifest in celestial
mechanics, so too did the Church of England and the social system with
which it was intertwined reveal the intentions of the Deity for the
rightful ordering of human affairs.
But the partisans of social stability could scarcely maintain a
monopoly over the totemic power of Newtonian physics. A deeper
understanding of science itself, as well as an entirely different set of
speculations as to what it might imply for the human political order,
emerged throughout Western Europe. This is symbolized by the growth
of Freemasonry as a sort of philosophical shadow government, by the
attempts of the Encyclopedists to systematize and codify the full range
of human knowledge, by the development of political economy as a
fruitful intellectual enterprise.1 The relationship between science as
such and these various tendencies was by no means fixed according to
any particular stereotype. It is, however, certain that sciencein
particular Newtonian physics and its related mathematicsheld sway
as a privileged model and inspiration, the very emblem of the power of
the human intellect to probe beneath surface appearances, to rectify
vulgar prejudices, and to exile habits of thought more ancient than
accurate.
In the sphere of social thought, the success of physics inspired
emulation in the form of analyses of society seeking general principles
that might be made to yield a deep understanding of the dynamics of
history, politics, and economic activity. The urge to prescribe, as well
as to describe and predict, ran strong in these attempts, in a manner
quite uncharacteristic of physics itself; but the boldness, indeed the
arrogance, required to set forth schemes for the radical improvement of
the human condition and for the rapid cure of its ancient ills reflects an
intellectual self-assurance that derives largely from contemplation of
the well-confirmed triumphs of eighteenth-century mathematical
science. If the few simple axioms adumbrated by the Principia could be
induced to yield precise accounts of the orbits of planets and comets, of
the eccentricity of the earth and the precession of its axis, of the pattern
of oceanic tides, why should there not be an equally elegant,
comprehensive, and reliable systemization of the study of human
affairs?
The obligations of hindsight impel us to look on most of these
attempts as failures variously fatuous, quixotic, or disastrous, whose
culmination is to be found in the self-defeating utopianism of the
French Revolution. Admirers of Adam Smiths economics, or of the
abiding wisdom of the American Constitution, will, on the other hand,
discern triumphs amidst the scores of false starts and blind alleys. Our
own position is that even on the most optimistic view such triumphs are
drenched in irony and soured by an unending stream of historical
misfortunes. These disputes, however, are not central to our point.
What we wish to emphasize, rather, is that the underlying strategy that
guides the intellectual enterprises of Smith, Diderot, Locke, Gibbon,
Herder, Hume, Jefferson, and (what was until recently) a pantheon of
others remains as an ongoing tradition that is unlikely to disappear
within the imaginable future. This is simply, in its most naked form,
the strategy of taking the social order, per se, as the object of ones
critical investigations, seeing it as describable, in large measure, on the
basis of discoverable first principles. It is to be implemented by
combining careful and exhaustive attention to solid empirical fact with
the construction of a more or less rigorous deductive model.
At their best, such theories yield chains of propositions which
themselves may be variously regarded as confirmed insights into the
social organism, or as tentative hypotheses to be tested in the hard
world of experience, as a trial of the soundness of the fundamental
postulates of the theory. That this accords, if only in a very rough
sense, with the epistemological model already set in place by the
physical sciences is, we think, so obvious as to need no further
argument.
It is important to attend to another aspect of such Enlightenment
for that is what we are describingsocial thought. It seems to us that
what a broad spectrum of thinkers have in common is their
determination to regard the social position of individuals as resulting
neither from the decrees of a transcendent divinity nor from the
processes of an optimal social mechanism. Rank, wealth, and power are
seen as contingent facts, rather than as the emblems of an innate or
achieved social perfection. Whatever their differences, none of these
philosophers cry along with Pope and Handel Whatever Is, Is Right.
Rather, schemes and prescriptions abound for the reconstitution of the
social organism to bring it into alignment with the dictates of reason
and nature. Furthermore, the ills and malfunctions of the existing order
are almost always located in the undeniable maldistribution of wealth,
power, prestige, and immunity that is to be found everywhere. Thus a
strongly implicit egalitarianism suffuses the thinking of the savants of
the time, at least of those whose work still speaks resonantly to us. This
may range from the openness to entrepreneurial innovation advocated
by Smith to Rousseaus near-mystical celebration of the General Will
and the unanimity of its votaries; but such distinctions seem more
important, we submit, in hindsight. The key point is that it came to be
seen that any system claiming to be based on natural justice must
accommodate the concept that at some level all individuals are to be
equally empowered by the fundamental political processes of the state.
It hardly matters that at this level of generality such ideas are as
ancestral to the apologies for free-market capitalism so dear to modern
conservatives as to the garrison-state socialism of North Korea or
Vietnam, and it hardly matters that the egalitarian view tended to be
blind, now and again, to particular parts of the landscape.
It is fair to say, in short, that by the time of the French Revolution
a certain suite of ideas had become regnant in European (and North
American) political philosophy. The empiricism and rigor of the
sciences were emulated in the analytic strategies of political thought;
and this, in turn, was for the most part linked to an emancipatory
project for the renovation or reconstitution of existing social systems.
It is of course possible, and tempting, to speculate whether a similar
system of scientific discourse might have arisen in an entirely different
social context. Might it have been possible, for instance, in Tang
Dynasty China or under the Pax Romana? Or could science have
matured only upon a substrate of subtly congenial social ideals and
institutions, like those found in seventeenth-century Europe? Such
speculation, though it continues actively and vigorously, is, in some
sense, futile, for we are speaking of an event that is in essence unique
and unrepeatable. Short of an utter collapse of our civilization on a
global scale, the opportunity to reinvent science will not arise. So the
association of Enlightenment ideas in the realm of politics with that
eras celebrationindeed, near-deificationof science may be largely
fortuitous. Nonetheless, at least to the extent that the political aspects
come up against the authority of religion as well as the mythic power of
other traditional rationalizations of the established order, science is a
weapon to be wielded both specifically and emblematically. Laplaces
famous explanationI did not find the hypothesis necessaryof the
absence of the Deity from his system of cosmology is both a succinct
lesson in the explanatory parsimony of scientific thinking and a war cry
of political and ideological defiance.
The disastrous failure of the French Revolution and the aftermath
of that failure is, of course, perhaps the most ringing example of the
triumph of inadvertence over intention in human history. It instilled in
Western thinkers a full measure of skepticism concerning utopian
systems and schemes for universal reform. Even before that, during the
headiest moments of early republicanism, the canny Burke had already
put his finger on the weaknesses of abstract philosophizing as a guide
to the attainment of social perfection. Burke, however, is but one of a
spectrum of thinkers who begin to show strong doubts about the
deification of the merely rational. Far more emphatic and impassioned
are the great figures of Romantic individualism, including Blake,
Wordsworth, Coleridge, and, above all, Goethe. It is in literature and
poetry that we first begin to encounter a reaction against Enlightenment
values that reveals a specific distrust of science, as well as a strong
reluctance to believe that mankind can be reformed along scientific
lines.
This is a vexatious topic: to do it justice, one must be endlessly
willing to draw distinctions. Blake is a very different animal,
politically and philosophically as well as poetically, from the Olympian
Goethe, and neither is very close in spirit to the reactionary
Wordsworth settled into his endless counterrevolutionary old age. Yet,
in point of attitude toward epistemological questions, and, quite
explicitly, toward the authority of science, the poets are linked by a
strong commonality of thought. Each distrusts the narrowly empirical
and the strictly rational, each celebrates the vital importance of the
intuitive, the irreproducible moment of insight and of direct access to
truth in its unmediated essence. Each accuses science, especially in its
schematic, mathematicized form, of blindness, or worse, stubborn
refusal to see. Each fears a world in which scientific thought has
become the sovereign mode, and recoils from the spiritual degradation
and servility that, in his opinion, must inevitably come to characterize
such a world. Blake makes his protest in the name of an ecstatic,
antinomian, revolutionary vision that comforts neither Jacobins nor
Royalists. Goethe speaks for an idiosyncratic classicism, neither fully
pagan nor fully Christian, neither revolutionary nor reactionary, as
singular as the great man himself. Wordsworth seems merely a self-
satisfied old Tory. But beneath these divergent visions, we find an
underlying distrust of straightforward, impersonal reasoning. The belief
in direct, revelatory, intuitive truth to be had from communion with
nature is the obverse of a deep epistemological skepticism about the
kind of systematic truth that is the core of scientific knowledge. In
this aspect, Romantic thought, even at its most revolutionary, is allied
to the caustic, all-encompassing skepticism of that relentless
reactionary Joseph de Maistre, whose most brilliant exercises in logic
and empirical inference are expressly designed to demonstrate the
unreliability and futility of logic and empirical inference.2
(We cannot resist the temptation to take note, in passing, of the
fact that the Romantic exaltation of intuitive Understanding above
merely cerebral Reason foreshadows the celebration of holism and
organicism by contemporary critics of science, who are impatient
with the disciplined analysis and methodological exactness of serious
scientific work. Likewise, Maistre, in his counterrevolutionary ferocity,
is the true spiritual ancestor of the postmodern skepticism so dear to
the hearts of the academic left.)
Whatever its effect on the history of poetry and sensibility,
however, the Romantic revulsion against the scientific worldview had
virtually no effect on the development of science itself. The nineteenth
century turned science into a profession. Its status as the preserve of
gentlemen-amateurs and isolated virtuosi dependent on aristocratic
patronage receded into history. The education of scientists was rapidly
systematized, and the universities, especially in France and Germany,
took on their now-familiar role as nurseries for aspiring scientists and
sponsors of experimental, as well as speculative, work. The
subdivisions of science came to be ever more clearly defined, and the
intense specialization that marks the science of our own day took
shape. At the same time, the link between theoretical science and direct
technological innovation became concretized in the growth of
institutions, both educational and commercial, that vastly expanded the
scope of the engineering profession, while tying it ever more firmly to
rigorous scientific foundations. The interval between the first
systematic attempts to derive an adequate mathematical theory of
electricity and magnetismthose of Gauss and Ampre, sayand the
systematic construction first of telegraph networks, then of electrical
systems to power whole cities is, by any standard, incredibly brief.
This fully symbolizes the degree to which Western culture, almost
unthinkingly, entirely altered its own material underpinnings. To
compare the European states, circa 1800 with, say, the Chinese or
Ottoman empires is a historical and geopolitical exercise dealing with
entities which, however greatly they differ, may be measured against
each other in terms of economic, industrial, agricultural, navigational,
and military capacity. By 1900, such a comparison is idle. The sudden
disparity has little to do with the traditional ebb and flow of power, and
everything to do with assimilation of the scientific enterprise into the
heart of the Western social fabric. It seems to us doubtful that
historians have yet come to grips with this development, in the sense of
having found a language to tell us exactly what happened in the space
of a few generations. We are still far too close to the scene,
chronologically, to take the measure of this revolution; it is an
upheaval yet in progress and its consequences cascade over us daily.
We are too numb to grasp its magnitude: that privilege must fall to
future historians.
We are nevertheless at liberty to make modest observations on the
political concomitants of these transformations. In the first place, it is
clear that millenarian hopes for the reconstruction of the social order
along scientific lines hardly disappeared with the collapse of
revolutionary idealism in France and the subsequent catastrophe of the
Napoleonic Wars. The tradition of social engineering continued in
the schemes of the Utilitarians, of Robert Owen and Charles Fourier, of
the New England Transcendentalists, and of Auguste Comte. 3 Though
of little historical consequence, these demonstrate how the habit of
assuming that society is a tractable category, analytically and
politically, had become ingrained in Western thought. They
demonstrate almost equally well the rough equation of a more
scientific social order with a more egalitarian one, and the
opposition between a view of the world informed by science and one
occluded by stagnant tradition. This observation takes on particular
poignancy when we consider the curious intellectual trajectory of Karl
Marx, an epochal thinker who eagerly admired science in the abstract,
envied the inevitability of its logic, conscripted its prestige for his own
polemical purposes, and still managed in the end to misunderstand it
thoroughly.
In speaking of science and its social consequences in the
nineteenth century, we cannot avoid the notion of Progress and its
role in the generally optimistic view of historical process that held
sway during that period. Contemporary critics have told us repeatedly
and with great sagacity how problematical the idea of progress is.
Progress for whom, in what direction, at what expense to which class?
The progress of the upstart manufacturer in the English midlands or the
New England mill town may well have affronted the seigniorial pride
of the landed aristocrat or the Tidewater planterhardly an outrage to
ones democratic sentiments. On the other hand, the industrialists
prosperity was the millworkers hell. The technology that minted
wealth for its owners forged chains for its servants. The superiority of
the technologized economic superstructure of Europe and the United
States exacted a terrible tribute from millions of Chinese, Indians,
Latin Americans, and Filipinos, who had no reason to praise the
scientific virtuosity that showered them with shells and bullets.
In the final analysis, a real if grossly imperfect alignment
persisted between the scientific outlook and the great emancipatory
sentimentsabolitionism, womens rights, social reform, socialism
itselfthat drove the most idealistic souls of the era. To put it another
way, the science that sustained the most ferociously antiegalitarian
ideasracist eugenics, social Darwinism, and the likehas long
since been effaced, while the claims put forth to bolster the egalitarian
view have endured, on the whole, rather well. At any rate, if we are to
judge a body of ideas by its worst enemies, it is simply absurd to
impugn science as the tool of the most embittered reactionaries. Those
forces, represented by Maistre and by Pius IX, the pope who denounced
socialism, modernism, and the scientific outlook in a single breath,
were convinced that their quarrel with science was a struggle to the
death. Martin Heidegger was their recent offspring. To the extent that
the liberatory and democratic ideals that roiled the nineteenth century
and persist to our day with amplified force face the adamant resistance
of dogmatic religions of one sort or another (hardly a dead issue in a
world beset by a swarm of angry fundamentalisms), science, it would
seem, has been and will be their strongest and least dispensable ally.
There are many reasonably well read people to whom the growing
antagonism toward science on the part of a large number of left-wing
intellectuals will come as something of a surprise. There is a tendency,
mostly justified, as we have seen, to think of political progessivism
as naturally linked to a struggle against obscurantism, superstition, and
the dead weight of religious and social dogma. In this effort, the
obvious ally and chief resource is scientific knowledge of the world and
the systematic methodology that supports it, as these have developed
over the past few centuries, chiefly in Western culture. Though the
specific achievements of science are of some polemical importance for
certain ongoing disputes, far more valuable and effective have been the
modalities of critical and skeptical thought that have matured for the
most part in a scientific context. The dissecting blade of scientific
skepticism, with its insistence that theories are worthy of respect only
to the extent that their assertions pass the twin tests of internal logical
consistency and empirical verification, has been an invaluable weapon
against intellectual authoritarianisms of all sorts, not least those that
sustain social systems based on exploitation, domination, and
absolutism. The notion that human liberation ought to be the chief
project of the intellectual community is, it seems to us, coeval with the
idea that superstition and credulity are among the most powerful foes
of liberation, and that science, in particular, holds out the best hope for
cutting through their fogs of error and confusion. Towering figures of
political and ethical thought over the last three or four centuries make
this point; one thinks, in this regard, of Galileo, Spinoza, Locke,
Voltaire, Diderot, Lessing, Hume, Kant, Mill, Herzen, Turgenev,
Russell, Einsteinthe list could be extended endlessly. And, of course,
one thinks of Marx, albeit with a sad irony that dwells on weaknesses in
his mode of thinking, whose consequences and echoes will, to a great
extent, comprise the focus of this argument.
Our era is singular, in that the commonplace wisdom cited in the
last paragraph (wisdom we hold to be as valid as any generalization can
be) has come under strident and increasingly scornful attack, not from
reactionaries and traditionalists, who have always feared science, but
from its natural heirsthe community of thinkers, theoreticians, and
activists who challenge both the material injustices of the existing
social system and the underlying assumptions and prejudices that
perpetuate them. As Timothy Ferris observes in his appropriately
skeptical review of a recent and popular anti-scientific polemic, The
scientific community today, for all its faults, remains generally open
and unsecretive, international and egalitarian: It is no accident that
scientists are to be found at the forefront among those who call for
global ecological responsibility, racial and sexual equality, better
education, an end to hunger, a fair break for indigenous peoples, and
other enlightened values.4 Yet the alliance, so historically familiar
that one is tempted to call it natural, between the scientific
worldview and the tradition of egalitarian social criticism, is not only
under challenge but, from some points of view, may be said already to
have dissolved. This has to be understood not as a hazy generality about
the zeitgeist, but rather as an observation about a specific community, a
particular, if rather limited, contemporary social formation: that of
self-conscious left-wing political intellectuals and those who follow
their work with attention and approval, and take a measure of
inspiration from it.
We are particularly interested in the American left, although its
pugnacity toward science is certainly echoed by left-wing intellectuals
in Western Europe. Some of the key ideas, now common currency on
American campusesthe strong programme in sociology of science
associated with the Edinburgh school, the compendium of
postmodern attitudes transcribed from Derrida, Foucault, Lyotard,
Baudrillard et alii, to take a few obvious examplesare, in fact,
imports. Nonetheless, the antiscientism of the American academic left
has its own idiosyncratic resonances, if only because it is integral to a
much broader array of challenges to received wisdom and settled ideas.
For many left-wing thinkers, a radically skeptical attitude toward
standard science is a means of burning ones bridges, of disavowing
ones connection to a spectrum of liberal Enlightenment values, moral
as well as epistemological. It is a symptom, therefore, of profound
distress at the inability of that value system to deliver on its promises.
In the present situation, the orthodoxies of liberal humanism seem to
have curdled, and the resplendent intellectual achievements that
symbolize the worth of liberal humanist attitudes seem ripe for
dismissal. The defiant bravado that marks the various critiques of
science (ill advised and vainglorious though we think it to be) is an
index of the pained confusion of the left in the face of a world that
seems impervious to its insights, however brilliantly thought out or
passionately expressed.
For many left-intellectuals, social justice and economic equity
seem ever more elusive as practical possibilities. American society and
the global capitalism of which the United States is still the epicenter go
their own way without taking much notice of left-wing thought. The
problem of race in this country seems to be more intractable than ever.
The changing demography of the American population seems to
promise not an amiable and beneficent polyculturalism, but rather an
increasingly venomous tribalism and nativism. Feminists see
themselves as driven into a defensive circle, and the agitation for
equitable treatment of homosexuals seems often to be answered by
paranoia and violence. The hope, which was never quite absent from
the heart of even the most disillusioned leftist, that actually existing
socialism in the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe might finally be
able to escape the horrors of its Stalinist past and take on the task of
building a worthy alternative to capitalism, is irredeemably dead. There
may be a resurgence of political liberalism in this country, but, if so, it
will be, at best, a pallid and compromised liberalism, unlikely to
accommodate very much in the way of redemptive social design. The
contemporary, popular definition of liberalism is a political tendency
to leave things pretty much alone, except that they are to be funded,
whenever possible, and monitored, by agents of a wise and beneficent
government.
Meanwhile, the historical constituency of the American left is
fragmented. The traditional moral language of the left, deriving as it
does from Enlightenment humanism, seems to have lost its power to
exhort and unite. It is hard, for example, to imagine a contemporary
black militant employing the rhetoric of Paul Robeson or Martin Luther
King; Malcolm X seems to be the only relevant historical figure.
Feminism has long since wandered into its own discursive universe.
The new immigrant groups from Asia and Latin America have little
familiarity with the themes of working-class emancipation that inspired
Irishmen, Germans, Swedes, Italians, and Polish Jews in the factories,
sweatshops, mines, and rail-yards of America a century ago.
We ought not to wonder, then, that so many academic leftists (as
opposed merely to Democrats who win elections), finding themselves
in a dispiriting historical corner, are in a sullen mood, a mood in which
it seems that the most immediate solace comes from devising reasons
for discounting and minimizing the proudest accomplishments of the
smug society that surrounds them. The history of Western artistic and
intellectual achievement no longer provides hope or inspirationon
the contrary, it taunts and irritates. As the wholly owned subsidiary of a
despised culture, it becomes the target for contempt and disparagement.
The philosophical concomitant of this attitude is, unsurprisingly, a
defiant relativism.
True enough, these instincts find expression in what often seems
like a positive program. The dethronement of the literary and artistic
canon, for instance, is packaged carefully and announced to all who
hear and read as a movement to empower the unempowered by letting
us all hear the voices of those heretofore silenced. New modes of doing
sociology and anthropology are proposed as ways of rescuing
historically subordinate peoples from the ignominious position of
objects of study, and endowing them with agency and meaningful
historical will. This is by no means a hypocritical or disingenuous pose.
These arguments do have moral force. They have to be reckoned with
(although not to the exclusion of countervailing ideas) by anyone
concerned with equity and the redress of historical injustice.
Nevertheless, the aroma of sour grapes is in the air. The urge to redeem
slides easily into an eagerness to debunk for the sake of debunking.
New candidates for venerationwriters, artists, musicians,
philosophers, historical figures, non-Western ways of knowingare
put forward not for what they are but for what they are notwhite,
European, male.
It is impossible to understand fully the academic lefts attack on
science without taking into account how much resentment is embodied
in it. Science is, if anything, a more natural target for the frustrated
spite of the left than literature or art or other aspect of high culture.
Shakespeare, Beethoven, and Rembrandt may adorn the theaters,
concert halls, and museums of the rich, but they are long dead; and, in
any case, there is a venerable tradition of regarding artists per se as
rebels, malcontents, and social critics. Science, on the other hand, is
anything but antique. It thrivesor, as its critics would have it,
fulminatesin the heart of the contemporary world. What is more, it is
an indispensable prop to the politics and commerce of that world. It
builds the bombs for the Pentagon and fiber-optics networks for the
stock exchanges of the world. It computes the macroeconomic
projections of the neoclassical economists and the demographic
projections of cynical political operatives. It creates an enormous
environmental mess and then charges us an arm and a leg to clean it up!
It has all of us by the throat.
Resentment is a strong force in human affairs; philosophical
caution is deplorably weak. The lefts resentment of science is no
sillier than that of, say, religious fundamentalists. Typically, it is
expressed with incomparably greater cleverness and verbal agility.
Nonetheless, resentment is not a trustworthy ally in any intellectual
endeavor. In the present case it has betrayed left-wing intellectuals into
futility.
Neither of us is a professional historian; yet we have undertaken a
study that has important historical dimensions. We cannot ignore them
or dismiss them with the currently fashionable glibness. The lefts
flirtation with irrationalism, its reactionary rejection of the scientific
worldview, is deplorable and contradicts its own deepest traditions. It is
a kind of self-defeating apostasy. But it is not the result of a sudden
whim or of spontaneous mass hysteria. It has a history. We owe the
reader some sense of our understanding of that history, non-
professional as it may be, before proceeding to the details of our
critique.
Science as Power
Explanation
In general, even when cultural constructivists make a more serious
effort to put forth an account of what is supposed to go on during this
process of cultural construction there is a strong flavoring of
circularity. It is assumed ab initio that cultural construction has taken
place. Thereupon, the historical and scientific record is subjected to a
strained and arbitrary reading that decodes it with the help of a great
deal of interpretive contortion and hermeneutic hootchy-koo. At last an
account is produced that explains how the culture has constructed the
theory. This is then put forth as a confirmation of the cultural
constructivist hypothesis. In form and soundness, this procedure
closely resembles the methodology through which the tenets of
psychoanalysis are confirmed by the interpretive prowess of the
psychoanalyst.14 In both instances, circularity and special pleading rule
the day, and little worthy evidence emerges.
In saying this, we are not trying to deny that social interests and
nonscientific belief systems often enter into the very human business of
doing creative science, sometimes to catalyze the process, more often
to retard or deflect it. The work of Stephen J. Gould15 (who must be
recognized as holding strong leftist views) is replete with incisive
essays on examples of this, presented in minute detail. But Goulds
well-informed work is by no means comparable to the cultural
constructivist program. Gould knows perfectly well that in the long run
logic, empirical evidence, and explanatory parsimony are the masters
(with apology to our feminist friends for the metaphor) in the house of
science. In this he echoes Thomas Kuhn,16 whose work has so often
been vulgarized and distorted by the cultural constructivist school.17
Cultural constructivism, at least in the full-blooded version of
ideologues like Aronowitz, is a relentlessly mechanistic and
reductionistic way of thinking about things. It flattens human
differences, denies the substantive reality of human idiosyncracy, and
dismisses the ability of the intellect to make transcendent imaginative
leaps, in a way that OBrien, 1984s master manipulator of
consciousness, would cheerfully approve. According to the
constructivist canon, all are puppets of the temper of an age, and
science is just another inadvertent ratification of its ideological
premises. Only the cultural constructivists themselves (of course) are
licensed to escape the intellectual tyranny of this invisible hand. For
their part, mathematicians, physicists, chemists, and biologists must all
succumb.
Aronowitz represents cultural constructivism with all its
philosophical and political cards on the table, so to speak. His program
is maximalist in both respects and forthrightly asserts its prescriptive
ambitions even as it makes its sweeping descriptive judgments. Other
theorists and publicists of the constructivist school are more
circumspect in their claims and cagier in their tactics. They are content,
for the time being, to conduct an irregular guerrilla war on behalf of
their doctrine, while Aronowitz insists on undisguised frontal assault.
Typically, in the face of all-out challenges from scientists and
philosophers armed to do intellectual battle, they edge away from the
strong version of the constructivist claim and retreat to the proper
territory of sociology or history. In the presence of a different audience,
one primed to hear science contextualized, relativized, and revealed as
the deformed offspring of capitalist hegemony, the constructivist claws
come out once more.
Plutocrats
Cultural constructivist theories of science have lately infested the
usually staid domain of the history of ideas. One well-known example
is the work of Shapin and Schaffer, whose book Leviathan and the Air
Pump has a wide circle of admirers. This work is rather more orthodox,
on a superficial level, than Latours. It is an intellectual history of some
of the resounding disputes that surrounded the birth of experimental
sciencephysics in particularin the last half of the seventeenth
century. What particularly concerns Shapin and Schaffer is the quarrel
between some of the most prominent founders of the Royal Society
Boyle, Hooke, and their circleand the philosopher Thomas Hobbes,
author of Leviathan. This is the fulcrum upon which they attempt to
push the case that, contrary to its flattering image as a uniquely wide-
open and tolerant enterprise, welcoming of all new facts, information,
and ideas that bear upon its investigations, modern science has been
from the first the province of a tightly organized, well-insulated
coterie, jealous of its prerogatives and hostile toward outsiders who
intrude without the proper credentials. Moreover, this self-appointed
scientific aristocracy is seen as organically connected to the ruling elite
of Western society. Its views are derived, albeit subtly, from the
dominant metaphors of that elite. By the same token, its prestige,
authority, and epistemological monopoly are guaranteed by the power
of the state and the social formations it principally serves. The
argument between Hobbes and the adherents of the Royal Society is
offered as an instance of this phenomenon:
The restored regime [i.e., that of Charles II] concentrated upon
means of preventing a relapse into anarchy through the discipline
it attempted to exercise over the production and dissemination of
knowledge. These political considerations were constituents of the
evaluation of rival natural philosophical programmes [i.e., that of
the Royal Societys experimentalists, as opposed to the a prioristic
rationalism of Hobbes].
Thus the disputes between Boyle and Hobbes became an issue
of the security of certain social boundaries and the interests they
expressed.27
Professors in the humanities are not, by and large, any more feeble-
minded than the general run of humanity, nor are they particularly
feckless in the affairs of day-to-day life. Moreover, despite the hopes of
readers of the National Review or the American Spectator, left-wing
political opinions are not especially inconsistent with high intelligence
either, nor do they lead to a generalized susceptibility to muddled
thinking. Why, then, has so large a proportion of the left-wing
professoriate in literature and adjacent disciplines been so ripe for
seduction by the potpourri of viewsdeconstructionist, Foucauldian,
and otherwisetraveling under the catchall term postmodernism?
Deconstructionism in its pure form would seem to be an unlikely
candidate for such popularity. It is a uniquely disenchanted and
crepuscular philosophy, carrying the reek of a decadent mandarinate
that has seen everything once too often. To toy with ideas in such an
idle and self-vitiating fashion would seem to confess a lack of interest
in bringing about salutary change in human affairs. For its part,
Foucauldian analysis, despite the tender-heartedness of some of its
instincts, seems equally to lead to resignation and quietism. If
consciousness is such a prisoner of powerand Foucault seems much
more gloomy than Marx in this respectthen hopes for a break with
the oppressive past must be futile indeed. Notes Alan Ryan, Princeton
professor of politics:
It is, for instance, pretty suicidal for embattled minorities to
embrace Michel Foucault, let alone Jacques Derrida. The minority
view was always that power could be undermined by truth Once
you read Foucault as saying that truth is simply an effect of power,
youve had it But American departments of literature, history,
and sociology contain large numbers of self-described leftists who
have confused radical doubts about objectivity with political
radicalism, and are in a mess.21
Philosophical Revenge
This sort of thing, while for the most part unimpressive to the
scientists, tended to convince many humanistsand a good part of the
social-science community as wellthat a craving for methodological
respectabilityscientism or physics envy as it was sometimes
calledmust lead to a sterile (and politically reactionary) view of
human affairs, denying ineluctable truths about the human situation.32
Thus it probably came to pass that when the brutally skeptical
views of the postmodernists began to gain currency some years later,
many humanists, and many social scientists as well, were quick to lay
hold of them as instruments of revenge.33 If the carefully crafted
opinions of literary experts were to be consigned to epistemological
limbo by analytic philosophy, those experts and their academic progeny
now had in handor so they thoughtan instrument that could drag
down the scientists and other pursuers of objective knowledge with
all the rest. This view accounts at least in part for the paradox that on
embracing postmodernism, humanist scholars have in many instances
cruelly repudiated the accomplishments of their own disciplines, even
to the point of denouncing their own earlier work.
However varied the reasons for the embrace of postmodernism in
the universities, it is clear that the phenomenon is almost wholly
associated with the self-described political left. As far as the
ideological right is concerned, the situation presents it with welcome
opportunities for polemical sallies, counterblows that avoid the
necessity for justifying the illogical or evil practices of their own
heroes and of whatever world (usually of the recent past) they like to
think of as the best of all possible worlds. With postmodernism the
target, conservatives easily move the discussion onto the loftier plane
on which the relativist caprices of Derrida, Lyotard, and the rest are the
principal focus. Roger Kimballs Tenured Radicals adopts this strategy
in part, but its underlying politics are relatively transparent, compared
to arguments that seem never to stray in the slightest from disinterested
philosophical inquiry. 34 It is often hard to read the writers political
position from such critiques, and some of them, in fact, issue from
impeccably left-wing thinkers.
For the first time in modern American history, right-wing theorists
seem on the point of establishing themselves upon the ethical and
philosophical high ground, thanks to the postmodern contortions of the
left. This fact, however, has little penetrated left-academic discourse;
the entanglement of would-be progressive intellectuals with the
conceptual freak show of postmodernism continues to isolate and
neutralize them, at least outside the hothouses (i.e., academic
departments and conferences) in which they flourish. One will cheer or
deplore this fact as ones political tendencies dictate.
We are obviously not able to consider here each and every intellectual
curio that arises from the now widespread effort of postmodern
theorists to bring science under their scrutiny. A few of the more
redolent examples must suffice to illustrate the general tendency. For
the sake of unity, and to reserve discussion of other sciences for later
chapters, those we consider here have to do with a certain recent
development in the mathematical sciencesso-called chaos theory
that has drawn an unusual (for a mathematical subject) amount of
public interest. Quite naturally, it has been a proving ground for
postmodern critics eager to try their apparatus in the venue of modern
scientific thought, and eager to justify their philosophic maxims by
appeal to ostensible paradigm shifts in science. This tactic is not so
rudely dismissive of science and scientists as Andrew Rosss frontal
assault. Nonetheless, in positing the emergence of a postmodern
science which, it is claimed, illustrates the validity of the postmodern
weltanschauung, these analyses in effect derogate the reliability and
accuracy of standard science, and snidely disparage those scientists
that is to say, the vast majority of all scientistswho have been
oblivious to this ostensible revolution in thought.
Any but the briefest description of chaos theory would be out of
place here. The term refers to developments in pure and applied
mathematics, particularly to a branch named dynamical systems
theory: the study of systems that change with time. Typically, these are
deterministic; that is, the state of the system at one instant completely
determines its state at all subsequent moments. The locus classicus of
dynamical systems theory is the great work of Isaac Newton on
celestial mechanics, that is, the theory of how stars, planets, moons,
asteroids, comets, and so forth move under the influence of gravity.
Chaos theory essentially addresses this conundrum: knowing that a
system is in theory deterministic is by no means equivalent to having
an effective means for predicting its behavior as a function of an initial
condition, namely, the state of the system at one particular time. The
optimism of late eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century
mathematicians, astronomers, and physicists that practicable methods
of computation would become available for making such predictions in
all reasonably simple cases turns out to have been premature, although
it inspired brilliant work sufficient to handle many such problems,
including most that have to be dealt with in engineering and day-to-day
science. As it happens, however, there are very simple systems, in the
sense that they involve a small number of parameters and a very
straightforward law of evolution, where prediction becomes
essentially impossible beyond a short period of time. Whats more,
there are significant qualitative as well as quantitative aspects to
this inability. For instance, the trajectories of evolution of two systems
that start out microscopically close, as far as their respective initial
conditions are concerned, can diverge wildly, not only in a numerical
sense but in their geometric aspects. Thus, to make matters more
concrete, an astronomer may find that it is impossible to make a good
prediction about the qualitative behavior of a planetary system because,
first of all, the methods at hand for solving the relevant differential
equations are far too inaccurate, and furthermore, even if the first
difficulty could be got round, a tiny error in determining the initial
condition (which is of course inevitable) can result in a gross
qualitative error in characterizing the long-term behavior of the
system.
Dynamical systems theory is a very geometric subject, as modern
mathematicians understand the term, and, in consequence, many of
these bizarre phenomena can be illustrated, with the aid of computer-
generated graphics, by weird and beautiful pictures. This alone
accounts for much of the public interest in these developments. (It
accounts as well, we must admit, for much of the popularity of the
subject among mathematicians themselves, not to mention legions of
computer-users with skill at graphics.) Nonetheless, despite their
didactic value, the accessibility of such pictures may have the effect of
deceiving the intelligent layman into believing that he grasps the
subject better than he really does. To be undiplomatic, a solid
understanding of what is really involved requires a considerable
amount of formal mathematical knowledge.
The foundations of the subject were laid at the end of the
nineteenth century by the great mathematician Henri Poincar, and in a
sense modern chaos theory represents a resumption of this work after a
long hiatus. The reasons for this slumber are as follows:
1. The attention that Poincares work should have attracted from
physicists and mathematicians was understandably diverted by the
stunning developments in theoretical physics that took place at the
beginning of the twentieth century (special and general relativity and
quantum mechanics). These quite naturally absorbed the lions share of
intellectual energy of those best placed to follow up Poincars
implications. (It is worth noting in passing that, even had Einstein
never been born, Poincar would almost certainly have come up with
relativity on his own at about the same time.)
2. The possibility of developing chaos theory as a mathematically
consistent subject depends on a huge body of foundational
mathematical work in such areas as topology, differential geometry,
and the theory of computational complexity, most of which was done
long after Poincars day.
3. Mathematical theories cannot grow without a host of specific
examples on which the mathematician must rely to sharpen and modify
his intuition before setting out to erect a systematic mathematical
structure incorporating them. So far as chaos theory is concerned, most
of the paradigmatic examples cannot be worked out by ordinary pencil
and paper computations; nor can geometric pictures easily be drawn by
relying solely on naive intuition. These examples were forthcoming
only after the development of high-speed electronic computers in the
1950s and 60s and the subsequent refinement of computer graphics
techniques.
The best-known book on the subject is James Gleicks ChaosThe
Birth of a New Science. While commendably accurate on the
underlying mathematical principles and their relevance for a host of
scientific questions, Gleicks book, perhaps inevitably, overdramatizes
the history of the subject in trying to make its protagonists fascinating.
In point of fact, there is nothing, on the level of personal idiosyncracy,
that can be said to distinguish specialists in chaos theory from other
mathematicians and theoretical physicists. They are not pointedly more
heretical in temperament. They just happen to work on dynamical
systems theory, as opposed to low-dimensional topology or geometric
measure theory or Hopf algebras. Moreover, chaos theory, for all its
beauty and scientific relevance, is not the dominant theme in
contemporary mathematics, for the simple reason that nothing is.
Mathematics is stupendously vast and varied, and every year results
appear in one specialty or another that are just as delightfully
surprising and involve just as great intuitive leaps as those of chaos
theory. So far as physics and the other mathematical sciences are
concerned, chaos theory is certainly a helpful source of new techniques
and insights, but it cannot by any means be said to put everything else
in the shade. If one insists on calling the development of chaos theory a
paradigm shift in the Kuhnian sense of the term, it probably does no
harm, as long as it is kept in mind that within the scientific community
there is not much sense of foundations being overturned. A more apt
metaphor is that a bright light has been turned on, better illuminating
what we already knew, making visible some fascinating fine detail, and
revealing promising paths for further investigation. There has been
very little in the way of culture shock.
We point out that some contemporary popular myths about chaos
theory are corrected in the book by David Ruelle,39 one of the founders
and accomplished masters of the subject. For those who want a brief
and clear exposition of the basic notions, we recommend also Harmke
Kammingas essay in, of all places, New Left Review.40 (This may
reassure some on the left who misunderstand the polemical intentions
of this book. On the other hand, even the most conservative reader will
be able to get through Kammingas piece without elevation of blood
pressure.) Kamminga wisely chose to write her exposition in
consultation with a number of experts, and she observes prudently that
chaos and nonlinearity may be in danger of being seen as the solution
to everything. Uncritical use of the notion of the butterfly effect and
glib assertions that life is a strange attractor threaten to turn chaos
theory into a new mysticism. Ruelle would certainly agree, as would
most mathematicians and physicists. This has not forestalled the
emergence of a fad among historians, social theorists, and literary
intellectuals, a number of whom are given to studding their essays with
knowing references to chaos theory as a way of dressing up truisms
about the complexity of life, art, and human experience.41
Her point seems to be that the Principia and the special theory are
products of the halcyon times of pre-World War I Europe (a conceit
that leads to the gaffe on logical positivism). This ignores the fact that
both efforts are the result of extreme intellectual crises, albeit crises of
which the general culture, and even the rarefied cultures of
philosophers and the literary intelligentsia, were entirely unaware. The
Principia sprang from Russells discovery of the set-theory paradox
that bears his name, which rendered unsatisfactory the prior work of
Cantor and Frege on the foundations of mathematics. Relativity derived
from Einsteins realization that the mathematics of Maxwells
equations raised serious questions about classical notions of absolute
time and space. These crises were known only to a handful of
mathematical scientists. The idea that something in the ambient culture
whether under Hayless interpretation or some competing version
stressing the subterranean tensions that led to World War Igenerated
these magnificent works is thus wildly implausible.
Correspondingly, Hayless idea that such intellectual projects as
the Principia, relativity, and logical positivism would have been far
more difficult after the war (ignoring even the fact that logical
positivism was one of the most characteristic such postwar projects) is
a febrile delusion of doctrinaire reading. The silliness of the cited
paragraph is perhaps most apparent when one considers that both
Einstein and Russell were highly conscious of the emptiness of
patriotic rhetoric long before the war, even as they were in the midst of
their great work on the foundations of physics and mathematics
respectively. The lesson to be learned, then, is that cultural
constructivist theories of science deserve to be treated with the gravest
suspicion, whether they derive from sociology, Foucauldian
historicism, or deconstructive literary theory.
All the strange pronouncements upon which we have focused
occur, as we note, on one page. There is nothing particularly special
about that page. This book is stuffed with similar solecisms, which
makes reading it a painful experience. Yet the work is published by a
distinguished university press and has garnered Hayles a substantial
degree of recognition, including an endowed chair at a major
university, a Guggenheim Fellowship, the presidency of the Society for
Literature and Science, and the chairmanship of the literature and
science committee of the Modern Language Association; so we ought
not to conclude that this is some kind of crackpot tract of the New Age
movement (although the word crackpot unkindly leaps to mind when
one has to read it). This is very much in the academic mainstream, as
commandeered by the votaries of postmodernism.
The point, finally, is not to berate Haylesor Best, for that matter
for mathematical subliteracy. That, in itself, is nothing like a
disgrace. Hundreds of millions of bright, able, and accomplished
people share this minor affliction (and quite a few mathematicians are
weak, to say the least, on postmodernist thought). But when such
solecisms as we find in these writings are confidently put forth as
scholarly discoveries, with every assurance that something profound is
being uttered, one must wonder about the systemand the ideology
that nurtures and rewards them. Whence, we must ask, does such
grossly misplaced intellectual self-confidence come? The smug,
hermetic, self-referential atmosphere of politicized academic
postmodernism obviously has a great deal to do with it. In this milieu,
there is not much thought given to simple scientific accuracy. The
caution and scrupulousness that working scientists are conditioned to
expect are swept aside, because, in the final analysis, postmodernist
work is in great measure prophetic and hortatory, rather than analytic:
it announces and cheers on a sweeping paradigm shift within our
civilization, a change that is supposed to liberate us all.
We suspect that the reader who has followed this brief survey will
be left with a few questions. First of all, why is the technical question
of mathematical linearity versus nonlinearity so intriguing to
supposed experts in culture and literature? Of course, as we have noted,
the success of Gleicks book on the emergence of mathematical chaos
theory and its scientific applications has left much of the literate but
scientifically inexpert public with a somewhat distorted sense of the
overall configuration of the mathematical sciences, of the enormous
compass of contemporary mathematics, both pure and applied, and of
the relative importance of various ideas within that field. The very
accessibility of Gleiks work, and subsequent efforts in the same line,
have thus had the unintended consequence of calling forth portentous
pronouncements from cultural critics, whose knowledge of the
relevant science is largely limited to these necessarily oversimplified
accounts.
Beyond this, however, there is a deep confusion of categories, and
a surprisingly naive sense that the use of the same English word in
widely separated contexts assures that there are deep thematic
similarities. To a paid-up member of the postmodern academic left, the
word linear, for example, carries negative connotations. It suggests
relentless sequentiality, unbending purposefulness, singlemindedness,
the triumph of the instrumentalin other words, the mentality that is
held to underlie the predicated Western ethos of conquest, domination,
objectification, and rigid delineation of oppressive categories via
binary oppositions.58 Inevitably, nonlinearity is seen by contrast to
have liberatory implications. It suggests many-sidedness,
multiculturalism, diversity, polymorphism, the effacement of
boundaries. Thus the revolution for which the postmodernist yearns,
realistically or otherwise, is one in which the linear regime of late
capitalist society will be supplanted by a nonlinear ethos, in which
multiplicity reigns in the cultural and sexual realms, and in which all
sorts of boundaries may freely be crossed.
It shouldbut obviously does notgo without saying that the
mathematical notion of linearity, or its absence, in regard to functions,
differential operators, dynamical systems, or whatever, while
technically indispensable, has nothing whatsoever to do with such
sociocultural questions. Of course, anyone is free to read pictures of
fractal geometry and the like subjectively as emblems for a revolution
in sensibilityor in politics, for that matter. The point is, however, that
this is utterly subjective; it is poetry of the most idiosyncratic sort.
Postmodern cultural transformation is no more inscribed in the
mathematical peculiarities of nonlinear dynamical systems than Nazi
doctrine is to be read in the geometric configuration of the swastika. To
hold otherwise is to revert to the magical, emblematic thinking of
premodern (rather than postmodern) times. It certainly doesnt deserve
the name of scholarship.
It is also useful to consider the sense in which these theoretical
extravagances of would-be philosophers of culture are hostile to
science and to scientists. Obviously, there is some subtlety here. Some
of these critics seem, after all, on the face of things, to be celebrating
science, or at least some of its recent achievements. They see certain
new themes in the sciences as harbingers of a desirable cultural change.
Hostility is there, however, and its presence becomes clearer when we
take note of the moralizing undertone. What is really being asserted is
that there is a modern science, linked to phallogocentric thought
and the mechanisms of capitalist-racist-patriarchal dominationin
other words, the science that William Blake, in an earlier era, decried
as single vision and Newtons sleep. By contrast, there is supposed to
be an embryonic postmodern science that points to the overthrow of
the old order. This theme can be traced in the continued insistence that
the chaos theory postmodernists think they are talking about is post-
Newtonian (even though it is perfectly clear to the mathematically
literate that Newtonian themes are central to these new developments,
whether they address Newtonian celestial mechanics or the fractal
geometry of the basins of attraction of the roots of a polynomial that
appear when Newtons method is applied in the complex plane). 59 The
Newton that postmodern cultural critics are trying to escape is
Blakes figment, not the preeminent mathematician and physicist of the
same name.
We conclude that hostility to science is, after all, an inextricable
element of these postmodern philosophical excursions. It takes the
form of the good guys (persons?) versus bad guys scenario that the
critics impose relentlessly on the history and sociology of science. It is
mirrored in the remarkable arrogance with which postmodernists
address these issues. Virtually all of them claim to discern important
intellectual themes and political motifs in past and current science,
themes and motifs that are quite invisible to the scientists themselves.
These supposed insights rest, as we have seen, on a technical
competence so shallow and incomplete as to be analytically worthless.
Their arrogance, then, is comparable to that of creation scientists in
addressing evolutionary biology, or to that of Galileos persecutors
within the Inquisition in their response to his cosmology. We probably
dont need to fear for the safety or intellectual freedom of the sciences
on the basis of these bizarre lucubrations: but that is not the issue.
What does concern us is that these intellectual misadventures are so
well received in nonscientific academic circles, especially on the left,
and that they provide the route to publication, tenure, reputation, and
academic authority for a growing body of would-be scholars.
We must hope that the painful bolus of postmodernism will pass
through the costive bowels of academic life sooner rather than later.
Pass, of course, it will eventually. 60 Keeping the hard sciences from
contamination should not be impossible, provided that the scientists
resistance to jargonistic snow jobs is as high as it ought to be. We do
worry about that, however. In the meantime, unfortunately, the
postmodernists will be out there trying to dominate every intellectual
conversation. Have they not imbibed the wisdom of the sage?
And everyone will say
As you walk your mystic way
If this young man expresses himself in terms too deep for me,
Why, what a very singularly deep young man
This deep young man must be!
CHAPTER FIVE
Auspicating Gender
Would not physics benefit from asking why a scientific world view
with physics as its paradigm excludes the history of physics from
its recommendation that we seek causal explanations of everything
in the world around us? Only if we insist that science is
analytically separate from social life can we maintain the fiction
that explanations of irrational social belief and behavior could not
ever, even in principle, increase our understanding of the world
physics explains.
SANDRA HARDING, THE SCIENCE QUESTION IN FEMINISM
Feminist Success
Feminist Algebra
Haploid Hermeneutics
Justificatory Strategies
An die Natur
Context Ineluctable
A few years ago, the novelist Ursula Le Guin, who is as much at home
in ordinary fiction as in fantasy and science fiction, scored a
considerable success with an unusual story, Always Coming Home, set
in the far future. The scene is a North America peopled by tribes
separated from each other politically and culturally, with hardly a
memory of the days of a continent-spanning nationstate. The tale
concentrates on one such group, the Kesh, whose ways and customs,
although they are Le Guins invention, strongly echo the folkways of
pre-Columbian Native Americans.
The Kesh culture is elaborately described in the novel: it is the
books true hero. An appendix provides information about the
language, poetry, music, and artwork of the Kesh, with specimens of
each. At its publication, the book was accompanied by a series of
ancillary productsrecordings of Kesh songs and chants, replicas of
Kesh paintingsall created by Le Guin in collaboration with artists
and musicians fascinated by her vision of this possible future. It proved
a popular line of goods at science-fiction bookstores and New Age
specialty shops, and the full setbook and recordingsremains a
popular item on university library reserve for students.
The strangest aspect of the Kesh culture is the degree to which it
has rejected not only technology as such (the Kesh live close to nature,
with minimal use of steam power and electricity, and every artifact
they produce is handmade and imbued with the qualities of art), but
also the entire set of attitudes, ambitions, and obsessions of what we
tend to think of as civilization. They have no interest in abstract
science. Their philosophy is embedded in their mythology. Nor do they
concern themselves with history or social theory, or brood upon the
destiny of man. The notion of knowledge for its own sake is alien to
them. Their values are at once entirely in the present and timeless. But
note: their ignorance does not come about because what we, in the
present, call knowledge has disappeared from the face of the earth. In
fact the human culture of the Kesh and the other tribes is paralleled by
a culture of sentient computers, with which the Kesh are in
occasional contact. The machines are willing to divulge to any curious
Kesh such details of scientific theory or historical fact as might be
sought. The point is that the Kesh simply arent interested. Their world
of myth, ritual, and song, and the slow turning of the seasons, satisfies
them. Science and knowledge expand; but that expansion is the
province of computers, which send probes to distant stars and seek the
facts of history in the ruins of previous human civilizations. It is as if
the Faustian impulse of humanity had been drawn off and perfused into
the circuitry of machines, leaving humans in an Eden of contentment
and forget-fulness, through whose gates they have at last returned.
Some readers are repelled by the somnolence of the Kesh and by
their renunciation of ambition; but many are charmed and inspired
(although Le Guin herself seems, at times, to be wryly ambivalent).
The psychology and the ideas of those who admire the Kesh and extol
the edenic virtues of such a society are what interest us here. Our
interest derives not from any concern with minor literary fads
although the talented Le Guin has our best wishesbut from the fact
that the admirers of the Kesh are so emblematicso coextensive, in
factwith radical environmentalism, whose ideology has made itself
widely felt in our time, but which is centered, in large measure, in the
same congregation that includes the academic left.
Among them, support for environmental causes transcends
doctrinal differences. The received version of environmental wisdom
has an unmistakably radicaland apocalypticflavor. The finality of
the conflict, the unflinching identification of one side with good and
the other with evil, are diagnostic. David Day, whose view of
Armageddon is entirely characteristic, introduces a practical workbook
on ecological issues this way, modestly: In the final analysis, the
outcome of the ecology wars will prove more critical than any ever
fought by the human race. What is at stake is not the dominance of one
nation over another, but the survival of life on the planet. 1 Tom
Athanasiou, writing in Socialist Review and in a rational, analytic mood
(for this is criticism of, among other things, ecological romanticism) is
nevertheless certain that the devastation is imminent:
The coming devastation will breed a vast hatred . It may even be
that the ideas of the green hard core are poised for a breakout
into larger domains. Fortunately, this is not the only possibility,
and radical outrage is not likely to remain eternally constrained
within the anti-communist frameworks of Cold War analysis
capitalismlike the atmospheremay soon cease to seem a part
of the natural, eternal world. (Emphasis added.)2
Environmental Realism
Attitudes
An Intellectual Embargo
It would be all too easy to place all the blame for the excesses of
ecological radicalism on the philosophical fancies and whirligigs of the
academic leftbut that would also be facile and incorrect. Some of the
responsibility must be borne by competent, in some cases
distinguished, scientists who have taken up environmental causes.
Much of the apocalyptic rhetoric of ecoradicals derives, albeit by a
process of systematic vulgarization and overstatement, from the public
pronouncements, books, and articles of such scientists. It represents the
last stage of a process of simplification and elision, whereby
speculation, hypothesis, and conclusions of the most provisional sort
are transmuted into certainties. We do not claim that the process is a
matter of wrongheadedness or error on the part of the scientists
involved. Nor are we blaming them, nor suggesting that there is an easy
remedy to be recommended. We are simply suggesting that the
political tactics of some environmentally concerned scientists have a
spectrum of effects; that some of these effects are of dubious value;
and that among the latter are (1) the reinforcement of apocalyptic
hyperbole among radical environmentalists and (2) the suppression of
arguments and evidence that suggest caution as to derived social
policy.
The underlying question is this: What is a responsible, socially
aware scientist to do when his researches and legitimate speculations
lead him to suspect that some aspect of modern technological society
might, in the long run, have horrendous environmental consequences?
We emphasize the hypothetical nature of such predictions simply
because, in their early stages, novel scientific ideas are usually first
approximationseven when they are not (as sometimes happens) false
alarms. Moreover, it is often the case that the direst possibility appears
not as a simple prediction, but as one possibility along a spectrum of
possibilities, one end of which is neutral or even good. This is clearly
the case as regards the effects on global climate of a (nearly certain)
doubling, in the next century, of atmospheric CO2.32
Received Opinion
In Dubious Battle
Thus I think a good case can also be made that the AIDS pandemic
is the fault of the heterosexual white majority.
LARRY KRAMER, REPORTS FROM THE HOLOCAUST
Evil is the oldest and most intractable of all enigmas. Alone among the
species, we know that misfortune is inevitable. And yet, if this
knowledge is universal, so is the propensity to see a malign agent
behind our misfortunes. But in each eventin the living act, the
undoubted deedthere, some unknown but still reasoning thing puts
forth the moulding of its features from behind the unreasoning mask.1
So says Ahab, and so say we all in our most anguished moments. Most
likely, this is a cognitive adaptation of our species, allowing us to
function and continue sane in the face of actual or expected calamity.
Out of it, however, there have emerged most of historys bloody and
wasteful conflicts.
In this chapter we consider certain social and political responses to
evils, real or perceived. In contrast to the arid disputes of the academy,
these are matters that actively and continually roil our civil existence,
and devastate the lives of thousands. Chiefly, we shall be concerned
with the abiding problem of racial justice, and with the AIDS epidemic
that has reawakened slumbering fears of plague and fatal contagion.
Science, obviously, has a great deal to do with the latter problem. In
fact it is our only defense, and our only source of hope. As regards
racial injustice, however, it is not at all clear that science, even in its
most forthright technological guise, has much to do with the situation.
Yet its iconic status as the emblem of intellectual authority and
material power in this era makes it one of the foci of the fantasies and
dreams of the dispossessed.
These problems are not primarily located in the academy, and,
indeed, where they intersectin the blighted neighborhoods where
AIDS is becoming omnipresent but a white face is rarely to be seen
the academy is but a rumor. Yet there is a peculiar and ultimately
unhealthy traffic between the world of rarefied postmodern theory and
the communities in which activism, though stemming from real and
terrible problems, overflows into paranoia and fantasy. Many of the
blind alleys down which activists charge have first been mapped out by
academics bedazzled by contemporary theories of discourse. Thus,
when questions of knowledge and authority arise in connection with
scientific and medical matters, or in a general context, the strange
combination of skepticism and credulity that characterizes the
postmodern stance is strongly echoed. By a process of tacit reciprocity,
the concerns of activiststheir tactics and rhetoric as wellfind
defenders and advocates among the left-wing scholars and cultural
critics to whom resistanceto the social norms of late capitalism
no matter how incoherent in its suppositions and doubtful in its
practices, is always a welcome development.
We also consider here a social stirringthe so-called animal
rights movementthat is, relatively speaking, small and eccentric, and
that arises from concerns that we see as far less compelling than those
that grip AIDS activists and crusaders for racial justice. This, too, is an
arena where the language and attitudes of the academic left are
deployed and, again, the cause is one that a growing number of
academics have come to rationalize, albeit the response is on a far
smaller scale than is the case with race and gender oppression.
AIDS
From the first, there have been legitimate questions within science
about the simple communicable-disease hypothesis, and these have
been followed by illegitimate arguments (mostly from the extreme
right, where homophobia is a reality) to the effect that there is
nothing much for ordinary people to worry about, and that there would
be nothing to worry about at all if certain people would stop doing
unnatural acts.
Best known among scientific critics of the HIV-AIDS hypothesis
has been Peter H. Duesberg, a distinguished Berkeley molecular
biologist. Reduced to its essence, Duesbergs argument is that the full,
classical proofs of causation that link a biological agent to a disease
process remain, in this instance, somewhat lacking; and that if we are
to be left with mere correlation, rather than proof, then the correlation
between AIDS and certain predisposing lifestyles (including heavy
drug use and the accompanying malnutrition) is just as strong as, or
stronger than, the one between AIDS and HIV se-ropositivity.16
Nor is Duesberg alone. Although his arguments have been negated,
successively, over time, as new science has appeared, the undeniable
specificity of the at-risk population persists, and certain lifestyle
characteristics of that populationof coursepersist as well. Serious
epidemiological work and examined clinical experience inevitably
produce correlations: to a large extent, that is what they are about. Thus
it appears that people who actually come down with AIDS are usually
subject to immunosuppressive factors. Among them are: semen-
induced autoimmunity following from anal intercourse; blood
transfusions; multiple infections; chronic use of recreational and
addictive drugs; and so on. This list is from arguments assembled by
Robert Root-Bernstein, a physiologist at Michigan State University. It
is a part of his argument to the effect that, whatever the role of HIV, it
is the predisposing factors, which are themselves products of particular
behaviors (some of them not choices but necessities, as in the case of
hemophiliacs, who need the clotting factors in order to live), that
determine whether AIDS develops. Put bluntly, as does one newspaper
in which this argument has been featured, healthy, drug-free people do
not get AIDS.17
That line of argument would hardly deserve mention in a book
concerned with the thinking of the academic left, since the lifestyle
argument, in its most magniloquent form, is mainly a preoccupation of
the right.18 But it is in fact also used by the left,19 when convenient, to
demonstrate the uncertainties, the indeterminacy, of standard science,
and in some extreme cases, to show that AIDS is a social malady first
and foremost, whereas the scientists are merely playing their
professional and careerist games of elegant research, heedless of the
apocalypse. We shall see samples of this below.
Granting, however, that predisposition to a full-blown syndrome
of any kind increases the likelihood of its appearancewhich is, after
all, a tautologynothing adduced by way of evidence so far has shaken
the infectious hypothesis of AIDS: quite the reverse. 20 In short, AIDS
is a communicablebut not an especially contagiousdisease. Its
communication is limited to particular kinds of risky behavior and
much more rarely to unprotected heterosexual21 contact with infected
persons or with their body fluids. The likelihood of infection in the first
instance, or of progression afterward, may be affected by other factors
of health status; but such modifications of the infection-disease
sequence are very weakly determinative. The disease is caused by a
virus; and despite brilliant, ceaselessly energetic work aimed at finding
effective therapies, there is as yet no treatment that stops the disease in
its tracks, let alone cures it. The most recent epidemiological data on
AZT, the most powerful anti-AIDS drug, show that it has little or no
effect on progression of the disease in seropositive, but still symptom-
free, people.22This is, sadly, no surprise: we havent done much better
with other viral diseases. Unfortunately, this virus, HIV, is a very
smart, successful, and brutal one: it hangs around long enough, silently
enough, in its victim to assure transmission to others, and only
thereafterlong afterdoes it kill.
And another:
My first thesis is that a psychoanalytic perspective on AIDS must
begin by acknowledging that each of us is living with AIDS: we
are all PWAs (Persons With AIDS) insofar as AIDS is structured,
radically and precisely, as the unconscious real of the social field
of contemporary America.
The analogy of social psychosis enables us to understand
AIDS as a condition of the body politic, an index of the socialized
body of the American subject caught in a network of signifiers that
renders it vulnerable to AIDS precisely because, by refusing a
signifier for AIDS, it faces the prospect that what is foreclosed in
the symbolic will return in the real. By persistently representing
itself as having a general population that remains largely
immune to the incidence of AIDS, America pushes AIDS ... to the
outside of its psychic and social economies 33
Either Dr. Moossa stops the course or I will shoot him in the head.
That was the anonymous telephone message from an animal rights
activist to the teacher of a postgraduate surgery course in which,
necessarily, animals were to be used. 40 Dr. Moossa, who has a wife and
children, and an employerthe University of California at San Diego
not even lukewarm about backing him up, stopped the course. And so
his students went without instruction or practice. Had Moossa not
stopped, he might have suffered the same fate as did the obstetrician
recently killed by a crazed activist of the antiabortion movement. We
make this comparison advisedly. Dr. Moossas travails are but one item
on a long list of harassments, threats, and sabotage directed in recent
years against individuals and institutions that do biomedical research
employing animal subjects. Actions include verbal abuse and invective,
picket lines, raids on laboratories to wreck equipment and liberate
laboratory animals, destruction of research notes and records, and, in a
few instances, reasonably well-demonstrated plots to inflict actual
violence on research workers.
These actions represent a surprising resurgence of the
antivivisectionist sentiment that prevailed in the United States and
much of the rest of the Western world in the nineteenth century. As it
happens, much of the renewed fervor can be traced to the foundational
work of one individual, the Australian philosopher Peter Singer.
Singers arguments first appeared in an article in the New York Review
of Books, later expanded into an immensely popular book.41 Singers
theories on the rights of animals, at least those whose neurological
organization is complex enough so that we may deem them sentient
entities capable of emotional states, derive, in the main, from his own
extension of nineteenth-century Utilitarianism. These arguments are
neither mystical nor antirational; Singer is an authentic descendant of
the Enlightenment. Although his politics are, roughly speaking, left of
center, we could not with honesty affiliate him with the academic left,
in the sense in which we have been using that term.
Others, however, have picked up and amplified Singers ideas. The
philosopher Tom Regan, in particular, has probably been the leading
American advocate of this school of thought.42 The influence of such
ideas has grown exponentially. Many campuses, including our own, 43
now have organizations dedicated to the vindication of animal rights, a
point of view that calls not only for universal vegetarianism and the
rejection of animal products like fur and leather but also for the
abandonment of animal research by scientists and physicians.
The relation of the animal rights movement to the academic left is
a question of some complexity. Clearly there are connections. There is
evidence in the popular stereotypes, jokes, and catchphrases that
encapsulate the common understanding of what the academic left, the
political correctness crowd, is all about. The standard caricature of
the full-blown PC personage limns an individual who is not only deeply
mindful of the sensibilities of nonwhite peoples and non-Western
cultures, committed to the necessity of introducing nonsexist
neologisms into every nook and cranny of English diction, militantly
devoted to the abolition of every last vestige of gender stereotype, and
deeply sympathetic toward homosexuality as a form of Otherness. She
is, as well, exquisitely alert to the status of nonhuman animals as an
oppressed and exploited class. In the prevalent folklore, she is careful
to call pets animal companions; intent on converting all her friends
to meatless (or at least eggs-only) diets; and inclined to heap
vituperation on fur-bearing humans wherever she encounters them.
In this instance, the antennae of popular humorists have, as they
often do, detected something significant about our times and foibles.
Stereotypes aside, one ought to be quite careful in any serious
discussion of the issue. Animal rights, in the direct sense, and as
opposed to concern for animal welfare, is a position that commands the
support of only a small fraction of the academic left. It is quite
different from a question like multicultural education, which is
without question a defining issue for all postmodern radicals. There are
thousands of campus types who have systematically replaced black
by African-American in their lexicon, who ascribe all the worlds ills
to the white, capitalist patriarchy, who would drive three hundred miles
out of their way to avoid heterosexist Colorado; but who nonetheless
eat steak with relish and wear, for appropriate occasions, leather
bomber jackets or deerskin moccasins. Even among committed
ecoradicals, animal rights is at best a lukewarm issue: it is a tricky
thing to champion hunter-gatherer cultures as paragons of ecological
wisdom without allowing that hunting may be a justifiable activity.
Likewise, feminists are, for the most part, nervous about endorsing an
ideology whose rhetoric and emotional appeal so closely parallel those
of the pro-life movement. AIDS activists are equally edgy about
aligning themselves with efforts that, if successful, will bring
contemporary medical research to a grinding halt.
On the other hand, there are positions within the spectrum of the
academic left that passionately embrace animal rights doctrine in its
most unmitigated form. One chapter of Morris Bermans recent book is
an asseverative paean to animal rights sentiment.
It should be clear, then, that how any culture relates to animals
says much about how people in that culture feel about their bodies.
This in turn reveals the essential structure of the Self/Other
relationship and does much to explain the particular history of that
culture, the body politic And it is in technological societies that
we find the greatest terror of the organic, in fact the deepest hatred
and fear of life, that this planet has ever known.44
Similar claims are made in the Baseline Essays. Behind this fustian lies
the fact that Adams has completed no work toward a degree beyond a
high school diploma and has no record of scientific publication. He was
employed at the Argonne National Laboratory as an industrial hygiene
technician; and he did no research there.59 He is, however, associated
with the secretive but increasingly controversial group known as the
melanin scholars, whose doctrine of an innate racial superiority of
peoples with dark skin forms a bizarre echo to the Aryanism of J. A.
Gobineau, H. S. Chamberlain, and Adolf Hitler. One can imagine what
is permitted to scholars under this strange new ideological confection
by noting that Adams now feels free to assert that the Dogon peoples
knowledge of the Sirius system need not have involved telescopes
after all.60 Apparently, he agrees with other melanists 61 that the
melanin of deep-hued Central Africans enhanced their psychic powers
to the point that such astronomical knowledge could be acquired by
direct and unmediated insight! We leave it to the reader to draw the
obvious inferences about the pedagogical competence of projectsand
of entire school systemsthat rely on such materials to instruct and
inspire young people potentially interested in science.
There have been far worthier attempts to claim science as part of
the black heritageinspirational biographies of Benjamin Banneker, E.
E. Just,62 and so forth. There are plenty of honest stories of struggle
and scientific achievement to be told. But the full-fledged Afrocentrists
find this altogether too unfulfilling. The confabulations of Adams, Van
Sertima, and their ilk are much more to their taste. Leaving aside
objectivity, simple sanity cries out on the dangers of this stuff to the
prospects of students who are prompted to take it seriously. We can
report from personal experience that there are many such students. At
the very least, they are wasting their time with nonsense during a stage
of their lives at which they should be learning basic science as rapidly
and efficiently as possible. Furthermore, they are likely to face
confusion and disillusionment as they acquire even a fragment of
intellectual sophistication. Far from inculcating self-esteem, teaching
science from the Portland Baseline Essays or from their proliferating
equivalents elsewhere must do the gravest harm to the minds of
minority students.
How is such foolery to be dealt with? Ideally, competent black
scientists and mathematicians, whose numbers are not as large as we
would like but certainly large enough for the purpose, would refute it in
no uncertain terms, while at the same time stepping in to provide
healthier role models than the invented ones of the Afrocentrists. In
reality, however, competent black scientists and mathematicians are
beleaguered with symbolic as well as practical responsibilities; andin
any casewhy should they be obliged to take on a burden that
initially, at leastmust make them the focus of opprobrious charges of
racial disloyalty, if not worse? Still: in the current political climate of
universities and especially of public education, it is hard to see how a
predominantly white scientific establishment could hope to have much
of an effect, even if it had the courage to speak up.
One might hope, at a minimum, that responsible universities and
scholarly presses would find their own courage to put distance between
themselves and the worst kind of Afrocentric fantasy mongering. 63
Competent referees are, after all, easy to find, and among them a few
might be willing to be quoted. Unfortunately, the academic left, in its
misguided loyalty to multiculturalism and the politics of identity, is
not likely to play any useful role. Its ideology has, in fact, opened the
doors of universities and schools of education to the nonsense we have
described.
It is not hard to see how poorly placed the hard-core academic left is to
protest against the cited mischief. Postmodern relativism undercuts any
possible protest grounded on the notion of objectivity. It entails a
perspectivism that finds no basis for epistemological distinctions
between science and fables. Feminists, indignant as they have been at
the strictures of scientific orthodoxy, bogged down in their own school
of indictment, are in no position to call Afrocentrists to account for sins
more ostentatious, but, at root, hardly more reprehensible, than their
own. The introduction to Hunter H. Adamss Baseline Essay in Science
glancingly reflects the influence of postmodern academic attitudes and
their usefulness as a first line of defense against the demands of
scientific thought. Adamss quotation from the great physicist Louis de
Broglie, for instance, is subtly amended to a misquotation, almost
certainly on the basis of a readingbut hardly a misreadingof
feminist science-criticism.64
Beyond reluctance to criticize Afrocentric pseudoscience, which
seems to be general, we find among some prominent academic leftists a
positive eagerness to endorse it. This is evident in a recent article by
Bell Hooks (or, to render the name in her chosen orthography, bell
hooks). Hooks, a black woman scholar at Oberlin College, is well
known as a militantly feminist, postmodernist scholar of literature and
culture. Her piece Columbus: Gone but Not Forgotten is, for the most
part, yet another recitation of the stylish counter-myth: Columbus as
founding father of all the iniquity and violence that followed upon the
European intrusion into the Americas, and thus of the continuing
injustice visited by the ruling elite in the United States upon Native
Americans, blacks, women, homosexuals, and so forth. To the extent
that white European settlement begat a swarm of evilsand, beyond
denial, it did sosome indignation (tempered by a minimal
understanding of history) is warranted. On the other hand, Hookss
implicit portrayal of the pre-Columbian America as a pacifist Elysium
is a type-specimen of the fatuous clich that has been repeated
endlessly in left-wing diatribes prepared for the Columbus
quincentennial. Thus it is not especially remarkable. What is
remarkable is the thesis that serves Hooks as the springboard for her
ruminations: again, we are confronted with the work of Ivan Van
Sertima, this time in the form of his book, They Came before
Columbus. Says Hooks:
Thinking about the Columbus legacy and the foundations of white
supremacy, I am drawn to Ivan van Sertimas groundbreaking
book They Came before Columbus. Documenting the presence of
Africans in this land before Columbus, his work calls upon us to
recognize the existence in American history of a social reality
where individuals met one another within the location of ethnic,
national, cultural difference, who did not make of that difference a
site of imperialist/cultural domination.65
Leaving aside the grave difficulty of making a site out of a
difference, which must be akin to the problem of silk purses and sows
ears, we can see that Hooks accepts unquestioningly Van Sertimas
thesis of ancient contact between seafaring West Africans and Meso-
American cultures, together with the further assertion that this
encounter was wholly peaceful and mutually enriching. We shall not
examine Van Sertimas book in any detail, noting only that the
assumption of transatlantic travel by ancient Africans is, in itself,
unsupported by any evidence.66 (We have already had a glimpse of Van
Sertimas evidentiary standards.) Conjoined with the further proposal
that black explorers and Native Americans met without violence or
exploitation, and that the ideas of Afro-Egyptian civilization provided
the seed from which the South and Central American high cultures
sprang, Van Sertimas hypothesis clearly belongs in the category of
wishful thinking. Thus it is hard to characterize Hookss embrace of
Van Sertimas ideas as anything other than superstitious credulity.
Yet unlike Van Sertima, whose reputation does not extend much
beyond fanatically Afrocentric circles, Hooks is a mainstay of the
academic left and a ubiquitous presence at conferences and symposia
devoted to questions of racial and gender justice. As even the brief
excerpt quoted above reveals, she has mastered the postmodernist
lexicon and the style that is de rigueur for fashionable campus radicals.
She is, in short, a far more prestige-laden and influential figure than
Van Sertima, ranking with highly respected black scholars such as
Henry Louis Gates of Harvard and her sometime collaborator Cornel
West of Princeton. Her susceptibility to Afrocentric fantasy and the
pseudoscience that supports it is thus particularly ominous.
An even more startling example confronts us in recent work of
Sandra Harding. As noted earlier, this feminist philosopher of science
has openly called for a revolution against science, for replacing it with
a multicultural, multiracial, ethnically diverse discipline, claiming that
it will be more strongly objective than the existing version. One can
garner some notion of what her enthusiasm really endorses by taking
note of her recent book, Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking
from Womens Lives . Several pages of that work are devoted to
repeating slavishly the claims of Blacks in Science, without so much as
a hint of skepticism or reservation.67 In the gospel according to
Harding, skepticism is to be reserved exclusively for scientific work
done by white males and backed by the methodologies of scientific
orthodoxy. Strong objectivity turns out to be another name for
pathetic gullibility. Clearly, to the extent that Harding and her feminist
admirers have any influence on the situation, they can only intensify
the pedagogical damage being wrought by Van Sertima, Adams, and
most of their collaborators.
To take another example, the sociologist Stanley Aronowitz has
also championed the cause of multicultural science and asserts that it
will revolutionize the content and the conceptual foundations of all the
scientific disciplines, as well as the demographic picture of those who
practice them. He is hardly well placed to object, even were he so
inclined, when his summons to remake science along multicultural
lines is answered by the purveyors of Afrocentric science. Likewise,
we have seen that Andrew Ross, Aronowitzs friend and ally among the
cultural critics, waxes indignant at any attempt of the scientifically
literate to inculcate a widespread public understanding of what
distinguishes authentic science from pseudoscience, New Ageism, and
superstition in general. In Rosss view, such people are mere bullies,
intent on preserving the unjust privileges of a scientific elite that works
hand in glove with other purveyors of bourgeois mystification. He is
not a very reliable ally in any attempt to undo the gross miseducation
of young black people.
All this strongly suggests that even if the universities of this
country eventually succeed in developing effective antidotes to the
myths of fervent Afrocentrists (and failure to do so will leave many
black students in an intellectual ghetto), they will do so without much
help from most of the campus left; more than likely, they will have to
proceed in the face of its indignant opposition. This may seem an
unkind characterization, but the direct evidence, sadly and shamefully,
supports it. The experience of Bernard Ortiz de Montellano provides an
example. Ortiz de Montellano is an anthropologist and ethno-historian
originally trained in organic chemistry, 68 who has been active in trying
to develop honest and legitimate multicultural approaches for
encouraging minority youngsters to scientific careers. Yet his
encounter with the Afrocentrists has sidetracked him into a new line of
work, one that has produced a series of painstaking and impeccably
documented refutations of Van Sertima, Adams, and their friends
among the melanin scholars.69 His attempts to convey these findings
have met, however, with severe frustrations from an unexpected
quarter.
When Ortiz de Montellano and some of his colleaguesall of
them nonwhite (he is himself Mexican-American) or female
attempted to present a critique of Afrocentric pseudoethnography at a
recent meeting of the American Anthropological Association, their
proposal was rejected. The tone and manner of this rejection suggest
strongly the heavy hand of a new orthodoxy among cultural
anthropologists, one that pretends to atone for the putative sins of
ethnography during the era of Western imperialism and colonialism by
abandoning the Western prerogative to judge the narratives of non-
Western peoples in the light of objective knowledge and scientific
methodology. All of this further confirms the rueful judgments of
Robin Fox, cited in an earlier chapter, concerning the decadence of a
subject that was, at its height, not only scientifically important but
intellectually bold and morally brave.
In the face of all this, one is left with a melancholy question. Can
the university, as the ultimate locus of scientific education, find the
courage to stand up to Afrocentric (and related politicized) nonsense
to the degree necessary to sustain and enhance the possibility of
scientific careers for young black Americans? We dont know the
answer: it is certainly not clear that it will be yes. Far more likely, in
fact, is increased agitation for black-separatist science to be
institutionalized alongside the standard variety, in a ghastly parody of
affirmative action. This has already and notoriously occurred in a few
places. And: on the basis of its record to date, we foresee that the wider
academic left, with its relativist and perspectivist intellectual
armament, its snide postmodern insistence that all narratives are
equally valid and equally invalid, is likely to cheer the latter process
on. Let us hope that all this is bad prophecy for the ultimate response of
higher education (at least as regards science), to AIDS extremism,
animal rights agitation, and Afrocentric fantasies. It must be a dim
hope, however, tempered by fear for the consequences of
nonfulfillment.
CHAPTER EIGHT
Does It Matter?
1. John Patrick Diggins, The Rise and Fall of the American Left,
35657.
2. Ibid., 363.
3. Heather MacDonald, The Ascendancy of Theor-ese, 360.
4. Diggins, The Rise and Fall of the American Left, 356.
5. See David Lehmans fine book, Signs of the Times, for a
devastating account of de Mans character.
6. See Thomas Sheehan, A Normal Nazi, 3035, in the New York
Review of Books, for a discussion of Heideggers zeal as a Nazi,
including a brief but telling discussion of Derridas machinations in his
attempt to occlude the obvious. See also the subsequent exchange in the
same journal (Feb. 11, 1993, and Mar. 25, 1993), of which Derridas
own letters form the unintentionally comic centerpiece. A continuation
of the exchange (Apr. 22, 1993) by a posse of Derridas American
camp-followers, including such stalwarts of the academic left as Judith
Butler, Jonathan Culler, Stanley Fish, Gerald Graff, Fredric Jameson, J.
Hillis Miller, Joan Scott, and Hayden White, adds immeasurably, if
inadvertently, to the high drollery.
7. See Lehman, Signs of the Times, for an account of the attempts
remarkable for their moral and intellectual opacityof Derrida and
deconstructionist faithful to defend de Man. See also Heather
MacDonald, The Holocaust as Text, for a merciless but well-earned
scourging of de Mans student, Shoshanna Felman, for her bizarre
attempt to get her mentor off the hook.
8. Foucaults most influential work is probably to be found in his
historical studies: Madness and Civilization, The Birth of the Clinic,
Discipline and Punish, and The History of Sexuality. It goes without
saying that despite Foucaults celebrity, many professional historians
are highly critical of his selective and impressionistic methodology.
Many of his admirers now concede that his histories are probably best
regarded as novels of a singular type, works which, for better or
worse, say more about their author than about the truths of history.
9. George Steiner, In Bluebeards Castle, 131.
10. Jacques Derrida, Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of
the Human Sciences, 267. (This citation appears in Ernest Gallos
short article, Nature Faking in the Humanities, to which we are much
indebted.) Note that Derrida follows this up with a peroration on
algebra that is as opaque as it is silly.
11. Jacques Derrida, Acts of Literature, 208. We cannot resist the
impulse to point out that in Derridas usage the word topology seems to
be virtually synonymous with topographyat least the index regards
them as identical. This recollects an experience of one of us (N.L.) at
the age of eighteen. When being interviewed by an insurance executive
for a summer actuarial job he was asked: What kind of mathematics
are you interested in? Topology, he replied. Well, we dont have
too much interest in topography, said the insurance man. Obviously a
deconstructionist avant la lettre.
Defenders of deconstruction and other poststructuralist critical
modalities will no doubt wish to point out that topos (pl.: topoi) is a
recognized term within literary theory for a rhetorical or narrative
theme, figure, gesture, or archetype, and that therefore it is permissible,
without asking leave of the mathematical community, to deploy
topology to designate the analysis of textual topoi. Ones suspicions are
reignited, however, when the term differential topology suddenly
appears. (In mathematics, differential topology is used to denote the
study of the topological aspects of objects called differential (or
smooth) manifolds, which are, roughly speaking, higher-dimensional
analogues of surfaces in three-dimensional space.
When we first encountered this usage in literary theory, we
guessed that sooner or later some ambitious but naive young scholar
would conflate the mathematical sense of the term topology with its
meaning within postmodern theory. Second thoughts, however, inclined
us to believe that no literary scholar, no matter how impressionable or
callow, could fall into such error. We were right the first time. See note
12.
12. Tim Dean, The Psychoanalysis of AIDS, 10786. Dean is a
graduate student in English. His guru is the psychoanalyst Jacques
Lacan. Lacan is cited as declaring that topology is a conception
without which all the phenomena produced in our domain would be
indistinguishable and meaningless. Since the citation is from a piece
of Lacans called Desire and the Interpretation of Desire in Hamlet,
it is pretty clear that someone has been getting literary topoi mixed up
with the subject matter of mathematical topology. Whether the
confusion is Lacans or Deans, we cant say. If Deans, it is probably
free of arrant fakery; but on the other hand, it then crosses the line from
mere confusion into the realm of actual stupidity.
Deans propensity for inadvertently comical confusion of
categories is underlined by the associated footnote, which asks: What
are we to make of the fact that the development of topological science
is historically coincident with the emergence both of the homosexual
as a discrete ontological identity and of psychoanalysis? (It is also, we
note, coincident with the era in which people played football without a
helmet. Would it be too cruel of us to wonder whether Dean is overly
fond of some similar activity?) For the record, non-Euclidean geometry
involves changing what are usually called the metric properties of
space. The topological properties, and thus topological mappings,
remain unaffected. Also for the record, Deans piece appears in
October, which is published at the Massachusetts Institute of
Technology. We doubt that it is vetted by the mathematicians of that
magnificent institution.
13. Jean Baudrillard, Le xerox et linfiniti.
14. J.-F. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, 45.
15. Alexander J. Argyros, A Blessed Rage for Order, 234. Argyros
himself is concerned with the philosophical implications of
contemporary mathematics and science, in relation to the postmodern
ideological positions promulgated by Derrida and others. He is critical
of many of these positions, although he finds some useful. He is also
slightly guilty of bluffing his way through mathematical points. In his
discussion of Lyotard, for example, he states: Lyotard has correctly
diagnosed the failing prestige of linear, or continuously differentiable,
functions. Of course, a mathematical functionlinear, continuously
differentiable, or otherwiseis not the kind of entity that carries
prestige, although a mathematician may be. In any event, the
mathematics of continuously differentiable functions, along with those
mathematicians who work on it, is in no particular danger of suffering a
decline in prestige. More important, Argyros seems to think that
continuously differentiable functions are, in general, linear, which is
grossly untrue.
What is really involved in this remark is Argyross naive
acceptance of Lyotards naive enthusiasm for what is called applied
catastrophe theory. This is a point of view, advocated by such
mathematicians as Ren Thom and Christopher Zeeman, for making
mathematical models of phenomena in physics, chemistry, biology, and
even economics, which exhibit sharp jumps or discontinuities.
Although it is based on beautiful mathematics concerning the topology
of function spaces (spaces of continuously differentiable functions, as
it happens), applied catastrophe theory has not, over the years, provided
empirical scientists much help in the way of insight or technique. There
have been stringent criticisms of the approach from other
mathematicians. (See R. S. Zahler and H. J. Sussmann, Applied
Catastrophe Theory.)
16. J. Crary and S. Kwinter, ZONE 6: Incorporations.
17. Here is a brief bill of particulars concerning the mathematical
sins of the cited authors of pieces in ZONE 6: Incorporations:
Deleuze (Mediators, 283): Gives an utterly incoherent,
essentially meaningless account of the notion of Riemannian
manifold (Riemannian space in the text) in an attempt to make it
relevant to film criticism.
Simondon (The Genesis of the Individual, 30lff): Tries to use
the notion of metastable point of equilibrium without much in the
way of an honest definition, the point being to find some philosophical
resolution to the problem of wave-particle duality in quantum
mechanics. This reads like so much metaphysical hand-waving and
doesnt make any particular sense in terms of mathematics or physics.
Eisenman (Unfolding Events, 425): Gives an utterly incoherent
account of the seven catastrophe theorem of Ren Thom.
Presumably, the idea is to exploit rhetorically the fact that unfolding
is a technical term in the mathematics of catastrophe theory.
Stone (Virtual Systems, 614): Misrepresents both the
chronology and the content of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle in
order to create a strained metaphor.
Turner (Biology and Beauty, 412): Gives a misleading
paraphrase of the Gdel incompleteness theorem (a common sin of
amateur logiciansand cultural theorists).
De Landa (Non-Organic Life, 137): Correctly points out that a
minimum of a potential function is a dynamical attractor (of the
simplest sort) but then (p. 163, note 27) claims, essentially, that such a
situation does not represent an attractor. In the latter discussion, there
is some muddle about linear versus nonlinear mathematics.
Nevertheless, de Landas paper, which is essentially a piece of
scientific journalism pointing out the insights into empirical science
provided or promised by recent developments in mathematics, is pretty
clear and straightforward, by no means a typical spate of postmodern
hyperbole. For a nonexpert, de Landa has done a good and honest job,
although one might wish for a more careful delineation of how much of
this is really speculative.
18. Robin Fox, Anthropology and the Teddy Bear Picnic, 51
52.
19. Ibid., 53.
20. Ibid., 49.
21. Alan Ryan, Princeton Diary. See also Ryans illuminating,
judicious, and fair-minded article Foucaults Life and Hard Times.
22. Frank Lentricchia, Reading FoucaultII, 57.
23. Ibid., 51.
24. Bogdan Denitch, address to Socialist Scholars Conference.
25. Argyros, A Blessed Rage for Order, 9.
26. Elizabeth Wilson, The Postmodern Chameleon, 187.
27. Kate Soper, Postmodernism, Subjectivity, and the Question of
Value, 128.
28. Kate Ellis, Stories without Endings.
29. Ibid., 47.
30. Vincent Pecora, What Was Deconstruction? 65.
31. Stanislav Andreski, Social Sciences as Sorcery, 12930.
32. An example of the hostility of some social scientists to the
authority of the exact sciences is to be found in the quixotic embrace
of the notorious crank Immanuel Velikovsky by a few notable social
theorists. Velikovsky ( Worlds in Collision) held that various mythical
catastrophes, e.g., the Noachian flood, really represented folk memories
of a time when the planet Venus was born from the gas-giant Jupiter
and initially careened around the solar system before settling into its
present (near-circular!) orbit. His defenders among the sociologists
(see De Grazia, 1978) were motivated by a desire to reveal hard
scientists as closed-minded and intolerant, and to display a case where
historical and ethnographic studies ostensibly revealed an astronomical
truth denied to mere astronomers. This, we submit, was an important
harbinger of postmodern relativism and antiscientism.
33. See J. W. Grove, The Intellectual Revolt against Science, for
an interesting account of this phenomenon.
34. See, for example, the right-wing libertarian journal Critical
Review, vol. 5, no. 2, 1992, a special issue devoted to postmodernism.
35. See the profile of the cultural studies phenomenon at the
NILS, and of Andrew Ross in particular, in Anne Matthews,
Deciphering Victorian Underwear.
36. Andrew Ross, New Age Technicultures, 535.
37. Andrew Ross, Strange Weather, 29.
38. Ibid., 60.
39. David Ruelle, Chance and Chaos. See also Ivar Ekland,
Mathematics and the Unexpected, for an equally intelligible treatment
(by a first-rate mathematician) of much the same material. On the
whole, Ruelle is probably preferable to Ekland because of its tone
(Ruelle is urbane where Ekland is somewhat histrionic in a way we
judge to be slightly misleading), completeness (Ekland scarcely
mentions quantum mechanics, which is quite important in any
historical and philosophical discussion of the physical significance of
chaos theory; Ruelle treats the matter thoroughly), and because of
Ruelles record of having been present at the creation of chaos
theory. This last gives added weight to Ruelles sensible advice to keep
matters in proportion when tempted to proclaim the chaos revolution.
Ruelles brief description of the typical mathematics seminar is also a
gem of sociological observation. On the other hand, Ekland concludes
his book, oddly enough, with a beautiful chapter of literary criticism
on Homer, to be precisewhich, in the context, is neither inappropriate
nor presumptuous.
40. Harmke Kamminga, What Is This Thing Called Chaos?
41. For a typical, relatively innocuous example of this sort of thing
see the concluding pages of Alan Beyerchens article What We Now
Know about Nazism and Science. Other examples abound.
42. Steven Best, Chaos and Entropy, 188.
43. Ibid., 204.
44. See Stephen J. Gould, Integrity and Mr. Rifkin. This is a
scathing analysis of Rifkins pretentiousness and incompetence, by a
distinguished scientist and educator whose pro-environmental and
politically left-wing views are well known. We shall have more to say
on Rifkin in another chapter.
45. Curiously enough, something similar happens in a recent paper
of the distinguished economic historian and theorist of Third World
development Immanuel Wallerstein (The TimeSpace of World-
Systems Analysis, section 4, pp. 1720). Wallerstein is under the
impression that somehow or other, quantum mechanics and nonlinear
topological dynamics have overthrown the claims of the physical
sciences to yield reliable knowledge about the world, and that
physicists are frantically throwing paradigms overboard. (Apparently
he hasnt heard the contrasting rumors, far more plausible although still
worthy of skepticism, that physics is closing in on a theory of
everything.) In short, most of the distortions of Bests paper are
reproduced, although without the political rodomontade, in Wallerstein.
The latters motives are clear. He is eager to believe that the social
sciences are now at the top of the knowledge hierarchy: But all of a
sudden, the physical scientists seem to be looking towards the
historical social sciences for models (Wallerstein, 20). We, on the
other hand, have noticed no such thing; but its understandable that a
social scientist would wish it to be so. As gauge of Wallersteins actual
knowledge of mathematical physics, we offer the following: Einstein
spent his life searching for the unified field theory, the single equation
that would encompass all reality. He only achieved E = mc 2, which
explained a large part of, but not all of, the physical world
(Wallerstein, 19). If ignorance is an excuse for bizarre condescension,
Wallerstein is excused.
46. Best, Chaos and Entropy, 203.
47. We might put things in a kinder light by taking Bests
assertion as a refutation of a favorite Creationist argument. The latter
asserts that since lifeof ever-increasing complexityrepresents
increasing orderliness, its existence violates the Law of Entropy,
and hence divine intervention must account for it. This is fallacious
reasoning, of course; and Bests point may be taken as a sketchy
indication of the error. Since, however, serious scientists have long
been aware of the fallacy, this can hardly count as a postmodern
development.
Also: we dont want to leave the impression that formation of
snowflakes and similar phenomena are perfectly understood. Nor do we
for a moment deny that there are exciting developments in the
statistical mechanics of self-organization in none-quilibrium systems.
(See, for an enthusiastic account, Gregoire Nicolas, Physics of Far-
from-Equilibrium Systems.) As with flowers that bloom in the spring,
however, dialectics and the postmodern zeitgeist have nothing to do
with the case.
48. Best, Chaos and Entropy, 225, note 5.
49. Thus one can readily compare Heisenbergs theory of
uncertainty and chaos theory with Derridas concept of undecidability,
or Bohrs emphasis on the discontinuous movement of subatomic
particles and Foucaults emphasis on the discontinuous breaks from
one episteme to another. Ibid., 212.
50. N. Katherine Hayles, Chaos Bound, 181.
51. The Feigenbaum number, approximately 4.66920, is a
universal constant (the term universal is off-putting to some
postmodern enthusiasts of chaos theory, including Hayles) that arises in
connection with any parameterized dynamical system where chaos
arises via a cascade of period doublings as the parameter is
increased. See Ruelle, Chance and Chaos, 6770, or Ekeland,
Mathematics and the Unexpected, 13738, for details.
52. Argyros, Blessed Rage for Order, 238. Argyross own
comparisons between mathematics and literary philosophy, while still
stretching analogies to what we consider a questionable degree, are
more cautious and tentative than those of Hayles. His mathematical
exposition is also far more systematic and coherent, although it is far
from flawless.
53. N. Katherine Hayles, Gender Encoding in Fluid Mechanics.
The standards Hayles sets in Chaos Boundfor erroneous accounts of
physics, hallucinatory history of mathematics, and substitution of
arbitrary analogy for logicare fully honored here. In short, dont
expect to learn much about Reynolds numbers or divergence-free
vector fields.
54. Both these mainstays of postmodern skepticism toward science
seem to have lost heart for this particular battle. Rorty is now, it seems,
chiefly concerned with old-fashioned politics and in this regard
advocates a moderate, pragmatic, and unideological brand of social
democracy. (See Rorty, For a More Banal Politics.) A telling and
convincing quote from Rorty, Love and Money:
All the talk in the world about the need to abandon technological
rationality and to stop commodifying, about the need for new
values or for non-Western ways of thinking, is not going to
bring more money to the Indian villages . All the love in the
world, all the attempts to abandon Eurocentrism or liberal
individualism, all the politics of diversity, all the talk about
cuddling up to the natural environment, will not help. Maybe
technology and centralized planning will not work. But they are all
we have got. We should not try to pull the blanket over our heads
by saying that technology was a big mistake, and that planning,
top-down initiatives, and Western ways of thinking must be
abandoned.
In the very same number we find the remark of Paul Feyerabend
already cited (Chapter 3) whose essential thrust is equally
cautionary: Movements that view quantum mechanics as a
turning-point in thoughtand that include fly-by-night mystics,
prophets of a New Age, and relativists of all sortsget aroused by
the cultural component and forget predictions and technology.
Supplementary Note
Should the reader guess that this kind of immaterial quibble might
be entirely characteristic of Harts critical equipment, we would not
spurn the presumption.
p. 96 The recent claims, both mathematical and philosophical, of
Ilya Prigogine have been subjected to withering scrutiny by the
physicist and specialist in statistical mechanics Jean Bricmont. (See his
essay Science of Chaos or Chaos in Science? in The Flight from
Science and Reason, 13175.)
p. 97 We should make clear that when we speak of the process of
snowflake formation, we mean to include the entire system: warm
water-vapor, cold air, etc. It is the entropy of the whole system that
increases, of course.
p. 98 N. Katherine Hayles responds to this critique with a rejoinder
(Consolidating the Canon, in Science Wars [book version], 22637).
We recommend this to our readers as a specimen of Hayless logical
rigor and scrupulous handling of evidence. Says Hayles, One of the
grotesque exaggerations in which Levitt and Gross indulge is the
fantasy that the cultural and social studies of science are responsible
for cuts in funding for basic scientific research (Science Wars , 234).
Readers of the present text are invited to scrutinize it, line by line or
even word by word, for any support of Hayless statement.
p. 100 For an extensive and devastating analysis of Hayless
Gender Encoding in Fluid Mechanics, see P. A. Sullivan, An
Engineer Dissects Two Case Studies: Hayles on Fluid Mechanics, and
MacKenzie on Statistics, in A House Buiit on Sand.
p. 101 The lingering doubts about the correctness of general
relativity on the cosmic scale still linger. Recently, for instance, there
has been renewed interest in the cosmological constant and similar
modifications.
p. 110 In stating that the only widespread, obvious discrimination
today is against white males, we may have created, inadvertently, the
impression that we think there is widespread, obvious discrimination
against white males in science. For that confusion, we apologize. Such
is not the case, by and large. Science departments have, on the whole,
avoided the kind of race-and-sex-conscious hiring and retention
policies that have been commonplace in other areas of academic life,
just as they have been more successful in avoiding exclusionary
practices of the traditional kind. (We cannot, and do not, deny that
there have been exceptions of both kinds.) We note also, however, that
there are precious few science departments that have not been told by a
dean or provost, in the decade now ending, We dont have a faculty
line for you, but, if you find a qualified woman or minority candidate
... What effect this has had in these days of chronic understaffing, we
do not pretend to know. Whether this practice constitutes
discrimination against white males is a question that we leave to the
judgment of our readers.
pp. 113 and 27273, n. 7 Toward a Feminist Algebra has now
appeared as an essay in S. V. Rosser, ed., Teaching the Majority (New
York: Teachers College Press, Columbia University, 1995), 12744.
We hope, somewhat forlornly, that its influence will be limited.
pp. 11617, 205 and 253 A current experiment in teaching
mathematics multi-culturally, as well as with a feminist slant, is
worth noting. It is a course, offered at the State University of New York
at Plattsburgh, designed to fulfill the mathematics requirement for non-
science majors. Here is a list of its objectives as given in the
syllabus:
After taking this course the student will be able to:
1. Describe the political nature of mathematics and mathematics
education.
2. Describe gender and race differences in mathematics and their
sociological consequences.
3. Examine the factors influencing gender and race differences in
mathematics.
4. Critically evaluate Eurocentrism and androcentrism in
mathematics.
5. Describe the role the culture plays in the development and
learning of mathematics.
6. Give examples of the historical role of women and people of
color in mathematics.
7. Critically evaluate research on the relationship of gender and
culture to mathematics and mathematics education.
In the context of this course, the descriptions asked for are already
inflexibly determined; they are built into the reading list and lectures.
The instructors clear task is to make sure the answers come out in a
way that will satisfy the right-thinking on all points. Just in case
someone might be tempted to slip into unorthodoxy, the course requires
that a journal be kept so that the instructor can keep weekly track of the
progress of the students opinions. Arts and crafts are not neglected; the
student is to make an Incan quipu, a quilt square (presumably
illustrating nonmale mathematics), or an African board game. A typical
lecture assigns readings on fighting Eurocentrism, the role of
mathematics in building a democratic and just society, becoming
critically numerate, and justice and equity, and mathematics
instruction.
pp. 11722 The argument that there is bias in developmental
biology for sperm and against eggs continues to be made, publicly and
with strong emphasis of its exemplary character, despite its perfect
emptiness. The usual system of circular quotation of a politically
favorable story that happens not to be true (but what matter?) is in full
career. E. Fox Keller, H. Longino, N. Tuana, E. Martin, B. Spanier, and
others cite one another and, of course, the Biology and Gender Study
Group, as authoritative sources on the matter. So far as we can see, the
only source in the recent scientific literature is the one cited by the
BGSG (Schatten and Schatten), and that is a gloss on earlier research of
Schatten and Mazia, the conclusions of which give no support to the
statement that an aggressive egg grabs the spermatozoon, with the
latter contributing nothing to the interaction. In fact the Schatten-Mazia
conclusions are to the opposite effect: the morphological change
signaling effective interaction starts with the acrosome reaction of the
sperm head. Martin refers to certain claims that the force exerted by the
spermatozoons flagellum is weak, and others in this game report
with glee and astonishment that many spermatozoa are malformed, or
swim in circles and dont seem to know where they are going. These
observations are textbook material in embryology and in the clinical
literature of fertility and sterility. They have nothing to do with the
spermatozoons incompetence or the eggs aggressiveness in
fertilization. An effort to compare this popular chapter in the book of
feminist science-critique with the facts, biological and historical, has
been made by one of us in Bashful Eggs, Macho Sperm, and
Tonypandy, in A House Built on Sand; but the effort may well be in
vain. You cant keep a good story down.
p. 141 For further analysis of Kellers misrepresentation of
McClintocks work and scientific style, see our essay in the AAUP
house-organ, Academe (N. Levitt and P. R. Gross, Academic Anti-
Science, Academe, November-December, 1996, 3842) We might
strengthen an observation somewhat: There are no developments in
the history and philosophy of science that prove, or even plausibly
suggest, a social construction of the final product of empirical science.
Finally, we note that the recent cloning of Dolly has been the signal for
a remarkable outpouring of commentary from self-appointed as well as
professional ethicists. Leaving the latter aside for now, it is clear from
the asseverations of the former that most of them have no idea of the
technique of nuclear transplantation, which dates back to the late 1950s
and early 1960s, or of what the Edinburgh group did to modify it so that
it works in mammals (rather than in amphibians, in which Briggs and
King, but especially John Gurdon, using donor nuclei from
differentiated cells, showed thirty years ago that it works pretty well).
The socio-political bombast has included quite a lot of commentary on
DNA that displays no understandingstillof the roles of genes,
chromosomes, nuclei, and the egg cytoplasm in the reproduction and
development of multicellular animals (like us).
pp. 146 and 230 An interesting new twist in the history of feminist
dogmatism concerning the social construction of gender roles has
just emerged. One of the most celebrated cases supposedly proving that
sexual identity is plastic at birth and that environmental cues push it in
either a male or female direction irrespective of physiology was that of
an unfortunate male infant whose penis was severed in a surgical
accident. The decision of physicians and psychologists at the time
(some thirty-five years ago), acting under a version of this theory
already firmly entrenched, was to castrate the child, surgically create
the external female genitalia, and raise the child as a girl, with hormone
treatments administered chronically to foster the development of
female secondary sex characteristics. The supposedly successful
adjustment to this gender reassignment has long been celebrated by
feminist theorists as confirming the constructed nature of
masculinity and femininity.
It has recently been revealed, however, that, unfortunately for the
theory, the child never accepted a female identity, engaging
repeatedly and defiantly in male behavior (e.g., trying to urinate in a
standing position). Finally, the unhappy parents confessed the truth,
and the child swiftly adopted an emphatically male identitywith the
aid of further reconstructive surgery. He is now married. We wonder
what Professor Longino makes of this particular case.
pp. 153, 178 Irony suffuses the role assigned to Francis Bacon by
recent feminist theorists. Supposedly, it was Bacon who bequeathed
modern science a covert set of values encoding the male (scientific)
desire for conquest, domination, and penetration of the female (nature).
But see Aubreys brief life of Bacon:
He was a . His Ganameds and Favourites tooke
Bribes; but his Lordship alwayes gave Judgement secundum
quum et bonum. His decrees in Chancery stand firme, i.e. there
are fewer of his Decrees reverst then of any other Chancellor.
His Dowager married her Gentleman-usher Sir Thomas (I
thinke) Underhill, whom she made deafe and blinde with too much
of Venus.
Does this mean that contemporary science ought to be regarded as
a branch of queer studies?
Books
Chapters
Articles
Miscellaneous
Supplementary References