Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von; Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Vater, Michael G.; Wood, David W.; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von the Philosophical Rupture Between Fichte And
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von; Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Vater, Michael G.; Wood, David W.; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von the Philosophical Rupture Between Fichte And
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von; Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Vater, Michael G.; Wood, David W.; Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von the Philosophical Rupture Between Fichte And
The Philosophical
delve further into this area, whether it is to learn
The Berlin Lectures Vater and Wood have given us a real gift: a strong and philosophically provocative edition of this
more about Schelling or to investigate Freydbergs
F. W. J. Schelling indispensible exchange. A thoughtful and very helpful essay that puts many of the issues into a fresh
interpretations. German Studies Review
Translated and with an Introduction and philosophical perspective precedes the letters, and some of the important primary texts germane to this
Notes by Bruce Matthews debate follow them. For lovers of German idealism, this is a text of great interest and its appearance
THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN
Rupture between
The rst English translation of Schellings nal calls for celebration.
FICHTES AND SCHELLINGS
existential system. Jason M. Wirth, author of The Conspiracy of Life: Meditations on Schelling and His Time
SYSTEM OF PHILOSOPHY
Michael G. Vater is Associate Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Marquette University. He translated An English Translation of G. W. F. Hegels
PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS and edited Schellings Bruno or On the Natural and Divine Principle of Things, also published by SUNY Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen
INTO THE ESSENCE OF
SUNY
P R E S S Life as the Schema of Freedom
State University of
New York Press Bruce Matthews
www.sunypress.edu
Locates in Schelling a new understanding of our
relation to nature in philosophy.
This page intentionally left blank.
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy
Dennis J. Schmidt, editor
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
The Philosophical Rupture
between Fichte and Schelling:
Selected Texts and Correspondence
(18001802)
Michael G. Vater
and
David W. Wood
Published by State University of New York Press, Albany
B2858.V38 2012
193dc22 2011014141
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
Notes
to Introduction 227
to FichteSchelling Correspondence 230
to Fichte Texts 243
to Schelling Texts 247
Index 271
This page intentionally left blank.
Acknowledgments
Almost all the texts translated in this volume are based on the established
critical editions, the J. G. Fichte Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften, eds. Reinhard Lauth, Hans Gliwitzky, Hans Jacob, Erich Fuchs,
Peter K. Schneider, and Gnter Zller [GA] and the Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph
Schelling Historisch-kritische Ausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissen-
schaften, eds. Thomas Buchheim, Jochem Hennigfeld, Wilhelm G. Jacobs, Jrg
Jantzen, and Siegbert Peetz [HkA]. The editor-translators of the present volume
are grateful to the commissions of scholars who have carried out this work, and
for the support of the Freistatt Bayern and the Bundesrepublik Deutschland for
these institutions and their long-term projects.
We are particularly grateful to Manfred Durner, Thomas Kisser, Walter
Schieche, and Alois Wieshuber for the critical edition of the relevant Schelling
texts and letters that have been published in the last two years, and to Erich
Fuchs, Peter K. Schneider, and Manfred Zahn for their critical edition and
notes of the Fichte texts and letters from the corresponding period 18001802.
Hartmut Traubs edition of the Schelling-Fichte Briefwechsel has been very helpful,
and Myriam Bienenstocks elegant French translation of that text and Emmanuel
Cattins of Schellings Presentation served both as inspirations and benchmarks.
Thomas Kisser, Ives Radrizzani, and Hans Georg von Manz provided helpful
assistance in the location of manuscripts and texts.
Both of us have especially beneted from long-term support and encourage-
ment in this eld from Karl Ameriks, Daniel Breazeale, Hans Jrg Sandkhler,
and Gnter Zller. All these people are responsible for whatever merit there is in
these translations and analyses; aws and mistakes of course rest on our doorstep.
Thanks are due to the Frommann-Holzboog Verlag for their kind permis-
sion to translate Fichtes short commentary Vorarbeiten gegen Schelling and
the excerpt from the Neue Bearbeitung der Wissenschaftslehre, and to the editor
and publisher of The Philosophical Forum, where earlier and partial translations
of the Schelling texts appeared. We are particularly grateful to Andrew Kenyon,
Diane Ganeles, and the State University of New York Press for welcoming this
manuscript into their collection of works on German idealism.
vii
viii Acknowledgments
1
2 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
We think the letters and published works have roughly equal standing, for when
the former turn to philosophical topics they generally focus on very broad issues
of philosophical presuppositions, certainty, and methodology left over after their
various and intricately argued versions of the system had been sent to their
respective publishers. The letters are placed rst to provide an introduction to
the texts that follow, not because they have explanatory priority or because the
cultural and biographical situations they reference illuminate the dierence
better than the published works. Similarly, the comments in the pages that follow
are oered to point out a possible reading of the legacy of German philosophy
after Kant, but they will not open up a royal road through the by-ways of the
history of philosophy nor will they suggest that what the principals and their
contemporaries saw as the one dierence was the one that will necessarily
stand today as the central philosophical issue. In particular, we are agnostic
on Hegelian presuppositions that outcomes are better than prior conditions
or that one can make an easy separation between reectionor the work of
intellectand reason or intellectual intuition. No philosophical distinction can be
univocally deployed, and if quantum indeterminacies arise in physics, one can
hardly expect unambiguous meanings in social discourse, much less philosophy.
By the early 1790s the bulk of Kants great systematic writings had appeared,
including the three Critiques and the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural
Science, but it was not widely recognized that the critical philosophy formed
a comprehensive system instead of multiple preliminary sketches for a future
system. Kant had given the Critique of Pure Reason a partial rewrite that distanced
his position from idealism, furthered its claims to have denitively reconciled
rationalism and empiricism, and announced that theoretical philosophy had
been given a scientic foundation by a Copernican reversal of perspective.3
The enduring achievement of the First Critique was to insist that philosophy
must settle questions of foundations and methodology before it embarked
on comprehensive explanationthat quid facti? could not be settled without
quid juris?4 If Kant thought his contribution had ended metaphysics or the
Introduction 3
attempt to think the supersensible, he did not foresee how the subjective or
Copernican turn coupled with methodological introspection could produce the
encyclopedic adventures in world-description that would ow from the pens of
Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel in the coming decades. The Critique of Practical
Reason sliced through the theoretical knot of freedom and determinism, declared
the primacy of practical reason in the phenomenon of conscience, and put
the would-be objects of metaphysical speculation within the reach of hope or
rational religion. The Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science provided a
theoretical framework for empirical physics, postulating matter as lling space,
compounded of opposite forces, supporting phenomenal properties such as mass
and density. Both of these works could be viewed as tidy solutions to pesky
but rather regional problems, as could the Critique of the Faculty of Judgments
limited justication for cognitive overreach by the artist and the empirical
scientist of theoretical bent. Yet something of the sweep of Kants analysis and the
grandeur of his philosophical nomenclatureare not the famous transcendental
deductions the consummate Rube Goldberg inventions?seemed to inate his
philosophical results beyond his personal intentions, and the wind which soon
lled the sails of the good ship Transcendental Idealism carried it swiftly out of
safe empirical harbor into uncharted oceans of Speculation.5 And despite the
popular message conveyed by the Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that
the transcendental critique had slain the dragon of dogmatism, Kants own
tidiness in crafting distinctions may have paved the way for the resurrection
of robustly nonempirical philosophy in the succeeding decades, for he closes
the First Critique by insisting on the distinction between a propaedeutical or
preparatory function of critique and the full systematic investigation of the reach
of reason in nature and morals that could legitimately be called metaphysics.6
A plausible, although none too tidy, reading of the state of Transcendental
Philosophy at the beginning of the nineteenth century could view Kant as
having denitely established the propaedeutic to an experiential metaphysics, while
Fichte and Schelling were hard at work attempting to expand and consolidate
the foundations of the metaphysics of morals and metaphysics of nature that
Kant had left behind. In this broad sense, Schelling and Fichte believed they
were collaborators on a shared scientic enterprise; even when they had
misgivings about each other, they were still eager to have the public perceive
them as united under the banner of Transcendental Philosophy as if it were
genuinely the perennial philosophy engendered by modernity, and not just
an isolated contribution.
Whatever Kant himself said about the future of philosophy, his texts seem
to point to quite dierent, although equally fertile, territories of development
once philosophy had torn itself away from the delusory project of trying
to make denite theoretical pronouncements about the supposedly ultimate
anthropological, psychological, and moral frameworks of human life.7 Reinhold
4 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
laid hold of the territory of epistemology (and later on, logic) in his attempt to
create a positive Kantian system that was in some sense empirically based or
objective. After a brief initial irtation with Reinholds foundationalism, Fichte
staked out the moral domain as his eld of endeavor and sought to enlarge the
phenomenon of conscienceon the model of Kants categorical imperativeinto
a model of world-embodied consciousness as such, closer to what we would today
call phenomenology than other forms of contemporary philosophy. Schelling,
schooled in Platos Timaeus as well as Kantian critique, sought to expand Kants
fragmentary account of matter as impenetrability-in-space to a holistic account
of the physical sciences, one based more on the emerging chemistry and biology
of the new century than on Kants Newtonian materialism. And Hegel would
take up Kants systematic leftoversreligion, social philosophy, economics,
politics, and historyand fashion them into an account of human reality so
bold and sweeping that it dropped the labels transcendental or critical and
proclaimed itself absolute or objective idealism. But this suggestion considerably
oversimplies the matter, for Kants heirs did not parcel up the masters domain
and each set to work on his own claimed turf; each contended he was the sole
inheritor of the whole estate and laid claim to transcendental philosophy from
his own point of the compass. Our history of philosophyan art invented by
Reinhold, Schelling, and Hegel tries to make sense of the tussle in a linear
fashion, but neither chronological order nor the metaphor of spaces divided into
dierent regions or by dierent directions quite succeeds in making clear sense
of German philosophy from 1790 to 1820.8 Furthermore, although we must be
content today to view philosophy as an autonomous although peripheral stage
of human endeavor, the German-speaking lands of the early nineteenth century
were guided by public intellectuals who were comfortable moving in multiple
disciplines that we think widely disparatereligion and politics, philosophy and
art, creative art and literary criticism, and even poetry and empirical science.
In many ways, the end of the eighteenth century in Europe was as disquieting and
unnerving as it was lled with promise. Neither Kants high-own transcendental
arguments for a legislative role for intellect in human cognition nor Reinholds
ordinary-language attempt to make the same point through an analysis of
Introduction 5
just as the wise reader will nd it unprotable to doze by the re with the
author of the Meditations on First Philosophy and will go to the Objections and
Replies for some fresh air, the reader of the vast systems of the German idealists
will turn to comments of public critics to get a handle on her authors, or, in
our case, to the letters Fichte and Schelling exchanged in their growth years,
where packed between tidbits of business and gossipand some overwrought
accusations and histrionicsone can nd some earnest attempts to probe and
uncover foundations and (un)certainties.
Just as Socratic elenchus and Platonic dialectic had as their social background
the aggressive confrontations of that singular Greek invention, the law court,
one might argue that the one-into-many, I-into-not-I, identity-into-dierence,
and I-into-We gymnastics of the new dialectic practiced by Kants successors
had as much to do with the plurality of social voices and the social conicts
unleashed by Enlightenment and Revolution as with the self-undermining
ratiocination that Kant diagnosed as the conduct of empty concepts loosed from
the controls of sensible intuition. Before the political old order dissolved in
the tumultuous events in France that began with the Declaration of the Rights
of Man in 1789, the voices of enlightened social critics such as Hume and
Adam Smith, Voltaire and Diderot, and Lessing and Herder had attacked the
power of ancient institutions and entrenched beliefs and had begun to show
that complex systems of human reason and sensibility, social organization and
individual initiative, deployed over a spectrum of development that was both
natural and historical, underpinned the emergence of bourgeois man. But the
old order did not spontaneously combust or disintegrate into the chaos of the
Parisian mob or the frenzied bloodbath of public safety ocials, at least in
German lands where some sense of sanctity, order, and history combined with
enlightened policy and a penchant for learning kept the most progressive
minds occupied in the corridors of powerseminaries, courts, and universities.
Battles were fought, of course, but largely with the pen and not the sword.
One can frame the disagreements of Fichte and Schelling in the context of four
notable debates or culture-war skirmishes that irrupted in German lands late
in the eighteenth century, and that pitted literary giants, the so-called classicists
Introduction 7
and romantics, against philosophers. The rst two surround the rehabilitation
of Spinoza, although perhaps the re- is a misnomer because even in the free-
thinking low countries of the seventeenth century, Spinoza could not teach in
any public way nor have visible disciples in the academy. The conversations on
Spinoza between the Enlightenment dramatist, historian, critic, and advocate
of religious tolerance Gotthold Ephraim Lessing and the younger anti-Kantian
polemicist and novelist Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi that occurred in July 1780
touched o a thirty-year restorm of pamphlets, tracts, and denunciations that
generally are referred to as the Pantheism Controversy. Whether Lessing was
engaging in sly humor or being quite sincere in confessing to Jacobi that he was
a Spinozistread atheist, determinist, nihilistJacobi was unambiguous
in his response, which was to jump o the cli of rationalism in hope that a
salto mortale into the I know not what of faith (Glaube) would save him from
the murky hen kai pan of Lessing and later the Jena romantics. The literary
fracas between Jacobi and Lessings posthumous defender, Moses Mendelssohn,
guaranteed that the very words Spinoza, pantheism, and faith provoked
immediate reaction for decades to come, visible everywhere from Goethes Faust
to the Correspondence between Fichte and Schelling, and even to Hegels Faith
and Knowledge.13 Lessing and Jacobis conversations triggered a deep confrontation
between skeptical and traditional voices in the enlightened world. The second
contest was a repercussion of the rst: By the 1790s, suddenly Spinoza was
fashionable, even touted as the only logically consistent dogmatist, whether
or not one wanted to stand with him. Everyone wanted to nd some sort of
synthesis of Spinozistic pantheism or determinism with whatever seemed to
still work of the old humanismthe Poesie of the romantics, the voluntarism
of the transcendental idealists, and the belief in religious inspiration among
orthodox theologians. Whether these elements can be mixed without provoking
inconsistency, laughter, or dialectic, everyone wanted to try his hand at it. Kants
posthumous notes from quite late in his life suggest that even he dabbled with
Spinozism. At one point he comments that Spinozism, with its seeing all things
in God, is quite like transcendental idealism in wanting to adumbrate a system
of all possible objects of experience under one principle; at another Kant calls
Spinoza, Schelling, and Lichtenberg (a follower of Fichte and a Naturphilosoph)
the past, present, and future of transcendental philosophy.14 Fichtes letters to
Schelling bristle with accusations of him being soft on Spinozism. Fichte had
been oended at the young Schellings suggestion (in the 1775 Philosophical
Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism) that one could view Spinozism and Critical
Philosophy as equally valid philosophies. For Fichte, ones decision between the
two will be led by ones interest: If one is interested in things one will opt for
Spinozism, if in becoming a free agent, for Criticism.15 At one point in the
Correspondence, Schelling recalls an apparently damning line from Fichtes 1794
8 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre where the author suggests that the
theoretical part of the Wissenschaftslehre is Spinozism made systematic, except
that every I is itself the one substance.16
The latter two debates are more about means than ends, for everyone
in Germany more or less agreed that Kant was on target with a morality of
conscience or obligation rather than results, and that the synoptic view of
reality promoted by the natural sciences could and should be reconciled with
an updated humanism that integrated the private conscience of the individual
and the social power of communities, economic association and small- and
large-scale political entities. Friedrich Schiller and Fichte took dierent routes
to a naturalistic morality of conscience, the former suggesting an aesthetic-
psychological attunement of reason and sensibility as a tool for mass moral
education, the latter dramatically bringing the Categorical Imperative from the
philosophers Olympus down to the marketplace in a social philosophy that made
the Other both the limit of my will and the remote source of the objectivity
of all my perceptions. Schillers On the Aesthetic Education of Man in a Series
of Letters (17931795) tempered the rigor of Kants uncompromising demands
centered on universality, the dignity of the moral agent, and a projected social
order that secured both freedom and dignity with the anthropological concerns
about moral pedagogy and behavioral reinforcement; the empty play of opposed
faculties that Kant had nodded to in his analysis of aesthetic creativity had a
positive social functioneducation into a lively and motivating sense of human
equality, free from the ambiguity of Kants term autonomy. What was essentially
creative in Schillers reading of Kant was to use the Third Critique as a tool for
reading Kants moral philosophy. Fichtes philosophy is more centrally concerned
with the moral order as envisioned by Kant himself, where the appearance of
an other will opposite mine both limits my agency and provides the push
back that shows up in cognition as the feeling of necessity (or reality)
correlated with perception and in a natural order of things constructed from
perceptions. That the other is the limit of my will is an idea that goes back
to Moses Maimonides17; that both my will and that of putative others arises
only in an intersubjective framework is a strikingly modern idea, especially
because Fichte makes the willing that I am and the constraint of the other the
primitive entities of his transcendental philosophy, much the way we commonly
project biological, social, and primitive moral constraints as the basis of our
neo-Darwinian anthropological explanations. The core of the social order and
the legal framework that cements it is the shared intuition that I must limit
my freedom by the possibility of the freedom of the other.18
A nal disagreement concerns the dierent directions that the romantic
writers and literary critics of Jena and the post-Kantian idealists took in fashioning
an account of the realms of nature and freedom, and of the tension between
Introduction 9
the role of the individual and the inuence of the social whole in critically
regulating human conduct. Although both Fichte and Schelling shared certain
enthusiasms and especially political beliefs with the Jena romantics, there was
a mutual distrust among them, based in part on the competition for public
forums for their views. A good deal of the Fichte-Schelling Correspondence in 1800
and early in 1801 recounts intrigues around the founding and editorship of a
common front journal that would generally advance the cause of transcendental
philosophy and specically review recent contributions in science, art, and letters
that harmonized (or failed to harmonize) with the Kantian spirit. Beyond this
competition for access to the educated public, the philosophers and literary
spirits of Jena took decidedly dierent approaches to locating the source of
human freedom, Fichte and Schelling in general looking to the tensions and
movements of the social whole, while the poets, critics, and theologians of the
Romantic Circle started and ended with the human individual.
G. F. P. Hardenberg (Novalis), for example, had a complicated relationship
to Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre. His earnest study of the 1794 Foundations of the
Entire Wissenschaftslehre propelled him, in the name of freedom, to a radically
free-form, antisystematic form of philosophizing. Breaking with Fichte pointedly
in the matter of form, Novalis advocated a micro-philosophy that encapsulated the
whole of phenomenal realitywhich Fichte had tried to catalog and laboriously
deducein the singular poetic insight. An authentic philosophical system
must systematize freedom and unendingness, or, to express it more strikingly,
it must systematize systemlessness, he writes in 17951796.19 Working on a
complex theory of signs where an individual item or trace can function now
as a subject, now as an object, Novalis attempts to capture the self-sundering,
self-objectifying, and ultimately self-recognizing creativity of the Fichtean I as
a play in which there is no privileged position: Being, being-I, being free and
oscillating are all synonymsone expression refers to the othersit is simply
the matter of a single fact.20
At the time that concerns us, Schelling was most inuenced by Ludwig
Tieck of all the Jena romantics, and it is probable that through Tieck and
Novalis he became acquainted with the theosophical dramas of Jakob Bhme
that would gure so prominently in his speculations on God, freedom, and
the nature of evil that occupied his thought from 1809 to 1815. Through
Bhme, Tieck introduced the idea of religious conversion, organic unity with
nature, and the practice of highly idiosyncratic creativity or Poesie to the Jena
circle.21 The retrieval of old and curious things, medieval religion included,
was a mark of Tiecks inuence. Poesie was innitely exible in form, capable of
retrieval of the past and prophetic ights to a utopian future. Its practitioners
were not constrained, as were their philosophical fellow-travelers, to account
for the world as it is, hence their unconventional, if not anarchic practices,
10 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
launched under the banner of the harmony of truth, beauty, and freedom. In
romantic hands, ction freed itself from verisimilitude and became prized as a
world-transforming power.
Friedrich Schlegel was probably the most philosophically erudite author of
the Romantic Circle. Between 1796 and 1801 he attended Fichtes lectures and
undertook lengthy studies of Kant, Herder, Fichte, and Spinoza. His philosophy
is as nonfoundationalist and antisystematic as that of Hardenberg and its mode
of expression even more striking. He championed an ideal of art as formed
chaos, and prized wit, irony, and narratives incapable of denite interpretation
as the ways to open up an innity of perspectives. Schlegels idea of romantic
form was universal and all-embracing, committed to mixing genres and
overturning xed convention. Like Novalis, his reaction to Fichtes endless and
tightly wrought deductions involved the deliberate antithesis, the embrace of
the fragment, which like a small work of art, has to be entirely isolated from
the surrounding world and be complete in itself like a hedgehog.22 Schlegels
idea of philosophical systemquite unlike Fichtes 1794 three ground-principles
or the exible mixed method of the 1796/1799 nova methodo lectures where
intellectual intuition, hypothesis, deduction, and bridging synthesis are all
deployed to bring one as near as possible to the whole truth23was blatantly
circular, and open to using not only alternative proofs but alternative concepts.
Essentially agreeing with Novalis that Everywhere we seek the unconditioned
[das Unbedingte], but nd only things [Dinge], Schlegel nds in the romantic
work of art a complete universe, an exercise of creativity that, freed from the
external reference of classical canons or conventional realism, provides its own
criterion and that erases the boundary between the work of art and criticism.24
Most importantly for our concerns, Schlegel hoped to produce a synthesis of
Fichtes philosophy of freedom with Spinozas naturalism, a hope shared by
Schelling at least in the years 1799 to 1801.25
If these words had not forced Fichte to resign his professorship in Jena and
depart for Berlin in June 1799, we would not have the remarkable series of
letters that passed between Fichte and Schelling in the succeeding two years.
Introduction 11
In eect, Fichte had red himself from the tolerant University of Jena rather
than receive a slap on the wrist reprimand from the Weimar Court over his
publication of a blatantly atheistic article by F. K. Forberg in his Philosophical
Journal entitled On the Development of the Concept of Religion, which he
prefaced with his own essay that was rather tame by Enlightenment standards
and not far removed from the spirit, if not the letter, of Kants moral religion.
Academic freedom was well-respected at Jena, although the Weimar Court had
technically acceded to the demands of the Saxony Court, which in response to
the complaints of an outraged parent, had ordered all copies of the oending
essays seized and destroyed and threatened to withdraw all its students from
Jena. With characteristic overreaction, Fichte had announced beforehand that
he would resign if censured, and so he removed himself from the hotbed of
transcendental idealism that Jena had become in the 1790s to a life of relative
obscurity in Berlin. Weimar issued its pro-forma rescript with an acceptance of
Fichtes resignation appended.27
There is no reason to doubt the sincerity of Fichtes claim in 1798 that we
can grasp no God other a living and eective moral order, but as his thinking
unfolds from 1799 to 1802, much more ontological weight accrues to this entity
or force that comes to be viewed as the ground of what humans experience
as consciousness, nature, and the intersubjective nest of right, obligation, and
moral demand. In The Vocation of Man (1800) Fichte begins to speak of faith
(Glaube), the situation where the actual world is seen as ringed by and determined
through the immediate consciousness of a preorientation of our freedom and
power toward a rational end, the future perfection of humanity. We act not
because we know, but we know because we are called upon to act.28 The nite
I is fundamentally will or deed, its own act, and causal chains of consequences
extend from it not only in the world of appearance but in an invisible or
intelligible order. One can only think of a harmonization of such agents in
an absolute will, whose function is to be the bond of the spiritual world
and enable will to act upon will. Whether this absolute will is really another
will or just an abstract aspect of my will in double appearance as the voice of
conscience commanding me to respect the Other and my pure obedience to
the command, it is clear that Fichtes absolute will is a moral God as gured
in this popular work. The Innite Will is itself the moral order.29
The unity-and-community of willing that Fichte sketches in 1800 looks
quite a bit like Leibnizs kaleidoscope of monads refracting and apparently
interacting with one another on the ground of a prime monad or cosmic
actor-presenter. Fichte struggles to give a properly philosophical account of this
intelligible world over the next two years. His letters to Schelling repeatedly
turn to the promise that the elaboration of the intelligible realm will clarify all
obscurities in the Wissenschaftslehre, or to talk of a nal synthesis. Schelling
confesses he cannot follow this new doctrine of religion and so can do no
12 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
the person one is. For a philosophical system is not a lifeless household item
one can put aside or pick up as one wishes; instead it is animated by the very
soul of the person who adopts it.45
Although Fichte and Schelling seem almost viscerally focused on rejecting each
others approach to explaining nature and freedom (as universal and singular
modes of activity), a subtler dierence between the two concerns the question
of philosophical methodology, or in their jargon, intellectual intuition and
philosophical construction. Each tries to convince the other that his eorts
have a credible and solid Kantian basisSchelling refers to the Third Critiques
discussion of reasons demand for unconditioned necessary, Fichte to the First
Critiques picture of knowing as a synthesis of concepts and intuitions. Fichte
claries his more recent thoughts about methodology in the Announcement for
the New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre as an active but systematic knowing,
a mathesis proceeding in something like geometrical evidence, whose every
element is an intuition.59 Indeed, Fichte had previously rejected the idea that a
thought is anything other than an arrested intuition, a single frame snipped
from the cinematic ow of the Is essentially self-reverting activity or agility.60
Introduction 19
is, rst-order or empirical, level. But such a correct grasp of relative truth is
just half-truth and will not provide the systematic foundation for transcendental
idealism that they both seek.
It is curious that Fichte writes to Schelling on these methodological
matters with such assurance, or that the writings of 1797 lay out such an
impeccably simple path to intellectual intuition and the I that performs it.
When one turns to the fragmentary sketches of the 1800 New Version of the
Wissenschaftslehre, one sees a writer tormented by doubts about whether he
can communicate what he thinks, or even whether he can steadily and clearly
think what he intermittently thinks. Schelling never lacks self-assurance, but
the round-about way he expounds intellectual intuition and its object (i.e., the
indierence absolute that is the neither-nor of all possible predicates) leaves him
open to Fichtes charge that his method is wholly conceptual, nothing other
than reection or discursive intellect seeking to heal the rift in reection itself
and so unable to get beyond a purely conceptual formula: the neithernor of
knowing and being, or subject and object, and so on.
Schellings best explanation of intellectual intuition in 18011802 is buried
in a footnote summary that links the two segments of his essays on methodology
that were separated in dierent issues of his journal. There he says:
1. Schelling in Bamberg to
Fichte in Berlin, May 14, 1800
21
22 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Please excuse the haste of this letter on account of the enormous distractions
that I have been caught up in ever since arriving here.
Gabler has orders to send you soon a vellum copy of my Transcendental
Philosophy, a copy of the Einleitung zur Naturphilosophie, and the second issue
of my Zeitschrift.5 I would be especially grateful if you could give me your
opinion of the rst two works.6
In deep friendship and with heartfelt respect,
Yours sincerely,
Schelling.
Berlin I discovered a similar plan at Ungers that had been passed on to me,
and which I have recast, as you can see.14
It is obvious that I can count on you, particularly for the main subject
of the philosophy of nature, of which you wanted to provide a critical overview.
Could you give me an idea when it might be possible for you to send the
description of nature?
For the rst volume, could I ask you to especially do something on the
fundamentals of a philosophy of mathematics, as well as a philosophy of history?
Regarding the latter, please do not simply deduce it in a transcendental manner,
but particularly consider its practical applications, including the questions: what
is a real fact (to avoid the premises of conjectural histories) and which real facts
belong in a system of history, of human history, of political history, and so on.
There is of course no general editor, but whoever is allocated a subject
will be in charge of it and have the nal say. This means that each of us is free
to choose his own collaborators, and will of course be responsible for checking
their contributions. Mr. Hermann, the former editor of the A.D. Bibl., will
look after the correspondence.15
Would you kindly tell me your decision as soon as possible and the
conditions for your participation? Im sure Unger will not hesitate to fulll
the latter.
With much respect and devotion
Yours,
Fichte
The existence of such a plan should become known only upon the
publication of the rst issue. All the invited collaborators are therefore requested
to exercise the utmost discretion: and the plan should be sent only to them.
At Knigsgraben no. 17.
I entered into contract with him to edit a Revision der neuesten Fortschritte
der Philosophie und der von ihr abhngigen Wissenschaften.18 I thought about
doing (at least for my part and in this particular eld) what I imagined to have
been given up on the whole. Now it is true that Cotta mentioned something
to me about a more general plan that he had discussed with Schlegel. But
because I believed it had been put on hold, there seemed to be no reason
to stop me implementing my more limited plan. However, after speaking in
more detail with Schlegel, I discovered that the Institutewhose plan he had
drawn upwas also going to start in 1801. And since it now appears doubly
important to join our forces, I thought it a good idea to integrate my work
into the larger group.19
So it is unfortunate to learn of your plan only now after I have fully
committed myself to Cotta. Nevertheless, I still hope to convince you to be
a part of Cottas plan, and for you to participate in it in a more specic and
extensive manner than even what Schlegel had dared to hope. I can assure you
that more than three years ago in Leipzig Cotta informed me about his long-
held idea of a more liberal institute that would not only review single works
but entire disciplines. For this reason he is much more deserving than Unger
to be the entrepreneur of this new institute. Without your intervention Ungers
plan would have doubtlessly remained a imsy narrow-minded product typical
of Berlin. He has even more right on account of his personal interest in the
matter, which cannot be said of such a rened book publisher as Unger. Cotta
is independent of foreign inuences and inconsiderateness, and best of all he
possesses the means to quickly generate a reputation, renown and solidity for
an institute of this kind.I am convinced that if you weigh up all these aspects
you will nd yourself more inclined to Cotta, for Unger has at most only your
word, while we on the other hand are all contracted to Cotta. I know the
latter very well, and I feel that he alone is a publisher worthy of publishing a
common eort that comes from us all.
The rst volume will contain from me an bersicht des ganzen gegenwrtigen
Zustandes der Philosophie,20 which is already partly written, and an appendix
with an analysis of Bardili, Reinhold (and if no one else takes it, perhaps Jacobi
as well, because of his open letter to you, and because of the patent inuence
he had on the dreadful review of my System of Idealism in the Lit. Zeitung).21
And since I can scarcely doubt that you will not join forces with us, I ask you
to quickly inform me of your decision and what you would like to contribute,
so that I can best organize everything.
I commend myself to your enduring good will and am, with deepest
respect,
Yours,
Schelling.
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 25
editor for the domain of science, and one for the domain of art would be
sucient. If you agree to this division [of labor] and there are no other reasons
stopping you, then you owe it to science to take on the rst role, since we
all recognize that you alone are worthy of this, and because of your authority
the world would also not harbor any doubts about you holding this position.
Schlegel would be responsible for the second function, and would certainly not
be out of place in his eld.
You yourself have dispensed with the subordination of editors-in-chief
and sub-editors in your new plan, and think that each individual participant
should be responsible for himself. In that case the function of the two main
editors would consist in the following:
1) One of the main editors would of course have to look after the mere
mechanical aspects of the arrangements, the correspondence, and the editorship
itself. Schlegel is happy to take on this side of things, since he is more skilled
at this than all of us, and we could obviously rely on his meticulousness.
2) All the projects carried out in the institute either belong to the eld of
science or to the eld of art or to both. You would have the deciding negative
vote in the rst eld, Schlegel in the second, and both of you in the thirde.g.,
if a position or an article cannot be accepted. If the author disagrees with this
and can provide good reasons, then the majority of the collaborators in the
eld concerned would have to decide, except in cases where political agendas
come into play and where the agreement of two editors suces.
3) In my opinion, the work of taking stock of all the noteworthy writings
at the dierent book fairs belongs to the mere mechanical aspects of the
editorship. The choice of these works may be settled by either the collaborators
themselves, or if, as may be expected, there remain important things in one
or the other domain that have not been chosen, the editor of the eld in
question should decide who is to take on the task. The same holds if there are
conicts, either because of a single work, or because a text has to be entirely
revised. For the rst issue, for example, I have already have drawn up the rst
elements of a survey of the state of present-day philosophy and believe I have
put forward some novel ideas. But if I had the hope that subsequently you
yourself might take over this survey, I would regard it as a fortunate thing and
cast my thoughts in another form.
The other divergences can mainly be boiled down to the fact that in
scientic matters you would prefer to have overviews, whereas we would like
to have criticisms of individual works. The following reasons are why I am of
the latter opinion, and I openly submit them to your judgment.
In many written works it is not simply the subject matter but also the
person or the individual that is the most interesting; e.g. his style may be
more or less eloquent, his manner of presentation, or his special intellectual
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 27
1). I cannot break my word with Unger about the promised articles, just
as little as I could ask you to break your word with Cotta. My secret wish and
hope is that Unger and Woltmann (whom I am now leaving entirely to their
own devices) will not nd any collaborators, or they will nd ones of the sort
that I could immediately declare that I cannot work with them. Furthermore,
I am not obliged to do anything for the rst issue except the promised articles
(which agrees quite well with the writers that you too would like to criticize,
Bardili, Jacobi, etc.).
2). Your sincerity calls forth my own.With regard to you, Schleiermacher
told utter lies.35 I received your letter36 in the morning; and I did not learn
anything new from it. In the afternoon Schleierm.[acher] brought me Schlegels
letter, which I read in his presence.37 I had the opportunity to notice a number
of things, especially concerning the peculiar phrasing of this letter, and to give
vent to my long-held annoyance to Schleiermacher in person.
a). I cannot know what I said to each and everyone of you. But I have
not at all renounced the plan, and I most likely told Friedrich Schlegel and Miss
Veit about the idea to secure here the wealthy Jewish traders Veit38 and Levi as
backers. Miss Veit has probably written to Veit, as she promised me, and Veit
is supposed to come and see me, because not long ago Friedrich Schlegel again
asked me if I had met Veit.You well know that among us the plan that I
tentatively drew up has not been criticized with regard to its subject matter but
only if its execution was considered to be feasible, by me not any less than by
our friends. It was an ideal to be measured against reality; and I did not have
anything against this. I was simply waiting for the external opportunity; and
believed I had been authorized to do so by these friends.
b). My plan had hardly been worked out when I unintentionally heard
even before I had written to any of youthat W.[ilhelm] Schlegel had likewise
drawn up and passed around a plan, similar right down to its title, under the
express condition that I should not be told anything about it, and for which
Friedrich [Schlegel] and Tieck criticized him, saying that he had only done this
in order to be in charge, and to also play a role, and so on.39
I said that this was deceitful and altogether wrong, and I wrote to him
and the others about this.40
(Your matter, my friend, is something completely dierent, and I request
that you do me the favor of not confusing me with W.[ilhelm] Schlegel. Your
separate plan is not at all like my general plan.41 After I received your letter42 I
could not be angry and was never angry with you.)
I have now received Schlegels letter and his plan with its evasive intrigues.43
His plan is identical to the one I drew up in Jena, right down to certain expressions,
as well as the title (only Yearbooks instead of Annals; a conrmation that
I later received from him as well), and it even contains a polemical passage
against my plan. Then to keep this plan secret from me, and force the other
partners to do the same; this plan, of which W.[ilhelm] S.[chlegel] has made
30 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
himself the editor, naively saying that the allocated remuneration for the editor
should be substantial: I would have bet this to be impossible until I received
this letter.How was I supposed to feel?
c). How was I supposed to feel about the idea that the Schlegels and their
friends, and unfortunately you too, my dear friend, because of an inappropriate
relationship (you ought to distance yourself from these things as the heavens are
from the earth), are only considered to be a clique by the vast majority of the
public, and that the association of their mere names has to be disadvantageous
for the plan that we drew up in the best interests of science. The Schlegels
deserve respect, especially the elder one due to his considerable knowledge and
unrivalled language skills; but even you still have not had occasion to take back
your opinion of himthe younger one has sucient depth and inwardness,
yet an obstinate incomprehensibilityI will pass over their collaborators in
silence, with the exception of Tieck, whom I admireand put at the head of
Germanof human literature!!
What could I have felt and expected from the blatant tendency of these
men to create a sensation in order to make money and to have to make money:
a situation into which I am sad to say they have fallen.
d). By nature man is inclined to nd himself again in the other person; I
realize that this is what I am now doing in this matterthis is not necessarily
the case for you, since in your last letter44 you were simply informing me of
what W.[ilhelm] S.[chlegel] had in mind.
I am so immersed in my own ideas that I can only be forced by duty
to read the works of others, especially bad books, and to write reviewsGod
is my witness. Anyway, I have to live just as others need to, so for the reasons
given above reviews are the worst way for me to earn money. I greatly despise
these considerations because of this, but I am in the same boat as the others.
I therefore accepted Ungers invitation without any particular inclination, partly
out of a love of science, partly with respect to the things we had already agreed
upon in Jena.
Thus, being in charge, gaining prestige and having a special remuneration,
are not determining factors for me. You yourself, my esteemed friend, will surely
believe this if you reect on it for a moment: and you will make the others
understand this if you respect me.
After all this I have decided the following: if the Unger plan does not
materialize, or if his institute fails, then I will gladly accept the conditions you
propose: but only if you are the editor of the section on the natural sciences. Thus
it does not depend on me but on the circumstances, and here we will have to
wait and see.By the way, I would advise against giving it a name, but this
also does not depend on me. The matter gains a reputation by means of the
work and not the namemoreover, the Schlegelian names are not helpful, they
ought to realize this.
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 31
Censeo, please burn this letter straight after reading it and do not tell
anyone about it. With pure love and respect,
F.
3). You know full well that I only told you my opinion of W.[ilhelm]
Schlegel because of the urgency of the situation (it was precisely in connection
with the plan); and it did not dier from your own opinion of him which
you had already communicated to me in Dresden before your arrival in Jena.51
And have I ever said anything as harsh about the two Schlegels as what you
said in your last letter?
How would I have appeared to him if you had repeated (?) this to
W.[ilhelm] S.[chlegel]? It would certainly not have pleased him, just as little
as it would have pleased him to hear your opinion. But he would never have
considered me false (just as presumably he would not have considered you),
because up until that point I had never shown him the slightest sign of respect,
neither in his presence nor in the presence of others (and this is presumably
not the case with you). Only later through a couple of his more recent articles
in the Athenaeum and a few of his poems did I gain respect for his talent. I
said this to him and others and I would still say this.52
Nevertheless, what I am talking about is: You accuse me of falseness,
and set W.[ilhelm] Sch.[legel] (who by God has not been honest with me)
against me. You hope that I will not take part in any kind of intrigue against
you. In spite of all your best eorts you could not refrain from making these
last declarations to me.
These declarations as such may also please me, but what upsets me is that
you thought this about me too; why did you not tell me about this earlier? You
allowed these misunderstandings to continue for so long between us.
You have the honor of being the rst person to accuse me of falsehood.
Excessive frankness, uninhibited and childlike devotionthese are the failings
that others have accused me of and which I, unfortunately, also far too frequently
see in myself.
In the meantime I am calmly explaining all these accusations solely with
the desire to restore the relationship between us as to how it ought to be.
4). As for the thing with Bardili? I do not understand you.53
The written sketch of my overview of the most recent philosophical
literature lies before me, I wrote it long before sending the printed plan to you54;
in any event, B.[ardili] is discussed in it in connection with the points that I
raised in my last letter.55 (What you say about his conversations is also clear
from his book: and it is also noted in my analysis.)56
You really do not believe me capableand to what end I do not know,
but God help me because this seems to be the case from what you sayof
pretending to have conceived this plan only later (to use your word), i.e. after
you told me about Bardili? Am I so well-known for my poverty of thought that
I have to lift my ideas from someone else; or if I do not nd anything new I
try working on the same thoughts that someone else has already had?That
your review of philosophical literature is almost fully worked out is in any case
34 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
I am not writing this letter to argue but to reconcile myself with you. I
will therefore ignore a number of harsh and oensive expressions in your letter.
For example: I betrayed our plan to W.[oltmann]I did not tell you about
thisand I hope that my word still countsthat U.[nger] and W.[oltmann]
already had a plan, that they and not I made the rst contact, that they rst
invited me, that I rst of all proposed not our but my plan instead of the Unger-
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 35
Woltmannian plan; and then you and the S[chlegel]s were invited to participate
in this plan.However, because I then communicated my thoughts to you in
Jena57 (I believe that they were my thoughts), and that no one else accepted them,
and no one else except you even bothered to discuss them with mebecause of
this, I am now not allowed to tell anyone else in the world about similar ideas?
I sold your labor to U.[nger]? Oh! When did I turn into such an excellent
businessman? I only invited you58; it was up to you to accept it or not. I even left
it up to each and everyone of you to negotiate your own conditions (I had already
negotiated mine; they were much better than I could have received from Cotta,
and it was certain that all of you could have obtained more than the Schegelian
oer of 3 Louis dorthough neither we nor the others have lost anything)you
did not accept it.59 You were perfectly right to do so: I did not get upset. Now
everything has ended up in this chaotic situation because of Schleiermachers intrigues
and our misunderstandings, as well as wanting to judge the matter according to
the idea, which is not my own, of intellectual property.And then W.[ilhelm]
S.[chlegel] expressly instructed everyone in on the secret not to mention any of
this to me: to say nothing of the drawing up of a plan that agrees with my own
in word and titleI have every right to be upset about all this.
_________
_________
But the most important thing of all, my dear friendand I call you a
friend from the bottom of my heart in the hope that these misunderstandings
36 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
To Professor Schelling
[. . .]61 If you have the opportunity of asking Tieck for me: whether at
any time during the entire winter he was struck by anything in my behavior,
and whether he found me to be less favorable to him than the previous summer?
If he answers this question in the armative then assure him in my name
that this change in me is merely to be ascribed to the slanders of Miss Veit
and Friedrich Schlegel, with which they have attempted, in my and Caroline
Schlegels view, to denigrate his character.
It is up to me to once again gain the respect of Tieck, just as my entire respect
and aection for him has again been restored, and to which I was attracted by the
very rst impression I had of him.I also do not see why I should have paid
the slightest attention to that denigrating manner of treating people, which
was obviously aimed at splitting up two people who had become close [. . .]
_________
As for the view whether I was right to sketch that plan for Unger, we
are still approaching it from opposite directions; your view actually gives me
too much authority, and for that reason ascribes ambitions to me that I do
not have. I have suciently explained my reasoning about this matter in my
last letter. I did not want to force you to do anything but for you to decide for
yourself whether to join or not.But a discussion of this would be too much
for a letter. Let us put this to one side until we see each other.
_________
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 39
_________
Goethe and Schiller are indeed the two invited contributors that I recently
had in mind. But they have not replied yet, and I really hope they do not: or
that they reject the oer. They are in your neighborhood, and so I not only give
you permission but ask you to tell them all the details regarding my participation
and how keen I am about this plan: but in such a way that I remain covered.
_________
_________
I took the liberty of speaking freely with Cotta about the Schlegels. I
also told him that we are of one mind and that he will soon hear from us.
_________
_________
If I spend the coming winter here it will be impossible for me to travel, and
not least, to allow Fr.[iedrich] Schlegel to take over the neglected transcendental
science.75 It is impossible for me to watch him destroy all the ground work,
and transmit to students the poetic and philosophical dilettantism from the
Schlegel circle instead of genuine scientic spirit, of which a foundation still
remains here.76 Before I had returned [to Jena], and unbeknown to me, Friedrich
Schlegel had already signed up a large subscription of students. However, after
I had held only four hours of lectures he was already killed o, and is now
indeed buried. He partly has himself to blame. Because he could not work
out anything for himself and presented sheer absurdities. From the proposition
that you alone among the moderns possess the synthetic method, he concluded
that the synthetic method has been hardly attempted up to now, and that he
(Friedrich Schlegel) would be the rst to completely carry it out. But in the
same context he declared that it is nonsense to want to have a system.
Have you received my [System of] Transcendental Philosophy? And my
journal as well?77 I gave orders that they be sent to you, but I have not heard
anything from you about them.
Yours sincerely,
Schelling.
P.S. This letter came too late for the post and was not accepted.
Today I received a new letter from Cotta in which he in any case says that
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 41
he gives me his word for the Review. I had already written to him beforehand
to express my hope that you would be soon joining up with us to jointly edit
a journal. I therefore ask you to decide as soon as possible so that the work
is not split up again. I am thinking of including in my Review everything
to do with philosophy, especially natural science in all its branches, and even
mathematics, history etc. You will have to negotiate your own contract with
Cotta, since I have already xed my conditions, and do what you promised
for Ungers plan, and at least appease him with the promised article (it would
be better of course if you did not have to do this), and you will subsequently
have your hands free for another institute. I impatiently await your reply, so
that I can get to work on the other matters.
Schelling.
_________
I accept your suggestion for the scientic periodical. Feel free to write the
rst issue alone. I have my hands full here this winter with my New Version
of the Wissenschaftslehre, with a report of it for the general public, and with
three courses.81
We still have time to agree on its name, the announcement, and all other
external matters. The sole condition, though, is that the issues do not appear
at designated times but whenever they are nished.
So, tell Cotta of my participation in this way. Hopefully nothing will
come of Ungers plans and my hands will be free from this side.Eight days
ago I sent Cotta an Announcement for my new Wissenschaftslehre, in which
I told the public that the past is the past and that in future I will study the
progress of \ [philosophy] in my own periodical.82 This is why I also cannot
say anything too serious and severe to our philosophasters83 until after the
publication of the Wissenschaftslehre. In my last letter to Cotta84 I also said
42 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
that I am willing to work with you but not the Schlegels, and that I stand
as one with you.
As for Fr.[iedrich] S.[chlegels] prowess at the lectern, I have already
received word of it in another letter.85On account of his exaggerations this
man undermines a lot of the respect for the good eorts. I think it could
not hurt to occasionally make fun of his insistent pleas concerning the lofty
things that are happening there, since he himself has not contributed to them
in the slightest.I have heard remarkable reports from Tieck of how, among
other things, Friedrich Schlegel behaves with his knowledge of the arts; how he
overhears other peoples judgments of books, books that he has never even read,
and immediately exaggerates and transforms them.
_________
I still have not received your journal86, but I did get your System of
Transcendental Philosophy: and I have closely studied the latter.87 Compliments
are not appropriate between us: I will only say that it is everything that I
expected of your brilliant presentation.
However, I still do not agree with your opposition between transcendental
philosophy and philosophy of nature. Everything seems to be based on a
confusion between ideal and real activity, which we have both occasionally made;
and which I hope to completely clarify in my new presentation. In my opinion,
the thing is not added to consciousness, nor consciousness to the thing, but both
are immediately united in the I, the ideal-real, real-ideal.The reality of nature
is dierent again. The latter appears in transcendental philosophy as something
thoroughly found. Indeed, as something nished and perfected; and the former,
to be sure, (is namely found) not according to its own laws, but according to
the immanent laws of the intelligence (as ideal-real). Science only makes nature
into its object through a subtle abstraction and obviously has to posit nature
as something absolute (precisely because it abstracts from the intelligence), and
lets nature construct itself by means of a ction; just as transcendental philosophy
lets consciousness construct itself by means of an equivalent ction.
As I write this letter I do not have your deduction of the three dimensions
of space at hand and I do not have time to look it up. For my part, I believe
the following: 1). Original space, or space as intuition, does not have any
dimensions. It is uniformly a sphere, whether small or large; and the work of the
imagination is to merely enlarge or contract this sphere. This is why the deduction
of the 3 dimensions is not at all incumbent upon the pure Wissenschaftslehre
but initially upon the philosophy of mathematics; and the philosophy of nature
presupposes this deduction from the latter. 2.) The three dimensions arise by
means of abstractive thought in space: and are nothing more than the universal
forms of thinking itself. First and foremost, the point; abstraction of the innitely
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 43
many points enclosed in the sphere (from which later angularity arises, since
everything is round in the intuition) and the form of positing in general. Then
the line: the abstraction made in the point continues; otherwise, with every
point of the line an innite number of points would be rendered concrete; form:
Kants subsuming power of judgment. Plane (I do not recall any more the above
abstraction) form: Kants reexive power of judgment. Solid: Kants reason, which
posits totality: and most of all approaches the intuition. The solid is then now
really a space, just as the intuition would like to be. It only betrays the work
of cognition and abstraction through the angularity.
All the very best.
Yours,
Fichte.
P.S. I have just received a letter88 from which I can conclude:
1). that I am now completely free of Unger, because Schiller and Goethe
have not agreed.
2). (Let us keep this completely between you and me so that no Schlegel
or any other uninitiated person gets wind of it!) We, i.e., you and I, but no
one else, will in all likelihood have Goethe and Schiller joining us to carry out
a large project. Just leave the execution up to me.
A collaboration of this kind ought to have far-reaching consequences.
Please nd enclosed my latest volume.89
F.
sick in bed for some days. The opposition between transcendental philosophy
and philosophy of nature is the chief point. I can only assure you: the reason I
make this opposition lies not in the distinction between ideal and real activity;
it is something higher. In the Introduction, where I rst seek to rise from the
standpoint of common sense to that of philosophy, I speak of object being
introduced to consciousness and of consciousness being introduced to object.
In this wording, the unity [of the two factors] seems an [external] addition.
Surely you do not think that I conceive the matter this way in the System [of
Transcendental Idealism] itself, and if you wish, unnecessarily, to examine the
point in the whole web of the system where I permit the ideal and the real
activity to simultaneously become objective, i.e., productive (in the theory of
productive intuition), you will nd that I posit both activities in one and the
same I, just as you doso the reason [for opposing transcendental philosophy
and philosophy of nature] does not lie here. The reason is that precisely this
ideal-real I, which is merely objective but for this very reason simultaneously
productive, is in this its productivity nothing other than Nature, of which the
I of intellectual intuition or of self-consciousness is only the higher potency. I
simply cannot imagine that in transcendental philosophy reality is just something
found, nor something found in conformity with immanent laws of intelligence;
for in that case, though it may be found according to these immanent laws
of intelligence of the philosopher, it would not be the laws of the object of
philosophy, which is not that which nds reality, but is itself that which produces
it; and truly for the philosopher himself, reality is not something simply found,
but only for ordinary consciousness.
Let me briey lay out for you the course of my thoughts which over the
years have brought me to the point where I now stand. First, I simply detach
myself from what concerns the Wissenschaftslehre; this stands on its own, there
is nothing to alter in it, nor anything to add; it is complete, and must be so
by its very nature. But the Wissenschaftslehre (in just the pure form as has been
advanced by you) is not yet philosophy itself; what is valuable about the former
is exactly what you say, if I understand you correctly, that it proceeds entirely in
pure logic and has nothing to do with reality. It is, as far as I understand it, the
formal proof of idealism, and hence science kat xocn.91 What I want to call
philosophy, however, is the material proof of idealism. In this latter discipline,
the task is to deduce nature with all its determinations, indeed in its objectivity,
its independence not from the I, which is itself objective, but from the I that
is subjective and does the philosophizing. This occurs in the theoretical part of
philosophy. It arises through an abstraction from the general Wissenschaftslehre.
Specically it is abstracted from the subjective (intuiting) activity that posits
the subject-object as identical with itself in consciousness, and through that
identical positing, it rst becomes = I (The Wissenschaftslehre fails to suspend this
subjective identity and is for that very reason ideal-realistic.) What remains after
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 45
this abstraction is the concept of the pure (solely objective) subject-object: this is
the principle of the theoretical or, as I believe I can accurately say, realistic part
of philosophy. The I that is the subject-object of consciousness or, as I also put
it, the potentiated92 subject-object, is only the higher power93 of the former. It
is the principle of the idealistic (up to now called practical) part of philosophy,
which rst attains its foundation in the former. The cancellation of the antithesis
that was established by this rst abstraction should yield an ideal-realism that is
not merely philosophical, but actually objective (art); this cancellation occurs in
the philosophy of art, the third part of a system of philosophy.
But I do not know:
1) If you were to argue against me that Wissenschaftslehre is = philosophy
and philosophy = Wissenschaftslehre, for if the two concepts are coextensive, we
would be disputing about words. If you call philosophy Wissenschaftslehre94 and
permit me to call what I had previously called theoretical philosophy physics
(in the sense of the Greeks), and what I had termed practical philosophy ethics
(again in the sense of the Greeks), I would be satised. What I call philosophy
of nature is then precisely what I have claimed, a science entirely dierent from
the Wissenschaftslehre. The Wissenschaftslehre cannot be opposed or contrasted
to philosophy of nature, nor to idealism, nor, if the presentation of the latter
be called transcendental philosophy, to transcendental philosophy (as I have
done in the Introduction mentioned above). Now, however, as you can see,
I no longer consider the natural and transcendental philosophies as opposed
sciences, but merely as distinguished parts of one and same whole, namely, the
system of philosophy, the parts of which are contrasted exactly the same way
that theoretical and practical philosophy were previously contrasted.
But if you were to
2) then say that the philosophy which I call purely theoretical is precisely
the science that you speak of in your letter, namely, one which would make
nature alone its object through free abstraction, and then permit it to construct
itself through a (justiable) ction, this is entirely and absolutely my view, if
you do not perchance mean by this abstraction such a one that would leave
behind something merely real, for simply nothing can originate from such a
residue. After this abstraction, there remains an ideal-real item, but as such
something purely objective, not grasped in its own proper intuition. In a word,
what is left is the same [item] that appears in a higher power as I; except you
can easily see that it is not a matter of indierence for the result whether the
philosopher takes up his object in the higher power (as I) or in the root.95 In
the Wissenschaftslehre,96 because it is theory of knowing (since knowing already
signies in itself precisely the highest power), the philosopher must from the
start take up his object as I (i.e., as primordially already knowing, hence not
merely objective). This is not the case in the philosophy of nature which (as the
theoretical part of the system) arises through abstraction from the theoretical-
46 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
with Jacobi104 that Fichte understands me with half the words! The rst issue
of Reinholds journal105 is already printed.
_________
Just consider what Reinhold is up to. I have had him sent (through
the editor of the Erlanger Zeitung) my review of Bardili and requested him to
study transcendental idealism slightly better than he has done so far. He takes
it deadly seriously and now wants to show that B.[ardi]lian philosophy does
not proceed from consciousness, or any fact whatsoever, since it does not admit or
require any empirical presupposition at all!!114 How will he do that?After my
50 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
No, I am not giving public lectures. The scholars here engage in malicious
intrigues, and the people who go to them with a thirst for learning, end up
confused; I have not done anything about [giving lectures], and so it has
remained like this. I only have two private students.116 Nevertheless, I will not
leave Berlin without also testing the minds of the people by means of lectures.
Take care, and keep my aection in mind.
Fichte.
To Professor Schelling in Jena.
matters, kept me from answering you earlier. Now I can do better through
the enclosed works122 than was possible by a letter. I ask you to please accept
them with my good wishes and hope that you can nd them in agreement with
your thoughts. I confess I have not yet been able to pursue the Presentation
[of My System of Philosophy] to the point where the relation of this system to
what has hitherto been thought of as idealism must become clear. For you,
there is no need to do this. Your last remark: You understand me well and
have always so understood me, only in light of what I would not comprehend
or derive from previously held principles of transcendentalism, but from
something perhaps rather opposed to them, from an enlargement of idealism
in its very principles123 makes me hope that at least you will be in general
agreement with my undertaking (which concerns this enlargement), although
I indeed do not know whether the kind of enlargement I provide is of the
same sort or is harmonious with that which you have intended for idealism.
Your Announcement124 of a new presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre necessarily
interested me very much and you can easily judge with what eagerness I look
forward to it, and to the Crystal Clear Report as well.125 In any case, I am
indebted to you for posting this announcement to me in which you do me
the honor of discussing my works, and I must in any case and without further
analysis acknowledge, since it is well-known to you, that in the particular
case of my works in the philosophy of nature, it never was my intention to
get access to the public through the transcendental viewpoint that is usually
credited to you or through the viewpoint that, according to what is said above,
is in contradiction to what I wish to say. My most ardent wish is that you
will soon have the leisure to expound the System of the Intelligible [World],
since I suspect this will be quite helpful in completely and forever resolving
all existing dierences, and every presentation that stays within the hitherto
prevailing circle of discussion brings me no closer to your genuine sense and
meaning, since, as you can appreciate, I stand on a point whose discussion falls
outside this circle on which, for this very reason, the whole meaning of your
system depends. It might be asking too much of your friendship if I would
request you presently to communicate some of your ideas on the appearance
of the enclosed Presentation [of My System].
I am always thinking how I could manage to come to Berlin next autumn
for a shorter or longer time in order to see you again and speak with you.
Nicolais Leben, of which I have a copy through your good oces, is a wholly
new acquisition for our literature, not only because of its contents, but equally
or more importantly because of its form. Hopefully this work is fatal not only
for the individual mentioned but for the whole race to which he belongs.
Be well, my dearest and esteemed friend, and remain well disposed to me.
Schelling.
52 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
like the noonday of existing absolute identity; and since the I alone is actually
existing identity, while all of nature is merely this same absolute identity insofar
as it is the ground of this its proper existence, so too idealism unfolds from this
point as the true, all-encompassing, all-comprehending, and penetrating sun; it
will be clear that everything lives and moves in this sun and in what exalted
sense everything = I and only = I.
You will have found that I treat Reinhold somewhat more disdainfully. I
have certainly not made the distinction you made and at least for the present
cannot accept that he has acted as no more than a mere student of Bardili,
but as a zealot and actual advocate. When you have a chance, read the essay
printed in the Teutscher Merkur. The title is: der Geist der Philosophie der
Geist der Zeit136 In the meantime, I would struggle in vain to put in words
my amazement at the manner and the art with which you have handled him.
Posterity will view this essay, perhaps alongside the Annihilation-acts,137 as
the peak of the polemic art of the whole age. Personal and I might almost say
physical antipathy have made me wholly incapable of doing anything better
in this aair. I know Bardili; I used to think that all his knowledge was a
penny-compilation from Plato, whom he pretends to read, some Leibnizean
propositions, Tbingen-Ploucquetish138 philosophy (here is the major source)
and nally some propositions from your system, which in any case he perhaps
just picked up, although it later came to my attention that he had really read
and re-read your writings and mine; I also know that this man who wanted to
do nothing more than vent long pent-up resentment cannot merit the least bit
of attention. The insolence of Bardili or Reinhold (I cannot exactly distinguish
what belongs to whom, since I have never read the former and just cursorily
read the latter)which perhaps is not as unconscious as you seem to imagine,
to steal the ideas from idealism itself in order to refute a distorted and badly
understood version of idealism, in this eort to turn them about and with
notable zeal explain them in a way that makes it easy to reject themthe
insolence was really singular. Whether Reinhold himself might not actually be
innocent in this aair, I do not wish to say. I know for sure that Bardili is
not innocent and that he knows what he has borrowed from you and yours.
The absurd babble about thinking as an objective activity has as what is true
in it nothing other than precisely the chief assertion of idealism itself, that the
uniquely existing [item]139 is the I, and every thing that is existent140 is subject
(Reinholds thinking) and object.
If I have treated Reinhold too rudely, you have given him too much
credit, as you yourself made known, just to be able to simply comprehend
him. In fact a friend who is very well acquainted with this matter assured me
that the Bardilian-Reinholdean A and the endlessly iteration of this A is simply
nothing other than the logically universal concept and that logical universality
and iterablility is thus really very far from the absolute cognition that we speak
54 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
of, which according to us recurs in everything, and which is really for us the
sole cognition; it is only a collective cognition, hence also one that has, quite
unacknowledged, a multiplicity of cognitions in it.141
Dear friend, please excuse the haste of this writing in both style and
substance. I wanted to convey my thanks and my positive feeling to you with
the next post. It is already late and I can only set down in sparse words:
1) that I have delivered all your messages,
2) that I am pleased to see you return to the idea of the journal. All
my wishes are with you in this. I promise to regularly contribute to it, with
true seriousness. For now, I await your precise news and ask you to arrange
everything else as you see t. I believe something of it should be able to appear
at the autumn book-fair.
Heartfelt greetings, my dearly beloved and worthy friend; I am, with
this sentiment
Completely yours,
Schelling.
Postscript: I have heard Goethe, to whom Cotta already delivered the sole
exemplar at the Easter Fair, speak of your essay142 with true love and admiration.
31st May143
Your letter of May 24, my dear and cherished friend, restored to me
such a joy and hope for science, something I had more or less given up on
for quite some time now. The rst positive thing is that it has allowed me to
speak entirely openly with you, without being afraid of prematurely bringing
up things, which would be better for science if they did not occur.
Respect between men who work on the same science, and who know as I
have known for the last 8 years that they have earned this right, can only consist
in mutually showing the utmost condence and tact with each other, and in
always explaining things to the other person in the most constructive manner; and
if the most constructive explanation is still insucient, in hoping that whoever
is wrong will be led by his talent back to the right path. This is how I have
always conducted myself with you, and when you thought that I was wrong,
this is how you acted with me. Let me now speak about my relationship to you.
Your earlier remark in the Philosophisches Journal concerning two
philosophiesan idealistic and a realistic onewhere both are true and can
coexist alongside each other, was gently but quickly rejected by me because I
considered it to be incorrect.144 It naturally made me suspect that you had not
penetrated into the Wissenschaftslehre; but you had expressed so many other
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 55
innitely lucid, profound and correct things there that I had hoped: In due
course you would make up for what was lacking.
Later you informed me about your conception of the philosophy of
nature.145 I perceived here again the same old error; but I continued to hope
that by elaborating this science you would nd the right path. I eventually
understood your view concerning the possibility of deriving intelligence from
nature.146 I will say to you what I doubtlessly would say to anyone elseto
remind you of the obvious circularity in deriving nature from intelligence and
intelligence in turn from nature, and that I do not understand how a man
such as you could have overlooked this. As you know, I explained this principle
of yours the way I did, but without further explaining whether it is right to
incorporate the intelligible into a philosophy of nature, because I thought here
too a hint would suce.
Finally I received your System of Philosophy and its accompanying letter.147
In the Introduction you say some problematic things about my idealism: in
the letter you speak of an ordinary view148 of idealism; if you conceive the rst
categorically, and with regard to the second, think that my view of idealism
might be this one, which is most surely the ordinary view, then it just proves
that your misunderstanding of my system persists. I do not have your earlier
letter149 at hand, but if I correctly recall you assert in it that I concede that
certain questions have not yet been settled by means of the principles existing
up to now. I do not concede this at all. The Wissenschaftslehre does not lack any
principles; but it certainly lacks completion. That is to say, the highest synthesis,
the synthesis of the spirit world, still has to be carried out. As I made a move
to carry out this synthesis the cry of atheism went up.
To the extent that I have read your system, we could certainly end up with
the same view regarding the substance, but not at all regarding the presentation,
and the latter here is an essential element of the substance. I believe, for example,
that I am able to prove that your system on its own (without tacit explanations
from the Wissenschaftslehre) does not possess any self-evidence, and could never
obtain any at all. This is immediately obvious from your rst proposition.
I hope to make this wholly clear to you with my new presentation [of
the Wissenschaftslehre].
So much for the moment. Questions as to whether the Wissenschaftslehre
considers knowledge to be subjective or objective, or whether it is idealism
or realism, make no sense; for these distinctions can only be made within
the Wissenschaftslehre and not outside it or prior to it; and thus they remain
incomprehensible without the Wissenschaftslehre. There is no particular idealism,
or realism, or philosophy of nature, and so on, which would be true here; but
everywhere there is only one science and that science is the Wissenschaftslehre:
and all the other sciences are only parts of the Wissenschaftslehre, and are only
true and self-evident to the extent that they rest on its foundation.
56 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
and the latter presupposes a thing-concept as its determinable: and for the rst
time here, in this small region of consciousness, there is a sense world: a nature.
Self-evidence152 is valid of everything (in consciousness C) and for everything
(in consciousness B). How does this come about? Where is the point of union
and turning point of this double validity? Answer: C is an In with regard to
B and a For with regard to itself.
Nothing is valid of everything which is therefore also not valid for
everything, and vice-versa: then the Of itself is only thatonly taken as a
determined For: and the For itself is only that, only taken as a determinable Of.
The Of proceeds from the For in a real sense153 (and therefore too the
world of the Of, the sense world, from the world of the For, the spirit world)
precisely because in absolute consciousness the former is the determined of the
latter, as something determinable.
Certainly, however, in an ideal sense154 the For proceeds from the From;
the universal is cognized through the cognition of the particular, the spirit world
by the cognition of the sense world.
We do not have any determined (individual) consciousness at all without
having determinable (universal of nite reason) consciousness, and vice-versa.
This law is precisely the fundamental law of nitude, and this alternating
point is its standpoint.
No one thinks it himself, or imagines he thinks it himself, though it is
certain he thinks.
Consequently, the entire consciousness C itself is nothing but an object of
consciousness A. However, it has absolute validity for everything to the extent
it is contained in the original form of consciousness A. If this entire enclosed
consciousness C is again taken up into A, it yields a system of the spirit
world (the above B) and an inconceivable real ground of the separation of the
single entities, and the ideal link of everything = God. This is what I call the
intelligible world. This latter synthesis is the highest. If you wish to give the
name being, indeed absolute being, to whatever still remains impenetrable to
this view, then God is pure being. Notwithstanding, in itself this being is not
some kind of compression, but it is absolute agility, pure transparency, light,
but not the light of reected bodies. It is only the latter for nite reason: it is
therefore only a being for the latter and not in itself.
_________
from its own fundamental point of view. However, for the Wissenschaftslehre,
which is itself a science, a penetrating of the universal consciousness, this point
is the impenetrable =X. Hence, far from trying to proceed from the individual
as such, the Wissenschaftslehre cannot arrive at this point at all. For life, though,
this X is factually (not genetically) penetrable.
Every individual is a rational square of an irrational root lying in the entire
spirit world; and the entire spirit world in turn is a rational square ofwhat is
for itself, and its universal consciousness, which everyone has and can havean
irrational square = the immanent light or God.
* The sense world, or nature, however, is none other than the appearance,
precisely of this immanent light. (A philosophy of nature may of course proceed
from an already nished and static concept of nature: but in a system of complete
cognition, this concept itself and its philosophy must be rst derived from the
absolute X that is determined by the laws of nite reason. An idealism, however,
which tolerates a realism beside it, would be nothing at all: or if it still wanted
to be something, it would have to be universal formal logic.)
* Im reading the ErlangerL.[iteratur] Z.[eitung] no. 67 at the moment.
Page 531 contains my entire thought: only I do not wish to express myself
with doubt but categorically.156 The reasoning on pp. 533f. is also splendid.157
_________
_________
It will certainly damage all the good work if the dierences between us
continue to grow, and become exploited by the enemies of science and the
ignorant in the worst possible way.
_________
_________
What is now your highest synthesis was at all events something unknown
in your earlier presentations, for in these the moral world-order (doubtless what
you now call the real ground of individuality and the ideal unity of all) is itself
God; this no longer the case now, if I see correctly, and this changes the whole
substance175 of your philosophy to a considerable degree.
All of this, which I consider a sign of your approaching true speculation
from the standpoint of mere philosophizing, also gives me the joyous hope
that we will meet at the point which, by your former method, you more or
less had to ee, and which moreover can never be reached by a gradual ascent
from below, but can only be grasped immediately and in an absolute manner.
In your last letter176 you seem to take back what you granted in your earlier
177
one, or perhaps to doubt whether you really penned it. For this reason it is
perhaps not pointless to communicate to you verbatim the passage in question.
I believe that I understand you quite well, you wrote, and indeed
that I had already done so beforehand. I just think that these principles do
not follow from the previous principles of transcendentalism, but rather that
they are opposed to them. That they can only be grounded in an even further
expansion of transcendental philosophy, even in its principles, to which in any
event we are urgently compelled by the demands of the time.178
Then you announce that after the completion of the new presentation of
the Wissenschaftslehre this expansion will be your rst task.
Your viewpoint implies179 that your philosophy must appear to you to
be the absolutely true philosophy merely because it is simply not false. Spinoza
posits thought and extension as the two attributes of substance. He does not
deny that everything that is can also be explained through the mere attribute
of thought and through a mere modication180 of innite thought. This kind
of explanation would certainly not turn out to be false, though it would not
be absolutely true, but it is comprehended in the absolute itself. Something
similar holds between us; which might explain to you in one way among others
why, despite our initial and fundamental dierence, I have nonetheless used
idealism as a tool181 [and] thereby was indeed able to produce so much clarity
and depth, as you admit.
To the real-ground of the separated state of individuals you give the
qualication: inconceivable. It is indeed inconceivable for the reective attitude
of understanding182 that ascends from below, that gets caught in insoluble
contradictions (Kants antinomies) with the opposition of the nite (your
separation) and the innite (your unity of all), but not for reason183 which
posits absolute identity, the inseparable union of the nite with the innite,
as the rst [principle] and proceeds from the eternal, which is [itself ] neither
nite nor innite, but both in equally eternal fashion. This reason-eternity184 is
the authentic principle of all speculation and true idealism. It is that which
annihilates the causal series of the nite, which it precedes by its essence
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 63
(natura)185 in every moment of time the same way it primordially precedes time,
just as, conversely, it precedes time in no other way than it now and forever
does, namely by its nature.
You must forgive me if I say that a complete misunderstanding of my
ideas runs through your whole letter, which is quite natural since you have
not exactly taken the trouble to really understand them. By contrast, none of
the ideas you have been kind enough to communicate to me in your letter is
foreign to me. I also know, as you will perhaps admit to me, in part from my
own use of them, all the tricks whereby idealism can be demonstrated as the
sole necessary system. These sleights-of-hand which were perhaps appropriate
against all your previous adversaries are without eect against me, since I am
not your opponent, even if in all probability you are mine. I have already said
above that I do not nd your system false, since it is a necessary and integral
part of mine.
It would have been quite desirable if you had always and on every occasion
followed what you expressed in your last letter: what idealism and realism are
can only be investigated within the Wissenschaftslehre. (From this it follows
directly that the true theory of knowledge, i.e., genuine speculative philosophy,
can as little be idealism as it can be realism. But have you not denitely enough
characterized your philosophy as idealism?) You would then be able to more
readily join in my claim that genuine philosophy can be completely indierent
externally, even if internally it can be dierent. This concept of the absolute
indierence of the true system on the outside was completely adequate to
justify for you the idea of my system as establishing two philosophies subsisting
alongside each other.
I may have expressed myself clumsily enough in the Letters on Dogmatism
and Criticism186 in the rst, raw and undeveloped sentiment that the truth
might lie higher than idealism could go, nonetheless I can refer to this very
early document of sentiment [for the same idea] that appeared to you no less
on the occasion of the atheism conict and forced you to fetch from faith the
proto-real187 (the speculative) that is absent in knowing (i.e., in idealism, to be
precise). My idealistic and realistic philosophies are related directly and exactly
as are your knowledge and faith, whose opposition, moreover, you still have
not totally transcended, and if you do not know what to make of me on the
former point, so for my part I have ceased to be able to follow you on the latter.
Those Letters [on Dogmatism and Criticism] may perhaps have allowed you
to see at once that I had not penetrated the Wissenschaftslehre. This might have
been the case much earlier, since, as those Letters began, I was in fact acquainted
with only the rst sections188 of the [Foundations of the Entire] Wissenschaftslehre.
But perhaps to this day I have not yet penetrated it in this sense, nor am I
disposed to ever penetrate it in this sense, that in this penetration I am what is
penetrated. I have never had the opinion of the Wissenschaftslehre, and have it
64 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
even less now, that it is the book by which henceforth everyone would be and
must be instructed in philosophizing, even if perhaps judgment in philosophical
matters would be considerably easier if it simply required a written testimonial
from you that one had understood it or not understood it.
If I tell someone that there are myths in the Old Testament and he were
to answer: how could that be, since it teaches the unity of God, would it be my
fault if this person could not hear the word mythology189 without appending
it to the trivial idea of stories of [pagan] gods190? Something like this happens
to me with many people with the concept of philosophy of nature.191 Is it
my fault if one ascribes to nature no other concept than what every chemist
or pharmacist has? But Fichte, who has completely dierent weapons [to use]
against me, makes it all too easy [for me] if he deigns only to refute me with
such an idea. I marvel all the more that you make of philosophy of nature
such an arbitrary idea that you yourself admit that this side of my system is a
completely unknown region to you. You say the sensible world, or (??) nature
is simply nothing but the appearance of immanent light.192 Is it possible, I
thought as I considered this, that it does not occur to Fichte that to prove
exactly this might be the purpose of philosophy of nature? How sad I am
that you would not be convinced of this by reading my recent presentation.193
Your view that you have annihilated nature with your system is not
unintelligible, though for the greater part of it, on the contrary, you do not get
beyond nature. Whether I make the series of conditioned [things or events] real
or ideal is, speculatively considered, a matter of complete indierence,194 since
in the one case as in the other, I do not step beyond the nite. You believe
you have fullled the whole demand of speculation through the latter [viz.,
taking the path of idealism to explain conditioned appearance]; and here is one
chief point on which we dier.
From the third basic principle [of the original presentation of the
Wissenschaftslehre] onwards, with which you arrive at the sphere of divisibility,
of reciprocal limitation, i.e., [the sphere] of the nite, your philosophy is a
continuous series of nite [items]195a higher causal series. The true annihilation
of nature (in your sense) cannot consist in accepting that it is real only in
an ideal sense, but only in bringing the nite into absolute identity with the
innite, that is, in conceding that there is nothing outside the eternal, nothing
nite in the real (common) sense of the term nor in the ideal (your) sense.
It is suciently known to me in what small region of consciousness
nature might fall according to your idea of it. It has for you absolutely no
speculative signicance, only a teleological one. But should you actually be of
the opinion, e.g., that there is light only so that rational beings when they talk
to one another can also see each other, and there is air only so that when they
hear each other they can also speak to one another?196
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 65
I have nothing to remark about what you say further on about an idealism
that tolerates a realism alongside itself, except that there you are caught in the
most crucial misunderstanding of me, which is just too far-reaching to resolve
in a single letter, especially since I can refer only to my latest presentation on
this matter. Should this not be sucient, I must place my hope on future
discussions between you and me on this central point.
You will shortly receive a philosophical dialog from me, which I hope
you will read.197 The continuation of my Presentation198 will also appear this
month and in coming months.
From my side, I shall withhold all categorical judgments about your system
as a whole until the New Presentation [of the Wissenschaftslehre] is published.
That goes without saying. Likewise, I expect you to wait for the completion of
my Presentation and that you really read this before you conceive and express a
verdict on it. Such turns of phrase as . . . as far as I have read your exposition
might not exactly have the best eect on the public.
But should the wish that the dierences between us not be bruited
about more widely be taken to mean that I will wait only until you take the
opportunity to make them known, or that meanwhile I allow you to extol me
in announcements of the new Wissenschaftslehre as your talented collaborator,199
while in Nicolais Leben and reviews in the Allg.D.B.,200 the ground is publicly
cut from underneath me in a thinly veiled way with the remark that I do not
understand you,201 you can well see that this suggestion is a bit unfair.
That my philosophy is dierent from yours I regard as a very slight evil,
one that of necessity I can still tolerate. But that I wanted to expound your
[philosophy] and was not even fortunate enough to do thatdear Fichte, this
is really too hard to bear, especially since, if the rst is conceded [i.e., that I
wished to expound your philosophy], your word alone, without any reason,
suces to establish the second [namely, that I failed in that task]. So if you do
not want a formal declaration of the dierence [between us], then at least do
not, as you did in the last announcement, extend to me the wholly undeserved
favor of accepting me as your collaborator; for this adoption before [the eyes
of ] the public comes at a time when you, for yourself, could have already known
to your own satisfaction that I do not have the same goal as you.
Calm about the end and sure of my cause, for the time being I gladly
leave it to each to discover for himself our relationship, but I also cannot deprive
anyone of his sharp sight or seek to dissemble in any way. So just today, a book
by a very talented person was published which bears the title: The Dierence
between Fichtes and Schellings System of Philosophy202; I had no part in it, but
also could in no way whatsoever prevent it.
You have forgotten to send the Crystal Clear Report. But it had come into
my hands anyway. The idealism presented therein seems fairly psychological to
66 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
through its own immanent laws under the hand of the Absolute)then you
will soon become acquainted with true idealism, and realize how you have
continually misunderstood me.
_________
Your letter has a second part that is painful for me to touch upon. How
is it possible that you cannot communicate with others without oending,
and that you so willingly think that the others you deal with are cowardly
and false? Have the decency to put yourself in my place, as I expressly tried
to put myself in yours, when I had to declare that no one, absolutely no one
had understood me.208 Was I supposed to have acted as though you had never
existed or written anything? In hindsight I see that this obviously would have
been best; but dear Schelling, at that time I did not yet have any idea about
your hyper-sensitivity and the true feelings that one had instructed you to
have against meineradicably it seems. It was only later that you made them
known to me. I thought this manner of treating things to be the friendliest.I
naturally had to believe that you had wanted to present transcendental idealism
in your Transcendental Idealism (this was your most recent text that I had in
my hands at that time)the sole possible transcendental idealism, namely the
one available to the world in Kants and my writingsbut it was obvious that
you did not understand itand that you still have not understood it, and that
if you continue on the path you are taking that will never understand it.At
that time, when I said this before the [eyes of the] public, I was supposed to have
known, for myself, that you had a goal that was entirely dierent to mine?209
My dear friend, at what point in time was I supposed to have known this? In
the Introduction to your new Presentation you assure me, indeed, you even
assure me in your letter containing the above words, that we could still reach
agreement on one point.
Now you even want to hold me responsible for the Nicolaitean
interpretations! The Nicolaites are going to prepare a sumptuous feast when
they see that they have succeeded in their aims with you.
There may conceivably be other reasons why I did not want to discuss
our dierences in public, apart from simply wanting to wait until I was in a
position to talk about them. I had hoped that you would reect on thisand
I admit that I hope you still doand then we could avoid the trouble and
embarrassment that would doubtlessly ensue from a public dispute between
us, and an eminent mind like yours could be retained for what I consider
to be the right cause. Furthermore, I never intended that you should refrain
from doing something you wanted to do because of our friendship or trying
to protect me. I personally am absolutely determined not to mention you in
public until either our dierences are resolved, if they can be resolved, or you
68 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
After receiving your letter of the 4th of this month, and after having read
the rst issue of your [Kritisches] Journal, I will rst of all reply to your letter.
Beginning with what was said to [A.W.] Schlegel alonewho, along with
Tieck, came to visit meabout a report of a declaration from you against me,
I nd that this kind of report, as well as everything you infer from it, does not
warrant the predicate gossip.211 For if you did not make such a declaration
[against me], then it obviously does not exist, and the rumor cancels itself out.
The course of events may be summarized as follows: A thoroughly
insignicant dilettante and experienced businessman, whose name is not in
Meusels educated Germany,212 and will never be in it, but who also receives all
the journals that I either get very late or not at all and when they arrive fresh
from the post often informs me about interesting pieces, told me on the way
home from an event one evening that you had stated in the A.L.Z.213 that you
want to completely break with me. When I protested against this he repeated that
he had indeed read such a thing, and promised to send me the paper. Typically, he
still has not done it. However, since then I have procured a few issues of the
A.L.Z. from my reading circle and assume that the good fellow probably mixed
up the Stuttgarter Allgemeine Zeitung (which I do not receive) with the A.L.Z.,
and probably therefore meant the Bttiger gossip reprimanded by you on page
120 of your [journal] that I did not know about214, and in his confused brain
transformed it into a note from you, and perhaps even confused the name of
Schelle215 with Schelling.
You should see from this that your presumptions of malice and spite on
my part for mentioning this report are unfounded. The man clearly did not
mean or intend any ill-will. If I believed your request that the matter would be
cleared up by telling you his name then I would do it; and I would be happy
to do so if you really insist. I only ask that his name does not become known
among our friends here, because this otherwise honest and upright man, who
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 69
_________
I am also enclosing my reply219 to your last letter which I did not send
at the time; I preferred to keep quiet, because I did not want to further excite
your already over-stimulated sensitivity.
_________
Thus, this is how things stood when I received the above report. And
now you have answered the second question yourself.
70 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
the opportunity in public to say that I would not publicly express myself on
this point unless there was an urgency to do so; and not because I wanted to
spare a particular person of whom I was not sure whether he is worthy of being
spared or not, but out of self-respect. I believe I have sucient self-respect to
not have to reply to an accusation on this point.
It is a dierent matter if you and Niethammer are now unfairly under
suspicion because of this. And I believe that the two of you, in the most
upright manner, and with the agreement of both, have come into possession of
this information, and are therefore justied in doing whatever you wish with it.
And although it may seem so, it does not in fact require my approval, because
I agree with it in every point.226
Thus, on the face of it, it is entirely left to your discretion [to decide
what to do], which is obvious, I think.
It is furthermore good of you to seek my advice as to how this decision,
if it is to be made, should be best taken.There are only two men in this
domain whose opinion, particularly that of the rst person, means something to
me: Goethe and Schiller. I am fully aware that you are also close to the former.
If you want, also inform Goethe in my name and on my behalf that you have
written to me about this point and what I have replied to you. Give him all
the facts in the aair and ask him if he has any advice.
Do you know exactly all the circumstances [of my dismissal from Jena]?
I will add the most relevant which could be unknown to you or which you
might have overlooked.The man [in question]227 meets my wife while out
on a walk228 and starts talkingwithout there ever being a conversation of this
nature beforehandto her, an anxious, overwhelmed foreigner, of his attraction
to a land of freedom like her fatherland, Switzerland, and of his decision to
accompany us there if the uctuating negotiations were to take a turn for the
worse. After hearing this, I visit him the following morning, and during a walk
he repeats the same thing to me, and I suggest the provisional measure of a
rst letter.229He shares my opinion; I send him an outline of the letter, he
tells me in a note that he fully agrees; I keep the original of the note in the
appropriate le. The well-known rescript230 arrives; he knew how to get hold
of it and privately informs me, holding up its circulation, even though I had
long made my decision, until he had harassed and tormented a second letter
out of me in the next 24 hours.231This second letter was his work and not
mine, as anyone who is familiar with my manner of thinking and style would
immediately see. He had only wanted to cover himself in the interpretation
of this second letterwhich I wrote, even though I clearly saw through all of
this, just to put an end to the incessant torments.I wrote what I would never
forgive myself to have even thought.
_________
72 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
If not for any other reason, the earlier enclosed letter had already moved
me to touch upon our scientic dierences in the present letter. You will no
doubt smile at the underlined passage in the letter, which is precisely why I have
underlined it.235 Numerous passages in the rst issue of the [Kritisches] Journal236
show that there absolutely cannot be any quantity and relation in the absolute
and yet you have indeed written the passage cited in my letter, and your entirely
new presentation forcefully asserts something similar.237AndI will addit
has to be like this.Your being238 and even your knowledge, also only exist in
relation, and since you know and talk about both, you have to explain the two
by means of something higher, which for this very reason you would also have
to know. Your system is only negative with regard to the Absolute, the [same]
accusation you have leveled at my systemas you understand it at least; and
your system does not raise itself to a fundamental reex,239 and accordingly you
believe that my system has equally remained at a point of reection,240 as I once
said of the Kantian system.
There is a relative mode of knowledge, the counterpart of being241Under
this relative knowledge, there is indeed yet another being. You have always
situated the Wissenschaftslehre at the standpoint of this mode of knowledge. The
counterpart of this mode of knowledge is the highest being, and for this reason
it is absolute being.Being, I say. You now believe you have elevated yourself
beyond the Wissenschaftslehre to the concept of this being; and you now unite
[both] counterpartsnot in a material sense through insight, but in a formal
sense, since the system needs unity; and not through intuition (which would
indeed supply something positive) but through thinking (which only postulates a
relation)in a negative identity that is the non-dierence of knowledge and being,
in an indierence-point etc. But if you consider, for instance, the most absolute
being that you could establish, you will nd in it the distinct characteristic
of a composition which understandably cannot conceptually occur without
division. This explains why you also correctly derive (relative) knowledge from
this being; and being in turn from this knowledge. You also nd something
similar in relative knowledge.Your [indierence-]point therefore lies higher
than the one in relative knowledge that you ascribe to the Wissenschaftslehre.
J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling: Correspondence 18001802 73
_________
My dear and revered friend, I hope that this letter clearly expresses my
respect and love for you, and that I do not need to conclude it with any
special guarantee.
Completely yours,
Fichte.
of the sentence in my letter where it is said, This absolute exists (appears) under
the form of quantitative dierence in the individual and, to the same degree,
[under the form of ] indierence in the totality. Moreover, I also had to smile
over the way that, in the communication mentioned, the same presupposition,
that I carelessly251 allow the absolute to exist in quantitative guise,is happily
again employed as the chief argument against me, whereupon I was really pleased
to nd at the end of what you wrote signs of an indirect conrmation of your
direct utterance, We might pretty much252 agree on this matter.
It is obvious that certain things in the situation have changed to a
considerable degree since my last letter. The clarication [of my position relative
to yours] that you requested from me does not exist, but your ambiguous
expression in the Announcement of the Wissenschaftslehre and the letter to Herr
Schad do indeed exist.
The upshot is that I will await your New Presentation [of the Wissen-
schaftslehre]. If you make Spinoza your imaginary opponent in it, that does not
seem to me to be the right way to proceed, since you may manage to refute
more than what is contained in Spinoza (presuming that it will not be less),
and then I shall have double the work that would otherwise be necessary in
having to sharply distinguish what belongs to him and to me, though I in no
way think I have to fear that anything of his will be misunderstood under my
name, or anything of mine under his.
That is all that I can reply to you right now. It is still my plan and my
hope to greet you in person in the spring.253
Schelling.
This page intentionally left blank.
Introduction to the Texts of J. G. Fichte
The Announcement
The small text entitled Ankndigung (Announcement) bears the date November
4, 1800 and was originally published in the Allgemeine Zeitung in January
1801. It was only reprinted for the rst time in 1988 in the J. G. Fichte
Gesamtausgabe.1 As the name suggests, its purpose was to announce Fichtes new
and reworked presentation of his system of philosophy. Although brief in length,
the Announcement is signicant for both personal and philosophical reasons.
On the personal level, the Announcement is notorious in the dispute between
Fichte and Schelling on account of Fichtes casual remark at the beginning of
the text that he could not say whether his talented collaborator, Professor
Schelling, has been more successful at paving the way for the transcendental
standpoint than he himself had been able to secure. Schellings later displeasure
at this passage was perhaps a result of Caroline Schlegels initial inuence, as
she was not entirely convinced of the innocence of Fichtes remark and even
pressed Schelling to seek Goethes opinion.2 In time, Schelling too appears to
have interpreted the remark as a sly aside signifying his lack of independence in
philosophical matters.3 Fichte rejected any ill intention and attributed Schellings
overreaction to his hyper-sensitive personality.4 Thus, this seemingly innocuous
remark proved to be one of the catalysts for the eventual rupture between the
two philosophers.
On the philosophical level, Fichtes Announcement is signicant for at
least two reasons. First, it provides an analysis of the relationship between the
Wissenschaftslehre and mathematics that is unique in Fichtes oeuvre. Second,
it contains signicant statements concerning the revolutionary nature of the
Wissenschaftslehre vis--vis Kants critical philosophy, especially after the latter
(as well as Jacobi) had publicly rejected Fichtes system in August 1799 as being
mere logic.5
Fichtes comparisons between mathematics and the Wissenschaftslehre turn
on his conviction that they share three principal distinctions in common. First,
77
78 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
in his view, they possess the same immediate self-evidence (unmittelbare Evidenz);
that is to say, like the axioms of geometry, the Fichtean starting proposition
exhibits a transparency and necessity whose truth is immediately apparent to
the mind. Second, they jointly share a determinacy (Bestimmtheit) or quality
of universality that allows every rational being to intuit the same invariable
intuition. In this respect the external signs (or language) of the system are of an
inferior status compared with the necessity and transparency of the immediate
inner intuition. Third, both the Wissenschaftslehre and mathematics harbor the
same irrefutability (Unwiderlegbarkeit). Here Fichte is not arguing for infallibility,
but simply pointing out a logical consequence of his intuition and postulate-
based model of philosophy. That is to say, as with any self-evident axiomatic
proposition, Fichtes own rst principle is by denition not capable of proof and
is therefore indemonstrable. Finally, in the Announcement, Fichte places himself
squarely in the Platonic tradition by suggesting mathematics to be a propedeutic
for his system. For Fichte, mathematics is an excellent intellectual training to
equip the prospective student of philosophy with the requisite comprehension
of the immediate self-evidence and universality of all postulates.
The 1799 public rejections of the Wissenschaftslehre by both Kant
and Jacobi, as well as his dismissal from Jena during the same period, were
obviously a huge blow to Fichte. Undaunted, he took stock and partly laid
the blame on his own imperfect presentations, believing in 1800 that he had
at last acquired the skill to clearly communicate his scientic philosophy to
others. And although Fichte continued to stress the full continuity between
his system and Kantian transcendental idealism until the end of his life, in the
Announcement Fichte appears to gain a new understanding of the innovativeness
of the Wissenschaftslehre within the history of philosophy.6 If in 17931794 he
had believed his accomplishment to consist in the discovery of a new Grundsatz
or rst principle for a philosophical system that was still essentially Kantian
in spirit, in late 1800 Fichte proclaimed its newness to consist in its scientic
nature, in the discovery of a brand new science whose very idea did not
previously exist. Fichte maintains that the innovativeness of this science should
above all be considered an epistemological one. In the Doctrine of Method
of the Critique of Pure Reason Kant had underscored the dierences between
the methods of mathematics and philosophy by arguing that the latter is a
form of rational cognition (Vernunfterkenntni) based on concepts, whereas the
former is a form of rational cognition based on the construction of concepts.7
For Fichte, however, the key to the scientic success of mathematics lies in the
fact that is a form of rational cognition based on pure intuition. And because
it is possible for a scientic mode of cognition based on pure intuition to exist
in the sphere of mathematics, in the Announcement Fichte argues for a similar
status to be accorded to the self-evident intuitions of his philosophy.
Thus, Jacobis 1799 negative criticism of the Wissenschaftslehre as mathesis
pura is turned to a positive by Fichte.8 In this spirit, at the close of 1800 Fichte
Introduction to the Texts of J. G. Fichte 79
Fichte wrote three short commentaries on Schellings work between 1800 and
1801. Although the correspondence between Fichte and Schelling sheds important
light on their views of each others writings, some of their harshest and most
detailed criticisms were either not sent or remained unpublished during their
lifetimes (see editors main introduction above). In this sense, the following
three commentaries constitute valuable supplementary material to Fichtes overall
thoughts on Schellings works.
In various letters from 1800, Schelling solicited Fichte for feedback on his
recently published System of Transcendental Idealism. In his letter of May 14,
1800 Schelling wrote that he had requested the publisher Gabler to send
Fichte a copy of his new System, and he also asked Fichte for his opinion of
the work (cf. letter 1 above). In a subsequent letter to Fichte dated August 18,
1800, Schelling again drew attention to his System by mentioning Reinholds
dreadful review of it. Fichte briey referred to Schellings work in his reply
of September 6, 1800, but only to say that he had not read Reinholds review.
By the end of September, Schelling was still at a loss to know Fichtes
thoughts, and in a letter that is no longer extant, he again appears to have
requested his opinion, and asking if Fichte had received his copy of the System
of Transcendental Idealism yet. That Fichte had in fact received his copy is rst
clear from his eeting but fateful mention of it in his Announcement dated
November 4, 1800. Fichte nally replied to Schellings query in his letter of
November 15, 1800. After initially complimenting Schelling on his brilliant
presentation, Fichte outlined a number of his criticisms. He especially took
exception to Schelling setting the philosophy of nature and transcendental
philosophy in opposition, and believed that Schelling had in fact confused the
spheres of ideal activity and real activity (cf. letter 13).
These criticisms are slightly expanded on in Fichtes small commentary
While Reading Schellings Transcendental Idealism. Fichtes text is notable for
his focus on Schellings classication of the sciences, as well as him imagining
Schellings possible replies to his criticisms. The latter especially concern their
divergent views on the origin and nature of self-consciousness, being, and
knowledge, leading Fichte to come to the following conclusion: Schellings
concept of transcendental idealism is clearly different to mine. Fichtes
commentary While Reading Schellings Transcendental Idealism was rst
published in German by Immanuel Hermann Fichte in his 1835 edition of
Fichtes works.
82 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Fichtes brief text entitled Preparatory Work Contra Schelling was presumably
written shortly after receiving a copy of Schellings Presentation of My System of
Philosophy in May 1801. In it, Fichte comments on the rst two paragraphs and
the introduction of Schellings new Presentation. If Fichte had disagreed with
Schellings conception of self-consciousness as a kind of being in his System of
Transcendental Idealism, in the following reections Fichte now takes issue with
Schellings view of intellectual intuition. For Fichte, Schelling had failed to grasp
the objective aspect of intellectual intuition, and only views it as a mode of
insight akin to perception [Wahrnehmung]. This confusion between perception
and the genuine in-sight of intellectual intuition led Fichte to conclude with
a summary of Schellings stance with the throwaway line: Polyphemus without
an eye.
Announcement14
For six years now the Wissenschaftslehre has been available to the German
public.15 Dierent people have received it in vastly dierent waysthe majority
have been vehement and passionate opponents, a number of unqualied people
have showered it with praise, and there have been a few gifted adherents and
collaborators..
For ve years a new presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre has been sitting
in my drawer, and I have regularly used it as a basis for my lectures on this
science.16 This winter I am busily revising this new presentation and hope it
will be published in the coming spring.17
My sincere wish is that the public provisionally, i.e., until they are in the
position of convincing themselvesaccept the following two assurances from
me and keep them in mind while reading this new presentation. The rst
assurance: apart from a few individuals (and my immediate listeners, to whom
this does not apply), virtually nothing is known of the Wissenschaftslehre among
the learned public. The second: this science is a newly discovered science whose
very idea did not previously exist, and which can only be obtained and judged
from the Wissenschaftslehre itself.
Concerning the rst point: as far as I can tell, the Foundations of the
Wissenschaftslehre (which appeared six years ago as a handout for my listeners),
has scarcely been understood and has not been used by anyone except my
immediate listeners.18 It seems to require oral explanations to make it accessible.
I believe I have been more successful with my Natural Right19 and System of
Ethics,20 and have more clearly presented my ideas on philosophy as a whole.
After hearing all the diverse opinions about and since the publication of these
books, it appears that the public has not advanced very far in understanding
their main points. Perhaps this is because people have customarily skipped the
introductions and rst sections of these works, or perhaps it is not really possible
to furnish self-evidence for the remote conclusions of my system without their
initial premises (for which one can quite easily provide premises). Only the two
introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre, and the rst chapter of a new presentation
85
86 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
of this system that were published in the Philosophisches Journal, seem to have
been better understood, and aroused more favourable expectations about the
Wissenschaftslehre in a number of open-minded people.21 Nevertheless, these essays
can only give at most a provisional idea of my undertaking, for this undertaking
is not actually implemented and carried out in these texts.
I will not discuss here the extent to which my talented collaborator, Professor
Schelling, has been more successful at paving the way for the transcendental
standpoint in his natural scientic writings22 and in his recently published System
of Transcendental Idealism.23
In another context,24 I once declared that I would hold myself responsible
for this almost universal past misunderstanding, if it would encourage the public
to undertake a reappraisal of this issue. After long practice with the most diverse
individuals, the author of this science now believes he has nally acquired the
skill to communicate it to others in the form of a completely new system, one
that has not been found by elaborating any previously existing version of this
science, but one discovered in an entirely dierent manner.
Hence, in order to facilitate a more successful study of the announced
presentation, it is my hope that while reading this new presentation people
will naturally not only put to one side any philosophical concepts they may have
acquired from other systems, but also any ideas they might have acquired from my
previous writings on the Wissenschaftslehre, to provisionally treat these writings
as though they did not exist, and to accept an invitation to a completely new
and open inquiry. Provisionally, I said, i.e., until one is able to assimilate these
concepts in a more lucid and justiable manner, and therefore view these writings
in a fresh and more useful light.
However, no one should believe that the fears repeatedly voiced by certain
cautious people who willingly refrain from occupying themselves with thinking
have now been realizedthat after having tormented the public to undertake a
strenuous study of an abstract theory I might sooner or later recant this theory,
and then all the applied eort would have been in vain..
We can only take back an opinion; what we have truly known, can never
be taken away. What we can know remains absolutely and eternally certain;
this certainty will remain with the person who has experienced it as long as
he himself remains. If I have really generated knowledge in myself through the
discovery of the Wissenschaftslehre, as I certainly claim, then though it may be
possible to more clearly present it to others (but not to me), it can never be taken
away. Thus, if any of my writings has succeeded in generating knowledge in
one of my readers, then it can never be taken away from him, even if through
illness or old age I myself were to become mentally incapacitated and cease to
understand my own writings, or were no longer to see what I now clearly see,
and in this misunderstanding reject them.
J. G. Fichte 87
composing itself, since then it would be its own ground, and hence would be free
and not necessary; but is the ground in something external to the composing?
Consequently, you would be always driven beyond the concept itself.
Ever since there has been talk of a critique of reason and of a cognition
of reason as something known, the task of reason has primarily been to cognize
itself, and to ascertain from this how it is possible for reason to cognize something
external to itself. From this it should have been obvious that reason can only
comprehend and grasp itself in its own immediate intuition, and not in anything
derived or that does not have its ground in itself, which is the case for the
concept. Therefore: if philosophy is henceforth to solely signify the cognition of
reason itself by means of itself, then philosophy can never be cognition based on
concepts, but cognition based on intuition.
Because mathematics indeed exists for us, it should have been abundantly
clear that the ground of immediate self-evidence, necessity and universal validity
is never present in the concept but lies in the intuition of comprehending itself.
Of course, such an intuition is never necessary or contingent or tells us that
something exists, but it simply absolutely is, and is what it is. It is universally
valid not just because it remains eternally one and the same, but because it
communicates its invariability to every concept that grasps it; i.e., precisely
because and to the extent that the concept grasps it. One should have gathered
from this that everything genuinely self-evident and universally valid in the pre-
Kantian philosophies and in the Kantian philosophy itself (even though these
philosophies may not have clearly realized this), does not have its ground in
the concept but only in the intuition.
In our time it has proved clear to everyone that language is no longer
sucient for reaching agreement on philosophical concepts, and it has even been
ironically suggestedwhich Herder28 and his spiritual ally Jean Paul29 ended up
taking seriously30to preface the critique of reason with a meta-critique of language,31
I said preface! And since in life we obviously arrive at really understanding
one another, there must be a higher means of unication than the concept, and
its frequently falsied second-hand impression: the word, which would allow us
to explain both the agreement and constant divisions in philosophy. Intuition
might well be this higher means of unication, which would be the tribunal
for both the concept itself and its representative, the word. It is now apparent
that philosophical language does not require any meta-critique, any more than
the expressions mathematical point, line, etc. require one.
Thus, philosophy would be cognition of reason itself through itselfbased on
intuition. The rst aspect is Kants important discovery, but which he did not
carry out; the second aspect has been furnished by the Wissenschaftslehre, and
is the condition for the possibility of carrying it out: and as a consequence, it
is a completely new science.
Now one should not indiscriminately and immediately reject this idea just
because one hears the words Wissenschaftslehre, intuition. and intellectual
J. G. Fichte 89
intuition (for the Wissenschaftslehre does indeed proceed from these) in Kants
sense. For he has recently declared both people and their expressions to be
unjustied, no matter how they are formulated: The Wissenschaftslehre ispure
logic; since it is futile to try and obtain a real object from it.32 Intellectual
intuition would bea non-sensible intuition of something that subsists in repose,
which is absurd.33
The Wissenschaftslehre is not at all logic to me; I would even banish pure
logic entirely from the sphere of philosophy. To me intellectual intuition is not
an intuition of something already subsisting. An intellectual intuition cannot
be conceptually explained, precisely because it lies higher than all concepts;
one learns to know it only when one has it. Anyone who does not know it
will have to wait for our presentation. In the meantime, let him picture in his
consciousness the drawing of a line (not the drawn line), which hopefully too
is not something subsisting. The Wissenschaftslehre is mathesis, not merely with
regard to its external form, but also with regard to its content. It describes a
continuous series of intuitions; and proves all of its propositions in intuition.
It is the mathesis of reason itself. Just as, for instance, geometry includes the
entire system of the limiting of space, so the Wissenschaftslehre includes the entire
system of reason. With regard to its material content, mathematics is the only
completely scientic undertaking that exists.
Hence, I wish that people had some knowledge of mathematics before
embarking on a study of the Wissenschaftslehre; i.e., not without rst obtaining a
clear insight into the ground of the immediate self-evidence and universal validity
of mathematical postulates and theorems. Whoever sees why, for example, the
proposition: there is only one straight line possible between two pointsincludes
within a single case the innity of all possible cases, and pictures to himself the
origin of the immediate certaintyhe will never encounter a case that contradicts
it, as long as reason remains reason. I can promise in good faith that this person
will understand the Wissenschaftslehre in its new presentation as easily as he
understands geometry. However, if anyone fails to see thisI have every reason
to believe that many people lack the above mentioned sense for self-evidence
and universal validity, and do not contradict geometry only because it is already
established as a self-evident scienceI would dissuade these people from studying
the Wissenschaftslehre. For it lies in a world that simply does not exist for them.
Because the Wissenschaftslehre is mathematics, it also has the distinctions
of mathematics.
To begin with, it has the same immediate self-evidence.34 There is no
hesitating, vacillating and weighing up, whether one fully admits this assertion or
not. Whoever does not hit upon the right point, completely fails to understand
the Wissenschaftslehre; whoever nds it, is surprised by its immediate clarity and
necessity; he cannot see it in any other way than like this.
[The Wissenschaftslehre has] the same thoroughgoing determinacy35 [as
mathematics]. It does not matter what sign the Wissenschaftslehre attaches to its
90 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
J. G. Fichte 91
_________
92 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Any oense that this Announcement and its tone may cause will disappear
once the announced presentation has been understood. Even this tone stems
from the subject matter and can only be judged from it.
The reproach of arrogance that has so often been brought against me
and the other defenders of the Wissenschaftslehre precisely overlooks the worst
aspect of our presumption; that we in all seriousness claim to posses and teach
scienceI said: science. Those people relating their opinions to each other have
to be mutually tolerant and polite, and humbly admit that the opinion of
someone else might have the same value as their own opinion. For them, it
is a question of: live and let live, imagine and let imagine. They have to be
outwardly modest, because inwardly they are thoroughly arrogant: because it is
the most outrageous arrogance to believe that it is up to the other person to
know what we mean. However, I have never understood why sciencewhich
is never the aair of individuals but the property of the entire kingdom of
reasonought to be humble toward ignorance. Hence, everything depends on
whether we are correct in our assumption that we are in possession of science.
Settling this question will also settle the question of our arrogance.
The enthusiasm of these so-called many-philosophers against a sole-
philosopher is strange.39 I can only understand it if I say that one is either a
sole-philosopher or not a philosopher at all; and until the latter has been proved
we will continue to count ourselves among the former.
_________
1). Without order and paragraphs in the or in the chapters: and the principles
of this critical examination.
2). Preliminary considerations on the type of proof.
Ad. 1. The principle is presumably that all extraneous matter will be separated.
All the dierent reections separated by . Here I have to make sure that I
pay close attention, so that everything will occur in this manner.
Ad. 2. It might be especially worth pointing out that we never enter into real
consciousness, but philosophically always hover at a higher potency. Think of
the I: this is an act that also frequently occurs: the actual consequence of
consciousness has taken place, but not the thinking of the I: This is an objective
[consciousness]. Our beholding42 and observing43 of this act is precisely the point.
1. In fact, the goal is still only to prove that intellectual intuition is the
condition of every possible consciousness. You will now have to see what the
principal content of the following is, and to what extent the (discovered)
constituents serve as a preparation for it.
2. Determinacy44, determinability45 / is above all necessary here.
3. The activity is the true object of intellectual intuition, proven / <real>;
the accomplishment and execution. Hence 2. is in any case necessary for
clarity. I have to think along the lines of a thoroughly determined foundational
thread, and in this way set down <an application.>
_________
93
94 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Whoever has thought of himself has found that the essential task of his immediate
consciousness is to become conscious of this thinking.
Historical Narrative*
Preliminary Remarks
Henceforth, the reader can and must forget everything he knows, and
retain nothing except what he nds here. Of course, these ndings must not
contradict what the reader genuinely knows and possesses: we are of the opinion
that if the reader were to nd a contradiction of this kind it would simply
prove that he has not correctly understood us. Naturally, he will have to wait
until he also obtains whatever is in his heart and whatever he is seeking. He
certainly needs to be patient. We are acutely aware that the reader himself has
to enter into our words, and perhaps even suspects us of a sleight of hand. Our
words are not to mean anything else than what we say: and if we are right,
our words could not mean anything else. (In any event, we will clearly indicate
every step to the reader before passing on to the next one.)
We will start from postulates. Hence, the reader should even forget the
author and this book; he should not allow a foreign train of thought to unfold
before his eyes, but should develop instead his own train of thought.
2). Our system does not appeal to any prior fact, but necessarily derives
all the facts of consciousness: as though we did not have any [prior] idea of
them.
In any case, it examines what is achieved through the free productionnot
the discoveryof a determination in our consciousness, and the entire force
of its proof is based on this inner intuition (though not in the development
of concepts, which only arise and are precisely grasped through intuition,
and whose correctness rst has to be examined through intuition, before the
slightest thing can be proved through an analysis of them). The necessity and
the universal validity of every rational consciousness that is to be found in this
intuition, is based partly on immediate consciousness, partly on the insight
into the necessary subordination of everything that was subordinated under the
condition found in the intuition.
Nevertheless, in the course of our science this point will be claried using
examples and by means of the entire method itself.
3) In this way the reader should absolutely forget any possible purpose
in this train of thought: He [should] consider it to be an invitation to free
thinking: this is supposed to signify nothing else than that the thoughts are
developed in this manner. It will be ultimately shown how useful and necessary
this is.
4) The reader should consider himself invited to thoroughly free thinking.
In life, everything he produces in himself is not genuine thinking, sensing,
perceiving, willing etc.; for here he lives and continues his path without making
any eort toward freedom or any eort to philosophize.
The thoughts he is able to generate in the course of our philosophizing,
however, and which become an element on his lifes philosophical path during
the development of this system, these kinds of thoughts are generated out of
him, and never stem from real nished life but from transcendental-philosophical
96 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Chapter One
The main point is that this is truly and genuinely thought by everyone who
accompanies us in thought: this is needed in order to forge a rapport between
usotherwise it would be an utterly empty study for the readerone has to
put aside (forget) everything else that is likewise self-evident; otherwise our
inferences and assertions would not be appropriate.
Thus
I does not mean and should not mean anything else than what we will
now establish and which arises through the postulated thought. It is assumed
that this has really come into being: if anything else has arisen in addition to
this then it should be put aside.
a.) Completely think the concept as the product of your thought,
setting it in opposition to every other thought: that of the wall [for example]
or something similar; then you will nd that what is thought in the latter,
the wall, is not the thinking agent, but is supposed to be in opposition to
it; in the former, however, the thought and the thinker should be the same.
I, the thinker, am also the thought. Hence, in it, the concept as the product
of a thoughtexpresses the identity of the thinker and what is thought
everyone will hopefully discover that this is the case: and nothing further is
assigned to it: however, anything else that it contains should be positively
dismissed.
). According to a second postulate (here it is simply a mediating one):
to become conscious of ones activity in thoughtmeans that the thinking of
oneself is to be characterized by this act in oneself: or the direction of the
activity. To go out of oneself.58
Namelyonce again one pays precise, lucid, vivid attention to ones state
of mind in the specic moment at which one is requested to do soto think of
oneself, and as a consequence of this summons, to be thought. In this connection,
ones thinking is glimpsed as an agility, so to speak, as a breaking free of the
state of inertia [; as an act] of lucid thinking, and a movement in a certain
direction. In [the act of ] thinking oneself, what then would this direction be,
compared to [the act of ] not thinking oneself? Clearlyeveryone is capable of
nding this intuition of the selfit is a reverting of thinking back into itself.
In contrast, [going out of oneself ] in thought, estranging oneself, and losing
oneself in the object (and which because of this becomes an object)[the
former] is a self-positing of thoughtthe latter is a positing of non-thinking,
and a forgetting of thinking. The rst is a reecting of thoughtthe second
is a derivationcentripetal, centrifugal.
Result: the concept of the Ior A.x.y.z., or whatever you want to call it
= the identity of the thinker and the thought. Thinking the I = reection of
thinking itself: and inversely, the identity of thinker and thought: etc.
The inversion states:
98 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
1). this same procedure produces something identical to what was proven
in intuition.
2). Nothing else ought to be brought into existence through the arbitrary
sign I except the product of this procedure.
(ad. 2. How can the proof be generalized through the intuition? Answer:
They are thoroughly identical propositions. There is still no synthesis. In the
designated act the predicate is only expressed in the I in a dierent manner:
as soon as this expression signies something else, it becomes sleight of hand,
and the propositions become false.)
What would be the pure result of this intuition? Answer: My thinking
can revert back into itself. Nothing more. This alone is the factual content.*
II.
3rd Postulate: to again become conscious of the thinking (and the type
of thinking) that has been carried out in ones consciousness.
[*] 1). Corollary. Immediate self-consciousness is always what is invariable
and subjective: and because it is isolated it can never become the object of
consciousness. This is also not the case for us.
Hence, what is now to be done? We infer it as a constituent and condition
of another consciousness, and then abstractly describe it.
2). Corollary. It is entirely like a mathematical proof. The principium a
quo is the intuition. Whoever cannot generate this intuition in themselves, or
cannot nd it within themselves (which should be considered impossible)for
them it lacks the force of proof.
It is completely false to say that philosophy is rational knowledge based
on concepts.59 The concept is never an archetype,60 nor any kind of thing, but
only a reproduction.61 The intuition is the archetype. The concept (and precisely
because of this, the word, its reproduction) actually has to render account to the
intuition. Precisely what is composed together in the concept, is indivisibly
co-existent in the intuition. A philosophical concept can only clarify and
render consistent an already completed system: however, it can never rectify its
fundamental errors: for it never arrives at the ground.
3) The concepts contained in the theorem, as well as what is posited on
the path of demonstration, are assumed to be approximately known as posited
from the ordinary use of the intellect. In any case, they are to be further
determined through their use and proof.
The A = A of the Foundations [of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre]62: the
former is a judgment that is related to an initial positing: the latter is the
original introspection back into oneself.63 Reection on oneself, as the condition
for all reection on A. This is very clearI do not believe that the current
presentation is more lucid [than the earlier 1794 presentation]. And yet, how
few people understood these earlier indications!! I didnt know at the time that
I was dealing with such a thoroughly un-philosophical and dogmatic age.
J. G. Fichte 99
Anyone* who makes the attempt and really conducts the experiment
will understand this: we assert that a thinking without a consciousness of
thinking is an absolutely unthinkable and utter absurdity.thinking itself is
a modeis necessarily conceived as a further determination of consciousness
itself: and hence a thinking without a consciousness of thinking is an impossible
thought. Whoever is unable to carry out this attempt cannot philosophize
with us: whoever conducts it and nds and says that it is dierent, has to be
[some kind of ] dierently constituted being to us, and cannot enter into any
kind of agreement with us.
[*above:] It is probable that the reader has put more into the given concept
than is contained in the task as we have understood it. It is envisioned like this;
if the task is neglected, then it contains something thoroughly unexamined.
5). To become conscious of the form in which the consciousness of these
immediately determined ideas, if further pushed, must be necessarily thought.
To become conscious of this.
To become conscious of the relations in which this consciousness of
determined thinking is necessarily conceived.
Ad: 6th: Ordering
Immediate: antithesis: I rst of all had to generate a certain consciousness:
and I could do it: Here I cannot think at all that it is rst understood through
an act, but is immediately and thoroughly indivisible there.
Conditioning, but not conditioned. Antithesis vid. On the back of the
page.
What is further determined in all consciousness. The pure reection
of something that is reected in a determined manner.
It is absolutely presupposing. If any kind of consciousness is posited,
then it is posited, but posited as conditioning.
Everything that is for us, is only within the same, its determination and its
object, and one can never step out of the same, without forgetting about oneself.
/ This is the immediate intellectual intuition; which never again becomes
objective; and I therefore become aware of it through something lower, thinking.[*]
[*] In the preface. The Wissenschaftslehre cannot be contradicted67; for
[the act of ] contradicting itself, of talking, is fundamentally conditioned. Every
contradiction shows that one has not understood the Wissenschaftslehre, and is
not speaking about it.
I am not praising myself; for the Wissenschaftslehre is not invented through
the freedom of any person; no one can claim to have invented it, who does
not already possess it. It belongs to everyone and it cannot come about
without a free actand is possessed by everyone who has become clear about
his reasonand I did not even rst think of it, but Kant.
The Wissenschaftslehre is mathesis of the mind. In actual mathematics one
only examines the products of the construction: here one examines the [activity
of ] constructing itself.
J. G. Fichte 103
Inferences
Corollary 1.
Corollaries.
_________
1). This means the lucid idea of course that is demonstrated there. Firstly,
inward activity, determinacy, determinability, the concept of purpose, and so on.
Consequently, I only need here quiet, determinacy, determinability.
Because self-determination as an immediate object of consciousness. For
this, and so on. Non-I, object, being, and so forth, thoroughly nd themselves.
2). Should I show in the second chapter that the transition from repose
to activity is a special act? Yes. That is the easy part. A general remark on
the synthesis: simply in order to make something intuitable.
3). Denite activity. Determinability. Activity, faculty. (Here it might
be good to enter into the synthetic series. Activity. Position of a line. Its zero
rest. Facultyanswer, determinacy, determinability, rest and determinability
faculty. It isnt necessary to stop here, because it is only found through itself.
Chapter Two
inactivity, and following from it. It is absolutely necessary to posit this state of
inactivity in order to construct the agility and to inwardly intuit it as such. The
latter ows continually forth: the former stands still. This owing forth can only
be precisely described by what stands still. Couldnt I make this better? We
have to rst of all posit what we continue and set in motion, and the rest is
present precisely in this positing.
4th Corollary. The ground of necessity and universality is intuited as present
in this mere activity of ours without considering its particular determination.
5th Corollary. Here it exhibits itself as an immediate and rst object of
immediate self-consciousness: activity.
<Incertior sum quam antea> for 1). Is it possible to combine both
propositions into a single theorem: no determined activity without a faculty?
2) Shouldnt a sequence, a chain, be discernable in my theorems? The second
theorem ought to work: the immediate object of the above self-consciousness
is our activity or an act.
Synthetic Theorem 3) there is no consciousness of activity without the
positing of a faculty. 4. not without a consciousness of self-determination; this
now becomes the actual object of self-consciousness.
What was I thinking when I tried to prove this second theorem, or when I
thought I had proved it. It cannot be proved until I arrive at self-determination.
Thus it says; I am only aware of my self as freely active. Hence, all other
consciousness presupposes free activity in its consciousness as the condition of its
possibility. I now have to arrive at this proposition by means of intermediate
elements.
1). Consciousness of activity as such is only possible as the consciousness
of the transition from a state of non-activity, hence, a consciousness of this
non-activity.
2). Consciousness of determined activity is only possible as a consciousness
of a transition from a state of mere determinability; that is, non-activity; or
a faculty.
3). a). Denition: Whatever is thought as a limited portion of a certain
sphere is called determined [bestimmt]. In a certain respect, it is opposed to
everything else that is external to it or lies in this sphere.
This is a mere explanation of the words. The thinking just described
abovethe thinking of something determinedhas to be found by everyone
in his own intuition, and he procures through this intuition a meaning and
insight into the above description.
b). Postulate: To become conscious of the activity when thinking ones
self as a determined activity.
We only think of ourselves in this thinking, this thinking simply reverts
back into itself; no Not-I is thought.*
J. G. Fichte 109
Demonstration
Demonstration
one part of the sum total of all possible thinking, i.e., according to the above
explanation, it is a determined thinking.
This determinacy is now intuited and constructed, insofar as the
indeterminacy arises from it; however, whether the I or a possible Not-I is
now conceived in itself, or in mere antitheses to indeterminacy, in relation
to the determinacy it is still determinacy, it is to be conceived as I or Not-I.
Accordingly, in the intuition it necessarily depends on the determinacy itself,
on the indeterminacy and determinacy.
Hence, the state of the repose, determinacy is the antithesis of the activity,
and indeterminacy is the antithesis of the specic activity. However, repose as
indeterminacy is a faculty (it is still determinacy). Thus, determinacy can be
added as a positive characteristic to the mere negative characteristic and inactivity
(they are never something for the intuition), which are to be still encountered
in the concept of the faculty.
(Faculty) We can conclude from this. This faculty and every act presuppose
a faculty. However, this is not necessarily a product of the imagination, in order
to make an intuition of the act, i.e. the act is subsequently to be preserved
as real and thoroughly not real.
Corollary. Do not start with the faculty and make it a fact.
Corollary. 1) The concept of a faculty is attached to the consciousness
of a specic act, and is synthetically in the intuition as a condition of the
consciousness of the rstwithout us having a hand in it, entirely of itself.
This proposition may be of importance.
Universality: Every consciousness is a determined [consciousness]: and
so forth.
4. In the consciousness of the activity only self-consciousness is opposed to
it (direct object of direct self-consciousness).
How can I imagine proving this proposition? I myself occur as duplicity,
and I am indeed real in it.
This is straightforward: 1). A real stands opposed to the ideal, which is
its object.
A real self stands opposed to self-consciousness, as an ideal self-consciousness.
1. A real self, however, is self-determination. it reverts back: it is
absoluteness, and in fact constitutes the I or the self.
1.) Postulate: to become conscious of ones own self-determining in the
described thinking, and in its mode.
As above: It proceeds absolutely: etc.
If one now especially reects on it by abstracting from what we have
determined (whether it is a thinking, or something else, a thinking of the I, or
of a Not-I), then it appears as a seizing and transferring in itself, its activity in
the limited sphere. Thus: this activity is thoroughly reposing and is simply
there: it is everything and nothing. It grasps and directs itself. Where does the
112 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
duplicity of the previous simplicity come from: the above seizing and directing
stands there, and how does it create out of the nothingness? It completely creates
itself and this entire state; it is absolute. (It is to be found in the intuition that
is ascribed to everyone.)
2). We become conscious of this self-comprehension. If we reect again
here on this self-consciousness, then we can distinguish consciousness and the
conscious in it.
How both appear opposed to one another. etc.
There is no other description (as everyone has to nd in himself ).
Consequently, both are only relatively determinable: are only possible in relation
to one another. for us.
Thus, self-consciousness has to have an object; a real self, otherwise it is
not consciousness.
3). This real must be self, i.e., in a real sense as an absolute reverting: this
is precisely the self-determining that was to be described: Q.E.D.
Corollary.
1). On the nature of this proof, which is partly developed from the concept
of a self-consciousness; however, it is also partly a synthesis of the intuition.
2). Does the real come from the ideal; or vice-versa? No both are
indivisibly united, though neither exists by itself. Already the entire division is
nothing in itself, but the result of our nitude. The former has absolutely no
meaning by itself.
Now 5. Self-determination, however, can only arrive at consciousness
in accordance with a freely outlined conception of determinacy, to which etc.
New resultconcerning the entire consciousness.
* Oh yes: it arises precisely from the opposition and is a precise characteristic
of the ideal. It is necessarily something xed.
** Limitation to us, i.e., to everything that the I says / which the
philosopher also has to clearly recognize.
Corollary 1. Why we give determinacy to an explanation, but not,
however, to the activity:
Determining is thinking. We explain it insofar as we construct it through
freedom before the eyes of the reader, as in the above concept of the I, and
it can be intuited. It is a mode of activity. Activity, however, cannot be
comprehended at all, but only intuited.
Corollary 2). Ground of the universal validity of this proposition.
Corollary 3). One can never start with the faculty. I cannot at all say:
I have a faculty.
Th[eorem]. 4. Only the self-determination of activity is the immediate
object of immediate self-consciousness.
Postulate: the self-determining of thinking oneself, and the way to become
conscious of this self-determining.
J. G. Fichte 113
We now have insight into the point of the transition from the one state to
the absolutely opposite state, from inactivity to activity, and from indeterminacy to
determinacy, and this connects up once again with our insight. If we now, as we
are able, (the grounds for this ability are left unexplained) ask how this transition
is mediatedaccording to the assertion of our immediate consciousnessand how
the inactivity is transformed into activity and the indeterminacy into determinacy,
then everyone who understands our task, and remains standing at immediate
self-consciousness will answer: absolutely through nothing. The transition is made
from inactivity to activity thoroughly because etc. The activity determines itself
and determines itself precisely so absolutely because etc. The activity itself makes
itself into activity and determines itself as an activity of this kind. It creates itself
out of nothing and creates itself exactly as it creates itself.
One intuits with all the abstraction through which one determines oneself.
We saw above that we precisely employ the same considerations concerning
self-determining: and we distinguish how we again become conscious of this
observation; this observation itself, consciousness, and the object of this observation,
what is conscious and self-determining. Activity also belongs (according to the
assertion) to immediate consciousness. In order not to misunderstand either of
the two, we will call the rst: ideal activity, the second: real activity, which is
a mere word denition and through which nothing can be proved.
We have now distinguished both; how do they appear to us in opposition?
Everyone is namely invited to intuit this distinction in his consciousness,
and to state what he nds there. A distinction of this kind is solely made in
and through intuition, because the distinction is indeed the intuition itself.
Consequently, we have to look for the characteristics of the distinction solely
in the immediate intuition. Everyone will nd that the ideal activity ought to
contain what is contained in it, and it is of such a kind as it is, not absolutely
because it is this, but because its object is like it is. It is intuited as determined
through the latter, attached to the same and advancing with it.
On the other hand, the real activity ought to be, because it is now like
that; not because the ideal that is attached to it is such and such. The real
now is what it is, the ideal as such is not at all, without a real, and is never
because it is.
It is so, because the real is like this. The former absolute: the latter
according to its determination, is dependent on the former.
The former appears viewed for itself, as an absolute being: in relation to
the ideal, as something appearing to the same. There are no other descriptions
apart from this relative description.
As I said, this is according to its determination. For according to its essence,
the ground of the ideality should be a spiritual forming* and forming an image,
* not a real creating. (how this is to be distinguished and what it rst
signies has to be discovered by everyone themselves in immediate intuition.)
114 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
_________
Inferences
Corollaries.
must also be the self, and can be intuited as such. According to the above. The
inner essence of the self is absoluteness, its form of reverting back into itself.
If the latter is perceived in a real sense, then it is not (as something ideal),
something self-forming; but something self-making; and indeed something
absolute, something self-creating; consequently, it is the same self-determining
that we proved above in the intuition.
Thus, we have here proved what we wanted to prove.
COROLLARY.
Only these few words in a note at the bottom of the text. I said in the
preface to the previous presentation: I assume there will be misunderstandings
that I could remove with a few words; but I did not say these few words in
order to bring the reader to think for himself, and to draw the readers attention
to something; and because of this I am considered to be unbelievably arrogant.
Nevertheless, I have not made this mistake in this new presentation and nd it
absolutely impossible to make it. However, in the process of working on this I
can perhaps head o a misunderstanding, and will therefore say the following
words: It has been said that the human being can procure himself, and he would
even be necessarily conscious of this self-procurement: what nonsense! These
words express a truly brute stupidity, and the same expression has already been
said of the general public. But please; we are not speaking about the public
here. Where has this concept already been derived? Where has this word even
been mentioned? Havent I amply recalled that my propositions are only valid
for what has been proved in intuition? Havent I, in the above 1, supplement
no. 2, explicitly recalled that the I here only signies the pure reex, and is
not even the thinking subject. Here it means the pure, real reex, and is not
yet a subject of this reality.
In any event, only self-determination procures the latter. Now let the
discerning reader judge whether I am able to prevent misunderstandings that
are due to forgetfulness and thoughtlessness. Do I now have to add a few more
cautionary words to prevent in turn misunderstandings of the above words (as I
most certainly know, for example, that brute stupidity will in turn misunderstand
J. G. Fichte 117
the above) and this in turn, the earlier words, and so on ad innitum, and
in the end I will not be able to nish a single 1. The above requirements
assume that we are able to elevate the absolute irrational through wit without
any ground to reason: which itself is irrational. Any reasonable reader will
therefore thank me for not taking into consideration every single irrationality.
SUPPLEMENT.
COROLLARY.
1). Whether this ideal is the real, or the real is the ideal.
2). Two dierent series of the real in an ideal sense and the mere products
of the imagination, have to be exactly distinguished in the entire following
derivation.
1). Someone could ask(and we pose this invalid question in order to
clarify our own thoughts:)whether the ideal would spring from the real or the
real from the ideal: whether we know because of volition (since as willing the
executed real activity appears here further under in the determined intuition) or
whether we have volition because we know. This question is absolutely invalid
and everyone ought to have seen its invalidity by means of the above: both are
equally absolute, and the intelligence constitutes both in its indivisible unity.
The intelligence is neither the one nor the other, but the unity of both*: not
subject, taken here as ideal, and therefore rst as an object, here taken as real,
but an absolute subject-object or object-subject. Yet the object does not exist for
itself, but only for the subject; and the subject does not arrive at itself, but at
the object: and both do not have any signicance separated from one another.
(Their specic relationship with each other.)
If idealism is to be called a system that derives all consciousness from mere
ideal activity, then the Wissenschaftslehre is not at all idealism. It rather rejects such
a system as utterly inconsistent and incapable of explaining the consciousness that
we all really have. (I also do not know if anyone has advocated this system. For
118 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Berkeley at least, the Godhead through which the representations are produced
in us was something genuinely real.)74 Yet a number of people who have tried to
refute the Wissenschaftslehre have taken it to be a system of this kind. Perhaps they
had only read the rst exposition of it, and were so exhausted by this that they
did not arrive at the second.75 In the latter they would have been immediately
placed at the summit of a certain striving, as the rst object of the consciousness
of the real, and mediating every other real consciousness.
If dogmatism is a system that starts from a real without any relation to an
ideal, as it really isthen through the foregoing propositions the Wissenschaftslehre
has safeguarded itself against all dogmatism, and everyone who only reects on
himself, and as long as he reects on himself, has fundamentally eradicated it
from the ground up.
In contrast to this system, the Wissenschaftslehre is ideal-realism or indeed:
a real-idealism, since it only necessarily asserts this derivation for an intelligence
that recognizes itself; however, it allows the thought of the inuence of foreign
laws of the thing to be valid and explain itself for ordinary consciousness.
* solely positable in itself = X (and cannot be conceived), insofar as both
are posited and indeed as one.
Transcendental idealism, on the other hand, signies with this idealism
a system in which all consciousness is derived from the immanent laws of the
intelligence, which for it are neither ideal nor real, but the unity of both, so
in this sense the Wissenschaftslehre is idealism. Indeed, since it only asserts the
necessity of these derivations for the intelligence that knows itself, for ordinary
consciousness [. . .]76
2). Thus, in contrast with the above 2 and 3 derived spheres of the
mere products of intuition, we receive here a sphere of the ideal-real. In itself
(it is really only ideal) and a consciousness of reality, is only achieved insofar as
the latter rst becomes intuitable through it. It is obvious that these are highly
dierent constituents of our knowledge. Both will be further determined in due
course, but it is necessary that one continually makes a distinction between them.
_________
J. G. Fichte
119
120 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
1.: [One gets there by] reecting on what presents itself in philosophy [as
occupying a position] between the subjective and the objective, which evidently
must be an item standing indierently over against both extremes.86 In
philosophy? There is clearly another system apart from the system of identity.
a). in philosophy, for what is conscious of itself appears there as something
consciousas something objective. The subjective and the objective are purely
united in it, however, i.e., it is therefore knowledge itself: kat exochin. . . . b).
which evidently must be an item standing indierently over against both
extremes. What does this mean?
In its unity it is also clearly not indierent against both, but the two
arise out of it.
from the thinking agentas substantially posited at the outset . . . Here
one really gets to the bottom of what Schelling understands by the I of the
Wissenschaftslehre, and by the word subjective.
However, let us now closely examine his abstraction, not from the two,
but from thinking and knowing itself.
a). What is my view of the matter? The former identity has insight into
itself, in the subjective and objective and in everything else. The philosopher
J. G. Fichte 121
merges himself with this insight, and renounces his independence in it. Since it
contains all knowledge, it obviously contains philosophical knowledge as well.
b). Schelling, however, now describes the former A, and reects on himself
[as separate] from what he has abstracted, but which invisibly drives his own
nature, according to what is in any event present in himself, i.e., according to
laws lying external to reason.
This method is thoroughly inverted, and no good can come of it.
And why not? Let he himself foretell how things will end up here. _). The
Wissenschaftslehre also thinks and believes in thinking; however, through intellectual
intuition it yields proof of the correctness of its thinking immediately in itself.
`). A. contains much more than the dierence of the subjective and the objective
if it is described as consciousness. Schelling can never arrive at this through mere
thinking. He can never get out of the indierence through mere thinking.
Every other word that he employs is surreptitiously obtained, and we shall
soon see from where.
c). What is intellectual intuition for Schelling? Only at most the
intervention of the A between subject and object. . . . i.e., something seen87
from philosophy, and the latter contains the subjective intuition of what remains
permanently and thoroughly objective. Thus, it is a perception.88 The whole thing
is a perceptual system. Nothing at all like the inherently immanent light, like
genuine intellectual intuition.
This is also why reason is not a pure receiving,89 but only what is ultimately
received.90
However, he does not deny (well not decisively) its objectivity, because
the latter is only possible in opposition to a thinking entity, and makes it into
the nal standpoint of philosophy. How is he in error here? That is to say,
how can his error be genetically explained?
Polyphemus without an eye. It is clear to me that he does not know the
original meaning of subjective, as it is in A, but that he can only grasp it
in relation to an already presupposed subject (a thinking agent in thinking).
Thus, he cant actually escape from his I as a presupposed substance, and this
holds for his entire system. But it would be interesting, and even amusing, to
make this clear to him.
From what kind of invertedness does a proposition of this kind arise? And
what would result from it . . . 1). According to me, absolute reection (subjective)
and the projection of knowledge are indivisible in intellectual intuition. A
self- presupposed (substantial) knowledge rst arises if a particular element of
knowledge is described (which is precisely thinking). Yet I have joined both in
a way that is still not entirely clear to me. It is only joined in this manner:
knowledge, in which the absolute appears, is prepared in this free act of higher
reecting, as it were: - Knowledge rst receives duplicity. (N.B. also make a
note of this for the manuscript that is to be prepared.) The process is the
following: I cannot know without having an insight into my knowledge as freely
122 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
the former proof once again only remains external, it builds its argument in
an absolutely untrue manner and which precisely contradicts the explicated
concept: the absolute identity is precisely, because it is absolute, both eecting
and eected, and this is the sole and appropriate concept. If it were nite,
then the ground of its niteness would certainly lie in itself, for it cannot be
externally limited or determined in any other way, so it is certainly absolute.
But it is not a contradiction to say that the absolute identity is simultaneously
nite through itself in its absoluteness or inniteness: absoluteness is precisely
pure self-determination. Here it is still profoundly unclear in general, especially
the concept of the consequence of determinations from the absolute; this means
that the principle of a variable is now joined to that of an invariable. However,
in an acute and constant deduction we would not know anything about this yet.
_________
in general it is not at all a matter of the things; we still do not presently know
that anything exists, except the being of the one absolute identity. (Precisely in
the Explication the writer allows a freer and more indicative language, and
hence we do not have to criticize these unproven expressions. A truth that
Spinoza alone of all previous philosophers acknowledged, even if he did not
fully carry out its demonstration, and express it clearly etc. Why isnt it fully
explained and clearly expressed? In truth, it is more complete and clearer than
in Schelling himself. Where is there a more precise expression of this than in
Spinoza: God is the immanent but not the transitive cause of all things?104
15. Absolute identity is only under the form of the proposition A = A; or:
this form is immediately posited through its being. Before proving this through
the proposition A = A the being of absolute identity is posited ( 6); and
obviously the absolute identity is only to be conceived and described under the
form of the proposition A = A; just as now, inversely, A = A is posited though
its being, so it can only be in the form of the proposition, hence it does not
allow it to be joined with any sense. In thought, A = A is the expression, the
schema for the absolute law of identity: to ascribe some kind of being to it,
or to assert that the identity necessarily exists (objectively, yet clearly) under
its form; furthermore, one has to ascribe a duplicity of subject and predicate
to it: and in the unity, it is at once subject and predicate: all of this does not
make any sense according to the above explanation: they are logical forms,
and it does not make any sense at all to elevate them to the level of objective
existence. Moreover, form and being are arbitrarily distinguished in the one,
simple and indistinguishable. However, both coincide here, the identity does
not have any other form than its existence. Therefore 1) would in general be
to prove how in the absolute identity form is to be distinguished from being:
it is nothing else than pure existence that is equal to itself ; but this self-equating
means nothing other than that the form has to be distinguished in the identity
from the being, nothing else than an expression of pure relation, position; (it is
this and nothing else). But conceding this too, then 2) A = A cannot be the
objective form of something; for this duplicity itself only exists as thinking and
for thinking; this distinguishes subject and predicate, which objectively does not
exist as a duality; for the judgment, e.g., the tree is green, exactly says that
the two are joined in a unity, it therefore negates all duality in it and precisely
holds the two apart only rst in thinking in order to even more rmly join
them together. Thus, in no sense can A = A become the objective form of
something or other. In corollary I we see that A = A is also called the form or
type of the being of absolute identity.
Corollary 2: What belongs merely to the form, is not posited in itself.
In itself, of which the antithesis: posited through another. Not the absolute,
but through the absolute; just as in Spinoza the attributes and modes are the
form of the absolute105; these are posited through the absolute, rst introduced
128 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
by its being; this especially distinguishes the thinking in it; otherwise there is
no succession or becoming in it.
16. Between the subject and predicate in A = A no intrinsic opposition
is possible. It is indeed the same as what is posited in A and in the universe;
this is self-explanatory. Yet here there is inserted another distinction between in
itself106 and not in itself,107 when he alludes to the factual oppositions; where
without bothering in the slightest about the derivation of this factitcity, the
proposition should be prepared, these oppositions do not exist in themselves.
This is already apparent from the above; rather, his chief concern ought to
be to make it understandable to us, and how it nevertheless appears capable
of doing this. Here the distinction between the in itself and existence is
overlooked, which is subsequently a good thing. Because if the same A represents
the position of the subject and predicate, then the form of absolute identity is:
one form of identity of identity (corollary 2).
17. There is an original cognition of absolute identity, and this is
posited though the proposition A = A. There is a cognition of identity as such
(This is a fact; we infer this because we immediately recognize the truth of the
proposition A = A.) Since everything that is, is in the absolute identity, then
knowledge is also in it; but since this does not follow from the essence of the
absolute identity then it follows from the form, and belongs to the form. But
the form is just as original as its being. Everything, therefore, which is posited
by the form, is likewise equally original with the absolute identity. This also
occurs with absolute knowledge. The absolute identity is therefore originally under
the form of absolute knowledge. (Which is now more distinctly emphasized
in 18.) Much could be raised against this. From the fact of knowing, the
latter, as fact, would exist integrated in the form of absolute identity: because
there is absolute knowing, the identity is also a kind of knowing. This can be
conceded with respect to the earlier assumed proposition: there is only One etc.;
however, we never arrive at proposition 18 through this: everything which is, is
the form of being in accordance with knowledge of the absolute identity._ Where
does this everything come from? This insertion is also revealed in the words
of the proof: if knowing belongs to the form of the proposition of absolute
identity, with the former inseparable from being, theneverything that is, is
the form of being according to the knowledge of absolute identity. What is
this supposed to mean: knowledge of the absolute identity? Nothing else was
said in the preceding except that the proposition A = A is immediately known.
The purpose is again merely a dierence and probably the most important
one, which is to blur the dierence between subjectivity and objectivity. This
is claried even more in the following proposition, where this form of being
and of absolute identity is described in more detail.
19. (If namely identity is absolute knowledge, then it can only be
self-knowledge, as absolute identity.) Absolute identity is only under the form of
J. G. Fichte 129
39. In singular entities the absolute identity exists under the same form
that it has in the whole, and vice-versa. It is the same in all singular entities,
the same is alive in everything; consequently, it is indivisible ( 34). Here
the earlier principle of quantitative dierence is again superseded by a new,
unexpected conceptual leap.
40. Everything singular is innite in the potency of its dierence:
hence another determination of inniteness. The dierence is only due to the
specic degree of the relation between subject and object; this degree (potency),
however, is innite in its singularities. Every single determinacy of this potency
propagates itself into innity; it then expresses the form of identity in a certain
manner; therefore as eternal etc. (adde 41).
44. All potencies of the absolute identity are absolutely simultaneous.
(?) Now some supporting principles are interpolated. I) A = B is the
expression of the potency: A the subjective factorB the objective factor. B
is therefore what is original, A in contrast, is what B cognizes (?). However,
this distinction as such does not occur in two elements but A is as much as
B; both are originally one and indivisible in existence. He then compares this
with Spinozas extension and thinking, and then adds: here they are not just
joined in an ideal manner, as Spinoza typically understood them, but really
and in reality. II) and III) A is the limiting, but B is the innite, yet limitable
(namely the universal extension according to no. I). Both factors, however, are
original and necessary, i.e., innite, but in the opposite direction, one as the
limitable, the other as the limiting principle. Thus, it is to be understood: B is
the entire communal side of the real, i.e., not the generating dierence in itself;
this belongs to A, which is added through the various increasing potency of
subjectivity). (Moreover, Schellings relation to the Wissenschaftslehre becomes
decisively clear through this: this subject-objectivity A = B for him is precisely
the I-form; therefore everything is in the I-form, whereas the Wissenschaftslehre
in contrast only makes nature into pure objectivity. He thinks he has proved
that the existential form in general is = I [Ich]; that nothing can have reality
without this. Couldnt one show him here the lack of clarity and confusion?
Not a distinct consciousness, but instinct, blind instinct. However, is this the
absolute principle of things, the original beginning? Does real reason rst
emerge from out of this conscious-less reason, to rst arrive at itself, and to
contemplate itself? Couldnt this contradiction be demonstrated to him in a
purely formal manner?)
45. Neither A nor B can be posited, but both are joined together with the
predominance of the one or the other, which is again reduced to indierence with
regard to the universal.
46. A and B can only be posited as predominating according to opposing
directions. Either the one predominates in one of the parts, or in another; in
the sphere where A is the predominating one, B is therefore the subordinate
J. G. Fichte 133
one, and vice versa; in this regard, however, the indierence always governs
in the totality. Consequently, this is obviously to be presented under the form
of his line.
Explication 2. What holds for the entire line, also holds for all the
parts of the same into innity. In every [part] either A = B or B = A with
A = A. Each of its points contains the same single absolute identity in the
subject-objectivity, but only insofar as one predominates. Thus, everywhere two
points are essentially and inseparably united. The constructed line is therefore
innitely divisible, and its construction is the ground (?) of all the divisibility
into innity (Here it is obviously not a question of the line as a geometrical
gure: it is only an analogy; i.e., only concerning what can be constructed in
it; thus, why is the question of the divisibility of the line, the ground of every
other divisibility? Etc. However, what he means is this: in every point of the
universe these two components are united, the universe is also divided into
innity, can be separated into distinctions; he is again speaking of what he
calls a single thing. However, in both the former and latter the derivation of
the ground of this distinction is still lacking, or this principle of nitude in
the absolute identity.)
47. The constructed line is the form of being of the absolute identity in
the singular as well as in the whole. He thereby means that in 39 he will also
clarify the requirement as to how the identity in every single part still remains
the same. The line is certainly not the form of the being of the absolute
identity, but the image110 of the form. In it the form can be constructed in its
innity, and therefore also be assumed in the later propositions; the line as the
perfected expression of the form.
48. However, A and B are contained in every point of the line since
the image is only under the form of the subject-object in the predominance
of the one or the other; A and B are therefore immediately posited with the
being of the absolute identity.
49. The constructed line (or the form), considered in itself, can contain
the ground of no individual potency; since it contains them all in it.
50. appears to us to directly follow from 48.
Explication. This presentation calls relative totality the joint reality (being,
existence) of A and B; both are really joined, exist, and belong as a whole to
it. According to the subject or object in this relative totality, various potencies
are now predominately posited.
51. The rst relative totality is matter. The relative totality is, as certain
as the absolute identity is; since this is only under the form of A = B; however,
the united being of both factors is thereby immediately posited.
The main elements of a comprehensive critique have been prepared, and
the entire dierence between Schelling and me can be traced back to a couple
of points of dierence.
This page intentionally left blank.
Introduction to F. W. J. Schellings
Presentation of My System of Philosophy1
(1801) and Further Presentations from the
System of Philosophy (1802) [Extract]
Friedrich Schellings new presentation of his system, the rst work in what
came to be deemed his philosophy of identity, was occasioned by a double
confrontation with Fichtean idealism in the summer and autumn of 1800: a
more general challenge (documented in the Correspondence) to the place of a
philosophy of nature in the transcendental tradition of the Wissenschaftslehre
that had slowly taken form in Fichtes mind as he read, sometimes cursorily,
Schellings writings from 1795 to 1800, and a more specic epistemological
challenge to the supposed independence of philosophy of nature that Carl
August Eschenmayer voiced in Schellings own journal on Naturphilosophie.2
Early in 1800, Schelling wrote to Eschenmayer to remind him of his
promise to submit some articles for the Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik.3 In a
letter from April of 1800 no longer extant, Eschenmayer expressed the view that
central claims Schelling had advanced in his 1799 essays on the philosophy of
nature were circular,4 viz., that the business of philosophy of nature is to eect
a self-construction of nature, that the idea of nature is necessary, and that it
necessarily involves a duality of principles. Either the idea of nature is a priori
or these suppositions are borrowed from an empirical overview of nature.5 In a
manuscript submitted to Schelling in the summer of 1800 for the Zeitschrift fr
spekulative Physik and printed in the rst issue of Vol. II, January, 1801 under
the title Spontaneitt = Weltseele oder die hchste Prinzip der Naturphilosophie,
Eschenmayer argues that there can be dual principles in nature only if there
are dual and opposite tendencies in the subject who is conscious of nature
rstly, a principle of spontaneity that tends to innity, secondly, a limiting
nature-principle that strives to limit and conne activity to nitude, and in
addition a synthesis that equalizes themwhich can only be drive or impetus
(Trieb), the foundation of sensation and intuition. As the rst presentation of
Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre had suggested, the laws of nature are projected upon
135
136 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
objectivity from the work of mind (Geist), since only in us is there to be found
a principle of spontaneity or originary motion.6 Since empirical science cannot
establish the claim to systematic unity in nature, a philosophy of nature needs a
propaedeutic or foundation, which it indeed nds in transcendental philosophy
(or Wissenschaftslehre). It is simply too soon, argues Eschenmayer, to proclaim
an independent philosophy of nature.7
In the same issue, which Schelling nished editing and sent to his publisher
early in the autumn of 1800,8 Schelling appends a reply to Eschenmayers critique
under the title ber den wahren Begri der Naturphilosophie und die richtige Art
ihr Probleme aufzulsen (On the True Concept of the Philosophy of Nature and
the Correct Way to Solve Its Problems). Later that autumn, Schelling receives
essentially the same challenge to his notion of the independence of philosophy
of nature from Fichte9, and he quickly replies to it in a letter10 that recounts
the history of the development of his philosophical views in general and those
on nature in particular in words that are almost identical to those used in the
True Concept essay.11 Though this theme of the independence of Naturphilosophie
will become the major point of contention in the Fichte-Schelling Correspondence
over the course of the next year, it seems that it was Eschenmayers attack that
directly occasioned the writing of the Presentation of My System of Philosophy.
In the True Concept essay, Schelling puts the disagreement between
Eschenmayer and himself in the starkest possible terms: while the Fichtean
Eschenmayer locates the activity of nature in the I, Schelling places it in
nature itself. This claim of agency in nature, the precondition of philosophys
attempt to present nature as self-constructing, for now remains unexplained,
but Schelling promises that the next issue (which appeared at the Easter book
fair on 26 April, 1801) will contain a new presentation of his system, one in
which Eschenmayers dualism of nature and spirit, and all other dualisms that
haunt ordinary consciousness, will be abolished and the oneness of the world
proved.12 But the one world Schelling has in mind is no longer the world
of consciousness, or a transcendental construction of the inward activity or
agility behind consciousness such as the newer versions of the Wissenschaftslehre
articulated; it is the natural world, the one place where the identity-in-dierence
of the absolute comes to expressionas in Spinozas one world which is both
natura naturans and natura naturata. Nature is not to be viewed as a product
of reason; reason itself comes to be in nature. In this reversal that Schelling
announces in the Presentation of My System of Philosophy, transcendental idealism
is transformed into objective idealism, to use the name Hegel gave to the
nineteenth-century heir of Kantian-Fichtean subjective idealism.13
The Presentation of My System of Philosophy was composed in a scant six
months, for Schelling writes extensively to Goethe late in January of 1801 on
a central theme of its version of Naturphilosophie14the role of metamorphosis
Introduction to Texts of F. W. J. Schelling 137
Preface.27
For many years I sought to present the one Philosophy that I know to be true
from two wholly different sides[both] as philosophy of nature and as
transcendental philosophy. I now nd myself impelled by the present situation
of science to publicly bring forward, sooner than I wish, the system that for me
was the foundation of these dierent presentations, and to make everyone
interested in this matter acquainted with views which until now were merely
my own concern, or perhaps shared with a few others. One who understands
this system as I now present it, who subsequently has the desire and the means
to compare it with those early presentations; who further perceives how many
preliminaries were necessary to prepare for the complete and certain exposition
that I believe I can now provide, will nd it natural rather than blameworthy
that I rst produced those preliminaries versions; working from wholly dierent
sides, I sought to prepare for the integral reception of this philosophy, which I
have the audacity to regard as the one and only Philosophy, before I dared bring
it forward in its entirety. Under these circumstances, no one should think (as
was occasionally imagined when I presented this system in lectures the past
winter) that I have altered my system of philosophy: for the system that appears
here for the rst time in its fully characteristic shape is the same one that I
always had in view in the dierent [earlier] presentations, and that I continually
used as my personal guide-star in both transcendental and natural philosophy.
I never concealed from myself or from others the fact that I take neither what
I term transcendental philosophy nor what I term philosophy of nature, each
in isolation, to be the system of philosophy itself, but instead I have announced
in the clearest terms in the Preface to my System of [Transcendental] Idealism, in
many places in this journal, etc., that I regarded each of them as nothing more
than a one-sided presentation of that system. If there were readers and critics
who were not aware of this fact, or for whom such announcements gave no
141
142 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
clue to my real intention, this is not my fault, but theirs, nor is it my fault that
[my] vocal protest against the way idealism is usually exhibited, which has existed
since [I started work on] the philosophy of nature, has to date been noticed
only by the sharp-sighted Eschenmayer,28 while it has been tolerated even by
the idealists themselves. I have always presented what I called philosophy of
nature and transcendental philosophy as the opposite poles of philosophical
activity; with the present exposition I situate myself at the indierence-point
[between them], where only the person who has previously constructed
[philosophy] from completely antithetical directions can correctly and condently
place himself. For most people faced with the task of assessing a philosophical
system, nothing more pleasant can happen than that they are given a single
word which they believe has the power to fetter and arbitrarily conne their
mind. If I should say, however, that this present system is idealism, or realism,
or even some third combination of them, in each case I might say nothing false,
for this system could be any of these, depending on how it is viewed (what it
might be in itself, abstracted from any particular view, would remain undecided),
but by doing so I would bring no one to a real understanding of this system,
for what idealism or realism might be, or some possible third position compounded
from the two, is by no means clear or obvious, but something still to be decided;
and dierent minds attach quite dierent ideas to these expressions. I do not
wish to anticipate the point in the following presentation where this matter will
of itself come up for discussion, but only to make some preliminary remarks.
It is self-evident, e.g., that I take as the actually elaborated system of idealism
only what I have expounded under that name, for if I took idealism to be
anything else, I would have expounded this alternative; therefore, I give idealism
no other meaning than what I have given it in that presentation.29 Now it might
very well have been the case, e.g., that the idealism which Fichte rst advanced
and which he still maintains had a meaning completely dierent than this;
Fichte, e.g., might have conceived idealism in a completely subjective sense while
I, on the other hand, conceived it in an objective one; Fichte might have
maintained an idealism relative to the standpoint of reection, whereas I situated
myself and the principle of idealism at the standpoint of production: to put
this contrast in the most intelligible terms, if idealism in the subjective sense
said that the I is everything, idealism in the objective sense would be forced to
say the reverse: everything is = I, which are doubtless dierent views, although
no one will deny that both are idealistic. I do not say that this is really how
things stand; I merely pose the possibility; but supposing this is the case, the
reader will learn from the word idealism simply nothing about the genuine
content of a system expounded under this name; rather, to the extent one is
interested in the matter one must resolve to study it and only then examine
what is understood or properly asserted by this term. The situation may be no
dierent for what used to be called realism than it is for idealism, and it seems
F. W. J. Schelling 143
to me, as I hope the following presentation proves, that until now realism in
its most sublime and perfect form (in Spinozism, I mean) has been thoroughly
misconstrued and misunderstood in all the slanted opinions of it that have
become public knowledge. I say all this only to this end, rst, that the reader
who wishes to become informed about my philosophy resolve at the start to
read the following presentation with quiet consideration, not as the recital of
something already known (in which case only the form of exposition might be
of interest), but as something still entirely unfamiliar;everyone is at liberty
afterwards to assure himself that he has long thought the same things;and I
especially request that one criticize as philosophy of nature only what I designate
philosophy of nature, as the system of idealism only what I call the System of
Transcendental Idealism, but that one decide to learn my system of philosophy
solely from what follows; secondly, I request that one form an opinion of my
presentations of natural philosophy and of idealism, but especially of the following
presentation of my system of philosophy, solely from those texts themselves, not
from other expositions, that one ask not whether this presentation agrees with
that exposition, but whether it agrees with itself and whether it has warrant30
or not, considered in itself and entirely abstracted from everything that exists
outside it; I especially hope that the reader will resolve provisionally to consider
Fichtes system and my presentation independently, since only through a further
development can it appear whether and to what degree the two are, and have
been, in agreement all along. I say provisionally, since I think it is impossible
that we will not eventually come to agreement, even if now, at least in my
opinion, this point has not been reached.31 But then would any educated
person believe that a system of this sort develops instantaneously, as it were, or
that it has already attained its complete development? Have people given Fichte
the time to reach the point where he must decide that his system is not just
idealism in general (since in my view, all true speculative philosophy is this) but
precisely this idealism [which I present]? I think Fichte has until now achieved
only the most general results. Some people may be pleased and others irritated
that I consider what has been done up to this point as only the beginning of
what will be done, and that the whole matter is therefore far from its end.
How could this development of which I speak be more eectively delayed than
by the eagerness of idle people who, by nature quite remote from the faintest
idea of speculation, nonetheless voice their opinion on these matters with the
blindest possible self-condence and who voice either their agreement or
disagreement before they have even grasped what the discussion is about? Where
must it end when, e.g., Reinhold declares with most naive candor that he has
never understood, either in the beginning or in the middle, not even shortly
before the end (he says end) what was the real issue in the latest philosophical
revolution32? Where must it end when such a personwho in the beginning
of this Revolution was a blind follower of Kant, then in a theory of his own
144 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
making proclaimed infallible, catholic philosophy, and toward the end gave
himself over to the bosom of the Wissenschaftslehre (with an equally strenuous
protestation of his deepest conviction)when such a person, after all these
proofs of philosophical imbecility, does not lack the courage to again (and as
he himself surmises, for the last time) prophesy the present end of the
philosophical revolution? a We avert our gaze from these sights and for the
moment recall only this: all further clarications of the relation of our system
to any other, especially to Spinozism and to idealism, are to be sought in the
following presentation itself. I hope this presentation will also put an end to all
misunderstandings [of my work]; the philosophy of nature was especially plagued
by them; as I remarked in an essay in the previous issue, since it should have
been self-evident that a First Sketch could contain no nished system,33 I have
for many years thought it better to remedy these misunderstandings by completing
the system than by a preliminary general discussion. Accordingly, I shall no
longer pay the least attention to any critical judgment that does not engage me
a. For anyone with a sense of science what we said in the text will be adequate to justify our opinion
of Herr Reinhold; we are bold to express it because privately we never had the least respect for him
as a philosophical mindhe never was one and he has, indirectly at least, given up all claim to the
title. He condemns himself to always be the schoolboy and plays the disciple to the point of absurdity;
on this score he has really made the grade. He never had anything more than a historical mind for
philosophy: He advanced his theory of the faculty of presentation on the basis of Kantian philosophy
(which it notoriously assumes to be true). Since from its viewpoint, presentation [Vorstelllung] is just
a fact, naturally nothing more than a factual deduction of it is possible. Since this rst and singular
expression of his own philosophical activity, Reinhold has had nothing more important to do than,
with the appearance of every new philosophy, conduct yet another review of all previous philosophers:
spiritualists, materialists, theists, and whatever else they may be called, and happily always pinpoint
their failings, but never recognize his own or see how useless his attempt to thresh the noble ancient
grain along with his straw wasa delusion surpassed only by his belief that he has solved the major
problems of philosophy with the principles of matter and form, or of the presenting and the presented
[elements of consciousness]. Since he has continued to live in profound ignorance of the authentic core
of all speculation, naturally nothing seems too grand for his power of judgment. But if this feeble mind
takes on Spinoza or Plato or criticizes other worthy gures of philosophy, it is surprising that he seems
to omit Fichte from this critical survey, and that he does so just as easily as he recently seemed to have
understood Fichte and have become deeply convinced of the truth of his philosophy. Honesty will not
permit me to intentionally distort isolated philosophical assertions that are as candid as the confession
[of ignorance] cited above; otherwise I might take the mutilations that some of my assertions have
suered in a certain review of my System of Transcendental Idealism seriously. I shall certainly not
waste my time on the matter, but instead formally invite Herr Reinhold to say whatever he thinks
appropriate of me in reviews, journals, etc., moreover, to help himself to my ideas and to my method
as a heuristic principle (which should be of good use), even to idealism, if he feels it necessary for the
honor of truth and the end of the philosophical revolution to refute ideas (even ones derived from
him), once they have been made suitably absurd. But what will people say when this Reinholdism
spreads all the way to explicit denunciations or to attacks from moral and religious quarters,
as happened in the latest issue of Neuer Teutscher Merkur? Surely one will see here again only the
temperament described above and see t to apply the golden word of [Schillers and Goethes] Xenien:
over rst principles, here expressed for the rst time, and that fails either to
attack these or to deny what necessarily follows from particular statements derived
from them. The method that I have employed in the construction of this
system will permit more detailed discussion at the end of the whole presentation
than at the beginning.34 Concerning the manner of exposition, I have taken
Spinoza as a model here, since I thought there was good reason to choose as a
paradigm the philosopher whom I believed came nearest my system in terms
of content or material and in form,35 but I also adopted this model because
this form of exposition allowed the greatest brevity of presentation and the
most accurate assessment of the certainty of demonstrations.36 I have made
quite frequent use besides of a general symbolic notation that was previously
employed by Herr Eschenmayer in his essays on natural philosophy and the
article Deduction des lebenden Organism (in Rschlaubs Magazine &c.).37 I
wish all my readers would read these essays, partly for their own intrinsic
interest, partly because it would put them in a more secure position to compare
my system of nature-philosophy and the sort of natural philosophy produced
by an idealism which, though produced quite necessarily, merely occupies the
standpoint of reection.38 For to grasp in its core the System of Identity which
I advance here, which is wholly removed from the standpoint of reection, it
is extremely useful to become closely acquainted with the system of reection
that is its antithesis, since reection works only from oppositions and rests on
oppositions. Generally speaking, with this system I take a double stance, [rst]
towards the philosophers of previous and contemporary times and [secondly,]
towards empirical physicists. As for the philosophers, I have partially explained
this point in this preface; a comprehensive explanation will occur in the
presentation itself; it is superuous to remark besides that by philosophers I
understand only those who possess principles and method, who do not merely
repeat the thoughts of others or cook up a strange stew from dierent scraps
and tidbits; as for the physicists, one can predict their reaction to the philosophy
of nature beforehand. By far the greater number of them will continue to ght
the inevitable; so they speak of gradually accepting the constructions of philosophy
of nature as probable explanations or conrming them by experiments, or even
of nally immortalizing the whole of dynamic physics in their textbooks as a
pretty good hypothesis.
This may suce for an authors statement. From this point on, the
subject-matter alone speaks.
_________
brief indication must be given, then, of how one comes to understand reason
this way. One gets there by reecting on what presents itself in philosophy [as
occupying a position] between the subjective and the objective, which evidently
must be an item standing indierently over against both extremes. The thought
of reason is foreign to everyone; to conceive it as absolute, and thus to come
to the standpoint I require, one must abstract from what does the thinking.
For the one who performs this abstraction reason immediately ceases to be
something subjective, as most people imagine it; it can of course no longer
be conceived as something objective either, since an objective something or a
thought item becomes possible only in contrast to a thinking something, from
which there is complete abstraction here; reason, therefore, becomes the true
in-itself through this abstraction, which is located precisely in the indierence-
point of the subjective and the objective.
The standpoint of philosophy is the standpoint of reason, its kind of
knowing is a knowing of things as they are in themselves, i.e., as they are in
reason. It is the nature of philosophy to completely suspend all succession and
externality, all dierence of time and everything which mere imagination39
mingles with thought, in a word, to see in things only that aspect by which
they express absolute reason, not insofar as they are objects of reection, which
is subject to the laws of mechanism and has duration in time.
2. Outside reason is nothing, and in it is everything. If reason is conceived
as we have demanded in 1, one immediately becomes aware that nothing
could be outside it. For if one supposes that there is something outside it,
then either it is for-itself outside of reason and is then the subjective, which is
contrary to the assumption, or it is not for-itself outside reason and so stands
to this something-outside-it as objective item to objective item, and is therefore
objective, but this again is contrary to the assumption ( 1).
Therefore nothing is outside reason, and everything is in it.
Remark. There is no philosophy except from the standpoint of the absolute,
throughout this presentation, no hesitation on this matter will be entertained:
reason is the absolute to the extent that it is conceived just as we determined it
( 1); the present proposition, accordingly, is valid only under this assumption.
Explanation. All objections to this view could only refer to the situation
that one is accustomed to viewing things not as they are in reason, but only
as they appear. Therefore, we do not tarry with their refutation, since in what
follows we must prove that everything that is, is in essence equal to reason
and is one with it. The proposition as formulated would need of no proof or
even explanation but would instead rank as an axiom, if so many people were
not entirely unaware that there could be nothing at all outside reason unless
reason posited it outside itself, reason never does this, however, only a false
employment of reason which is joined to an inability to make the abstraction
demanded above and to forget the subjective40 element in itself.
F. W. J. Schelling 147
3. Reason is simply one and simply self-identical. Were this not so, the
being of reason would require some additional ground other than reason itself:
since reason itself contains only the ground that it is, not that some other reason
would be; reason would not be absolute, which is contrary to the assumption.
Reason is therefore one in an absolute sense. But if one supposes the reverse of
the second clause, namely that reason is not self-identical, then that in virtue
of which it is not identical to itself must still be posited in it, and, since outside
it (praeter ipsam) there is nothing ( 2), this other factor must therefore express
the essence of reason, and since, moreover, everything is in-itself only in virtue
of its capacity to express the essence of reason ( 1), this other factor too,
considered in itself or in reference to reason, would again be equal to reason,
united with it. Reason is therefore one (not only ad extra, but also ad intra, or)
in itself, i.e., it is simply self-identical.
4. The ultimate law for the being of reason, and, since there is nothing
outside reason ( 2), for all being (because it is comprehended within reason)
is the law of identity, which with respect to all being is expressed by A = A.
The proof follows immediately from 3 and the propositions that precede it.
Corollary 1. By all other laws, accordingly, if there are such, nothing is
determined as it is in reason or in itself, but only as it is for reection or in
appearance.
Cor. 2. The proposition A = A is the sole truth posited in itself, hence
without any reference to time. I designate such a truth an eternal truth, not
in an empirical but in an absolute sense.
5. Denition. I call the A of the rst position the subject, to dierentiate
it from that of the second, the predicate.
6. The proposition A = A, conceived universally, says neither that A
on its own is, nor that it is as subject or predicate. Instead, the unique being
posited through this proposition is that of identity itself, which accordingly is
posited in complete independence from A as subject and from A as predicate. The
proof of the rst assertion is furnished in the Wissenschaftslehre 1; the second
part of the proposition follows of itself from the rst and is contained within
it. Since abstraction is made from the being of A in its own right, and also
from its status as subject and predicate, the sole thing remaining from which
abstraction cannot be made, which is therefore really posited in this proposition,
is absolute identity itself.41
7. The sole unconditioned cognition is that of absolute identity. Since it alone
expresses the essence of reason ( 3), the proposition A = A is also the unique
unconditionally certain proposition ( 4, Corollary 2), but absolute identity
is also posited through this proposition ( 6). Therefore [its cognition] is etc.
Remark. The preceding series of statements was advanced merely to show
the unconditioned character of this cognition. For this cognition itself is not
really proven, precisely because it is unconditioned.
148 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
has not entered into being, but simply is; therefore it is posited without any
connection to time and outside all time, for its being is an eternal truth ( 8,
Cor. 2). Consequently, everything viewed as being in itself is absolutely eternal.
14. Nothing, considered intrinsically, is nite. The proof is drawn from
10 in the same way as that of the preceding proposition.
Cor. It follows that from the standpoint of reason ( 1) there is no nitude,
and that considering things as nite is precisely the same as not considering
them as they are in themselves. To the same extent, to consider things as
dierentiated or multiple means not to consider them in themselves or from
the standpoint of reason.
Explanation. The most basic mistake of all philosophy is to assume that
absolute identity has actually stepped outside itself and to attempt to make
intelligible how this emergence occurs. Absolute identity has surely never
ceased being identity, and everything that is, is considered in itselfnot just
the appearance of absolute identity, but identity itself, and since, further, it is
the nature of philosophy to consider things as they are in themselves ( 1),
i.e., insofar as they are innite and are absolute identity itself ( 14, 12), true
philosophy consists in the demonstration that absolute identity (the innite)
has not stepped outside itself and that everything that is, insofar as it is, is
innity itselfa proposition that Spinoza alone of all previous philosophers
acknowledged, even if he did not fully carry out its demonstration, nor express
it clearly enough to avoid being misunderstood ever after.
15. Absolute identity IS only under the form of the proposition A = A, or
this form is immediately posited through its being. Because it is in a simply
unconditioned way and cannot be in a conditioned way, unconditioned being
can be posited only under the form of this proposition ( 8). Therefore this
form is immediately posited along with the being of absolute identity, and
there is here no transition, no before and after, but absolute simultaneity of
being and of form itself.
Cor. 1. Whatever is posited along with the form of the proposition A = A
is also immediately posited with the being of absolute identity itself,42 though it
belongs not to its essence but only to the form or mode of its being. The proof for
the rst part of the proposition follows directly from the preceding one. The
second part of the proposition is proved as follows. The form of the proposition
A = A is determined by the character of A as subject and A as object. But
absolute identity is posited in this very proposition independently of A as
subject and A as predicate ( 6). So too, whatever is posited along with the
form of this proposition belongs not to absolute identity itself, but merely to
the mode or form of its being.
Cor. 2. Whatever belongs merely to the form of being of absolute identity, but
not to identity itself, is not posited in itself. This is because only absolute identity
itself is in its essence posited in itself. Therefore etc.
150 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
only under the form of cognizing, so it is only under the form of cognizing
its self-identity.
Cor. The entirety of what is, is in itself, or considered in its essence,
absolute identity; considered in its form of being, the whole is the self-cognizing
of absolute identity in its identity. This follows immediately [from the above].
20. The self-cognizing of absolute identity in its identity is innite.
For self-cognizing is the form of its being.47 But its being is innite (
10). So this cognizing is also an innite one.48
21. Absolute identity cannot cognize itself innitely without innitely
positing itself as subject and object. This proposition is self-evident.
22. It is the same identical absolute identity that, with respect to its form
of being, if not with respect to its essence, is posited as subject and object. This
is so because absolute identitys form of being is the same as the form of the
proposition A = A. In this proposition, however, one and the same entire A
is posited in the position of the subject and that of the predicate ( 16, Cor.
1). There is, therefore, one and the same identity which according to its form
of being is posited as subject and object. Further, since it is only with respect
to the form of its being that it is posited as subject and object,49 it is not so
posited in itself, i.e., with respect to its essence.50
Cor. In itself 51 no opposition occurs between subject and predicate.
23. Between subject and predicate,52 none other than quantitative dierence
is possible.53 For 1) any qualitative dierence between the two is unthinkable.
Proof. Absolute identity is, independent of A as subject and object ( 6), and
it is equally unconditioned in both. Now since it is the same equal absolute
identity that is posited as subject and object, there is no qualitative dierence.
Consequently, there remains 2) since there is no possible dierence between
the two in terms of being itself (because they are equally unconditioned
as s.[ubject] and o.[bject], thus the same in essence), there remains only a
quantitative dierence, i.e., one that obtains with respect to the magnitude of
being, such that the same identity is posited [as subject and object], but with
a predominance of subjectivity54 or objectivity.55
Explanation. We ask the reader to follow us in this proof with at least the
provisional trust that it will become perfectly intelligible after one simply forgets
previously obtained ideas, especially those of the customary concepts subjective
and objective, and thinks in each proposition exactly and only what we wish
thought, a suggestion which we make here, once and for all. This much at least
is clear to everyone at the start, that we admit no opposition between subject
and object (since what is posited in the one position and in the other is the
very same identity; subject and object are thus in essence one), but perchance
just some sort of dierence between subjectivity and objectivity, which since
they pertain to the form of being of absolute identity, belong to the form of
152 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
every being, perhaps not in an identical way, but subsisting together in such a
way that they can be alternately posited as predominantall of which we do
not yet assert here, but only advance as a possible conception. For the sake of
greater clarity, we add the following remark. Since the same A is posited in
the predicate and in the subject position in the proposition A = A, doubtless
there is posited between the two utterly no dierence at all, but an absolute
indierence of the two, and dierence, and consequently discriminability of two,
would become possible only if either predominant subjectivity or predominant
objectivity were posited, in which case A = A would have changed into A = B
(B is adopted as a designation for objectivity); now either this factor or its opposite
might be the predominant one, but in either case, dierence commences.56 If
we express this predominance of subjectivity or objectivity by the exponent of
the subjective factor, it follows that if A = B is posited, there is also conceived
a positive or negative power of A, so that A0 = B must be the case just as
much as A = A57 itself, i.e., it must be the expression of absolute indierence.
Dierence is simply not to be understood in any other way than this.
24. The form of subjectivity-objectivity IS not ACTU58 unless a quantitative
dierence of the two is posited.
Proof. This is so because it is not actualized if subjectivity and objectivity
as such are not posited. But since the two cannot be posited as such, they
might still be posited with quantitative dierence ( 23).59 Thus the form of
subjectivity-objectivity is not actualized or really posited unless quantitative
dierence is posited between the two.
25. With respect to absolute identity NO quantitative dierence is conceivable.
Since this identity is identical ( 9) to the absolute indierence of
the subjective and the objective ( 1), neither the one nor the other can be
discriminated within it.
Cor. Quantitative dierence is possible only outside of absolute identity.
This proposition is just the inversion of the preceding one; it is certain,
even if there is nothing except absolute identity.
26. Absolute identity is absolute totality. Because it is itself everything
that is, or, it cannot be conceived as separated from everything that is ( 12).
It is, therefore, only as everything, i.e., it is absolute totality.
Denition. I call absolute totality the universe.
Cor. Quantitative dierence is possible only outside absolute totality. This
proposition follows directly from 26 and 25, Cor. 1.
27. Denition. What exists outside totality I designate in this context an
INDIVIDUAL being or thing.
28. There is no individual being or individual thing in ITSELF. For the
unique in-itself is absolute identity ( 8). But this is only as totality ( 26).60
Remark. There is also nothing in itself outside totality, and if something
is viewed outside the totality, this happens only by an arbitrary separation of
F. W. J. Schelling 153
the individual from the whole which is eected by reection. But in itself
this separation simply does not happen, since everything that is, is one
( 12 Cor. 1) and is absolute identity itself inside the totality ( 26).
29. Quantitative dierence between subjectivity and objectivity is conceivable
only in reference to individual being, but not in itself, or in light of the absolute
totality. The rst part of the proposition follows directly from 27 and 26,
Cor., the second part from 25 and 26.
30. If quantitative dierence in fact occurs in the perspective of the
individual thing, then, to the extent that it is, absolute identity is to be understood
as the quantitative indierence of subjectivity and objectivity. The proof follows
immediately from the proposition that absolute identity is absolute totality
( 26).61
Explanation. Expressed in the clearest way possible, our assertion is this,
that if we could view everything that is in the totality, we would perceive in
the whole a perfect quantitative balance of subjectivity and objectivity,62 hence
nothing else than a pure identity in which nothing is distinguishable, however
much in the perspective of the individual a preponderance might occur on
one side or the other, that therefore we would perceive that precisely this
quantitative dierence is in no way posited in itself, but only in appearance.
For since absolute identitythat which simply is and is in all [] is not in
any way aected by the opposition of subjectivity and objectivity ( 6), the
quantitative dierence of these two cannot happen with respect to absolute
identity or in itself, and the things or appearances that appear to us as dierent
are not truly dierent, but are realiter63 one, so that all things together, though
none for itself, display clear unclouded identity itself inside the totality in which
primordially opposed potencies cancel each other out. This identity, however,
is not produced, but original identity, and it is only produced [in the totality]
because it is. Therefore it already is in everything that is. The power that bursts
forth in the stu of nature is the same in essence as that which displays itself
in the world of mind, except that it has to contend there with a surplus of
the real, here with one of the ideal, but even this opposition, which is not
an opposition in essence, but in mere potency, appears as opposition only to
one who nds himself outside indierence, who fails to view absolute identity
itself as primary and original.64 It appears as a produced identity only to the
one who has separated himself from the whole, and to the extent he isolates
himself; to one who has not withdrawn from the absolute center of gravity, it
is the rst being, the being that never was produced but is if anything at all is;
it is to such a degree that even the individual being is possible only inside it,
while outside it, apart from things separated in mere thought, there is really
and truly nothing. But how is it possible for anything to separate itself from
this absolute totality or be separated from it in thought, is a question that
cannot yet be answered here, since in its stead we prove that such a separation
154 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
which we therefore refer anyone who is not yet acquainted with the proof and
who wishes to further follow our demonstrations.
I) If it is granted that A = B stands for a potency (quantitative dierence
relative to the whole), then in A = B, B is posited as that which originally is
(hence as the real principle), A on the other hand as that which is not in the
same sense as B, but which cognizes B, hence as ideal principle. For a closer
discussion of this statement, see my System of [Transcendental] Idealism, page 74
and especially 84.79 Yet this opposition has utterly no standing in itself or
from the viewpoint of speculation. For in itself, A has being just as much as B,
because A, like B, is the whole of absolute identity ( 22), which exists only under
both forms, but under both equally. Since A is the knowing principle, while B,
as we shall discover, is what is intrinsically unlimited or innite extension, we
have here quite precisely both the Spinozistic attributes of absolute substance,
thought and extension. We do not merely think these attributes are identical
idealiter,80 as people commonly understand Spinoza, we think them completely
identical realiter.81 Accordingly, nothing can be posited under the form A that
is not as such and eo ipso also posited under the form B, and nothing can be
posited under B that would not immediately also be posited under A. Thought
and extension are thus never separated in anything, not even in thought and in
extension, but are without exception [everywhere] together and identical.
II) If A = B is generally the expression of nitude, then A is to be
conceived as its principle.
III) B, which originally IS, is the simply limitable, in itself unlimited
[factor in A = B], while A is the limiting one, and since each is in itself innite,
the former is to be conceived as the positive innite, the latter as the negative,
therefore opposite in tendency.82
45. Neither A nor B can be posited in itself, but only one the same
[identity] with predominant subjectivity as well as objectivity and the quantitative
indierence of the two.83
Proof. There is nothing in itself outside absolute identity ( 8), but the
latter is posited unto innity under the form of s.[ubjectivity] and o.[bjectivity]84
( 21 .), therefore, unto innity (e.g., in some single part) neither subjectivity
nor objectivity can be posited for itself, so when quantitative dierence
(A = B) is posited, it is only under the form of the predominance of one factor
over the other, and this occurs equally in the whole and in the part ( 39).
But there is no reason that one should be posited as predominant over the
other. Therefore both must be posited as predominant simultaneously, and this
again is inconceivable without the two reducing their opposition to quantitative
indierence. Therefore neither A nor B can be posited in itself, but only the
identical with predominant s.[ubjectivity] and o.[bjectivity] at the same time,
and the quantitative indierence of the two.
F. W. J. Schelling 159
+ +
A=B A=B
_________________________
A = Ao
wherein the very same identity is posited in each direction, with predominant
A or B in the opposite directions, while A = A itself falls at the point of
equilibrium. (We signify the predominance of one factor over the other with
the + sign).
Explanation. For further consideration we attach some general reections
about this line. +
A) The same identity is posited throughout the line, and even at A = B
is posited not B+ in itself, but only [that factor as] predominant. Exactly same
holds for A at A = B.
B) What holds for the line as a whole, holds too for each individual
section of it unto innity. Proof. This is because absolute identity is posited
endlessly or unto innity, and is posited endlessly under the same form ( 39).
Therefore what holds of the whole line, holds too for each part of it unto innity.
C) Accordingly, the constructed line is divisible unto innity, and its
construction is the ground of innite divisibility.
Remark. From this it is evident too why absolute identity is never divided
( 34, Cor.). That is, in every section [of the line divided] there are still
three points, i.e., the entire absolute identity which is only under this form.
But just this fact, that absolute identity is never divided, makes possible the
innite divisibility of that which is not absolute identity, which is therefore
86
( 27) an individual thing.
+ +
D) I designate A = B and A = B the poles [of the constructed line],
but A = A the indierence-point. So each point of the line, depending on
how it is viewed, is the indierence-point and -pole or its opposite [one of
the end-poles]. For since the line is innitely divisible (C), and division is
unconstrained in every direction, since the same [identity] is in every direction
(A), then every point can also serve as indierence-point relative to some other,
or become now one, now the other of the two opposed end-poles, depending
on how I divide [the line].
Cor. From this it is clear: a) how the line, abstracted from the fact that
I divide it (idealiter) is, when viewed realiter or in itself, absolute identity in
160 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
which there is simply nothing to divide. b) how with this line, since it is the
fundamental form87 of our entire system,88 we never in abstracto89 step outside
the indierence-point.
E) The two poles may be considered as innitely close to one another or
as innitely remote from each other. This follows directly from the preceding
propositions.
F) An innite lengthening of this line could never produce more than these
three points. This proposition is the mere inversion of one part of the above.
47. The constructed line ( 46, Corollary) is the form of being90 of absolute
identity in the part as in the whole. The proof includes the above theorems from
45 on. This line accordingly satises the requirement of 39.
48. The constructed line is the form of being of absolute identity only insofar
as A and B are posited as BEING91 in all potencies.92 This is so because absolute
identity is only under the form of A and B, that is, if A and B themselves are,
then surely absolute identity is, and since identity is only under the form of all
the potencies ( 45), A and B are therefore posited as subsisting in all potencies.
Cor. The degree of subjectivity with which A subsists ( 45), must therefore
be entirely independent from this being93 it has in all potencies, since the dierence
of potencies depends precisely on this dierence of degree ( 23, Expl.).
49. The constructed line, considered in itself, can contain the ground of
no individual potency. Since it is in the whole as it is in the part ( 47), it
expresses all potencies just as it expresses a particular one.
Cor. The same holds true for the formula A = B, since it is the symbol
for a potency as such ( 23, Expl.).
50. The formula A = B can signify a being only to the extent that A and
B are both posited in it as SUBSISTING.94,95
Proof. This is so because every A = B, because it designates a being, is an
A = A relative to itself ( 41, Cor.), i.e., a relative totality, but a relative totality
is only what absolute identity expresses for its potency under the same form, the
innite for instance ( 42), although absolute identity is in [a potency like] the
innite only because A and B are posited as being under all potencies ( 50). So too
A = B signies a being only to the extent that A and B are both posited as being.
Cor. The degree of subjectivity or objectivity with which A and B subsist
is entirely independent of this being of A and B. ( 48, Cor.).
Explanation 1. If we signify the two opposed factors of the construction96
by A and B, then A = B falls neither under A nor B, but in the indierence-
point of the two. Now this indierence-point is not the absolute one, for at
the latter falls A = A97 or quantitative indierence, but in the present one
A = B or quantitative dierence.98 In A = B, A is actual as mere cognizing,
B as that which originally is, the former thus posited as merely ideal, the latter
as real ( 44, Remark 1). It cannot be this way, since A is as much as B (ibid.)
and should be equal to it, i.e., have being in common with it, not just idealiter,
F. W. J. Schelling 161
but realiter, and only under this condition does B too subsist. If both should
equally be posited as real, a relative doubling necessarily occurs in the passage
from relative identity to relative totality, yet this doubling happens only after
the two are equated realiter. The following schema will serve to make this clear.
A B
1. A = B (relative identity).
2. A B
(relative doubling).
3. A = B
(relative totality).
The following remarks may be made about this schema: The schema
distinguishes relative identity from relative totality.99 Absolute identity, in contrast,
is also absolute totality ( 26), for in it A and B do not subsist as dierent and
so are not posited as ideal or real. To the extent A = B is posited as relative
identity, there is necessarily also posited a stepping out from identity on As
part, since not only is it posited as subjective but as having being ( 50) or as
real. The totality of this schema is caused, then, by A being posited jointly with
B under B.100 This A = B, in which A is posited with B as being, is, considered
in complete isolation or in- and for-itself, really the A = A of this potency, it
is A = B, i.e., predominant objectivity or subjectivity, only with respect to the
whole, not in itself ( 42, Def. 2). We request [the reader] not to disregard these
remarks, for even though they primarily serve to explain our method, they are
for that very reason necessary and indispensable for a basic understanding of the
construction of this system. The following will serve to clarify still more the
meaning of the schema set out above. In A = B (conceived as relative identity)
absolute identity is posited only generally under the form of self-cognition,
from the viewpoint of the originally objective, it is limited by the subjective,
we designate the tendency or direction in which B (as innite extension) is
limited the outward tendency, [and] the one alone in which A can be limited
the inward. Now absolute identity is posited as an innite self-cognition
( 19, 20); consequently there can be nothing in it (e.g., the condition of being-
limited) that would not also be posited under the form of self-cognition, and this
situation is necessary and must be carried forward until it is posited under the
form of absolute self-cognition. So with A identity must also immediate cognize
itself as limited in its subjectivity, with B as limited in its objectivity, and when
this limitation is posited as mutual [in A = B], it must recognize itself in the
relative totality, therefore a necessary transition from relative identity to relative
totality follows directly from the innitude of absolute identitys self-cognition.
2. Relative totality is the common reality of A and B (1). Outside absolute
identity, therefore, there is posited relative to the subjective a pervasive tendency
162 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
toward being or reality. This tendency cannot subsist anymore within absolute
identity itself, since there is in it utterly no opposition between the subjective
and the objective, [and] in it, ultimate reality and ultimate ideality coalesce in
an indivisible unity. One can say of reality therefore, though not of objectivity,
that it is the predominant element in the whole series [of potencies and of
individuals within potencies], since everything, even the subjective, strives toward
it. In the highest instance of reality one again nds absolute totality, absolute
balance of subjectivity and objectivity.
3. Since the schema noted above is derived from the universal concept of
potency (A = B), it is necessarily the schema of all potencies, and since, further,
absolute totality is constructed only through a realization of the subjective in
all potencies, just as the relative totality is constructed through a realization [of
subjectivity] in the determinate potency, so must the succession of potencies
follow according to this schema.
51. The rst relative totality is matter.
Proof.
a) A = B is not anything real, either as relative identity or as relative doubling.
In the individual just as in the whole, A = B can be expressed as identity
only through the line [ 46, Cor.]. But in this line A is everywhere posited as
having being. Therefore this line generally presupposes A = B as relative totality
( 50, Expl. 1); relative totality is therefore the rst item presupposed, and if
relative identity is, it is only through totality.
The same thing holds for relative doubling. For since A and B can never be
separated from one another, the only way relative doubling would be possible,
would be that the identity of the line ACB
A ______________ B
C
+ +
in which A signifies the A = B pole, B the A = B pole, and C the
indierence-point, be suspended and AC and CB be posited as dierent
A
lines (under the schema of the angle B, hence under form of the rst two
dimensions).
C
But since AC and CB are, each for itself, the whole, relative doubling
presupposes relative totality just as relative identity does, and if it is, it is only
through totality that it can be.
b) Relative identity and doubling are not contained actu, but they are still
potential in the relative totality. This is so because the two precede relative totality
not actually, but potentially, as is evident from the deduction ( 50, Expl. [1]).
c) The same A = B therefore is simultaneously under the form of the rst
dimension (pure length) and the rst two dimensions (length and breadth), and
F. W. J. Schelling 163
General Remark
b. Only someone who has followed us but lacks true insight into the meaning of our system could
interrupt at this point with the question, so is this system realism or idealism? One who has understood
us sees that this question makes no sense whatsoever in reference to us. For us of course, there is simply
nothing in itself except the absolute indierence of the real and the ideal, and only this is in the proper
sense of the term, while everything else has being only in it and relative to it. So too matter is, but it
is not as matter, but only insofar as it belongs to the being of absolute identity and expresses absolute
identity for its potency. We wish to take this opportunity, which seems most appropriate, to show
by the example of matter how Spinozas three types of cognition can be displayed in our system and
what meaning they have in it. The lowest stage of knowing is to regard matter as such as the real, to
see in matter what it has in common with the innite (totality, relative to itself ), therefore to know it
generally as nothing but totality, is the second, and nally to acknowledge that, considered absolutely,
matter is simply nothing and that only absolute identity is, is the ultimate level or genuine speculative
cognition. Authors Note in original edition.
164 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
which is equivalent to the third dimension. 3) One must think the quantitative
being-posited of A and B concretely. If one assumes, e.g., that A is innite and
that it innitely returns from B, it would be innitely forced inward; in that
case it would merely be an inner, and for that very reason also no inner, since
this concept has standing only in opposition and opposition occurs only within
quantitative dierence, but never within indierence. The same thing holds if
we innitely posit B (the factor that moves outward) or, nally, if we innitely
posit both, A as well as B. There is an inner and an outer only within relative
totality. Therefore, because matter as such is posited, it is also posited with the
quantitative dierence of A and B.
52. The essence of absolute identity, insofar as it is immediately the ground of
reality, is power.101 This follows from the concept of power. For every immanent
cause of reality is designated a power. But if absolute identity is the immediate
ground of a reality, it is immanent cause as well. This is so because it is really
only the immanent cause of a being ( 32. 38, Remark 2). Therefore, etc.
53. Immediately through absolute identity A and B are posited as being or
as real. The proof includes all previous propositions, since we have derived
the fact that the prime existent (consequently also A and B) has being directly
from absolute identity itself.
Cor. 1. Hence, as the immediate ground of reality of A and B, absolute
identity is power or force ( 52).
Cor. 2. A and B are the immediate ground of the reality of the prime
existent,102 and since both of them are in essence equivalent to absolute
identity(since the same absolute identity is in each of them) ( 22) both of
them, A and B, are forces ( 52).
Cor. 3. As immediate ground of the reality of the prime existent, A is
attractive force, B is repulsive force. The demonstration of this proposition
is presupposed. Cf. System of Tr.[anscendenta]l Id.[ealism], p. 169 .
54. As the immediate ground of the reality of A and B in the prime
existent103 absolute identity is gravitational force.
This so because A and B, as subsisting in the pr.[ime] e.[xistent] and as
the immanent ground of its reality, are the attractive and repulsive104 forces
( 53, Corollary 3). But the power by which these two are posited as subsisting
and as the immanent ground of the reality of the pr.[ime] e.[xistent]105 is
gravity.106 (For the proof, see vol. 1 of this journal, issue 2, p. 19 and 24.).
Therefore, etc. . . .
Remark. It is quite probable that for many readers this proof still contains
some obscurities. It might be asked, rstly, e.g., in what sense gravity can also
be conceived as the ground of the reality of B, since this is primordially ( 44,
Remark 1). But B is only thought to be subsistent or objective within relative
identity, while relative identity itself is nothing real ( 51). B is therefore, like
F. W. J. Schelling 165
1. A = (A = B)
(within relative identity)
2. A A=B
(within relative opposition)
3. A = (A = B}
(within relative totality).
c. The theory of what we term dynamic process falls under the phase of relative opposition in this
potency. Since this topic has been discussed often in other places, we take the liberty of asserting many
theorems here without repeating their proofs, since it is more our purpose to provide a total concept
of our system rather than to linger on specic items.
168 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
so-called empirical proofs of this nihilistic hypothesis, and which posits the
purest and simplest claims of nature itself in place of the articial and deformed
experiments of the Newtonian school, that this whole system of identity
advances itself. For this reason it is not remarkable, but completely natural and
quite comprehensible, that physicists who have sworn feudal allegiance to the
Newtonian theories oppose investigations which prove quite undeniably that
even in the part of physics where previously they were accustomed to possess
the most extensive, indeed almost geometrical, evidence [viz., optics], they have
found themselves in the most baseless errors with respect to essential points.
Such experiences, in the long or short run, could undermine the faith among
the people in these blind priests of the veiled goddess and give rise to a general
surmise that things stand no better in all the other parts of authentic physics
(namely, the dynamic disciplines), and that the true physics must rst now
begin to develop and extricate itself from error and darkness. A future history
of physics will not fail to remark what a retarding inuence the Newtonian
view of light exercised upon the whole science and how, on the other hand,
the opposite view, once adopted and made basic, opens nature up, as it were,
and makes room for ideas which up to that point were virtually banned.
Explanation [1]. In view of everything above, one will be able to formulate
the relation of gravity to the power of cohesion and of the latter to light. Gravity
is absolute identity insofar as it produces its form of being168; the power of
cohesion is gravity which exists in the general form of being (A and B)169; light
is absolute identity itself insofar as it is. In gravity, absolute identity subsists
merely in essence,170 i.e., ( 15, Cor.) abstracted from the form of its being
(which is initially produced), light is the existence of absolute identity itself,
and this is the reason for the dierent [modes of ] being of gravity and of light.
2. To a great extent, most people think that what is ideal exists or subsists
less than what is real, and so they value the former less than the latter. Others
do the reverse, and despise the real as if it were not equal to the purity of the
ideal. This may especially be noted in the way the latter see in light a purely
ideal, actually existent principle.171
94. Absolute identity is established as light only insofar as A and B are
factors of cohesion, and conversely, A and B are established as factors of cohesion
only through light. Proof. For, directly from the positing of A = B, A2 is also
established ( 58, Cor. 7). But A = B is directly posited as the substrate of relative
identity through A2 (the higher potency) being posited ( 64); it is established
only as relative identity, since relative duplicity also reduces to relative identity
( 83, Cor. 3), and relative identity is the form of cohesion ( 65, compare
with 67). Therefore, 1) A and B themselves are directly established as factors
of cohesion through absolute identity as A2 being posited as light, 2) Absolute
identity itself subsists as A2 only insofar as A and B are factors of cohesion.
176 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
Explanation. It might seem to many that the preceding theorem and its
proof went in a circle, [but] this [misimpression] will be cleared up if we more
carefully spell out the relation between light and gravity.
A = B is relative totality, but only in reference to a higher potency, for in
reference to itself it is absolute [totality] ( 42, Def. 2). Now complete indierence
is posited in the absolute totality. Gravity as absolute totality would, therefore,
posit the complete indierence of the attractive and repulsive force. However,
with regard to the particular, it quantitatively posits both A and B indenitely (
57) and only with regard to the whole does it posit them in perfect equilibrium
(ibid, Expl.); it is determined to the former [quantitative positing] through the
higher potency [viz., A2], and for that reason, it is only relative totality. With
this establishment of attractive and repulsive forces in quantitative dierence, the
degree of cohesion is also posited ( 72); hence gravity is determined to posit
cohesion only through the higher potency. Cohesion is established, therefore, in
just the way that A = B is generally posited as relative totality, that is, just as
primordially as A = B itself is posited; conversely, the higher potency (hence
absolute identity as A2) is established in that A = B can be posited only as
relative totality under the form of quantitative dierence (cohesion). In this
situation, therefore, [where gravity and light mutually posit one another] there
is no before and no after, but absolute simultaneity of the [two] powers as such (
44). I say as such, for although simply considered A = B precedes A2 (it is
the rst ground of all reality, 54, Cor. 1), as a potency it does not, for all
the powers mutually presuppose one another, as can easily be seen from 43.
Cor. Since absolute identity is light (A2) only insofar as A and B are
factors of cohesion ( above), cohesion is necessarily also the limit of light itself,
and the whole dominion of light (and thereby also of the dynamic process172)
is conned to the territory of cohesion, a theorem which will shortly prove to
be important.
95. The material universe is formed through a primordial process of cohesion.
Proof. This is so because gravity is the ground of things only according to
substance ( 70, Remark) not according to form (accidental aspect). But gravity
itself is active173 only under the form of cohesion ( 92), for through cohesion
it is established under the general form (accidental aspect) of being, as A and
B ( 70, Remark); but the actual being of gravity is the material universe (
57): therefore, the material universe is formed through a primordial process of
cohesion.174
Remark. The proof also immediately follows from the fact that matter is to
be viewed, within the totality just as in individual instances, as a magnet ( 69).
Cor. 1. Our planetary system in particular is formed through a process
of cohesion, and in it as a whole is a magnet, in the same way that the earth
is one on an individual scale.
F. W. J. Schelling 177
Absolute identity is not intrinsically light, but only insofar as the identical
A = B is posited under the form of the subsistence of A and B, these conceived
as factors in cohesion (evident from 94).
Insofar as it is light, absolute identity cannot overstep the limits of
cohesion, since it is only under the condition of the latter.
Absolute identity, however, endeavors not to subsist under this or that
form (A = B), but simply under the form (A = A).
Cohesion is therefore an actual boundary of light insofar as light is
absolute identity.
So once this limit is established, i.e., once absolute identity is simply light,
it necessarily tends again to annul cohesion in this sphere where it is light. The
chief problem of cohesions deconstruction is thus iron and this will be resolved
into opposite directions.
Viewed from the speculative standpoint, though, matter as a whole and in
particular is primordially posited under the form of quantitative dierence with
respect to the individual and indierence with respect to the whole. Hence we
view metamorphosis as something primordial and posited along with the total-
magnet of terrestrial matter in its complete totality. This much [may suce]
for a preliminary explanation.
1) The location of cohesion insofar as it is active lies in the indierence-
point itself, hence in the perspective of the whole series [of chemical elements]
in iron. Accordingly, active cohesion is present in iron.
2) Quantitative dierence is established in two opposite directions [of
the series of chemical elements], in one direction with a predominant positive
factor, in the other with a predominant negative one.
3) Outside the indierence-point, I term cohesion a passive [force] and
it is understood to increase in the negative direction, while in the positive
direction it gradually approaches total dissolution.
4) Along the negative side fall those elements closest to iron in coherence,
the so-called noble metals, until the series resolves into bodies of the greatest
passive coherence (e.g., diamonds) and manifests as pure carbon.
5) Along the positive side fall certain metals in which the cohesion of
iron gradually loses itself and on this side nally disappears in bodies of the
least coherence,177 and nally in pure nitrogen.
6) From (3) it is evident why carbon generally appears in concrescence
with earth elements (even in plants), while nitrogen does so apart from cohesion
with them (even in animals).
7) As long as the potencies of dierence (A and B) are fully separated
in opposed directions, matter falls in the absolute indierence-point. This is
signied through water (the primordial uid element, wherein the pure third
dimension is produced, 51, c).
8) In this whole process of metamorphosis, the substance remains the
same ( 78, Def.), and only the accidental feature or cohesion is altered.
F. W. J. Schelling 179
for themselves, the forces simply have no quantity, since as the form of the
subsistence of absolute identity, both are innite; quantity is attained only in
and through this ratio. Accordingly, the extensive magnitude of a body can be
expressed through nothing other than the addition of this ratio to itself, and this
addition is established through cohesion. Of itself, there is no addition; A = B
is simply one, absolute constancy. With the transition from this185 to a relative
one, a part (discrete magnitude) and the addition of one part to another rst
becomes possible. The formula A : R signies a mere 1; the schema of cohesion
is the series 1 + 1 + 1 . . . without end. A 2 is rst posited through relative
duplicity, hence electricity ( 89, Cor.). In primordial production there is not
addition, but pervasion, utterly no part, but absolute unity.186 But it is another
question how the magnitude of this addition is itself determined; on this topic,
the following is oered. Since passive cohesion increases along the negative side
[of the series], the metamorphosis necessarily passes through the maximum of
specic gravity. But the cohesion process of heavier bodies187 cannot be continued
for long at such a marked degree, since the original proportion does not allow
this reduction of attractive force for long; in the opposite direction, however,
it displays the positive factor more extravagantly, until it nally produces the
greatest magnitude at the indierence-point, which may be demonstrated most
clearly through investigations of the planetary system and the amount of iron
in the earth. Hence there subsist in the [universe as a] whole one attractive
force and one repulsive force which is aggregated more or less only in opposite
directions. The physicist might be at liberty to explain the distribution of
forces through an endless process of diminution (of the [forces] of individual
bodies to the earth, and of the earth to the planetary system as a whole) etc.
[Philosophical] speculation, which does not sanction such a regress, annihilates
it through totality and absolute identity, which comprehends everything.
96. Absolute identity, insofar as it subsists as light, is not power but
activity. For as light it is not the ground of reality, but is itself reality ( 93).
But it is not a particular being, for it is being itself ( 8), also not limited, i.e.,
passive, and so pure activity ( 36).
97. Absolute identity is directly posited through the force of gravity being
established as subsistent. For thereby all the conditions of its subsistence are
established, as is evident from a comparison of what was just said with 45, 46.
98. Absolute identity is not in itself light, but is such only insofar as it
is the absolute identity of this potency. For it subsists only as A2 = light ( 62).
This follows still more directly from 94.
Cor. 1. Conversely, if light is considered in itself (abstracted from the
potency [it occupies]), it is absolute identity itself.
Cor. 2. As the absolute identity of this potency, light is posited only
through the limit of this potency, hence, through cohesion ( 94, Corollary).
99. Denition. In light, identity is transparency.
F. W. J. Schelling 181
Cor. The power of gravity188 ees from light since it emerges from it as
the immediate ground of its existence. But gravity is transparent for absolute
identity, since for it everything is identical. However it is not transparent for
absolute identity insofar as it is light, since identity is = light only insofar as
the power of gravity189 is itself posited under the form of quantitative dierence
( 94) hence not as pure identity itself. Hence opacity is primordially only
relative, and is established neither with respect to the force of gravity nor with
respect to light, each considered absolutely.
Explanation. Not only is each of the individual factors within light, A and
B, the same in essence (since each of them is the same absolute identity, 22),
but light is also the absolute indierence of the two. Opacity arises only through
the two factors being posited in relative indierence, or quantitative dierence,
since in this relation the two mutually darken one another. Accordingly, in the
cohesion series constructed above, transparency for light is precipitated only at
the absolute indierence-point ( 95, Cor. 4, Expl. 7) and at the two extremes
of the gradations of cohesion, where against the predominance of one factor,
the other nearly disappears, and so again brings forth undistorted identity. The
greatest opacity necessarily falls in the point of the greatest weight posited under
the form of cohesion. (Platinum and the rest of the metals).
100. Directly through absolute identity being established in opposition to
the power of gravity, it is posited as mere light, i.e., as the absolute identity of this
potency.
Explanation. We do not doubt that it will seem contradictory to most
people when we speak of an absolute identity of this potency, i.e., of an absolute
identity that nonetheless is not absolute; this contradiction disappears, however,
when the following is taken into consideration.
Considered in its essence, light is absolute identity itself; considered in
its existence, it is the absolute identity of this potency. If one subtracts the
potency, i.e., the mode of existence, light is simply absolute identity; if one adds
this mode in thought, it cannot be annulled as absolute identity ( 11); it is
therefore in essence absolute identity in this potency just as it is also absolute
identity according to its being with respect to all potencies. The reader will
steadily keep in mind that all opposites that may have been produced completely
disappear from the standpoint of absolute indierence and are in themselves
utterly nothing. So it is easy to see, e.g., that the existence of light only signies
the point of the whole [universe] where the preponderance falls wholly on the
real side, so that gravity and light with respect to the whole form just one real
entity, and so in no way stand in opposition.
101. Light cannot be posited as light without being posited under the
universal form of being (A and B).
Proof. This is because according to its essence ( 98) it is not light, but
absolute identity itself. That whereby it is light, therefore, does not belong to its
182 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
essence, and so also not to the essence of absolute identity; hence it is merely
a form or mode of its existence190 ( 15, Cor. 1). Light as light is itself only
a191 form of the subsistence of absolute identity. Now since the universal form
of the subsistence of absolute identity is A and B, necessarily light is posited
as light under the form of A and B.192
102. Light is not posited in its essence under the form of A and B. This
is so since it is not light according to its essence ( 98) but is [posited] as light,
etc. ( 101). Therefore it is also not [posited] in its essence etc.
103. Light according to its essence is posited independently from A as
well as B, which are both mere forms of its existence. This follows with the same
evidence as 6.
Cor. Since neither A nor B is in itself light, but only absolute identity
insofar as it is posited under the form of both, so it will be posited as light
only in their relative indierence.
Remark. With respect to light, A and B are factors of cohesion (this
is evident from 94), B the expansive cohesion-reducing and +E [factor]
(potentiating hydrogen), and so A the opposed [factor] (potentiating oxygen).
With this, we return to a proposition put forth earlier (von der Weltseele,193 p.
27); though it was left undeveloped then, it here for the rst time receives both
its conrmation and justication. In precisely this quantitative indierence of
+[E] and E is posited under completely opposite modes of existence one and
the same identical entity (light).
We expressly make this remark so that one does not view our proposition
as a conrmation of the supposition of some physicists that light is composed
from some heat-substance and some other [physical] principle, light-substance.
Concerning the composition of light, see 102. According to our deduction,
A and B pertain not to the essence of light, which is absolute identity itself,
but to the mere form of its existence as light. It is itself able to exist as light
only in the indierence of A and B. Therefore even if our B is the heating
principle, yet that which we signify by A is not considered the illuminating
principle in light. The reason is that light and illumination as well immediately
exist at the point where there is the complete indierence of both [factors], and
which therefore is neither the one nor the other.
Denition. I call distorted or beclouded194 light the light that is posited
under the form of A and B with quantitative dierence.
105. For light, all transparency is a merely relative one. This is evident
from 99, cp., its Expl.
Lemma 1. The eect of a relatively transparent body upon light is refraction.
The inner ecacy of refraction is to distort light, i.e., [ 103 Def.] to posit it
under the form of A and B with quantitative dierence. Its outer eect is the
shifting or displacement of a luminous object.
F. W. J. Schelling 183
the compositeness of light. A special essay in the following issue [of this journal]
will provide a detailed proof of this assertion.
Corollary. According to its essence, light is colorless, or light is in its essence
not determined through color. This is so, since light is only distorted, but never
colored; what is colored is only the image or object. Accordingly, color is not
something that can ever pertain to the essence of light.
Remark. From this it is apparent that even if an actual dierence could
be detected inside the prismatic image, yet this would in no way have anything
to do with color, but would be wholly independent of it.
107. The warmth- and electrical conductive-power of a body is determined
by its place in the cohesion-series. Because this is one function of cohesion ( 91).
Cor. 1. All conductivity is merely the endeavor to produce active cohesion.
Now if one posits (1) a body wherein one factor in cohesion is predominant,
e.g., the negative side, it will not in itself be able to produce active cohesion,
but only through the help of a second item which introduces the other factor in
cohesion, and so conductivity too. One may term such a body an insulator, since
it only conducts at the point at which it is touched. If one posits (2) a body
which approximates the equilibrium of active cohesion (e.g., all metals), it will
be an excellent conductor of heat and electricity, both in itself and in contrast
to another, though the power of greatest conductivity will not coincide with the
point of greatest active cohesion (because this point can be established to a lesser
degree outside the equilibrium, so too it will be determined to conduction to
a lesser degree); the point of maximum active cohesion will fall in the product
of the element closest to it in cohesion (e.g., silver, copper). (3) In the case of
bodies where the positive factor of cohesion predominates, the rst case will
occur [again] and insulators be precipitated anew (e.g., sulfur, etc.). (4) Only
one body falls in the absolute indierence-point, water; this element and the
ones residing closest to it are in themselves simply not conductors, since in
them all active cohesion is annulled; they are themselves capable of no 1 + 1
+ 1. . . , but are an absolute unity with respect to the conduction-process. But
since, to take an example, water is outwardly completely indierent, it can be
introduced into every conductive process as this unity202; therefore it can relatively,
but not in itself or absolutely, be a conductor. (Here lies the justication of
modern ideas about the nonconductive property of liquids). Finally (5), where
the series terminates in its poles so that the matter represents only one or the
other factor (nitrogen, oxygen, hydrogen), there necessarily recurs the power
of nonconductivity.
Cor. 2. From what was just said, one can also understand the dierent
ways that magnetism and electricity propagate themselves. Since the magnet is
a perfect totality with respect to itself ( 70) and is in itself active cohesion,
neither of its poles can be altered from without (though it may happen through
a stronger [magnet]); rather just the opposite occurs, and each will posit its
opposite (with which it coheres) outside itself.
F. W. J. Schelling 185
General Explanations
1. The proof of 112 could have been directly shown from 69. Since the
same holds for the total-magnet as for the individual one, the former will tend
to collapse its extremes and revert into itself just as much as the latter. But this
occurs through the chemical process which joins the extremes of the [cohesion]
series ( 94, Expl.) and unites them under one common schema.
2. It is generally known that Volta,212 to whom modern experimental
physics owes its greatest discoveries, in experiments conducted on so-called
galvanism,213 long ago found the law that as the necessary condition for the
fullest galvanic action two dierent solid bodies in contact with one another
188 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
are required along with a third uid [medium]. But these are the most rened
conditions of the chemical process as is evident from the deduction ( 112)
wherein I believe I rst showed how and why chemical action follows from
precisely these conditions. That it results from these conditions, or at least
is promoted and assisted by them, was already certain from the well-known
researches that Ash214 made. From this there doubtless follows not, as many
had imagined, that chemical action is caused by galvanism, as if galvanism
were an essence or activity of a specic and characteristic sort, but rather the
reverse, that galvanism is the chemical process itself and nothing more, and so
that the two are not linked in any causal relation, but in a relation of identity,
therefore so-called galvanism must totally disappear from the list of specic
forms of activity (called processes). There is only magnetism, electricity and
the chemical process, whose purest form is the [phenomenon] previously termed
galvanism. The question: what then is this galvanic phenomenon that the
chemical process activity causes? has not previously been addressed. The confusion
that has surrounded this name in many minds will be completely dissipated
once one is no longer satised with a mere word, but looks to the thing itself
and observes the real details of the process in the so-called [galvanic] series; to
this date, however, no physicist has yet exhibited these details, and the above
construction is the rst, and as one might well be satised, successful attempt
to make the matter comprehensible and bring it closer to clarity.215 The clear
conditions of natures action in general are discovered either by following the
path of a priori construction, which by its nature abstracts from everything
circumstantial, or to discover it by experiments in which happy accident or the
acuity of the discoverer sets aside everything nonessential. Volta has presented
the galvanic phenomenon as just such an experiment insofar as he rst separated
the biological part216 of the experiment from the series and showed that the
[reaction occurred in the biological specimen] as a mere moist conductor (hence
in an altogether universal quality), and that the same eect could just as easily
be produced across any other moist medium. Thereby the galvanic phenomenon,
freed from its biological signicance,217 rst became an important acquisition
of general physics, and had this discovery borne no other fruit than this (to
display the chemical process under its primordial conditions), it would have been
reckoned among the greatest and most noteworthy discoveries ever made. For
those who are capable of the idea, no further proofs of the identity of galvanism
and the chemical process are needed than that the conditions of the former can
be understood from the latter and can also be derived a priori from them alone,
that therefore they are really the conditions of the latter. If in the meanwhile
more of our physicists further pursue the renowned utility of Voltas ideas and
experiments they will soon convince themselves and all mere empiricists too that
galvanism as galvanism, i.e., as a distinctive form of activity, never has existed,
nor can it be investigated as such in the future.
F. W. J. Schelling 189
114. In the chemical process are contained all other dynamic processes,
not just potentially,218 but actually;219 this is so because the chemical process is
the entirety of the dynamic process ( 112).
Cor. 1. For this very reason, conversely, all other dynamic processes can
be investigated as chemical ones. E.g., nothing stands in the way of saying
the magnetic pole which is elevated in cohesion is oxidized at the expense of
its opposite.
Cor. 2. In the triangle [postulated in] 112 carbon and nitrogen come
together through AB and AC, while through BC oxygen and hydrogen are
joined ( 95, Explanation[s] 4, 5, 11); but since these exact items are the four
dynamic potencies which support the whole play of the so-called process, it is
again evident from this how in the chemical process, the dynamic totality or
the four world-regions are united.
Cor. 3. The following general reections about the construction may be
added.
a) The schema of the three basic forms of the dynamic processes is, as is
known, the line, the angle, and the triangle, or in addition, these three processes
are equated with the rst three prime numbers of the arithmetic series. Just as
2 results only from the addition of 1 + 1, and 3 from the joining of 1 to 2 (so
therefore these numbers are not powers of 1), so too, therefore, the three stages
of the dynamic process [result from successive addition]. Even the chemical
process arises from a triple repetition of the same 1, namely, the magnet, which
in AC, AB and BC is only added to itself, and in this addition displays the
rst totality. Just as 1 is contained in 2, and 2 and 1 in 3, so magnetism is
contained in electricity, and magnetism and electricity in the chemical process.
We need only to look at the gure where ACB subsists only in the line ACB
displaced in the form of the D to note that in this [phenomenon, viz. the
chemical process] we do not step beyond of the conditions of magnetism.
b) The D represents the fundamental conditions of all being, AB the
negative, AC the real form of being, and nally the basis or BC the substance
or the identical posited under the form of A and B (gravity).
c) Kielmeyer220 has already hinted at the law that the activity within the
galvanic series, i.e., and hence within our D, = the dierence of the degrees of
anity of both bodies to oxygen. Expressed in greater abstraction, this law reads:
the moment of activity = the dierence of the degrees of cohesion of AB and
AC, whereby must be understood the natural degree not of active, but of passive
cohesion. For real active cohesion does not subsist without dierent degrees of
passive cohesion ( 73). Expressed this way, this law nds no exceptions, and
the table of respective exciting powers of bodies in the galvanic series fully
harmonizes in this way with the cohesion-series constructed above.
115. Indierent bodies that touch one another reciprocally posit active cohesion
in themselves and also between each other. For they tend to heat themselves (
190 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
84). But active cohesion is the reverse endeavor of heating (evident from 91,
Cor. 1). Hence they will establish reciprocal active cohesion in themselves, that
is, magnetism ( 68), and since this obtains reciprocally (by 107, Cor. 2),
they also reciprocally establish cohesion between them.
Remark. The proof may directly proceed from 70 and 80. For two bodies
that are indierent cannot jointly produce a totality which is dierent ( 74);
each must therefore tend to be the totality in reference to itself, i.e., a magnet.
Cor. The endeavor to posit active cohesion in itself and under itself
continues into the endeavor to heat itself, and persists until bodies are heated.
Proof. This is so because a body is heated only insofar as it conducts heat
( 88, Cor. 1). But all conductivity is a function of cohesion or of magnetism
( 91 a[nd] Cor. 1). Therefore, etc.
116. Conversely, dierent bodies will posit only active cohesion between
each other, but not reciprocally in each other. Regarding the rst part, see
80, Cor. 3. The second part follows from 75. Since the two bodies together
produce totality, it is not necessary for each to produce it for itself, i.e., for it
to establish magnetism in itself ( 70).
Expl. 1. From these theorems it is suciently clear why generally only
indierent bodies are magnetized, rather than only dierent bodies being electried.
2. It is further evident that what one has hitherto investigated as adhesion
is primarily magnetism, as least with respect to a solid body, except perhaps
that this magnetism is not capable of duration as in iron, but is limited to
the bare time of contact [between bodies]. The law governing all adhesion is,
indierent bodies adhere to each other most strongly, e.g., glass with glass,
marble with marble, and even here in the series of so-called adhesion, iron is
once again found at the top [of the list], and indeed that a (smooth) body
that is slower to respond to magnetism surpasses one less responsive (steel) in
strength of adhesion.d
117. Denition. I limit the concept of adhesion to the attachment of
a uid body to a solid one. This is so since uid bodies do not determine
themselves to active cohesion between themselves (as solid body and solid body,
since even in their owing together they form no relation of cohesion), but
only achieve a determination to adhesion through the latter [solid body]; in any
case there is here the ground of a distinction that is not valid with respect to
d. See [Louis Bernard] Guytons Grundstze der chemischen Anitt [Berlin, 1794]. In the eect of
iron on the metals nearest to it in the cohesion series (cobalt, nickel, etc), adhesion still appears under
the specic form of polarity, though quite naturally the phenomenon (not the thing itself ) disappears
in proportion to the distance from the mid-point of all cohesionwhich it makes visible under the
form of magnetism. (Note in original edition.) (Guyton [17371816] was a chemist and politician
who served revolutionary France in the National Assembly and the Committee on Public Safety, and
became a provincial governor under the Directory. [Tr.])
F. W. J. Schelling 191
the thing itself. This is so because the same rule governs uid and solid bodies
as governs one kind of solid and another ( 116, Expl. 2). Thus, mercury
adheres to those metals that are closest to it in specic weight and many other
properties, gold and silver to the strongest, while iron, on the other hand,
bonds to the weakest.
118. The moment of magnetism221 in chemical process as such is the moment
of adhesion.222 This is so because ( 110, Cor. 2) chemical action as such is
rst established through the addition of the uid body, BC, [to the solid ones,
AB and AC] ( 112). But between this AB and AC is possible (not so much
cohesion as) only adhesion ( 117). Accordingly, the moment of magnetism
as such can present itself in chemical action only under the form of adhesion.
Cor. This does not deny that AC or AB themselves, if they are bodies of
discernible active cohesion (e.g., copper, iron, silver), can present such a magnetic
moment in themselves, outside of the polarity that they present in interaction.
But this depends upon an accidental condition that we take no note of here.
119. The moment of electricity in the chemical process as such depends
on the liquid [medium] being potentiated into oxygen and hydrogen. It is evident
from the proof of 112.
Remark 1. From this it is clear that all the moments of the dynamic
process are exhibited in liquids considered as such, or that the latter in their
transformations traverse all [dynamic moments]. Water is the uid magnet (
95, Cor. 4, Expl. 7) and in its unbiased state represents the223 indierence point.
In the state of adhesion it approximates mere relative identity, in the state of
separation into oxygen and hydrogen it passes over to the moment of relative
duplicity. The third moment (of the chemical process in the chemical) will be
more closely dened in a while.
Remark 2. It would be very natural if, in light of the assertion that so-called
galvanism is nothing other than the chemical process itself, one would be led to
the grand concordance that undoubtedly obtains between galvanic and electrical
phenomena. For what has also been advanced counter to this harmony is of
no signicance, since, e.g., bodies that prove to be the poorest conductors for
the strongest galvanism are not weaker conductors for the strongest electricity,
like ethyl alcohol and others. But this concordance is already comprehensible
from theorem 114. The so-called galvanic process is at once magnetism,
electricity, and chemical process (the last understood in the narrow sense). See
this journal, vol. I, issue 2, p. 77. But precisely because it is these [three all
at once], galvanism is the chemical process itself displayed in the totality of
its conditions, under which too electricity is necessarily displayed. Accordingly,
it is equally necessary that the voltaic battery produce the most surprising224
electrical phenomena and the most important chemical ones as well.
But before we can discuss this, we must rst say something about the
construction of this remarkable totality which contains forever bound the Proteus
192 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
no more than what is contained in the former. The body that is increased in
cohesion determines water to [the state of ] water potentiated by +E, the one
decreased in cohesion (in order to restore itself by means of this reduction) is
determined to water potentiated by E (oxygen); it is oxidized. Only the two
outermost links of the chain, when it is not closed [into a gure], remain isolated
with their + and -. Accordingly, they can present none other than electrical
appearances (since a third [medium] is lacking), though these phenomena
doubtless appear under that form in which they previously presented themselves;
only with the addition of a third [item] (e.g., water) are the conditions of the
chemical process with respect to the whole fully given; but then it completely
occurs by the instantaneous exhaustion of the liquid element through oxidization
or deoxidization, depending on the individual circumstances. This much will
doubtless suce to indicate in a preliminary way the viewpoint from which
this remarkable subject is to be surveyed.
120. Even if it acts in all dimensions, the chemical process aects mere
cohesion in all of them. Proof. This is so because cohesion is the boundary of
all chemical action ( 94, Cor.).
Otherwise [proved]: because even the chemical D is reducible to the straight
line ( 114, Cor. 3. a); the entire dynamic process stands under the schema
of magnetism ( 65), hence, of cohesion ( 67), or what is again the same, of
mere addition ( 95, Cor. 5).
Remark: Hence it is to be expected that the ultimate ground of all
arithmetic lies here.e
121. Bodies are not altered in substance through the chemical process, but
merely in their accidents. This is so because the process aects only cohesion.
But what is posited through cohesion is not substance (which pertains to the
power of gravity228), but the mere accidents of it ( 70, Remark). Therefore
only accidental features will be altered through the dynamic process. But the
substance exists independent of the accidents (ibid.); so it cannot be altered
through alterations of accidents, and accordingly it is unalterable by chemical
process.
122. All so-called qualities of matter are mere potencies of cohesion. The
proof includes everything previously stated. For a more ample discussion, see
the Abhandlung von dynamischen Proce, vol. I of this journal.
123. The substance of every body is completely independent of its qualities
and is not determined by them. Evident from 122, comp.[are] with 121.
Remark 1. Hence, e.g., what one calls nitrogen and carbon are entirely the
same in substance, even if their powers229 are opposite. The relative in-itself
e. A thought that Herr Eschenmayer also expressed to me on the occasion of the Abhandlung von
dynamische Proce (Vol. 1, issues 1 & 2).
194 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
of the two is the one and the same indierent [item] viewed as substance,
namely iron.
Remark 2. So even here matter is subject to the universal law of being. For,
apart from the potency under which it is posited, all being is one ( 12, Cor. 1)
Remark 3. Therefore, if one abstracts from its potency, the being of matter
is identical to universal being, and entirely the same as it.
124. No body is composite in substance. This is so because in substance
it is absolute identity itself ( 123, Remark 3).
Cor. 1. So too whatever can be divided or decomposed is not destroyed
in substance. This follows from the [above], cp., 34, Cor.
Explanation. So it would be false, e.g., to say that metals consist in or
are compounded from carbon and nitrogen. For these two are mere forms of
existence of one and the same identical [item] and are not themselves that
which exists.230
Cor. 2. That a body is chemically decomposed or resolved means: the one
identical existent is posited under dierent forms of existence.
Remark. The so-called elements231 that are supposed to compose bodies
are therefore rst established through decomposition, and are products of
decomposition.
Cor. 3. From this it follows that a body, even if it can be decomposed,
is still not composite, but is one.
125. All matter is internally identical and is dierentiated merely in
its externally directed pole. This is so because it is not dierent in essence
( 12, Cor. 1) or in substance ( 123, Remark 2), but merely in its form of
existence. But the form of existence as such is cohesion ( 92, compare with
70, Remark); hence the sole form of existence is polarity232 ( 68), accordingly
bodies are dierentiated merely through the pole under which they exist or
(since the essence of a thing is the internal dimension, its existence the external)
through the pole whereby it acts externally.
Expl. 1. Thus, e.g., an acid and an alkali are in themselves perfectly
indierent and doubtless are dierentiated (at least in the process of neutralization,
because every moment of it alters [their] accidents) merely in that the former
turns the hydrogen-pole, the latter the oxygen-pole toward the outside. Substance
escapes our notice in just this action, since every body can be altered only
by another ( 36), and since in every moment of the process it is another in
terms of its form of existence, without pure and formless essence ever being
able to come forward.
2. The inward-acting pole of each body can also be called the potentiated,
the outward-acting one the potentiating [pole].
126. In no process can anything enter a body that is not already there
potentially.233 This was previously proved for magnetic ( 115), electrical, and
F. W. J. Schelling 195
heat processes ( 86, 88). A body, e.g., conducts its own heat and electricity,
not that of another body. [That the same holds] for the chemical process follows
directly from 69, Cor. 1. For all [properties] that are established in a body
through the chemical process are mere potencies of cohesion ( 120), but since
all other substances234 are contained in each single one, and since all substances
are dierentiated from each other only by the potencies of cohesion ( 125),
this says as much as: all potencies of cohesion are already virtually contained
in every substance; hence etc.
Expl. So, e.g., a body that is oxidized surely coheres with (or is bound
to) a substance whose potency is the negative factor of cohesion (oxygen); but
oxygen, whereby this substance acts externally, is its own [E] that rst comes
into eect when its +E is limited or annulled by an external potency. This
notion applies to every chemical process.
Cor. 1. Every body is a monad.
Cor. 2. Nothing that arises in the chemical process is intrinsically an origination,
but merely a metamorphosis ( 78).
127. The universal tendency of the chemical process is to turn all substances
into water. This is so because natures tendency is to reciprocally annul and
extinguish all dynamic potencies through each other, hence to produce absolute
(dynamic) indierence. But this state exists only in water ( 95, Cor. 4, Expl.
7). So within the chemical process, nature moves toward the production of
water or the transformation of all substances into water.
Cor. 1. In this tendency the chemical process is limited only by active
cohesion, which once established235 cannot be cancelled, and constructing power
in general is entangled in an eternal contradiction in the universal chemical
process whereby it annuls every dynamic potency though its opposite, but can
never remove the opposite without again positing its opposite: it is therefore
impossible that it ever (in this potency) attain its end, but through precisely
this contradiction all bodies are intertwined into a universal reciprocity (and so
at all events into a relative totality).
Corollary 2. Since water belongs to no potency236 ( 111, Cor.), but all
dynamic potencies are powers of cohesion, so water is entirely depotentiated iron.
128. Lemma. Acids should be viewed as intermediate steps in the
transition from solid substances into the powerless237 state (water).
Cor. From this it follows that the so-called radical of every acid must
either be a solid body or the sort of substance that at least functions as a factor
of active cohesion.
Remark. For the factors of passive cohesion actually reduce each other to
indierence ( 95, Expl.) and no acid arises from this situation. The primary
acids are carbonic acid and nitric acid. Secondary acids have a solid body as a
basis (sulfur [in sulfuric acid]) or a metal (as, apparently, hydrochloric acid238 does).
196 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
129. The chemical process239 inside the chemical process is the transition
from oxygen and hydrogen to absolute indierence, i.e., to water ( 119). This
directly follows from the above [theorems and corollaries, 127 .].
Cor. 1. This transition is necessarily tied to the presence of light. For
its two modi existendi240 ( 103, Remark), +E and E, which mutually cancel
each other, are given ( 95, Corollary 10).
Cor. 2. Hence, this transition is combustion.241
130. The basic law of all chemical process is that the body that is reduced in
cohesion to a measurable degree is oxidized. Evident from the rst construction,
112.
Remark. With respect to the universal law it is all the same whether the
reduction of cohesion occurs through the most primitive form of the chemical
process242 ( cit.), or through an electrical spark, or through the direct action
of heat.
131. All chemical composition is the depotentiation of matter. This is
so because in all so-called composition, nature aims at reciprocally suspending
opposite potencies of matter ( 109, Cor.) or at producing water ( 127).
Therefore ( 127, Cor. 2), every so-called composition is a (more or less
accomplished) depotentiation of matter.
Corollary. From this it follows, conversely, that every so-called decomposition
is a potentiation of matter, which can also be directly understood from 124,
Cor. 2.
132. Oxidization (e.g., of a metal) cannot be the basis of solution. This
is so because the latter is the reduction of cohesion, while the former enhances
cohesion ( 95. Expl. 10). Therefore, etc.
Cor. 1. Accordingly one must say just the reverse, that carbon (in the
diamond), metal, etc, tends to resist reduction [in cohesion] insofar as it is
oxidized, and if it is reduced it is not because it is oxidized, but because it has
been continually reduced in its cohesion.
Cor. 2. A body that is oxidized becomes specically lighter insofar as it
becomes absolutely heavier. This follows from what was just considered, and
from 72.
Cor. 3. An acid is in itself completely identical ( 124, Corollary 3),
therefore also not acid; it is acid only in contrast to a body that tends to
increase its cohesion.
Cor. 4. The decomposition of metal in acid occurs according to the universal
schema of the chemical process 112. If, e.g., there is the decomposing metal
silver, and nitric acid as the dissolving agent, carbon and nitrogen are in contact
with each other and with water, i.e., the totality of the chemical process is
given ( 114, Cor. 2).
133. Acids too in their action upon metals follow the universal law of
polarity, namely that only opposite poles work in opposite directions.
F. W. J. Schelling 197
Cor. 1. Opposite the metal of the carbon-pole is ranged the acid of the
nitrogen-pole, and opposite the metal of this latter pole is ranged the acid of
the carbon-pole.
Cor. 2. Iron is attacked by all acids, even mere water. The rst part is evident
from the above , cp., 76, the second part from 113.
134. Absolute indierence can only produce the factors of passive cohesion,
not of active.
Cor. It is necessary that chemical metamorphosis243 proceed in opposite directions
and end in free-standing poles. Since the chemical process ends in the production
of absolute indierence, while this latter is possible only with respect to the
potencies of passive cohesion, but not of active cohesion ( above), so the series
of chemical products ends in opposite poleswhere one represents one factor
of a[ctive] c[ohesion], the other the other factorwhich are futilely placed side
by side in the chemical process.
135. It is not the dynamic process that is the essentially real,244 but the
dynamic totality245 [reciprocity] that is posited by it, because in general only the
totality is essentially real ( 50, Explanation).
Remark. The honor of presenting this totality with respect to the terrestrial
bodies goes to Steffens in his oft-cited Beitrge.246 Using a sharp-sighted
combination of facts, he was the rst to explain the result that the [chemical]
earths (the greatest products of the chemical, hence the second metamorphosis)
form opposed series, of which one (the heat-hardened series) represents the
carbon-pole, the other (the cool-hardened) the nitrogen-pole.
136. Directly through the positing of the dynamic totality is posited the
addition of light as its product, i.e., the relative totality of the whole potency
is posited ( 58, Cor. 8, Remark). Proof: since light as the ideal principle
nds its limit directly through relative totality being posited ( 94, Corollary,
cp., 134), it ceases to be immediately ideal and becomes real, or appears as
a product ( 58).
Corollary 1. The expression of the total-product247 is therefore light united
to gravity.
Corollary 2. The unique reality248 of this potency is the total-product (
58, Cor. 8, Expl. 3).
137. Directly through the establishment of relative totality in the whole
potency ( 58, Cor. 8, Remark), gravity is posited as a mere form249 of being of
absolute identity. This is so because just as by the position of A = B as relative
totality, A2 is established ( cit., Cor. 7), so A3 is established by the position
of A2 = (A = B); but A3 is absolute identity insofar as it is posited as existing
under the form of being of A2 and A = B. Therefore, etc.
Explanation. Gravity is absolute identity not in so far as it is, but insofar
as it contains the ground of its being ( 54, Remark). Now in cohesion it is
posited as subsistent ( 92). But it cannot be established as absolute identity,
198 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
since being belongs to the essence of identity ( 8, Cor. 1), while what pertains
to the essence of gravity, on the contrary, is not to be. Therefore it cannot be
posited as existing in itself, while it is also posited merely as existing insofar as
absolute identity is posited as light ( 94), which too does not subsist in itself
( 98); and since it therefore cannot generally be posited as existing in itself,
it can only be posited as a form of being of absolute identity ( 15, Cor. 2),
which is exactly what happens in the relative totality of this potency.
From this it is also clear that the entire activity of this (dynamical) potency
arises from the positing of gravity as the form250 of being of absolute identity,
which can occur only by means of its relative opposition to A2 (the other form
of being), therefore only by means of the dynamical process, though this latter
occurs not with respect to the totality of this potency (i.e., not in itself ), but
only in the particular perspective, or outside of the totality of this potency ( 27).
138. By being posited as a mere form of being of absolute identity, gravity
itself is posited as accidental. This is evident from 70, Remark.
Cor. A3 is therefore the substantial reality251 in relation to gravity.
139. Denition. That gravity is posited as accidental with respect to
absolute identity means: it is posited as a mere potency ( 64, Def. 1) or as a
mere pole [of activity]. Regarding the latter, s.[ee] the proof of 125.
Remark. Consequently, we can express more precisely than before the
relationship between the original process of transformation252 ( 95) and what we
have called the second [series], which is rst established through the dynamical
and then the chemical process: original process of transformation indicates the
gradual establishment of gravity as a mere form of the being of absolute identity;
within this sphere absolute identity subsists only as light (A2), while gravity is
established neither as gravity nor as mere power. Gravity itself, however, is the
direct cause of the rst process of transformation, or the immediately positing
agent in this rst series which contains all primordial matters. The direct cause
of the second series of transformations, on the other hand, is [the explicit or
active form of ] gravity which, since it is torn from its resting state through the
rst process of transformation seeks to cancel the potencies under which it is
posited through the magnetic, electrical, and (in the totality) chemical processes.
140. Gravity can be posited as a mere power or pole [of activity] only in
opposite directions;253 this directly follows [from the above ].
This is so because the concept of direction is already included in the
concept of pole. Now since gravity is in itself indierent, there is no reason for
its being posited primarily in one direction, it will necessarily be established in
the same manner in opposite directions.
Corollary. This law holds unto innity,254 as do all the laws of the being
of absolute identity. Therefore it holds for the individual just as it does for
the whole.
F. W. J. Schelling 199
it is again the ground of its being (in a still higher potency), we can say in
general: we understand by nature absolute identity as such, considered not
insofar as it is subsistent, but as the ground of its being, and from this we
anticipate that we will call everything nature that lies outside the absolute
being of absolute identity.257
Cor. 1. In accordance with this we can say: the cause by which the
substance of the organism is conserved as substance lies within nature.
Cor. 2. Since the organisms ecacy ( 144) arises simply from positing
A2 and A = B (substance) as forms258 of its existence, while A = B as substance
can only be given to it from the outside,259 therefore the organism is determined
to ecacy from without.
Denition. This process of being determined, etc., is becoming sensitized
or excited. Further, since the reason that A = B with respect to the organism is
a simple form260 of existence lies in its identity with A2 ( 137), and since this
includes the reason that the substance of the organism must be provided from
without, i.e., that it must be externally determined to its ecacy, therefore A2
in its identity with A = B must be conceived as sensitivity,261 while the ecacy
itself whereby the two are established as forms of existence of the organism
(since the organism is merely the ground of the possibility of the ecacy, and
since the determination to ecacy is expected from without)is conceived as
the organisms capacity for indierence.
Cor. 3. We see quite well that the living organisms capacity for indierence
is one and the same with the cause whereby light is posited alongside with gravity,
each equally and together jointly as the form of existence of absolute identity;
at the same time we understand quite precisely that absolute identity is just as
much the direct cause of organism (or the ground of the common reality of A2
and A = B) as it is the ground of A and B in the Primum Existens262 ( 53).
The organism is therefore the secundum Existens;263 and since absolute identity as
the immediate cause of the organism is again the ground of its existence, so it
presents itself anew as the gravity of the higher potency ( 54). Consequently,
absolute identity as ground of its own being precedes itself insofar as it exists,
and we therefore also follow gravity through the whole series, as if it were the
maternal principle which, impregnated by absolute identity, brings forth itself;
it is evident from the whole [of nature] that the organism is just as primordial
as is matter, but also that it is just as impossible to empirically present the rst
burst of light within gravity as it is to present the rst breakthrough of the
ideal principle into what is simply real ( cit., Remark).
Def. 2. The formula A2 = (A = B), understood as relative totality, denotes
absolute identity not insofar as it exists, but insofar as it is ground or cause
of its existence by means of the organism, so too by means of the organism
itself [as product]. The formula A3 = [A2 = (A = B)]264 denotes absolute identity
existing under the form of A2 and A = B ([the substance] of the organism).
-This follows from the preceding [corollary].
F. W. J. Schelling 201
150. The organism articulates matter not only in its accidents but also in
its substance. This is so because it establishes the whole substance of matter267
[merely] as accident ( 137).
Cor. Otherwise stated (by 137), it forces matter to turn the inner (as
pole [of activity]) outward. Hence it enters most intimately into the existence
of matter.
151. Organization, in the individual as well as in the whole, must be
conceived as coming to be through metamorphosis. Evident from 140, comp.
[are] with 78.
Cor. Accordingly, organization can be viewed both in the whole and in
the individual entity as a magnet.
152. Lemma. With respect to the whole, the plant represents the carbon-
pole, the animal the nitrogen-pole.268 The animal is therefore southerly, the plant
northerly. With respect to the particular, the masculine sex is signied by the
latter [nitrogen-] pole, the feminine by the former [carbon-pole].
Cor. The masculine and feminine sexes are related in the particular as the
plant and the animal are in the universal.
153a. The organization of every heavenly body (e.g., the earth) is the
outward elaboration of the inner dimension269 of this heavenly body and it is
formed through internal transformation (e.g., of the earth). This follows from
150, Cor. a.[nd] 151.
Explanation. The diculties one has encountered up to now in conceiving a
rst origin of organization from the inside of every heavenly body primarily had
their ground in the situation that one neither had a cogent idea of metamorphosis
nor of the primordial but already dynamically organized state of every heavenly
body ( 148, Remark); hence even Kant regarded the idea that all organized
entities, e.g., the earth, were born from their own womb as quixotic or almost
frightful. This idea follows necessarily from our fundamental principles, and
in a natural way. We ask those [readers] who have not yet come to trust this
idea only this, to rst merely distance themselves from false opinions that most
people embrace, e.g., that the earth has brought forth animals and plants (and
that therefore there is a genuine causal relation between the two, whereas there
is instead a perfect relation of identity. Earth itself becomes animal and plant,270
and it is precisely the earth evolved into animal and plant that we now perceive
in organized entities). Then, further, [we ask that one put aside the false view
that], as we have [usually] imagined, that the organic entity as such arises from
the inorganic (since we absolutely do not concede this, or that perhaps the
organized entity has come to be, but rather conceive the organism as present
and existing from the beginning, at least potentia271). The seemingly inorganic
matter lying before us is surely not that matter from which animals and plants
have developed or which could be altered to the point where it could become
organic, hence the residue of organic metamorphosis; as Steens presents it, the
F. W. J. Schelling 203
externally twisted skeleton of the entire organic world. But in general keep in
mind that we have not at all conceded the usual and up to now predominant
notion of matter, while one can understand from the above that we maintain an
inner identity of all things and a potential presence of everything in everything,
and that we therefore consider so-called lifeless matter itself as a sleeping
animate- and plant-realm, which though animated by the being272 of absolute
identity, can fail to participate [in that life] for such a duration where it lacks
experience. For us, the earth is nothing other than the epitome or totality of
the animal and plant, and, if the former stands for the positive-pole, and the
latter the negative-, the earth itself is the bare indierence-point of the organic
magnet (hence itself organic).
153b. Organic nature is dierent from so-called inorganic nature merely
in this, that in the former, every level of development273 in characterized by an
indierence, while in the latter, by relative dierence (that of sex).
Cor. If so-called inorganic matter is externally dierent, but internally
indierent ( 125), organic matter is the reverse, internally dierent, externally
indierent. Hence there is no intrinsic opposition here, but merely an opposition
in orientation.274
154. Nitrogen is the real form of being of absolute identity. This is so
because it is the positive factor in cohesion ( 95, Cor. 4, Expl. 5).
Cor. 1. Hence the animal is preeminently animated ( 152).
Remark. This is also the ground of animal warmth.
2. Through all of nature, the male sex is the animating or procreative
[agent] ( cit.). The female is the producer275 of plants whose propagation is
mediated by a higher cohesion-process.
3. The plant is animated only by the species, for only through the species
does it attain to the presentation of the real form of being, and hence to life
( 147); the animal is alive independently of the species.
155. The species, which connects the plant to the sun, fastens the animal
to the earth. This is so because the plant, originally in concrescence with the
earth ( 95, Expl. 6), is from the earths perspective bound to absolute identity,
hence to the sun ( 149, Lemma 4) only through the species ( 154, Cor. 3).
In the case of the animal, on the contrary, which is linked to absolute identity,
hence to the sun, independently of the species, species instead become the means
of cohesion with the earth.
156. The potentiated positive pole of the earth is the animals brain, and
among these, the human brain. This is so because, since the law of metamorphosis
holds not only with respect to the entirety of organized entities, but also with
respect to the individual, and the animal is the positive pole (nitrogen) of
the universal transformation, so in the animal itself the highest product of
transformation will be the most perfect, i.e., most potentiated positive pole. But
the brain, as is known, is the highest product, etc. Therefore, etc.
204 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
f. We must break o our presentation at this point for now. Time and circumstances do not permit
a prompt continuation [of this project] in a subsequent Issue [of this journal]; nor does the [current]
state of aairs and the necessity to elaborate certain points more explicitly, as we wish to do, permit us
to oer them in a more concentrated form. While admittedly for one who wants to learn this system
and then form a judgment about it, there is the disadvantage that the whole document is not at once
available, yet for those who do not express the feeling that they have already grasped the sense of the
whole from this fragment (which is not impossible), this is but a cause for deciding not to overreach
in their judgment. But those who express this sentiment, and I believe this will be the case for the
majority of my readers, and who can anticipate my presentation in their own thoughts, would follow
it with greater aptitude if I could pursue it from the stage of organic nature to the other where the
most sublime expression of activity [is found], to the construction of absolute indierence or to that
point where absolute identity is established under perfectly equal potencies. If I could summon them
from this point to the construction of the ideal series and again go through the three potencies that
are positive with respect to ideal factors just as I now rehearse these three that are negative with respect
to them, I could arrive at the absolute center of gravity wherein truth and beauty coincide as the two
highest expressions of indierence.
206 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
II
Proof That There Is a Point Where Knowledge of the Absolute
and the Absolute Itself Are One.
The presence283 even in its bare idea of a philosophy in and for itself
shows the necessity of assuming that the knowledge one obtains through the
usual ways is not true knowledge, and since philosophy strives to discover the
grounds and conditions of the science to which evidence284 is ascribed in another
respect, [viz.,] mathematics, this shows that with the postulation of philosophy
[as absolute science] we also assume the merely conditioned truth of this other
body of knowledge.
What follows is the general groundwork for the discovery of philosophy.
Of whatever sort our native capacity of knowledge may be, this much
at least is clear, it is established in necessary connection to some merely nite
existence and is a knowledge reecting this nite [item]. But nally (this too
can be immediately appreciated) this nite existence again subsists only for us
[but] in connection to and in contrast with an innite factor. This innite factor,
which we can also call the ideal, is neither limited nor capable of limitation, while
the nite is forever, always, and unto innity only a determinate something.
Thereby is established in consciousness itself the universal opposition of
the ideal and the real, the innite and the nite; for it is necessary that concept
and object be opposed to one another in being connected to each other, since
more is always contained in the innite, whose immediate expression is the
concept, than in the nite, whose direct expression is the object.
Of every alleged philosophy that is not true philosophy, one can say in
advance that no matter what form under which it appears, it remains xed at
this antithesis.
Geometry, however, and mathematics as a whole are entirely beyond
this opposition. Here thought is always adequate to being, concept to object,
and vice versa, and never can the question of whether what is correct and
certain in thought is also real or in the object, or whether what is expressed in
being attains to conceptual necessity, even arise. In a word, there is no dierence
here between subjective and objective truth, subjectivity and objectivity are
absolutely one and there is in this science no construction in which they are
not one.
That mathematical evidence rests solely on this unity has already been
shown ( I.); indeed, this unity is pure evidence itself, though it appears
in geometry and in arithmetic in some determinate subordination, in the
rst subordinated to being, in the second to thought (this point will be
comprehensible only to those who have generally come to understand how
everything is contained in everything, and how what is expressed on the one
side in being, and on the other in thought, reects the entire organism of
reason): now to perceive this evidenceor the unity of thought and being,
not in this or that context but simply in and for itself, consequently, as the
evidence in all evidence, the truth in all truth, the purely known in everything
knownmeans to elevate oneself to the intuition of absolute unity and with
that to intellectual intuition as such.
208 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
One who is outside this unity of thought and being or of the subjective
and objective, is simply, entirely, and from the very start outside all objective
certainty;285 with this unity, the principle of identity used in demonstration
is abandoned all at once or remains at best a principle of the understanding;
proof is progression inside [mere] logical identity, inside the conceptual unity
of reection, without truth or purchase. Reason, even in its more imperfect
eorts, has always associated the highest and most immediate evidence with this
unity of thought and being. Even for the dogmatist, this opposition between
thought and being interwoven through all the concepts and forms of nite
knowledge was merely subjectively unsurpassable, and even he recognized as the
highest objectivity of knowledge a unity in which being immediately followed
from and was joined to concept, and reality to ideality. Connected with this
[recognition] was the so-called ontological proof of the existence of God, which
the systems of reection rightly regarded as the point of purest philosophical
evidence. It [i.e., dogmatism] did not lack the idea of the absolute, only its
mode of knowledge was topsy-turvy. Reection relies in its very nature on the
antithesis of thought and being. The unity of thought and being was for these
systems only just another case of being (something objective); only in this
[objective] unity were thought and being united, and God was absolute insofar
as the antithesis was unied in him, insofar as relative to God, being or actuality
followed directly from idea or possibility. But thought remained outside this
unity and in subjective opposition to it; the antithesis was abolished in God, but
not in the cognition of God. In this way, accordingly, the identity of thought
and being in the absolute itself was downgraded to a mere case of being, related
to the philosophers thinking as the real to the ideal, or as objective item to
subjective item; the being of God no longer followed from the idea in God
himself, but from the philosophers thinking [about God]; hence, the very idea
of the absolute, to be the identity of thought and being, was as good as lost.286
This fact, that the reality of the absolute in no way follows from the mere
thought of it (because the reality of a golden mountain does not follow from
my ability to imagine it, or, to put it in a quite Kantian way, ones cash balance
is not increased by imagining one hundred dollars), and because Criticism has
introduced a deep and profound uniformity of opinion on this matter, has
grown into a universal prohibition against all positive, categorical cognition of
the absolute, and has brought about a situation where, unless one decides to
entirely renounce thinking of the absolute, one is forced at very least to begin
philosophizing hypothetically, with pure thought or the understandings principle
of identity, and then see if one might come upon being in addition.
The basis for reections eort to take the absolute as absolute but
nonetheless x it as something objective lies in its ignorance of the absolute
mode of cognition, but this ignorance is not more, or more evidently, responsible
than is the mere apparently opposed tendency of Criticism, which can point out
what is contradictory in reections eort, but is unable on its own to point to
F. W. J. Schelling 209
anything that surpasses this sphere of contradiction, and which is thus shown
to be, compared to the true philosophy, merely an impoverished skepticism,
itself entirely deformed by reection, and which thinks it that at one blow it
has vanquished philosophy itself and negated it as speculation. True skepticism
is entirely directed against reections mode of cognition, but from the principle
of true speculation, except that it cannot express this position categorically, since
it would then cease to be skepticism; but one can be sure that skepticism will
never nd any weapons against speculation or absolute cognition except those
derived from common-sense or relative knowledge, whose reality it must itself
impugn since they are not only objects of its doubt but are unconditionally
rejected by it. Related in this way, skepticism and philosophy can never be
brought together, since the former stands to the latter as its absolute privation,
almost the way darkness stands to light, for which darkness simply does not
exist and is immediately287 abolished by it.
The absolute mode of cognition, like the truth that subsists within it, has
no true opposite outside itself, and if it cannot be demonstrated [to one who
lacks it] just as light cannot be demonstrated to those born blind, or space to
someone who lacked spatial intuition (were it possible that an intelligent being
lacked it), on the other hand, it cannot be contradicted by anything. It is the
dawning light that is itself the day and knows no darkness.
Whoever sets foot in the territory of philosophy is compelled by every
circumstance to incorporate the living sense of this absolute cognition, which of
course can neither be given him nor forced upon him; yet from acknowledging
this preliminary, merely formal kind of absolute cognition, it is but a small step
to the insight that this cognition is immediately a cognition of the absolute
itself, and is accompanied by the abolition of all dierences that contrast the
absolute as cognized to the subject who cognizes it.
With [just] a few strokes we complete the proof that for consciousness
there is a point where the absolute itself and knowledge of the absolute are
simply one.
That thought as such, since it has a necessary opposite in being, neither is
nor can become absolute cognition is a matter suciently clear, and one placed
totally beyond doubt by the preceding remarks. Thus on the whole an absolute
cognition can only be conceived as one in which thought and being are not
opposed, [a unity] in which they are completely equivalent forms, separated
only in reection or the understanding, but in themselves absolutely inseparable.
Furthermore, it is immediately clear to anyone who in some sense has
the idea of the absolute (quite apart from whether he ascribes reality to it or
not) that in this idea is conceived one identical absolute unity of ideality and
reality, of thought and being.
Here at the start, we do not want to presume anything about the absolutes
essence, about which we assert nothing here. We speak solely of the idea of the
absolute, and set down the following for the sake of explanation:
210 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
What is united in all being288 are the universal and the particular; the
former corresponds to thought, the latter to being. Now with respect to no
nite or individual thing does the particular follow from the universal. The fact
that some one individual human exists, or that right now, e.g., just so many
humans exist, not more and not less, cannot be understood from the concept
of a human being. Here being in no way follows from essence; no individual
thing is determined to existence through its concept, but through something
that is not its concept.
The essence of all things is one, and considered by itself there is in it no
ground of the particular: that whereby they are separated and distinguished is
form, which is the dierence of the universal and the particular and is expressed
in them through their existence.
In order not to repeat what is already familiar to everyone, that with
respect to the absolute being immediately follows from essence, we propose to
more closely dene this [relation of the universal and particular]. Universal and
particular are simply one in the case of what is absolute, its concept (to absolutely
be) is at the same time its particularity; it is, of course, absolute in both respects,
consequently, it is neither like any other thing (through some universal concept)
nor unlike it (through its particularity); it is absolutely and essentially one, and
simply self-identical. Now since it is form by which the particular entity is a
particular, [and] the nite item a nite, so too form is one with essence, each of
course absolute, since in the absolute the particular and the universal are absolutely
oneand here in this absolute unity or identical absoluteness of essence and form
lies the proof of our above-stated principle, the disclosure of how it is possible that
the absolute itself and knowledge of the absolute can be one, of the possibility,
therefore, of an immediate cognition of the absolute.
Since, according to our assumption that there is in intellectual consciousness
a formally absolute cognition, the absolute subsists in cognition in its formal
aspect, so, because the absolute indierence of essence and form belongs to its
idea, it also subsists in the essential aspect of cognition; the absolute unity of
thought and being, of the ideal and the real, not dierentiated from its essence,
is the absolutes eternal form, the absolute itself; for, since the dierence of the
ideal and the real also posits the dierence of essence and form, and since the
latter are one in the absolute, it follows that the unity of the ideal and the
real is necessarily the form of the absolute, and equally that in it, form is itself
absolute and identical to essence.
Now there is in absolute cognition just such an absolute unity of
thought and being (as was shown); the sole opposition that might remain is
that cognition, formally dened and as such, might be opposed to the absolute
itself, but form is the absolute itself, unity of essence and form pertains to its
idea: and, consequently, formally absolute cognition is necessarily a knowing of the
absolute itself. Therefore, there is an immediate cognition of the absolute (and
F. W. J. Schelling 211
only of the absolute, since only in its case is this condition of immediate evidence
possible: unity of essence and form) and this is the rst speculative cognition,
the principle and the ground of possibility of all philosophy.
We call this cognition intellectual intuition: Intuition; because all intuition
is an identication of thought and being and because only in intuition as such
is reality: In the case under consideration, the mere thought of the absolute,
granted that this is determined in its idea as that which is immediately through
its concept, is in no way yet a true cognition of the absolute. This is found
only in an intuition that absolutely identies thought and being, which because
it formally expresses the absolute also becomes the expression of its essence.
We call this intuition intellectual because it is reason-intuition, and because, as
cognition, it is absolutely one with the object of knowing.289
Philosophy rests [a] on this point of coincidence between formal absolute
cognition and the absolute itself, [b] on its cognizing the mode of this coincidence,
and [c] on insight into the uniqueness of the point where cognition can be
absolutely one with its object(this is of course conceivable only in with
respect to the absolute). All philosophical certainty290 follows from this point;
it is itself the ultimate evidence.
The requirement on which every science bases its reality is that what is
absolutely cognized by it: the idea, can also be the real itself; in geometrical
construction this coincidence of idea and reality shows up directly, since it is
granted to geometry to display the archetypes, as it were, in outer intuition;
in philosophical construction this point of coincidence is simple, absolute,
context-free intellectual intuition, in which absolute cognition along with the
kat xocn291 real, the absolute itself, are recognized as the uniquely true and
real things, and so too the modes of this cognition.
In this indierence of form and essence lies also the uniquely possible
and necessary point of union for idealism and realism.
Idealism entirely reduces philosophy to form, to knowledge, to cognition.
If this knowledge or cognition is itself absolute knowledge, absolute cognition,
then what is needed to correct the view that it is antithetical to realism is
merely reection on the proposition that absolute form (absolute knowledge)
is also absolute essence, being, substance. But cognition is not yet cognized as
absolute if one views it in antithesis to being and does not also recognize it
as absolute reality.
Realism alleges that it starts from an absolute being, but if this being is
really absolute, it directly follows that it is a being located in the ideas, and as
simply absolute, in the idea of all ideas, in absolute cognition.292 This relationship
is what we have called the relation of indierence (not some inane synthesis,
as many have represented it).
The absolute mode of cognition, since it is the principle of all rational
comprehension, is also the principle of its own comprehension. The living
212 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
principle of philosophy and of every faculty by which the nite and the innite
are identied is absolute cognition itself insofar as it is the idea and essence of
the soul; it is the eternal concept by which soul subsists in the absolute, neither
originated nor transitory, it is simply eternal, without temporal dimension; it
identies the nite and the innite inside cognition, and is at once absolute
cognition and the unique true being and substance.293
Moreover from this one can conclude that any intuition, in other respects
arbitrarily dened, in which the opposition of the nite and the innite is
not absolutely destroyed is not intellectual intuition. Therefore an intuition
can never be called intellectual intuition in which something of the empirical
subject, or of the I in some sense other than that in which it is universal form
(or pure subject-object) remains outside this form; the same goes for any sort
of intuition that in the act of intuiting itself reaches only to the identity of the
subjective subject-object (in this case intellectual intuition would be distinguished
from all sorts of empirical intuition only in this respect: in the latter something
dierent from the subject is intuited, while in the former what intuits and what
is intuited are identical).
_________
IV.294
On Philosophical Construction or the Way to Exhibit
All Things in the Absolute
Since we now proceed to the other part of our inquiry that considers science and
the way it is generated from the unity of rst cognition [or intellectual intuition],
we do not doubt that there are some who will think its realization intrinsically
impossible, while others will at the very least not clearly recognize its possibility.295
Since we have left behind everything on which nite understanding
is accustomed to insist and have even cut o all return to the realm of the
conditioned by our declaration that philosophy subsists entirely and completely
in the absolute, it is hardly our intention to allow anything to remain behind
which we might use to return to the conditioned, [we now face a double
diculty] : most people will comprehend neither, in general, how we can
see so clearly into the absolute that we can ground a science in it (although
its possibility surely resides in what we have proved before), nor, specically,
how we intend to draw material for a science from the simply identical and
thoroughly simple essence of the absolute. For it will be argued that no science
is possible of something that is simply one and ever the same, that something
else is required which is not identical, but multiple and dierentiated; and that
even if what is demonstrated is forever and necessarily one and the same, by
F. W. J. Schelling 213
contrast, that in which unity is demonstrated is necessarily not one, but many,
as happens in geometry, where the identical form and absolute unity of space
is expressed in the dierent units of triangles, squares, circles, etc.
Clearly with this [diculty] we nd ourselves situated again inside the rst
opposition of unity and multiplicity, and the pictorial image296 of a production
of the latter from the former, and though we might imagine these thoughts
canceled once and for all in the cognition of such a unity in whose scope
the contrast of unity and multiplicity had utterly no meaning, where instead
multiplicity subsisted within unity, without prejudice to the higher unity that
includes them both, we must expect to see them forever recur, since the idea
of an absolute unitya unity that directly, without going through multiplicity,
is also totalitycan be assumed to be the possession only of those who have
really mastered the supreme point of philosophy.
So to put this idea in the brightest possible light and still stay with this
contrast between what is proved and that in which it is proved (the former of
which is supposed to be ever and always one, the latter not-one and multiple),
I say this: what is proved, which we assume is ever the same, is the absolute
unity of the nite and the innite; for the present purpose I call it the universal.
That in which it is proved is a determinate unity, and is accordingly called the
particular. Now demonstration is absolute identication of the universal and the
particular, that [universal] which is proved and that [particular] in which it is
so. These are necessarily and simply one in every construction, and only where
this is the case can a construction of philosophy be deemed absolute. Now since
the former, the universal, is by supposition absolutely and eternally one, but
both members are equal in the construction, it follows that the particular is
also absolutely one in every construction, so that neither of the two is one or
many in contrast to the other, but each is for itself one and many in absolute
unity, both therefore the identical unity of the nite and the innite, and the
unity between them a real and essential one.297
With this it is clear how in every construction, if it is true and genuine,
the particular is abolished as particular in its antithesis to the universal. The
particular is itself exhibited within the absolute only insofar as it contains the
entire absolute exhibited within itself and is only ideally dierent from the absolute
as universal, viz., as a copy is dierent from an original, while intrinsically or
really it is entirely identical to it. But to that extent, the particular itself is also
nothing that could ever be multiple or be counted, for it includes all aspects
of number, both what enumerates (the unit-concept) and what is enumerated
(the particular).
In this identity298 or equal absoluteness of the unities that we distinguish as
particular and universal resides and is found the innermost mystery of creation,
the divine identication299 (imaging) of original and copy that is the true root
214 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
of every being. For neither the particular nor the universal would have a reality
for itself if the two were not formed into one300 within the absolute, i.e., unless
both were absolute.
With this is also illustrated the mode or possibility of exhibiting all unities
within the absolute; for the dierent unities have no substance301 in themselves
as dierent, but are merely ideal forms and gures under which the whole is
minted, and because the whole subsists in them, they are the whole world
itself and have nothing outside themselves to which they could be compared
or contrasted. The entire universe subsists in the absolute as plant, as animal,
as human being, but since the whole is in every part, it subsists therein not
as plant, not as animal, not as human being or as the particular unity, but as
absolute unity; it is rst within appearance, where it ceases to be the whole,
where the form pretends to be something for itself and steps out of indierence
with essence, that each becomes the particular and the determinate unity.
With the particular entity, then, not even considered in its species or
natural kind,302 there is nothing in the absolute. There is no plant in itself or
animal in itself; what we call plant is (not essence, substance, but) mere concept,
mere ideal determination, and all forms obtain reality only because they receive
the divine image of unity; but, due to that, they themselves become universes
and are designated ideas and each one ceases to be a particular entity in that
it enjoys the double unity in which absoluteness consists.
Even the philosopher, therefore, knows not a distinct essence, but only one
essence in all the original schematisms of world-intuition; he does not construct
the plant or animal, but (the absolute form, i.e.,) the universe in the gure of
a plant, the universe in the shape of an animal; these schematisms are possible
only in virtue of their ability to take into themselves the undivided fullness of
unity, so that they are negated as particular. For as particular, they would limit
absolute essence, in that they exclude other forms from themselves. But insofar
as every one of them grasps the absolute, and in each all recur and all in each,
they show themselves to be the forms of divine in-forming [or imagination],
and are truly or uniquely real since they are possible in the context of the
absolute, because in it there is no dierence between possibility and actuality.
Since in this way absolute cognition comprehends all forms within itself,
every one of them in perfect absoluteness, so that within its scope (each is
absolute for itself ) everything is contained within each (since it is absolute),
and for just this reason nothing [particular] is included in any one of them, it
is clear to what extent that it can be said that it contains everything precisely
because it contains nothing, and further, how in a manner similar to the absolute
itself, every idea is also both identity and totality, not each separately, but each
in the same way, in the same undivided essence.
It is also evident, on the other hand, how every particular as such is
immediately and necessarily also an individual. For by its essence each thing
F. W. J. Schelling 215
is like every other and in this capacity expresses the whole; so when its form
becomes particular form, it becomes inadequate to essence and is in contradiction
with it, and the contradiction of form and essence makes the thing be individual
and nite ( II.).
Consequently, all the things of appearances are copies of the (original)
whole, even if highly imperfect, and strive in particular form, as particular to
express in themselves the universe. Their being303 as particular things resides
in the particular schematism, which is nothing in itself, and even if each thing
accepts as much universality as possible into its particularity and as nite
endeavors to be innite, still due to its imperfection in reaching this goal,
it is partially subjected to [external] law as its universal, and does not attain
the full perfection which only the ideas truly can enjoy and, to a greater or
lesser degree, those creatures most like the ideas, in that they include a wider
range of other beings within themselves, namely, the perfection of being law
themselves and of comprehending the universal in their particularity and the
particular in their universality. Everything lives and moves because of this
twofold striving, and this striving springs from the rst forming-into-one304
[identication] or from the fact that the undivided essence of the absolute is
stamped identically upon the real and the ideal, and that substance subsists
only in this way.
The preceding remarks clearly illuminate this feature of cognition, that
philosophy subsists in the absolute and that its entire business and enterprise
rests in this; from this we can see the error of those pictures of philosophy that
locate its task a) in a derivation, whether from the absolute or from another
principle in its place, or b) in some deduction of the actual,305 appearing world,
as such, or of the possibility of experience.
For, in the rst place, how could philosophy know something derived
or that could be derived, since only the absolute is [without qualication] and
everything that we can cognize is a fragment of the absolute essence of the
eternal principle, only cast in the form of appearance, while philosophy considers
only what everything is in itself, i.e., in the eternal?
But [secondly,] how could it be a derivation of the real world as such,
since in this world there are no ideas, not, e.g., the idea of triangle or the idea
of human being, but always individual triangles, individual humans? Though
if one wished to say that philosophy still has to exhibit the real world in its
immediate possibility, viz., in the necessary and universal laws that determine
appearances like the law of cause and eect, I answer, rst, that all these laws,
far from expressing some true possibility of the things of appearances, are
instead truly expressions of their absolute nothingness and insubstantiality, e.g.,
the law that substance endures while accidents change expresses [the notion]
that in things there is no unity of form and essence, therefore no true being,
no self-derived being, which is further expressed in the law that each thing is
216 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
and the whole of geometry? Doesnt every truth stand out as a particular
world, or can you draw a line from one to the other and display continuity
mechanically? Choose from the universe whatever fragment you will and
realize that it is innitely fruitful and is impregnated with the possibilities of all
things! Can you place [all] the forms of nature on a [single] line, or doesnt
every one of them remind your reective and conditioned understanding309 of
their absoluteness? Can you command a metal to appear at the point where
it lies in the taxonomy your understanding produces, or the plant to bloom
where you rank it in a classication, or any being at all to distinguish itself
the way you mentally separate it, or doesnt everything instead lie before you
in divine confusion and complexity? Doesnt everything that in your attitude of
separation ies light-years apart press toward unity and live peacefully together,
everything joyful in its own way? This unity causes each of them to form an
image of the totality and with this to mirror the other within itself. Thus it
happens in the same way and for the same reason that everything is one and
yet each item is separated.
Yet on this topic I believe that, just as universally every noble element is
enhanced by its form, so in this particular case a cognition so sublime cannot
be left to chance insight, but since at all time it arises in some exceptional
individuals in more or less universal form, we need to think of putting it riches
in their absolute form and make a transition from the patchwork of particular
knowledge to the totality of cognition.310 I declare that this is the nal goal and
purpose of all my scientic eorts, which, had not most people followed with
closed minds, would have been easy to see in all my writings, and I believed
nothing was too dear for attaining this end which necessitated this concern
with [philosophys] form, not even lingering at stages that did not correspond
to the degree of my own cognition. For, I wanted to know the truth in all
its particular directions in order to freely and without distortion plumb the
depths of the absolute. This cannot be a matter of a facile and hurried harvest
of thoughts which lie before us in a plentiful mass, but of fashioning a worthy
and enduring conguration which brings all the particular tones and colors of
truth into concordance and harmony, and which expresses the archetype that
each sees in part. You will readily discover the most excellent of all pieces of
knowledge311 in the fragments of the most ancient wisdom; you will nd the
doctrine of ideas already in Pythagoras and even more so as a tradition in Plato.
Even Heraclitus was not the rst to recognize unity in opposition (identity in
duplicity) as the universal form of the universe. You will readily perceive the
doubled unity of all things, how each is primordially absolute in its particularity
and in its absoluteness particular, in Leibnizs doctrine of monads, whose origin
you can again follow into indeterminable distances, and nally you will certainly
encounter the teaching that comprehends all this, going back to Spinoza and
Parmenides, as far as the history of philosophy and human knowledge reaches,
F. W. J. Schelling 219
of the unity that is indivisibility present in each thing and the substance of them
all. These wellsprings ow for everyone, but still have grown into knowledge
in [only] a few, since the latter is born only from an inner living form and
from the impulse of ones own skill. In general, the greater the knowledge you
achieve, the more you will perceive how all the dierent teachings that have
been formally elaborated312 are nothing other than images displaced in dierent
directions of the sole true system, which, like eternal nature, is neither young
nor old and is rst according to nature, not in time. So too the eort that is
seriously focused on the sole true object can be none other than to extricate the
entirety of cognition that courses through all human thought and [is deployed]
in all directions in more or less visible veins, put this into a visible shape which
displays its primordial beauty and bring this to eternal recognition.
What can most eectively strengthen everyone in this endeavor is to
consider how it was possible that a cognition of the purest evidence, which
indeed is evidence itself, and from which all fundamentally powerful thoughts
ow and to which they return, has to date not yet achieved enduring form.
There is no other cause of this situation than the fact that in philosophy, where
a foundation for cognition has been established, but before science has broken
through to universality, a rebuttal exists [which asserts] that only the last totality
comprehends and carries everything and resolves all contradictions, and that
only in it can everything nd its enduring place.
In this situation what is at rst and preeminently operative is the ambiguity
of all determinations and concepts of reection, which show themselves to be
empty understanding in just their separation, [the fact] that for instance one
item can appear as real or nite on one side, but can be shown to be ideal or
innite on another, and vice versa, just as every point of the magnetic line is
positive, negative, or indierent depending on how it is considered, [and] then,
in this uctuating, living totality one factor plays with the other, like color
in color, time in nature, space in history, and everything that understanding
[usually] xes is without stability and nothing is clearly cognized in its conjoint
particularity and universality, until, thanks to a construction carried to the point
of totality which actually comprehends everything in everything, this almost
divine chaos is exhibited in its simultaneous unity and disorder.
In addition, whatever limits that might be placed on human [cognitive]
capacities and whatever limits might reside in the nature of its object, which,
as I am well aware, make it impossible to draw up a crystal clear report on
the universe,313 I retain this certainty at least, that once this system is presented
and recognized in its entirety, the absolute harmony of the universe and the
divinity of all being will be eternally established within human thought, and
furthermore that no doctrine can arise from a universal uncertainty which
rebuts or misapprehends [this system], so that henceforth no limitations can be
supplied or lent currency which poverty of spirit and utmost God-forsakenness
220 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
the geometer constructs is certainly not an actual, i.e., individual triangle, but it
is the absolute, simply real one, in contrast to the actual or appearing triangle
to whose share falls no substantiality.
By this is seen the profound absurdity and deep-rooted unreason of
those people who require that there be something particular outside the idea
of absolute unity in order to arrive at actuality, who want to x individuality,
which as such is the absolute negation of universality or complete suspension
of idea, in a universal that they designate stu or matter. For matter, insofar
as it is absolute, i.e., real, and is essence, subsists within absolute form itself
and is identical to it, for this latter requires for reality nothing outside itself.
Moreover, since absolute form is absolute essence too, and therefore there
is nothing outside it, if anything is posited as real under the form of nonidentity
that contradicts it, it is immediately abolished in thought, just as, on the other
hand, if this form is posited as absolute, everything resistant to and incompatible
with it is directly established as insubstantial.
But by this relation of absolute form to essence, it is easy to comprehend
what procedure can be the sole true method of philosophy, i.e., the one under
which everything is absolute and no one thing is the absolute.
For if you want to understand the particular through philosophy, i.e., to
comprehend it in the absolute as its principle, you no doubt wish you could
understand in the same act of comprehension two distinct things, how everything
is one in principle and how within this unity every form is absolutely distinct
from the others; you cannot attain either of these goals without including the
other with it, since you cannot absolutely isolate one form from the others
without making it into absolute unity or into the universe in and for itself, for
only the universe is truly and absolutely denite, since there is nothing outside
it that it could be like or unlike; conversely, you cannot grasp the particular
form as a universe for itself or conceive it absolutely without in the very process
submerging it as particular in the absolute.
From this, one can immediately perceive that the true method of philosophy
can only be the demonstrative one, but since it is unusual to encounter even
a general idea of demonstrative method, I shall explain this more particularly.
Demonstration321 does not precede construction, but the two are one and
inseparable. In construction the particular (the determined unity) is exhibited as
absolute, namely, as absolute unity of the ideal and the real for itself. For, since
as unity it is the unity that cannot be canceled in anything or in any manner,
so there can be no construction in which in general any particular, hence a
purely nite or innite entity, could be expressed as such without the identical
unity and undivided perfection of the absolute being expressed, and it is only
because this is the case that philosophy does not step outside the absolute. For
since in form the nite stands related to the innite as the real to the ideal, but
form as such is always and necessarily their unity, therefore each of them, the
F. W. J. Schelling 223
nite and the innite, insofar as it is really, i.e., absolutely posited, is the entire
unity of the nite and the innite, neither of them nite nor innite viewed
apart from its ideal determination, but each absolute and eternal. From this,
it is self-evident that this unity of the nite and the innite, which is in the
absolute and is the essence of the absolute, is a real unity and also an identity
of identity, as we have previously shown (Zeitschr.[ift fr spekulative Physik], vol.
2, issue 2).322 For both the nite considered in itself and the innite contain,
each of them, the same (formal) identity of the nite and the innite. Therefore
we had to understand the former, real unity before we understood the latter,
formal one (III., 5).
If all this is granted, construction is, rst and in general, exhibition of the
particular inside absolute form, and philosophical construction in particular, the
exhibition of the particular within form considered without qualicationnot
as itself ideal or real, as in the two branches of mathematicsbut form as
intuited in itself or intellectually. To understand on this basis how absolute form
is not abolished in any constructionthe particular, by the way, is either nite
or innite (for ideal determination)we must especially consider that because
of the complete relativity of this contrast, since neither a nite entity nor an
innite one subsists in itself, but only in relation, every particular being insofar
as it accepts the entire absolute into itself is negated as a particular (nite or
innite) entity and merely reunites the nite and the innite in itself.
The other [thing that needs explanation] is demonstration itself, which
is the identication of form and essence within a structure such that, from
what is constructed in absolute form (or whose absolute ideality is certain323)
its absolute reality is also immediately proved.
For since absolute form immediately includes absolute substantiality, its
indierence as form (or cognition) with essence (or object) follows with respect
to every construction, i.e., absolute evidence.
This will suce to recognize the nature of demonstration, which is entirely
grounded in the fact that every particular subsists in the absolute precisely because
it is absolute, and vice versa; we cannot conceive the former without the latter
nor the latter without the former. Accordingly, all science depends on cognizing
and identifying a twofold unity, one by means of which a being subsists in itself,
and another by means of which it subsists in the absolute. Construction is thus,
from start to nish, an absolute kind of cognition and (for exactly this reason)
it has nothing to do with the actual world as such but is in its very nature
idealism (if idealism means the doctrine of the ideas).324 For it is precisely this
world that is commonly called actual that is abolished by construction. You call
the appearing world actual325 only because for you form has become something
for-itself. You call the particular form, e.g., the plant or animal, etc., actual.
But precisely this is abolished within construction, for (according to what was
proved earlier) the construction contains no more than the possibility of, e.g.,
224 J. G. Fichte/F. W. J. Schelling
the plant, as form of the universe. This is precisely what the actual plant is not,
and, were it this and did it not separate itself from its essence, it would not
be actual (as a plant), and hence the converse too, none of the things called
actual can be in the absolute,326 for in the absolute, no form is divorced from
its essence, everything is internally related as one being, one stu, and from
this single root all ideas are produced as divine shoots, since each is fashioned
from the entire essence of the absolute. For that reason, the essence (the in-itself)
of a thing cannot be this thing itself; so if you seek the actuality of a being of
appearance in the absolute world, you will not nd it there, and what there
stands in absolute reality, you will not nd here. The actuality of the appearing
world as such cannot be acknowledged, therefore, not even insofar as its essence
subsists in the absolute, but only its absolute unreality.
Our assertion, however, that philosophys every construction and cognition
is equally absolute might seem to contradict [our previous claim] that under the
form of demonstrative method one cognition serves as a means to another, and
each demonstration in the complex of the whole is possible only through others.
We resolve this seeming contradiction the same way we solved the earlier
one.
That which makes every construction absolute is identical or one and
the same with what serves as the principle of connection for philosophical
demonstration.
This is so because the identical absoluteness of all constructions in
philosophy rests on the fact that the features of nitude or innitude are nothing,
while their unity is everything and the same in everything, but just this same
pervasive real unity is the reason that what is in-itself or absolute according to
form can be nite or innite inside the relative opposition and have, as nite
or innite, its ideal opposite in the other, while at the same time, since the
identical is expressed according to essence in both opposites, the two combine
into a real unity, so that everything returns to and takes root again in the same
absolute identity and the identical abyss of divine unity.
Therefore within every construction only the ideal element provides
opposition and with it connection to the other, but this purely ideal determinacy
is in turn negated in the construction, since in every one of them the same
absolute unity is exhibited in and for itself.
Since this ideal dependence of one cognition upon another along with
the identical absoluteness of each for itself belongs to the form of philosophy
as science, it is clearly important that each person make sure, all in the same
way, that no necessary intermediate member is skipped over. My System of
[Transcendental] Idealism was especially precise in this regard, though its purpose
was to present but one side of philosophy, namely the subjective and ideal, in
it was sketched out the general framework of construction whose schematism
must also be the foundation of the completed system.327 For since the I in the
F. W. J. Schelling 225
Notes to Introduction
1. Tr. H. S. Harris & Walter Cerf (Albany: State University of New York Press,
1977) p. 82.
2. Tr. Paul Guyer & Allen Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1998), pp. 70001.
3. See Critique of Pure Reason, Preface, Bxvixvii.
4. Ibid., 13: Principles of a Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts
of the Understanding, A86/B116 f.
5. Ibid., Phenomena and Noumena, A235/B294-A240/B299.
6. Ibid., The Architectonic of Pure Reason, A841/B869 f.
7. See Kants famous three questions, The Critique of Pure Reason, On the Ideal
of the Highest Good, A804/B832 .
8. A few competing accounts of the history of nineteenth-century German
philosophy should be mentioned. Schelling and Hegel both lectured on the history of
contemporary philosophy and attempted to outank each other. Within fteen years of
Hegels death, Johann Eduard Erdmann produced three volumes on the development
of German speculation after Kant; see Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen Darstellung der
Geschichte der neuern Philosophie (18341853), vols. 57 (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt:
Frommann-Holzboog, 1977). Richard Kroners Von Kant bis Hegel, 2nd ed. (Tbingen:
J. C. Mohr, 1961) set the standard for erudite, although argumentative historiography.
Walter Schulz reversed the all roads lead to Hegel narrative with Die Vollendung des
deutschen Idealismus in der Sptphilosophie Schellings (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1955). H.
S. Harris and George di Giovanni enlarged the eld of discussion to hitherto neglected
gures such as Friedrich Jacobi, G. E. Schulze, and K. L. Reinhold in Between Kant
and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 2000). Three recent works have enlarged the discussion
to include the early German Romantics, intimates of both Fichte and Schelling in their
Jena years: Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe & Jean-Luc Nancy, The Literary Absolute: the Theory
of Literature in German Romanticism, tr. Philip Barnard & Cheryl Lester (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1988), Manfred Frank, The Philosophical Foundations of
Early German Romanticism, tr. by Elizabeth Milln-Zaibert (Albany: State University of
227
228 Notes to Introduction
New York Press, 2004), and Frederick C. Beiser, German Idealism: The Struggle against
Subjectivism (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002).
9. Quoted in Daniel Breazeales introduction to Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings
(Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press, 1988) p. 14.
10. Heideggers attempt to retrieve Schellings philosophy in his 1936 lectures
on Of Human Freedom bravely lays bare the impossibility of genuinely rejoining the
German idealists in their quest for system. Whatever the t or jointure of being and
human being may be, it is not within the grasp of one person or of organized learning
in general, whether segregated in academic institutions or globally oating on a virtual
cloud supported by machines nicely called servers. See Schellings Treatise on the Essence
of Human Freedom, tr. Joan Stambaugh (Athens, OH & London, Ohio University Press,
1985) pp. 2268. Hereafter cited as Schellings Treatise.
11. Athenaeum-Fragmente, #82, cited in Schellings Treatise, p. 82.
12. Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg), Fichte Studies, ed. Jane Kneller (Cambridge
and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003) #566.
13. See Grard Valles introduction to The Spinoza Conversations Between Lessing
and Jacobi: Text with Excerpts from the Ensuing Controversy, tr. G. Valle, J. B. Lawson,
and C. G. Chapelle (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1988) pp. 336.
14. See Kants Opus Postumum, Erste Hlfte, ed. Artur Buchenau (Berlin & Leipzig:
de Gruyter, 1936) 12.59 and 1.87, respectively.
15. See Fichtes Second Introduction [to the Wissenschaftslehre], GA I, 4: 19495.
16. See Letter 20 (Schelling in Jena to Fichte in Berlin, October 3, 1801) translated
in this volume. Schelling apparently did not adequately understand, even in 1801, how
the practical philosophy of that work grounded the theoretical, not the reverse.
17. Maimonides argues that human wrongdoing will not cease until the following
condition is met: every individual among the people not being permitted to act according
to his will and up to the limit of his power, but being forced to do that which is useful
to the whole. Guide of the Perplexed, Vol. II, tr. Schlomo Pines (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1963), p. 510.
18. J. G. Fichte, Grundlage des Naturrechts, GA I, 3, 358; Foundations of Natural
Right, ed. F. Neuhouser, tr. Michael Baur (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2000) p. 49.
19. Novalis, op. cit., #648.
20. Ibid., #556.
21. See Paola Mayer, Jena Romanticism and Its Appropriation of Jakob Bhme
(Montreal & London: McGill-Queens University Press, 1999) pp. 6367, on Schellings
initially anti-religious reaction to Bhme and the transformation of his identity-philosophy
18011802 by his use of Platonic and Neoplatonic sources, see pp. 18292.
22. Athenaeum-Fragmente #206.
23. See Daniel Breazeale, Men at Work: Philosophical Construction in Fichte
and Schelling, forthcoming.
24. Allen Speight, Friedrich Schlegel (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/schlegel/),
2007.
25. See Frederick Beiser, Friedrich Schlegels Absolute Idealism, in German
Idealism, pp. 43561.
Notes to Introduction 229
48. See Letter 14. Schelling in Jena to Fichte in Berlin, November 19, 1800.
49. See Letter 15a, translated in this volume.
50. This draft was rst published by F. Medicus, Fichtes Leben und literarische
Briefwechsel (1922), and included in Fichte-Schelling Briefwechsel, ed. Walter Schulz
(Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1968) p. 114. Hereafter cited as Schulz.
51. See Letter 15, Fichte to Schelling in Jena, December 27, 1800.
52. See Letter 15a (cf. Schulz, p. 115).
53. See 1800 New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre, translated in this volume.
54. See Letter 14, Schelling in Jena to Fichte in Berlin, November 19, 1800.
55. See Presentation of My System, translated in this volume.
56. Fichte, GA II/6: 220f. (cf. SW II: 82).
57. Ibid., pp. 30506 (cf. SW II: 14344).
58. Ibid., pp. 29091 (cf. SW II: 13031).
59. See Fichtes Announcement, translated in this volume.
60. J. G. Fichte, An Attempt at a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre
(1797/1798), in Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre, op. cit., p. 118. GA I, 3, 280.
61. See Schellings essay on intellectual intuition in Further Presentations from the
System of Philosophy, translated in this volume.
62. See Fichte, On the Presentation of Schellings System of Identity, translated
in this volume.
63. See Fichte, Preparatory Work Contra Schelling, translated in this volume.
64. See Second Introduction, 3 & 5, and Chapter One, II of Attempt at a
New Presentation, in Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre, as cited, pp. 4041 4649,
& 11015; GA I, 3: 21213, 21619, 27478.
65. See Letter 23, Fichte to Schelling, January 15, 1802. Compare the equally
dicult Letter 19, Fichte in Berlin to Schelling in Jena, May 31 to August 7, 1801,
where intellectual intuition is said to access not just the transcendental ground of the
nite I but the divine self-consciousness that is both the ground of the separation of
nite Is and their essential unity.
66. Schellings Werke, IV: 39192n.
67. See Schellings two essays on methodology, the rst on intellectual intuition,
the second on philosophical construction, translated in this volume.
Notes to FichteSchelling
Correspondence
1. Schelling went to Bamberg at the beginning of May 1800 partly due to his
medical interests and partly to accompany Caroline Schlegel (cf. GA III/4: 242).
2. Ueber die Jenaische Allgemeine Literaturzeitung. Erluterungen (On the
Jena Allgemeine Literaturzeitung. Commentaries), originally published in Jena and Leipzig
in 1800 (reprinted in Schelling, SW I/3: 63565).
3. Karl Leonhard Reinhold (17571823) was Fichtes predecessor at the
University of Jena where he rst expounded Kantian philosophy on a systematic, in
fact, foundationalist basis. He briey became an exponent of Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre,
Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence 231
but around the turn of the century joined forces with C. G. Bardili to propound a
logical realism.
4. Christoph Gottfried Bardili (17611808) was a cousin of Schelling and
taught Kantian philosophy at the Stuttgart Gymnasium. His Grundriss der ersten Logik
(Outlines of First Logic) was published in Stuttgart in 1800. Reinholds review of
Bardilis Logik appeared in nos. 127 to 129 of the Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung on May
57, 1800.
5. Schelling is referring to the following works: System des transzendentalen
Idealismus (Tbingen, 1800); English translation: System of Transcendental Idealism
trans. Peter Heath, introduction by Michael Vater (Charlottesville: University Press of
Virginia, 1993); Einleitung zu der Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie (Jena, 1799;
Introduction to the Outline of a System of the Philosophy of Nature); Zeitschrift fr
spekulative Physik, vol. 1, issue 2, 1800.
6. Fichte nally wrote some detailed comments on these works of Schelling,
but they were never published during his lifetime. See Fichtes texts Commentaries on
Schellings Transcendental Idealism and Presentation of My System of Philosophy (18001801),
translated in this volume.
7. Cf. Schellings letter of May 14, 1800 (Letter 1), which Schelling had sent
accompanied by a number of books.
8. Ueber die Jenaische Allgemeine Literaturzeitung. Erluterungen (SW I/3:
63565).
9. In his dispute with C. G. Schtz, the editor of the A.L.Z., in the end both
parties had to pay damages: Schelling 10 thalers and Schtz 5 thalers (cf. GA III/4: 260).
10. Fichtes review eventually appeared in nos. 214, 215 of the Allgemeine Literatur
Zeitung on October 3031, 1800: Recension von Bardilis Grundriss der ersten Logik
(GA 1/6: 43350).
11. See Reinholds letter to Fichte dated March 1, 1800 where he encourages
Fichte to read Bardilis Logik (GA III/4: 23538).
12. Most likely a reference to the Berlin banker, Salomon Moses Levi (cf. GA
III/4: 260).
13. See the plan for a journal entitled: Jahrbcher der Kunst und Wissenschaft
(Yearbooks of Art and Science), written by Fichte and Karl Ludwig Woltmann (1770
1817), and a Critical Institute (reprinted in GA I/6: 42526). For a detailed account of
Fichtes plan and the idea for an institute, see SchellingFichte Briefwechsel, ed. Hartmut
Traub (Neuried: ars una, 2001) pp. 24368.
14. The journal was to be issued by the publisher Johann Friedrich Gottlieb
Unger (17531804).
15. M. G. Hermann (born 1754), was editor of the Neue allgemeine deutsche
Bibliothek from 1794 to 1799.
16. Fichtes letter of August 2, 1800 (Letter 3).
17. Letter of July 30, 1800. Concerning Schellings reception of Fichtes invitation,
see A. W. Schlegels words to Schleiermacher on August 20, 1800: Schelling received
a few days ago, and I myself yesterday, an invitation from Fichte accompanied by the
printed announcement of a Jahrbcher der Kunst und der Wissenschaft to be published
by Unger. He immediately agreed that our current plans with Cotta as the publisher
were right for him. Partly by all manner of contingencies, he has managed to delay his
232 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
answer, which is extremely good. Quoted in: Aus Schleiermachers Leben. In Briefen, ed.
Wilhelm Dilthey, vol. 3 (Berlin: Reimer, 1861), p. 218.
18. Review of the Latest Developments in Philosophy and those Sciences
dependent on it.
19. Schelling was asked by A. W. Schlegel in July to participate in his planned
journal Kritischen Jahrbchern der deutschen Literatur (Critical Yearbooks of German
Literature), also called: Jahrbchern der Wissenschaft und Kunst (Yearbooks of Science
and Art). (See GA III/4: 40914; also reprinted in: SchellingFichte Briefwechsel, ed.
Hartmut Traub, pp. 25965).
20. Overview of the Entire Present State of Philosophy.
21. Reinholds review of Schellings System of Transcendental Idealism appeared in
numbers 231 and 232 of the Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung on August 13, 1800.
22. Schellings letter of August 18, 1800 (Letter 4).
23. The plan cited in note 19 above.
24. Fichtes letter of August 2, 1800 (Letter 3).
25. The so-called Entwurf zu einem Plane ber ein zu errichtendes kritisches
Institut (Outline of a Plan concerning the Establishment of a Critical Institute) that
accompanied Fichtes letter of December 23, 1799 to August Wilhelm Schlegel and
Friedrich Schlegel (in: GA III/4: 16874).
26. Schelling himself published a number of these separate notices in his journal
Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik.
27. Concerning the Woltmann plan, see note 13 above.
28. Fichte wrote to A. W. Schlegel on September 6, 1800 (cf. GA III/4: 301303).
See note 17 above concerning A. W. Schlegels similar plan.
29. F. G. Klopstock (17241803), German playwright. The quote is from his
Die deutsche Gelehrtenrepublik (Hamburg, 1774).
30. Fichte, System der Sittenlehre (1798); see English translation: System of Ethics,
eds. D. Breazeale and G. Zller (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
31. Reviewed by K. L. Reinhold in the August 1800 issue of the Allgemeine
Literaturzeitung.
32. Schellings letter is actually dated September, 5 1800 (see Letter 5).
33. The letter of September 612, 1800 (Letter 6).
34. Letter to A.W. Schlegel dated September 6, 1800 (see GA III/4: 30103).
35. Fichte is referring to a conversation from August 27, 1800 (cf. note in GA
III/4: 28789).
36. See Schellings letter dated August 18, 1800 (Letter 4).
37. See note 17 above.
38. The Brothers Veit were Berlin bankers.
39. See A. W. Schlegels letter of June 9, 1800 to Schleiermacher: I therefore
think: Kritische Jahrbcher der deutschen Literatur (Critical Yearbooks of German
Literature). . . . Fichte will have to be informed about the real state of aairs, but I
think this should only be done after we have secured a publisher. . . . Fichte can still
carry out his plan, but we have made it clear enough to him that he will have to nd
other collaborators and not us. In: Aus Schleiermachers Leben, ed. W. Dilthey, vol. 3,
pp. 183f (cf. GA III/4: 308).
Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence 233
40. Cf. Fichtes letter of August 2, 1800 to Schelling (Letter 3) where Fichte
mentions his plan, as well as the letter of September 6, 1800 to H. E. G. Paulus (GA
III/4: 30304), and the letter of September 6, 1800 (sent September 12) to A. W.
Schlegel: I nd your plan that Schleiermacher passed on to me to be far similar to the
one that I drew up in Jena than you are willing to admit, my dear friend, and a great
deal more similar to my new plan (GA III/4: 301).
41. I.e., Schellings plan with the publisher Cotta for a: Review of the Latest
Developments in Philosophy and those Sciences dependent on it.
42. Dated August 18, 1800 (Letter 4).
43. A. W. Schlegel to J. G. Fichte, August 1820, 1800 (cf. GA III/4: 28788).
Schlegels Entwurf zu einem kritischen Institute (Outline for a Critical Institute) and
journal proposal are reproduced in GA III/4: 40914.
44. Schellings letter of September 5, 1800 (Letter 5).
45. Schellings letter is not extant. Nevertheless, Fichtes next letter dated October
3, 1800, refers to a series of questions that appear to have been posed by Schelling in
this missing letter from the end of September 1800.
46. The sheet of paper is no longer extant.
47. Fichte is referring to a question in Schellings previous (missing) letter. See
endnote 45 above.
48. In the draft of this letter from October 2, Fichtes formulation is more direct:
I recall often speaking with Fr. Sch. about the synthetic course of my Wissenschaftslehre;
and he remarked that none of the other exponents of tr.[anscendental] id.[ealism] possess
this method. It is possible that in this context I said the same thing about you, because
this is what I think: but I see in this no oense to you. (GA III/4: 31718).
49. Cf. Fichtes draft of this letter from October 2: Whatever I said, I could
have only said it out of respect and friendship for you, because I have never ceased to
feel this: it can only occur in a context that evokes these [feelings]; it [can only] be
initiatedI do not mean to say that Fr. Sch. tried to catch me out since I am not
used to speaking about people without it being initiated(I am not going to ask you
what you think of me). (GA III/4: 318).
50. An allusion to Schellings presence at the home of Caroline Schlegel.
51. Schelling spent six weeks in Dresden (from August 18 to October 1, 1798)
before going to Jena in October 1798.
52. See the draft of October 2: Can I ever have said to you about W. Sch.,
about whom we have always thought the same, anything as harsh as what you said in
your last letter about the two Schlegels? It is quite possible that I could have said to
you what I really thought (I now have a more favorable opinion of him after a couple
of his more recent articles in the Athenaeum and a few of his poems). How would I
have appeared if you had repeated (?) this to W. Sch.? As though he would have judged
it as anything less than false or two-faced; because neither he himself, nor you, nor
anyone else, may recall that I have ever said the contrary of this possible opinion. But
you accuse me of blatant falseness (GA III/4: 319).
53. In his letter of May 14, 1800 (Letter 1) Schelling had asked Fichte to write
a review of Bardili. On August 18, 1800 (Letter 4), however, Schelling informed Fichte
that he was going to write a review himself.
234 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
54. The plan accompanying the letter of August 2, 1800 (Letter 3).
55. See Fichtes letter of September 612, 1800 (Letter 6).
56. Fichte is here referring to his own review of Bardili.
57. Fichte is referring to his project for a new journal that he outlined in a letter
to Wilhelm August and Friedrich Schlegel on December 23, 1799 (cf. GA III/4: 16874).
58. See Fichtes letter of August 2, 1800 (Letter 3).
59. Cf. Schellings letter dated August 18, 1800 (Letter 4).
60. Fichte is alluding to Schiller and Goethe.
61. Schellings letter to Fichte is no longer extant. This fragment consists of the
literal words of Schelling that Fichte quoted in a letter he sent to Ludwig Tieck, circa
October 22, 1800 (cf. GA III/4: 344).
62. The corner of the letter with the date is torn. The letter most presumably
dates from October 21 or 22, 1800.
63. Both these letters are missing: see the fragmentary remarks from Fichtes letter
to Tieck (Letter 10) and its accompanying endnote.
64. In a letter dated September 12, 1799 (cf. GA III/4: 6876).
65. In December 1799.
66. As mentioned above, this letter is missing.
67. See the sonnet Schellings Weltseele [Schellings World Soul] in Athenaeum,
volume 3, part 2 (1800), p. 235.
68. This is obviously an error for the bridge over the river Saale in Jena.
69. That is to say, that Schelling had perhaps not mastered the synthetic method.
(See Letter 9, Fichte to Schelling, dated October 3, 1800).
70. Schellings brother, Karl Eberhard Schelling (17831855), had been a medical
student in Jena since 1799.
71. Fichte refers to the question mark in the sentence of the letter of October 3, 1800:
How would I have appeared to him if you had repeated (?) this to W.[ilhelm] S.[chlegel]?
72. See endnote four of the correspondence above.
73. See the translation of Fichtes New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre, in this volume.
74. All of the correspondence between the publisher Cotta and Schelling is no
longer extant.
75. Friedrich Schlegel obtained his doctorate from the philosophical faculty of
the University of Jena on August 13, 1800. For the winter semester 1800/1801 he had
announced lectures on Transcendental Philosophy and On the Vocation of the Scholar.
For his part, Schelling too had announced that he would lecture on transcendental
philosophy, as well as the philosophy of art and the philosophy of nature.
76. August Wilhelm Schlegel also had announced philosophical lectures on aesthetics.
77. The journal: Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik.
78. In Letter 12 from the end of October/November 1800.
79. See the fragment of approximately October 13, 1800 (Letter 10).
80. With a letter of October 22, 1800. See J. G. Fichte to L. Tieck (GA III/4:
344f.).
81. See Fichtes Announcement and New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre, both
translated in this volume.
82. As Fichte here mentions, he had written an Announcement to advertise his
forthcoming New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre 1800. The Announcement bears the
Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence 235
date November 4, 1800, but was rst published in the Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung on
January 24, 1801.
83. Philosophaster: a pretender to philosophy.
84. See Fichtes letter to Cotta, dated October 1820, 1800, which contains a
brief history of the entire journal aair from Fichtes standpoint (GA III/4: 33437).
85. A reference to a letter that is no longer extant; both the author of this report
and letter have not been ascertained. However, as Fichtes next words indicate, it was
perhaps from Tieck. (cf. GA III/4: 351).
86. Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik.
87. See Fichtes short commentary on this work, translated in this volume: While
Reading Schellings Transcendental Idealism (1800).
88. Probably a letter from Schiller that is no longer extant (cf. GA III/4: 351).
89. Der geschlossene Handelsstaat (1800) (The Closed Commercial State).
90. Letter 13, Fichte to Schelling, November 15, 1800.
91. In the preeminent case.
92. Potenzierte.
93. Potenz, lit., exponent, potency.
94. Taken in its literal sense as a Theory of Science or Theory of Scientic
Knowledge. See too the full title of Fichtes programmatic text when he rst arrived in
Jena in 1794: Concerning the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre or, of So-called Philosophy
(in: Fichte, EPW, pp. 94135).
95. einfachen, lit., simple or basic power.
96. Wissenschaftslehre, again, literally, as a theory of knowing.
97. Allgemeine Deduction des dynamischen Processes (General Deduction of
the Dynamic Process), appeared vol. 1, issues 1 and 2 of the Zeitschrift fr spekulative
Physik (1800) (cf. section 63, SW IV, 7578).
98. See note 97 above.
99. Empndung, lit., perception, sensation.
100. Der geschlossene Handelsstaat (The Closed Commercial State, 1800).
101. Christian Ernst Gabler (17701821), publisher of Schellings journal.
102. Fichtes review appeared in the Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung on October
3031, 1800.
103. Gottlieb Ernst August Mehmel (17611840), professor of philosophy in
Erlangen.
104. In a letter to Fichte in March 1799 (GA III/3: 224).
105. Schelling is referring to the rst volume of Reinholds six-volume work: Beytrge
zur leichtern Uebersicht des Zustandes der Philosophie beym Anfange des 19. Jahrhunderts
(Contributions to an Easier Overview of the State of Philosophy at the Beginning of
the Nineteenth Century; 18011803).
106. This is Fichtes draft for the following Letter 15. Dated October, this draft
was more likely written in December 1800.
107. Die Bestimmung des Menschen (Berlin: Vosssche Buchhandlung, 1800); the
third book is entitled Glaube (Faith).
108. Issues 1 and 2 of the rst volume of the Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik
that Schelling had sent with his letter of November 19, 1800 (Letter 14).
109. Marginalia from Schelling: Yes indeed!
236 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
132. Erkennen.
133. Wissen.
134. Darstellung, lit., presentation.
135. Gedanken.
136. Rather: Der Geist des Zeitalters als Geist der Filosoe (The Spirit of the
Age as the Spirit of Philosophy), in: Neuer Teutscher Merkur, issue 3, March 1801, pp.
16793.
137. The editors of the Fichte Gesamtausgabe consider this a reference to
Fichtes Vergleichung des vom Herrn Prof. Schmid aufgestellten Systems mit der
Wissenschaftslehre (GA I/3: 23566). [Excerpt in English: A Comparison between
Prof. Schmids System and the Wissenschaftslehre, tr. D. Breazeale, in: J. G. Fichte, Early
Philosophical Writings (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993), pp. 31636]. Hartmut
Traub argues that it might equally well refer to Fichtes review of Bardilis Grundriss der
ersten Logik or Fichtes Friedrich Nicolais Leben und sonderbare Meinungen. See Schelling
Fichte Briefwechsel, ed. Hartmut Traub, p. 198 n. 2.
138. Gottfried Ploucquet (17161790): German philosopher in Tbingen who
followed Leibnizs idea for a logical calculus in his 1761 Dissertatio historico-cosmologica
de lege continuitatis sive gradationis Leibniziana.
139. das einzig Existirende.
140. alles Existirende.
141. The distinction Schelling tries to make here is that between (supposed)
immanent universality and mere semantic generality. Bardili and Reinhold adopted a
Humean epistemology.
142. Friedrich Nicolais Leben und sonderbare Meinungen.
143. In Schellings own hand the year 1801 has been added, as well as the
remark: First received in August.
144. Fichtes is referring to Schellings Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and
Criticism which appeared in the Philosophisches Journal in 1795: My reason for asserting
that the two thoroughly opposed systems of dogmatism and criticism are both perfectly
possible, and that both will coexist alongside the other because all nite beings do not
stand at the same level of freedom, is as follows: both systems have the same problem;
however, this problem can be only absolutely solved not in a theoretical manner, but only
practically, i.e., through freedom (Sixth Letter, p. 187). Without singling out Schelling
by name, Fichte rejected this view in his own two Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre,
which also appeared in the Philosophisches Journal, in 1797 (cf. GA I/4: 210).
145. See Schellings letter to Fichte dated November 19, 1800 (Letter 14).
146. For example, see Schellings article: Anhang zu dem Aufsatz des Herrn
Eschenmayer betreend den wahren Begri der Naturphilosophie, und die richtige Art ihre
Probleme aufzulsen (1801): There is an idealism of nature and an idealism of the I;
the former is original for me, the latter is derived (Werke, I/4: 84).
147. Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy, translated in this volume.
Schelling sent Fichte a copy with his letter of May 15, 1801 (Letter 17).
148. See Schellings preface to his Presentation of My System of Philosophy translated
in this volume: . . . nor is it my fault that [my] vocal protest against the way idealism
is usually exhibited, which has existed since [I started work on] the philosophy of nature,
has to date been noticed only by the sharp-sighted Eschenmayer.
149. Letter of May 15, 1801 (Letter 17).
238 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
150. Seyn.
151. Sehen.
152. The following seven short paragraphs are contained on a separate piece of
paper. They are inserted here at this point in the Schelling HkA; in the Fichte GA they
appear one paragraph earlier.
153. realiter.
154. idealiter.
155. Unbegreiichen.
156. Eschenmayers review of Schellings two works: Einleitung zu dem Entwurf
eines Systems der Naturphilosophie and Erster Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie
in the Erlanger Literatur-Zeitung, April 7, 1801, also employs geometric examples to
illustrate his arguments.
157. Ibid.
158. Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre (1794); English: J. G. Fichte, Science
of Knowledge, tr. P. Heath (New York: Appelton-Century-Crofts, 1970).
159. Fichte in fact forgot to enclose a copy of the Crystal Clear Report to the Public
(1801). See Schellings remark in his letter of October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
160. See Reinhold, Der Geist des Zeitalters als Geist der Filosoe in the Neuer
Teutscher Merkur (1801), pp. 16793.
161. ist, lit., is. Schelling uses exist only for nite, conditioned, individual
phenomena or modes of being.
162. See I. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Paul
Guyer and Eric Matthews, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
163. trben, lit., becloud, muddy, make turbid.
164. Wirklichkeit.
165. in the preeminent case.
166. Presentation of My System, 2530.
167. Gleichheit, which can also be rendered as sameness or identity.
168. Getrenntheit, lit., separated state.
169. Fichtes previous letter to Schelling, dated May 31 [1801].
170. Cf. Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre (GA I/2: 282). This passage is
not assertoric; it comments only on the resemblance between the theoretical part of the
Wissenschaftslehre and Spinozas dogmatism: It is Spinozism made systematic, save only
that any given self is itself the ultimate substance. J. G. Fichte, Science of Knowledge,
tr. P. Heath, p. 119.
171. Sehen.
172. Wissen.
173. das Ur-Reale.
174. Wissenschaft.
175. Sache.
176. dated May 31 [1801] (Letter 19).
177. See Fichtes letter to Schelling of December 27, 1800 (Letter 15).
178. Ibid.
179. bringt es so mit sich., lit., carries with it.
180. Modos, lit., mode.
181. Organ.
Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence 239
182. Verstandesreexion.
183. Vernunft.
184. Vernunftewigkeit.
185. nature.
186. Briefe ber Dogmatismus und Kriticismus. In the Philosophisches Journal, issues
7 and 11, 1795.
187. Urreale.
188. Bogen, lit., sheets.
189. Mythologie.
190. Gtterlehre.
191. Naturphilosophie.
192. Fichtes letter of May 31 [1801] (Letter 19).
193. Presentation of My System of Philosophy.
194. vllig gleichgltig.
195. Endlichkeiten.
196. See J. G. Fichte, Foundations of Natural Right, 6 Fifth Theorem, Corollaries,
tr. Michael Baur (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) pp. 7578.
197. Fichtes editor-son refers to: Ueber das absolute Identitts-System und sein
Verhltni zu dem neusten (Reinholdischen) Dualismus (On the System of Absolute
Identity and its Relation to the Newest (Reinholdean) Dualism), which appeared in the
rst issue of Schelling and Hegels Kritisches Journal der Philosophie in 1802, pp. 190.
Perhaps Schelling is thinking in advance of the dialog Bruno, not published until 1802;
English: Bruno, or On the Divine and Natural Principle of Things, tr. M. Vater (Albany:
SUNY, 1984).
198. Eight essays in this series appeared in the April and October 1800 issues of
Schellings Neue Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik under the title Fernere Darstellungen aus
dem System der Philosophie (Further Presentations from the System of Philosophy) in:
vol. 1, issue 1, pp. 177; vol. 1, issue 2, pp. 1181. Two of these essays are translated
in the present volume.
199. In the Announcement for his New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre Fichte had
written: I will not discuss here the extent to which my talented collaborator, Professor
Schelling, has been more successful at paving the way for the transcendental standpoint
in his natural scientic writings and in his recently published System of Transcendental
Idealism. Schelling and the Jena romantics perceived the remark as a repudiation of
any claim to understand or present transcendental philosophy.
200. Allgemeine Deutsche Bibliothek.
201. The anonymous reviewer writes in the Neue Allgemeine Deutsche Bibliothek:
Mr. Fichte seems to want it made known that Mr. Schelling has not accurately presented
the Fichtean Wissenschaftslehre (cited in: GA III/5: 88).
202. G. W. F. Hegel, Dierenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen Systems der
Philosophie (Jena, 1801); English: The Dierence between Fichtes and Schellings System of
Philosophy, trans. H.S. Harris and Walter Cerf (Albany: SUNY Press, 1977).
203. Georg Christoph Lichtenberg (17421799): experimental physicist who
explored electricity. He was chiey known for his posthumous published notebooks
or waste-books, which expounded no systematic philosophy but oered interesting
aphorisms on human nature.
240 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
204. Although written earlier in October 1801, this letter was only sent to
Schelling along with Fichtes letter of January 15, 1802 (Letter 23). Hence, in terms of
the chronological reception of the letters, it was only received by Schelling after he had
again written to Fichte on January 4, 1802 (Letter 22, no longer extant, see excerpted
fragment). For this reason the present letter could also be placed after Schellings
[fragmentary] letter of January 4, 1802.
205. See Schellings letter to Fichte dated October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
206. Proton pseudos.
207. diese Form einheimsch sey.
208. In the Announcement in this volume.
209. See Schellings letter of October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
210. This letter is lost. The letter was sent via A. W. Schlegel along with a copy
of the rst issue of the Kritisches Journal, authored by Schelling and his new collaborator,
G. W. F. Hegel. As far as the personal relations between Fichte and Schelling go, the
letter evidently mentioned malicious and spiteful gossip that Schelling had publicly
broken with Fichte. A letter from Caroline, as well as Fichtes reply, testify that Schellings
tone toward Fichte was warm and cordial in this letter. As concerns the substantive
philosophical matters, the letter broached the themes of the relation between philosophical
or scientic knowing and the absolute, how and to what degree the absolute exists
under the form of quantity, and the n-ka-pa ~n of Spinozas philosophy. See H. Traub,
op. cit., pp. 21113.
211. Throughout this letter Fichte both explicitly and implicitly refers and returns
to events surrounding his departure from Jena in 1799, and certain more recent reports
from friends mentioning that Schelling apparently intended to break with him. In Jena
in 1799 it appears that both Schelling and Paulus made declarations about Fichtes
impending censure, Schelling to a small group of condants, Paulus to Fichte himself
(as the concluding paragraphs show). When news of Schellings declaration, which
supposedly was supportive of Fichte, later reached Fichte in Berlin (perhaps by way of
Schad or Hegel), Fichte understood the declaration to be a denunciation (again, perhaps
on account of the unnamed friend who presumably had confused the names Schelle and
Schelling), and hence a violation of the presumptive pact made in earlier letters not to
go public on their disagreements. Fichte elliptically refers to all these events and reports
in an apparent eort to nally clear up the continued misunderstandings between himself
and Schelling. (For further details, see Schelling, HkA III, 2, 2: 77983).
212. Johann Georg Muesel (17431802), professor in Erlangen, was the editor
of a volume listing the most important deceased German writers in the second half
of the eighteenth century: Lexikon der vom Jahr 1750 bis 1800 verstorbenen teutschen
Schriftsteller. Ausgearbeitet von Johann Georg Meusel (Leipzig, 1802).
213. Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung.
214. On page 120 of the rst issue of the Kritisches Journal there is a criticism
of the gossip surrounding Schellings relationship to Fichte after the announcement of
Hegels Dierence text and their jointly edited volume.
215. Karl Gottlob Schelle, was a private teacher in Leipzig. On November 11,
1801 he published a declaration in the A.L.Z. deploring what he perceived as the bias
of the Erlanger Literatur Zeitung in favor of the German idealistic philosophers.
Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence 241
216. Fichte is alluding to the report of the new Kritisches Journal, edited by
Schelling and Hegel.
217. The last section of the letter of October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
218. As the following paragraph shows, Fichtes own reply and further agreement
with Schellings earlier voiced proposal that they do not attack each other in public was
communicated in his letter written and dated October 8, 1801 (Letter 21). However, as
already noted (see endnote 204 above), this letter of Fichte was only sent to Schelling
in January 1802 (enclosed in Letter 23).
219. A reference to Fichtes letter of October 8, 1801 (Letter 21), which was sent
to Schelling together with this letter dated January 15, 1802.
220. Schellings no longer extant letter of January 4, 1802 (see endnote 210 above).
221. Presumably, another reference to Fichtes and Schellings mutual agreement
not advertise their respective dierences (cf. Fichtes letter to Schelling of May 31/August
7, 1801 and Schellings reply of October 9, 1801), and subsequent letters.
222. Klatscherei.
223. ReektirPunkt.
224. See the correspondence of September to October 1800 where Schelling had
accused Fichte of falseness (Letters. 811).
225. Fichte is referring to Schellings letter of October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
226. As the following paragraphs show, Fichte is now explicitly referring to
information and events surrounding his censure and departure from the University of
Jena in 1799.
227. H. E. G. Paulus (17611851), a professor of theology at the University of
Jena from 1789 to 1803. Fichte is now providing Schelling with some of the further
details concerning his dismissal from the University of Jena in March 1799, in which
Paulus had earlier said to Fichte that he would also leave the university if the latter were
to be dismissed. For more details of this aair, see D. Breazeales Introduction: Fichte
in Jena in: J.G. Fichte, Early Philosophical Writings, pp. 145, especially pp. 4144.
228. This walk, in which Paulus met Fichtes wife, was most likely on March
20, 1799. Johanne Marie Fichte (ne Rahn) (17551819), was originally a native of
Zurich in Switzerland.
229. The rst letter that Fichte wrote to Privy Councilor C.G. Voigt, March 22,
1799, stating that he would resign from his position at the university if he were to be
ocially reprimanded for his philosophical activities (cf. GA III/3: 28386).
230. The rescript or rescind of March 29, 1799 issued by Duke Karl August,
reprimanding Fichte and Niethammer, the editors of the Philosophisches Journal, with
its postscript accepting Fichtes resignation (cf. GA III/37173).
231. Letter of April 3, 1801 (cf. GA III/3: 29193).
232. A reference to Reinhold, whom Schelling had called Zettel and ascribed
to him an imaginary letter in the rst issue of the Kritisches Journal. See: Ein Brief von
Zettel an Squenz, vol. 1 (1802), pp. 12230.
233. Wilhelm Traugott Krug (17701842), a professor of philosophy in Frankfurt
an der Oder. See Hegels article: Wie der gemeine Menschenverstand die Philosophie
nehme, dargestellt an den Werken des Herrn Krugs in the Kritisches Journal. English
translation: How the Ordinary Human Understanding Takes Philosophy (as Displayed
242 Notes to FichteSchelling Correspondence
in the Works of Mr. Krug) in: Between Kant and Hegel, eds. and trans. G. di Giovanni
an H. S. Harris (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett, 2000), pp. 295310.
234. Reviews of Krugs works appeared in the Neue Deutsche Bibliothek in vol.
56, pp. 13441; vol. 69, pp. 168f.
235. See the sentences in italics in the beginning paragraphs of Fichtes letter of
October 8, 1801 (Letter 21).
236. Fichte is above all referring to Schellings article: Ueber das absolute
Identitts-System und sein Verhltni zu dem neuesten (Reinholdischen) Dualismus
in the Kritisches Journal, vol. 1, pp. 190.
237. See section 2 of Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy.
238. Seyn.
239. GrundReexe.
240. ReexionsPunkte.
241. Nebenglied.
242. Letter of May 31, 1801 (Letter 19).
243. Ein Sehen.
244. Cf. Spinoza, Ethica, I, De Deo.
245. See sections 21 and 22 of Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy.
246. Aeusserung.
247. und jedes zweite Wort ist vom Uebel, lit., any second word is detrimental,
or wrong.
248. of October 3, 1801 (Letter 20).
249. Einlenken, lit., coming around, or be accomodating (the expression with
which Fichte concludes his letter of January 15, 1802: Letter 23).
250. Fichte wrote to a former student in Jena, Jean Baptiste Schad (17581834),
on December 29, 1801 that Schelling had never understood him. This letter is no longer
extant, but there does exist in Schellings own handwriting a partial but apparently literal
excerpt of the passages in question: . . . As for Professor Schelling, what you kindly
inform me about him is not unknown to me. I hope that my new presentation [of the
Wissenschaftslehre], which is to appear at Easter, will show up his pretension of further
extending my system which he has never understoodin all its weakness. . . . He now
clearly admits that he thought the Wissenschaftslehre derives the thing from the knowledge
of the thing (leite das Ding von dem Wissen vom Dinge ab), and that earlier with his
own idealism he had therefore actually meant this; hence, that he has understood the
Wissenschaftslehre, as Fr.[iedrich] Nicolai has understood it (quoted in: Fichte, GA III/5:
100). A letter from Caroline to A. W. Schlegel reports that Schad showed this letter to
Schelling in mid-January of the following year, claiming to be equally sympathetic to
both philosophers. Cf. J.G. Fichte/F.W.J. Schelling: Correspondance (17941802), ed. and
trans. M. Bienenstock (Paris: P.U.F., 1991), p. 40, n. 126.
251. glcklich, lit., happily, but also by chance or haphazardly.
252. ziemlich, lit., tolerably.
253. This is the nal letter in the exchange between Fichte and Schelling. The
latter did indeed go to Berlin for two weeks in May 1802, but it appears that no personal
meeting took place between the two philosophers at this time, or in the future, nor was
their correspondence ever continued.
Notes to Fichte Texts 243
15. The Announcement bears the date of November 4, 1800, whereas the rst
systematic presentation of Fichtes system, the Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre,
was available to his students in Jena in September 1794.
16. A reference to the Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo, on which Fichte lectured
in Jena from late 1795 until early 1799. The lecture manuscript from 1795 is no longer
extant. See the translation of the later manuscripts by Daniel Breazeale: J. G. Fichte,
Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre) nova methodo (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1992).
17. Cf. The New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre, translated in this volume.
18. The Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre (17941795) initially was only
intended as a handout for Fichtes students. English translation under the title: J. G.
Fichte: The Science of Knowledge (1794), ed. and trans. P. Heath and J. Lachs (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1982).
19. Grundlage des Naturrechts (17961797); English translation: Foundations of
Natural Right, ed. F. Neuhouser, trans. M. Baur (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2000).
20. Das System der Sittenlehre (1798); English translation: System of Ethics in
accordance with the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre eds. and trans. Daniel Breazeale
and Gnter Zller (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
21. See Fichtes Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre, first
published in the Philosophisches Journal in 1797/98; English translation: Attempt at
a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre in: Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre
and Other Writings (17971800) ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1994), pp. 2117.
22. A reference to Schellings writings on Naturphilosophiethe philosophy of
nature. See the bibliography for a list of these writings in English.
23. Schelling, System des transscendentalen Idealismus (Tbingen: Cotta, 1800);
English translation: System of Transcendental Idealism, translated by Peter Heath, with
an introduction by Michael Vater (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1978,
2nd ed., 1993).
24. Cf. the preface to the Attempt at a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre,
in: Fichte, IW, p. 4.
25. Footnote by Fichte: I do not consider Prof. Beck, as the author of the
Standpunkt, to be a member of this school, as Kant himself has noted. Prof. Beck was
on the path to the Wissenschaftslehre. If he had only made his intentions wholly clear
to himself he would have discovered it.
26. Cf. I. Kant, the Doctrine of Method in the Critique of Pure Reason, A
837/B 865 (AA III: 541). Here Kant argues that the dierences between the methods
of mathematics and philosophy is that the latter is a form of rational cognition
(Vernunfterkenntni) based on concepts, whereas the former is a form of rational cognition
based on the construction of concepts.
27. This reference to a mathesis of mathesis is most likely linked to Fichtes
reading of the German philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (16461716); see his
concluding remarks at the end of this Announcement. Mathesis for Leibniz signied a
science of philosophical rst principles having the same scientic rigor as mathematics.
(Cf. too the editors remarks on Spinoza, Jacobi, and mathesis in the introduction to
Notes to Fichte Texts 245
Fichtes texts). Fichtes remarks also recall his frequent assertions that the Wissenschaftslehre
is to be a science of science. See, for example: Fichte, Concerning the Concept of the
Wissenschaftslehre (1794), in: Fichte, Early Philosophical Writings, pp. 94136.
28. Johann Gottfried Herder (17441803), German writer, philosopher, and
theologian.
29. Jean Paul Friedrich Richter (17631825), German Romantic writer and novelist.
30. Footnote by Fichte: Jean Paul in his Clavis Fichtiana. The key wont indeed
unlock; for the manufacturer of it has not gained entrance anywhere. See Jean Paul,
Clavis Fichtiana seu Leibgeberiana (Erfurt, 1800).
31. An allusion to Johann Georg Hamann (17701788) and his 1800 article:
Metacritik ber den Purismus der Vernunft.
32. Footnote by Fichte: In Kants Erklrung concerning the Wissenschaftslehre in
the Jena L.Z. See Immanuel Kants Erklrung in Beziehung auf Fichtes Wissenschaftslehre
of 1799 (AA XII: 370f ); and the letter of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi to Fichte, March
321, 1799 (GA III/3: 227).
33. Footnote by Fichte: This is Kants sense, though he does not use the same
words, in his essay against Schlosser: ber den vornehmen Ton in die Philosophie. See
Kants essay: Von einem neuerdings erhobenen vornehmen Ton in der Philosophie (AA VIII:
387406).
34. unmittelbare Evidenz.
35. Bestimmtheit.
36. alle Vernunft.
37. Unwiderlegbarkeit.
38. Footnote by Fichte: And has not, for all his contemporaries to hear, the
founder of an apparently new dogmatic system (the blessed Werner) indicated that:
The assertion of the innite divisibility of space is nonsense from geometersand has
brought dishonor on an otherwise useful science. Georg Friedrich Werner (17541798),
professor of military science in Gieen. Fichte is referring to his book: Erster Versuch
einer allgemeinen Aetiologie (Gieen, 1792), p. 85.
39. Viel-Philosophen gegen die Allein-Philosophen. A reference to Friedrich Heinrich
Jacobis criticisms in his Open Letter to Fichte, March 321, 1799 (cf. GA III/3: 22481).
40. allgemeine Charakteristik. Cf. Leibniz, Preface to a Universal Characteristic
in: Leibniz, Philosophical Essays, eds. R. Ariew and D. Garber (Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company, 1989), pp. 59.
41. Fichte, Neue Bearbeitung der Wissenschaftslehre (1800). Fichte wrote his
manuscript from October to December 1800; it remained incomplete and Fichte never
returned to it. The German text was rst published in 1979 in: GA II/5: 331401. This
is a translated extract of approximately half the text, pp. 33167.
42. Beschauen.
43. Beobachten.
44. Bestimmtheit.
45. Bestimmbarkeit.
46. See ad. 2.
47. A = A refers to the problematic starting point of Fichtes Foundations of the
Entire Wissenschaftslehre from Jena, 1794 (cf. GA I/2: 256).
48. Nicht Denken.
246 Notes to Fichte Texts
49. Although jotted down with this text, these thoughts belong to the Provisional
denition of the title on the back of the title page of Fichtes text: The Closed Commercial
State.
50. See the Introduction to the Foundations 1794 and the two introductions
from 1798/1799.
51. The Crystal Clear Report [Sonnenklarer Bericht] was a work published by
Fichte at Easter 1801.
52. Abbildung.
53. Postulat.
54. Theorem.
55. Hinleitungen.
56. Lehrsaz [sic].
57. Hilfslinie.
58. This latter sentence is found in the margin without any corresponding
reference mark.
59. Vftererkenntnis [sic] aus Begrien. Fichte is here referring to Kants presentation
in the Critique of Pure ReasonSee Fichtes more detailed discussion of this point in
the Announcement.
60. Urbild.
61. Nachbild.
62. Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre, Jena, 1794.
63. das ursprngliche Einkehren in sich selbst.
64. Vorstellungen.
65. See the preface to Schellings System of Transcendental Idealism.
66. See Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (B 132).
67. Cf. Fichtes Announcement for a similar argument.
68. There are two illegible words here in the original manuscript.
69. Cf. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (B 132).
70. Gegensetzende.
71. Johann Wolfgang Goethe (17491832), German writer, poet, and scientist.
72. Illegible passage in manuscript.
73. Illegible passage in manuscript.
74. See George Berkeleys (16851753): A Treatise Concerning the Principles of
Human Knowledge. Part 1, Dublin, 1710.
75. See Fichte, Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre, 14.
76. Manuscript breaks o.
77. Bei der Lectre von Schellings tr. Idealismus: First published in: Fichte,
SW XI: 36869; reprint: GA II/5: 41315. Fichtes text is a brief commentary on F. W.
J. Schelling, System des transscendentalen Idealismus (System of Transcendental Idealism)
published in 1800 by Cotta in Tbingen.
78. Ibid., p. 3.
79. Erkennen.
80. Wissen.
81. Die Bestimmung des Menschen (Berlin: Vosssche Buchhandlung, 1800). English
translation: The Vocation of Man, trans. Peter Preuss (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987).
82. Schelling, System des transscendentalen Idealismus (Tbingen: Cotta, 1800), p. 28.
83. Friederich Bouterwek (17661828), professor of philosophy in Gttingen.
Notes to Schelling Texts 247
84. Cf. Schelling, Erster Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie (First Outline
of System of a Philosophy of Nature), Jena, 1799, p. X.
85. Vorarbeiten gegen Schelling GA II/5: 48385. This text is a brief commentary
on Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy.
86. See Schelling, Presentation of My System of Philosophy, section 1.
87. geschautes.
88. Wahrnehmung.
89. Vernehmen.
90. Vernommen.
91. Fichte, Zur Darstellung von Schellings Identittssysteme (SW XI: 37189;
GA II/5: 487508).
92. Cf. 1. of Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy translated in
the present volume. Concerning Fichtes references to the propositions, corollaries, and
remarks of Schellings Presentation, readers are referred to this translation. Any signicant
departures or paraphrasing of Schellings wording will be signaled in the following notes.
Fichtes use of emphasis will be retained (indicated by italics), and occasionally diers
from that employed by Schelling in his original text.
93. Vernunft.
94. Nichts.
95. Allheit.
96. Grund.
97. Bestimmtheit.
98. Fichtes citation is a slight abbreviation of Schellings proposition. See
proposition 4 of Schellings Presentation of My System of Philosophy, translated in this
volume.
99. Fichtes citation is a paraphrased and abbreviated version of Schellings 9
proposition and its corresponding corollary.
100. Fichtes reference is to the original Latin edition of Spinozas work: Ethica
Ordine Geometrico demonstrata in: Opera postuma (1677).
101. Ibid., Book 1, prop. XVI, p. 16.
102. die ganze Unterscheidung ist nur Produkt des den Begri des Durchsichselbstseins
analysirenden Denkens.
103. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Book 1, prop. XXI.
104. Cf. Ibid., prop. XVIII.
105. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, prop. XXV, Corollary.
106. an sich.
107. Nicht an sich.
108. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Book 1, prop. XV.
109. Ibid., prop. XXI.
110. Imago.
Vol. XXXII, no. 4 Winter, 2001, pp. 33971; it appears here with the permission of
that journals publisher.)
2. See the editorial comment on Eschenmayer by Thomas Kisser and associates
in Schelling Werke HkA, III, 2, 1, Briefe 18001802, pp. 7277.
3. F. W. J. Schelling to C. A. Eschenmayer, February 10, 1800, Werke HkA
III, 2, 1, p 184.
4. Erste Entwurf eines Systems der Naturphilosophie and Einleitung zu dem Entwurf,
Werke HkA III. Translated by Keith R. Peterson in F. W. J. Schelling, First Outline of a
System of the Philosophy of Nature (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2004).
5. Eschenmayer expressed these views in print one year later in a review of First
Sketch of a Philosophy of Nature and Introduction to a Sketch of the Philosophy of Nature
in the Erlanger Litteratur-Zeitung, Nr. 67 (April 1801), pp. 52940.
6. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik, Band
2, edited and annotated M. Durner (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2001), p. 239.
Hereafter cited as ZsP2.
7. Ibid., pp. 26667.
8. Schelling to Ch. E. Gabler, 7 September, 1800, HkA II, 2, 1, p. 232.
9. See Letter 13, Fichte in Berlin to Schelling in Jena, 15 November 15, 1800,
translated in this volume.
10. See Letter 14, Schelling in Jena to Fichte in Berlin, 19 November 19, 1800,
translated in this volume.
11. See ZsP2, pp. 306310.
12. Ibid., pp. 31718.
13. See Frederick C. Beiser, German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism,
17811801 (Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 2002) pp. 48890,
55860.
14. Schelling an J. W. v. Goethe, January, 1801, Werke HkA III, 2, 1, pp. 30007
15. Schelling an J. W. v. Goethe, February, 1801, Werke HkA III, 2, 1, p. 323.
Cf. the editorial note in HkA III, 2, 2, p. 695.
16. By summer 1800, Schelling clearly stated the dierence between the way nature
actsas one and all-at-onceand the moments or stages (Potenzen) that philosophy of
nature must employ to genetically explain the working of nature to aid in speculative
analysis (zum Behuf der Spekulation). We must not imagine that nature actually goes
through these stages in the course of time, rather they are dynamically, or, if you will,
metaphysically grounded in it. Allgemeine Deduktion des dynamischen Prozesses, 30.
ZsP2, p. 113
17. See the lengthy editorial comment on Goethe in Werke HkA III, 2, 1, pp.
97117.
18. The note promises a complete system of identity-theory, nature, and
consciousness. The last-named is missing. Disputes with his publisher, Gabler, prevented
the appearance of a planned Vol. III of the Journal for Speculative Physics, so that the
continuation promised in the note to 159, Corollary 2 did not materialize.
19. See F. W. J. von Schelling, On the History of Modern Philosophy, edited and
translated by Andrew Bowie (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press,
1994), pp. 11433.
20. Since he read widely in contemporary English physics and chemistry, Schelling
instinctively adopted an Anglophone vocabulary for his metaphysics of identity and
Notes to Schelling Texts 249
32. Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Beytrge zu leichtern Uebersicht des Zustandes der
Philosophie beym Anfange des 19. Jahrhunderts, issue 1 (Hamburg, 1801) pp. IIIV. [Tr.]
33. Erster Entwurf einer Systems der Naturphilosphie, 1799. [Tr.]
34. See the essays on intellectual intuition and philosophical constructions
from the 1802 Fernere Darstellungen aus der System der Philosophie that follow in this
volume. [Tr.]
35. Schelling was not the only one to speculate about a transcendental interpretation
of Spinoza. Late in life, Kant sees Spinoza as doing something similar to transcendental
philosophy in that in his seeing all things in God, he adumbrates a universal system
of all possible objects under one principle [Kants Opus postumum, Erste Hlfte, ed. Artur
Buchenau (Berlin u. Leipzig: de Gruyter, 1936) 12.59, 2023)]. [Tr.]
36. See Michael Vater, Schellings Philosophy of Identity and Spinozas Ethica
more geometrica, in Spinoza and German Idealism, edited by Eckart Forster & Yitzak
Melamed (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
37. Magazin zur Vervollkommnung des theoretischen und praktischen Heilkunde, ed.
Andreas Rschlaub, vol. 2, H. 3 (1799), pp. 32990. [Tr.]
38. Reection is the subject-centered cognition that is the antithesis of the identity-
philosophers speculative knowing. That cognition is reected suggests it is secondhand,
diminished, passive. In the body of My System Schelling contrasts reection to reason and
associates it with the temporal and dynamic perspective of mechanism. It is synonymous
with appearance or with the individuals self-separation from totality that denes its
nitude. In Further Presentations, where its use might resonate with Hegels Dierence,
it designates cognition tied to a nite existence or associated with sensation; it is also
used synonymously with understanding to designate the standpoint where being and
cognition confront one another as opposites. [Tr.]
39. Note: For imagination is related to reason, as phantasy is to understanding.
The former is productive, the latter reproductive. [Unless otherwise labeled, all notes
that follow are taken from an authors copy.]
40. Addition: isolating, individual.
41. Note: The principle A = A needs no demonstration. It is the ground of all
demonstration. What is posited by it is only unconditioned being-posited. But where
this unconditioned being-posited manifests is completely a matter of indierence for the
principle. This A in the subject position and the other in the predicate position is not
what is really posited; what is posited is only the identity between the two.
42. Note: What is derived from this same form is therefore equally eternal with
absolute identity.
43. Addition: or are absolute identity itself.
44. Addition: i.e., an attribute of absolute identity itself.
45. Note: Only innite in its very self, hence not to be distinguished from being.
46. Addition: apart from the one doing the cognizing.
47. Addition: of the being of absolute identity.
48. Addition: therefore indivisible.
49. Addition: in a divisible way.
50. Note: Were this form not a cognizing, it would generally not be divisible
qua form.
51. Addition: relative to absolute identity.
Notes to Schelling Texts 251
totality of these forms, so that it is indeed always posited in individuals with dierence,
but with indierence in the whole. Quantitative dierence is in general posited only
through the act of separation and it holds with respect to [that] separation.
62. Addition: of the real and the ideal.
63. in reality [Tr.]
64. Note: This opposition appears as an opposition only when I separate myself o.
65. Addition: and so too, that of knowing and being.
66. Note: The universe does not = the material. Identity is to all eternity just
identity, but a universe means a whole of dierent things.
67. Addition: being and cognizing.
68. in potency, or potentially [Tr.]
69. Addition: not qualitative.
70. Note: Divisibility = quantity: Absolute identity [is] independent of all quantity.
71. Note: The primitive basis of the principle of causality.
72. Addition: one dierence presupposes the other.
73. Gesetze der Art [Tr.]
74. Addition: and to the extent it is innite, it is not subject to the law stated
in 36.
75. Correction: in its mode of being.
76. Addition: e.g., innite divisibility or, instead, indivisibility.
77. Note: The concept of power or potency can be most accurately understood in
the following way. What is in existence is always [and] only indierence, and nothing
truly exists outside it: but it exists in innite ways too, and it never exists otherwise
than under the form A = A, i.e., as cognition and being. We can consider it either in
the individual or in the whole. It exists in the individual under the same form as in the
whole. Within the whole, the opposition under whose form it exists is that of innite
being and innite cognition, and that which falls in this indierence-pointin the
absolute one between these two can for that very reason be neither one nor the other,
neither innite cognizing nor innite being, and only to the extent that it is neither as
the one nor as the other it is the in-itself. Further, being is just as innite as cognition,
and both, innite being and innite cognizing, are expressed by the proposition A =
A. Since the proposition expresses both, the innite thus stands under the form of the
proposition A = A with respect to cognition and to being. The indierence of cognition
and being is therefore not a simple identity of A as subject and A as object (Spinoza),
but the indierence of A = A as the expression of being and A = A as the expression of
cognition. Qualitative indierence would be posited if A as subject and A as object were
to be posited over against one another. But this is never the case, except in regard to
the nite. In the scope of the innite, there is not A as subject and A as object, but A
= A and A = A, i.e., one identity posited over against another. Each is equally innite,
hence indivisible, but precisely because they are equally innite, they are bound together
not through some synthesis, i.e., not through something subordinate to them, but through
what is superior, through the absolute in-itself. Now since innite being, like cognizing,
[exists] under the form of the proposition A = A, that which compared to absolute
indierence is a mere being is again posited under this form of indierence, i.e., it is
in reference to itself once more the indierence of cognizing and being. What constitutes
a power or potency is just this, that relative to the absolute [something exists] merely
Notes to Schelling Texts 253
under the attribute of knowing or that of being, that it belongs under A = A either as
the expression of being or as that of cognizing.
78. Note: All causal derivation is thereby precluded. That of thought from being
as well as that of being from thought. The failing of idealism is to make one potency
the rst.
79. See F. W. J. Schelling, Smtliche Werke, 3: 385, 390. [Tr.]
80. ideally [Tr.]
81. in reality [Tr.]
82. Richtung, lit. direction [Tr.]
83. Note: Put in other terms, the proposition would read: Neither A as subject nor
A as object can be posited in itself, but only one and the same A = A with predominant
ideality (as the expression of cognition) and reality (as the expression of being) and the
quantitative indierence of the two.
84. Addition: A as subjectivity or A as objectivity.
85. Note: Therefore we never leave the form of subjectivityobjectivity, we never
emerge from A = A. All dierentiation consists just in this: A = A is posited in one
direction or tendency as innite cognition, in the other as innite being.
86. Addition: which is conceived under the concept of quantity.
87. Addition: of the construction.
88. Note: The same thing for the philosopher that the line is for the geometer.
89. abstractly [Tr.]
90. Correction: of existence.
91. Addition: as equally real.
92. Note: With complete indierence whether identity be conceived under the
attribute of one or that of the other.
93. Addition: this real-being.
94. Seyend [Tr.]
95. Addition: as equally real.
96. Addition: subjectivity and objectivity. [Some of the Remarks and Explanations
that follow were originally set in smaller type when Schellings Presentation appeared in
1801. See Editorischer Bericht HkA, I, 10, p. 3. - Tr.]
97. Addition: as the indierence of cognition and being.
98. Addition: of cognition and being.
99. Note: All construction starts from relative identity. Absolute identity is not
constructed, but simply is.
100. Addition: expressed by A = B.
101. Kraft [Tr.]
102. Addition: of the rst quantitative dierence.
103. Primum existens, which is not translated as rst existent since, properly
speaking, there is only one existent, nature itself. [Tr.]
104. Expansivekraft [Tr.]
105. Addition: of the rst quantitative dierence.
106. Note: Quantitative dierence aside, it is not gravity but absolute indierence.
107. Reellseyns [Tr.]
108. seyend [Tr.]
109. Addition: alone.
254 Notes to Schelling Texts
the particular into universality. Just as absolute cohesion or the simple rst dimension
[arises] through magnetism, through electricity [arises] the secondlength and breadth.
151. Addition: and why in magnetism manifests nothing more than the pure
appearances of attraction and repulsion, in this case contact and separation are
inconceivable.
152. Note: The basic law of all electrical processes.
153. Schelling uses E and +E to signify negative and positive electricity. [Tr.]
154. Note: because the condition of the former is contact between indierent
bodies, and of the latter, contact between dierent bodies.
155. Addition: +
156. Addition:
157. Addition: that is, a process of increasing cohesion.
158. Addition: an inverse ratio of generating heat and electricity.
159. Addition: i.e., loss of heat stands in a proportional ratio to the electrical process.
160. Note: In general, almost all the theorems which follow prove that everything
is subject to the schema of reection or the imaging of identity within dierence.
161. Addition: mere.
162. actu [Tr.]
163. Addition: i.e., thereby, in quantitative dierence.
164. Note: Hence, absolute identity as ground of existence = gravity, which again
can be established as existing only through being posited under the form of A and B,
with quantitative dierence. In this way, however, it is posited only as gravity. Only when
identity establishes A and B as the form of one being does identity posit itself in light.
165. Schelling cites this passage in the 1809 Essay on Human Freedom as one of
the precursors to the distinction he there elaborates between being and the ground of
being. That being or reality results from a ground without being identical to its ground
furnishes the logic for distinguishing nature and God, and also nature and humankind;
the former are marked by necessity, the latter by freedom or decision. See Schellings
Werke 7, 35758. [Tr.]
166. Cp. Ibid., 358, where this sentence is virtually reproduced. [Tr.]
167 Johann Wolfgang Goethe. [Tr.]
168. Note: More precisely: it produces the being wherein the form of its existence
can arise.
169. Note: More precisely: it is gravity insofar as the universal form of existence
has already arisen in it.
170. Note: Accordingly, the essence of matter is really = the essence of the innite
and is immediately expressed in nothing concrete.
171. Principium mere ideale actu existens [Tr.]
172. Schelling started to use the term dynamic explanation in 1800 for the a priori
or constructive approach to physics he favored over the atomistic approach practiced
by empirical investigators (See Allgemeine Deduktion des dynamischen Prozesses 63.)
This approach harks backs to Kants construction of matter from attractive and repulsive
forces in Metaphysische Anfangsgrnde der Naturwissenschaft (1786) A 5294. For a fuller
discussion of dynamic process, see below 108, Remark. When Schelling uses it in a
broad sense, the dynamic process includes the rst two of the high-level powers or orders
Notes to Schelling Texts 257
of nature, gravity and light; used in a ner sense, the term denotes density (specic
gravity), gravity, magnetism, and perhaps electrical phenomenaall mediated by changes
in cohesion for two or more bodies in relation. Electrical phenomena are sometimes
included in the dynamic process, though in galvanism electricity seems to be associated
with chemical interactions. Insofar as he works with empirical phenomena, Schelling
sometimes seems to favor chemical interaction as the terminus a quo of explanatory
reductionand at other times cohesion. When it comes to mapping empirical variations
onto the metaphysics of indierence of the Presentations earlier sections, magnetism is
the key for exhibiting identity-in-dierence, and so provides the moment of Evidenz or
insight on which the plausibility of the whole construction depends. [Tr.]
173. actu [Tr.]
174. Note: If the question of the true origin of the material universe is posed,
one can neither say that it had a beginning nor that it had none. This is because it is
simply or in its very idea eternal, i.e., it has no relation whatsoever to time. All time
determinations reside only within nite reective cognition, while in themselves all
things are contained in an eternal and non-temporal way in the absolute. But if one asks
after the act of sundering whereby the material universe separates itself from the all for
reective cognition and goes over to temporal existence, the magnet ([or] its product,
cohesion) is the principle of individuation, [or] actively expressed, self-consciousness.
What separates itself [from the absolute], separates itself only for itself, not in the
perspective of the absolute. This is certainly [exhibited] most clearly in the highest act
of separation, the I. I am only in that I know of myself, and apart from this knowing,
nothing [subsists] as I. The I is its own act, its own deed.
In bodily things, however, there is a passive expression of the act of separation
which is living and self-active in the I, a principle of individuation in them that is
expressed in the absolute itself in order to separate them, not in the perspective of the
absolute, but rather in their own perspective. The individual enters time, yet in the
perspective of the absolute, it does not stray from eternity. Everything that pertains to
the form of the universe is comprehended in the absolute, only not in a temporal way.
Since this form is quantitative dierence (i.e., nitude in the individual) and indierence
(i.e., innitude in the whole), so nite beings, even the entire series of them, are equally
eternal and simply present in the absolute, just not as nite. This eternal order of things,
within which one posits the other and is itself possible only through the other, is not
originated, or if it is originated, it originates anew with every consciousness.
Absolute identity is like the moment of the universal dissolution of all things;
nothing in it is dierentiated, even if everything is contained in it. Finite cognition,
self-consciousness, turns this state of utmost transparency opaque, and, if we may extend
our simile, the material world is a sediment or precipitation of absolute identity, while
the ideal world is a sublimation of it. These two are not separated in the absolute, but
are united; and, in turn, that wherein they are united is the absolute.
175. chemical elements [Tr.]
176. chemical transformation [Tr.]
177. Note: Sulfur, phosphorus.
178. Addition: rst.
179. Addition: and form products in the middle.
258 Notes to Schelling Texts
180. Correction: The former pair will increase cohesion, the latter decrease it.
181. Addition: and conversely, in the sense in which one can decompose any
other matter, it too is water.
182 Addition: south, north, east, and west poles.
183. This sketch of the foundations of chemistry relies on the primitive ideas of
gravity and cohesion. Steens reports in 1800 that Schelling then considered oxidization
and deoxidization to be fundamental natural processes (Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik,
vol. 1, issue 1, p. 143). See section 112 . [Tr.]
184. Addition: quality.
185. Addition: absolute constancy.
186. Note: For just this reason the common notion of specic gravity is likewise
impossible (as if it rested on a multitude of small particles). Every A = B already [has]
specic gravity.
187. Correction: [bodies] of the greatest specic gravity.
188. Correction: gravity [Schwere for Schwerkraft [Tr.]]
189. Correction: the real unity.
190. Addition: indeed of this determinate existence whereby it = light.
191. Addition: determinate mode or.
192. Addition: of the true indierence-point of the cohesion-series, and so posited
where dierence is posited and in the same ratio as dierence.
193. Von der Weltseele, eine Hypothese der hhern Physik zur Erklrung des allgemeinen
Organismus (Hamburg: Friedrich Perthes, 1798). [Tr.]
194. getrbtes [Tr.]
195. Addition: the positing of light [happens] under one or the other form [viz.,
refraction or reection].
196. Note: with quantitative dierence according to form, but not according to
essence.
197. J. W. Goethe, Contributions to Optics (Weimar, 1791). [Tr.]
198. Wilhelm Herschel (17381822), a Hanoverian musician, astronomer and
scientist, credited with the discovery of Uranus and its two moons, as well as two moons
of Saturn. Schelling refers to an experiment he performed in 1800 in which he passed
light through a prism and discovered a sharp rise in temperature in a thermometer placed
at the red end of the spectrum. Herschel later inferred the existence of a nonvisible
infrared light. [Tr.]
199. Farbengespenst, lit., color-ghost [Tr.]
200. Refrangibilittsordnung [Tr.]
201. Reagentien, lit., reagents [Tr.]
202. Addition: without [regard to] any dierence of mass.
203. Correction: in the dynamic process.
204. Addition: since [in them] there is no absolute indierence.
205. Addition: mere.
206. Addition: as in, e.g., the magnet.
207. Proce [Tr.]
208. Addition: a decomposition.
209. Addition: relatively.
210. Sauersto, lit. sour-stu [Tr.]
Notes to Schelling Texts 259
293. In this very feature, that it proceeds from absolute cognition, philosophy
also pursues its self-demonstration (it can prove itself only because it is absolute science).
It leads us to the point where this absolute knowledge, which = the absolute itself, is
informed in us as the idea and the essence of our soul. Authors note.
294. This continuation appeared in Neue Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik, vol. 1,
2. Stck, 1802 under the specic title Der fernere Darstellungen aus dem System der
Philosophie anderer Theil.
295. Recapitulation. Our previous discussion has furnished us with the following
items of cognition as material for the whole of the subsequent construction; their
development and proof was the goal of all our previous inquiry. 1. Absolute knowing is
also the absolute itself. Proof. Absolute knowing = unity of thought and being, hence this
necessary form or mode of being [holds] with respect to the absolute, and this form or
mode of being and the absolute itself are again one by virtue of the idea itself. Therefore,
the form or mode of being the absolute subsists along with absolute knowing, and so too
the absolute itself. 2. Of the absolute [itself ] there is no thought and no being, hence also
no subject and no object, but the absolute is exactly and only what is absolute, without
any further determination. But this very absolute, by virtue of the necessary form of its
essence, which is absolute ideality, posits itself objectively, i.e., it posits its own proper
substance which in contrast to the object now takes on the character of the subject, of
the innite; it posits its own substance as innite within the nite, but, conversely, for
this very reason, it posits the nite within itself as inniteand both in one act. This
is the way the innite and the nite originate from the absolute, namely through its
own subject-objectication (not an origination in time, however, but an eternal one).
In this respect, the absolute is determined as that which is intrinsically neither thought
nor being, but which, for that very reason, is absolute. Since reason is challenged to
conceive the absolute neither as thought nor as being but still to think it, a contradiction
arises for reection, since for it everything is either a case of thinking or one of being.
But intellectual intuition enters into even this contradiction and produces the absolute.
In this breakthrough lies the luminous point where the absolute is positively intuited.
(Intellectual intuition is therefore merely negative within reection) Through this positive
intuition, philosophical construction as such is rst made possible, or exhibition in the
absolute, which is the same thing; this is the topic of IV. Authors note.
296. Vorstellung [Tr.]
297. The recurring antithesis of the universal and particular thus is resolved itself
in that each of them is established, the universal and the particular, and with the rst
identity is posited the second. Every particular within the absolute is itself this (the
absolute), i.e., the unity of the innite and the nite, only intuited in a particular form.
The particular forms are = possibilities within the universal identity of the nite and the
innite. These possibilities are to be explained in their innite ramications. Authors note.
298. Gleichheit [Tr.]
299. Ineinsbildung; the term also resonates with Einbildungskraft (imagination). [Tr.]
300. In eins gebildet [Tr.]
301. Wesenheit [Tr.]
302. der Art nach [Tr.]
303. Seyn [Tr.]
304. In-eins-Bildung [Tr.]
305. wirklichen [Tr.]
Notes to Schelling Texts 263
a particular object. But the objection considers a concept that is opposed to the object,
which is not the case in the idea. Every particular object is in its absolute status idea,
and accordingly the idea is also the absolute object itself, just as the absolutely ideal is
the absolutely real. Authors note.
321. Demonstration, a term, like many of Schellings technical vocabulary, borrowed
from English. [Tr.]
322. See Presentation of My System, 117, but especially 17, Corollary 2. [Tr.]
323. Erwiesen [Tr.]
324. It is not yet idealism to say that the world of sense is nothing. Authors note.
325. wirkliche. Actuality is the second of Kants three modal categories, all of
which are predicated of appearances, so it does not connote ontological status. [Tr.]
326. For the actual originates precisely through this separation of form from
essence, from the in-itself, from the universe. Authors note.
327. On this matter compare the comment [Schelling made] later in Einleitung
in die Philosophie der Mythologie, [F. W. J. Schelling, Werke, Vol. XI,] p. 370, n. 1. Ed.
328. Wesenheit [Tr.]
Select Bibliography
Translations of Correspondence
].G. Fichte/F.W.J. Schelling: Carteggio e scritti polemici. Edited and translated into Italian
by F. Moiso. Naples: Prismi, 1986.
].G. Fichte et F.W.J. Schelling: Correspondance (17941802). Edited and translated into
French by Myriam Bienenstock. Paris: P.U.F., 1991.
Selections from FichteSchelling Correspondence 18001801. Trans. E. Mittman and
Mary R. Strand. In: Schulte-Sasse, Jochen et al. Theory as Practice: a Critical
Anthology of Early German Romantic Writings. Minneapolis: University of Min-
nesota Press, 1996, pp. 7389.
FichteSchelling. Correspondencia completa. Edited and translated into Spanish by Ral
Gutirrez and Hugo Ochoa. PdF le, electronic publication.
WORKS OF J. G. FICHTE
Fichtes Werke. Ed. I.H. Fichte, 11 volumes, reprint of edition of 18341846. Berlin: de
Gruyter, 1971. [= SW]
J. G. Fichte: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Eds. Reinhard
Lauth, Hans Jacobs, Hans Gliwitzky, Erich Fuchs et al., 42 volumes. Stuttgart-
265
266 Select Bibliography
[Ankndigung:] Seit sechs Jahren (dated November 4, 1800). First published: Beilage no.
1, Allgemeine Zeitung, January 24, 1801, pp. 14. Reprint (1988): GA I/7: 153164.
Neue Bearbeitung der Wissenschaftslehre (1800). Extract pp. 331367. Text rst
published in 1979 in: GA II/5: 331401.
Bei der Lectre von Schellings tr. Idealismus (1800). First published Werke XI: 368369.
Reprint 1979 in: GA II/5: 413415.
Vorarbeiten gegen Schelling (1801). First published in 1979. In: GA II/5: 483485.
Zur Darstellung von Schellings Identittssysteme (1801). First published in Werke XI:
371389. Reprint 1979, GA II/5: 487508.
The Science of Knowledge (1794). Ed. and trans. P. Heath and J. Lachs. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1982.
A la lecture de lidalisme. Trans. Myriam Bienenstock. In: J.G. Fichte et F.W.J. Schelling:
Correspondance (17941802). Paris: P.U.F., 1991, pp. 151153.
Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre) nova methodo. Trans. and ed.
Daniel Breazeale. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992.
Early Philosophical Writings. Trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1988, 2nd ed., 1993. [= EPW]
Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings (17971800). Ed. and trans.
Daniel Breazeale. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994. [= IW]
Sur lexposition du systme de lidentit de Schelling. Translated into French by
E. Cattin. In: Schelling, Exposition de mon systme de la philosophie. Paris: Vrin,
2000, pp. 173187.
Foundations of Natural Right. Ed. Frederick Neuhouser & tr. Michael Baur. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2000. [= FNR]
The System of Ethics in accordance with the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre. Eds. and
trans. Daniel Breazeale and Gnter Zller. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2005. [= SE]
The Science of Knowing: Fichtes 1804 Lectures on the Wissenschaftslehre. Trans. Walter E.
Wright. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2005.
J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (17981800). Eds. and trans. Yolanda Estes and
Curtis Bowman. Ashgate, May 2010.
WORKS OF F. W. J. SCHELLING
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schellings Smmtliche Werke. Edited by K.F.A. Schelling. Stutt-
gart: Cotta, 185661. [= SW].
Select Bibliography 267
Ameriks, Karl, ed. The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000.
Asmuth, C., Denker, A., & Vater, M., eds. Schelling: Zwischen Fichte und Hegel. Amster-
dam and Philadelphia: Grner/Benjamin, 2000.
Beiser, Frederick. German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 17811801. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002.
Bowie, Andrew. Schelling and Modern European Philosophy: An Introduction. London:
Routledge, 1993.
268 Select Bibliography
A = A (see also identity), 98, 106, 124, posited as the form of one being, 256
125, 126, 127, 128, 133, 139, 148, primordially one, 163
149, 150, 151, 152, 154, 156, 157, real subsistence of, 165
160, 161, 169, 245, 250, 251, 253 A2 = (A = B)
A = B (see also dierence), 131, 132 expresses equilibrium in excitation, or
133, 152, 155, 157, 158, 160, 161, health, 201
162, 163, 165, 166, 167, 175, 176, expresses sensitivity and capacity for
253, 258 indierence, 201
A as attractive force, 164 ground of existence of absolute iden-
A as innite, returned from B, 164 tity as organism, 200
A as objectivity, 253 A3 = [A2 = (A = B)], absolute identity
A as subjectivity, 253 as ground precedes its existence as
A the ideal principle which cognizes organism, 200
B, 158 abolish, (see also annul, cancel, suspend),
A the limiting factor, 158 148, 155, 222, 223
B as repulsive force, 164 abolition, 209
B the factor that moves outward, 164 absolute
B the limitable factor, 158 being, 12, 113, 255
B the real principle, that which origi- cognition, 209
nally is, 158 consciousness, 57, 101
as immediate object of A2, 168 identity (see also indierence), 12, 19,
being of, 167, 168 106, 123, 124, 125, 126, 127, 128,
in conict with A2, 168 129, 130, 131, 132, 133, 138, 139,
signies a determinate potency, 254 148, 149, 151, 152, 153, 154, 156,
under form of subsistence of A and B, 157, 159, 161, 162, 163n, 164,
178 165, 174, 175, 178, 197, 199, 200,
A and B 205n, 224, 225, 250, 251, 253,
as factors of cohesions, 175 257
being of, 164, 165, 174 appearance of, 148
in quantitative dierence, 163, 164 as A2, 176
jointly posited, 165 as A3, 197
posited as subsisting in all potencies, as actual in light, 174, 175
160 as cause of the organism, 199
271
272 Index
intuition, 14, 15, 18, 56, 60, 72, 88, 90, Copernican Revolution, 2, 3
98, 99, 103, 107, 110, 112, 114, Critique of Practical Reason, 3
115, 116, 135, 212 Critique of Pure Reason, 2, 18, 78,
act of intuiting, 212 229, 244, 246
as identication of thought and being, Critique of the Faculty of Judgment, 3,
211 8, 18, 60, 238
formal, 109 deduction of categories, 104
ideal, 117 German philosophy after, 1, 5
immediate, 100, 101, 106, 113 Kantian idealism, 66, 67
inner intuition, 94, 95, 107 Metaphysical Foundations of the Philoso-
of absolute unity, 207 phy of Nature, 2, 3, 256
outer, 211 method in mathematics and philoso-
particular, 117 phy, 244
positive, 262 Opus posthumum, 250
product of, 110, 118 representation I think that accompa-
pure, 206 nies all acts of consciousness, 12,
real, 117 13, 100, 104
self-intuition, 106, 109, 139 repudiation of Wissenschaftslehre, 77,
sensible, 261 78, 88, 243
spatial, 209 Kepler, 261
subjective, 109, 121 Kielmeyer, 189, 259
universal, 105, 106 Kierkegaard, 5
iron, 170, 171, 178, 179, 190, 190n, Kisser, 248
204, 205 Klopstock, 28, 232
amount of iron in earth, 180 knowing, 45, 46, 95, 96, 120, 128, 220,
as the in itself of carbon and nitro- 261
gen, 194 as identity of knower and known, 13
attacked by acids, 197 certainty of, 86
depotentiated, 195 of the absolute, 210
metamorphosis of, 171 subjective context of, 216
irrational, the, 117 knowledge, 63, 72, 73, 80, 118, 119,
irrefutability, 77, 90, 91 120, 121, 122, 128, 218, 219
irritability, 140 absolute, 73, 128, 211, 220, 221, 262,
263
Jacobi, 7, 27, 28, 29, 39, 48, 77, 78, archetypal, 261
79, 92, 227, 244, 245 connected to a nite object, 207
Jean Paul (J. P. F. Richter), 88, 245 nite, 208
judgment, 127, 144n human, 218
reexive, 43, 47 ordinary, 206, 207
subsuming, 43, 47 organ of, 206
of the absolute, 263
Kant, 36, 59, 87, 91, 102, 138, 143, particular, 219
202, 227, 228, 243, 244, 256, 264 philosophical, 121
antinomies of reason, 62 projection of, 121
Clarication regarding Fichtes Wissen- relative, 72, 209
schaftslehre, 243, 245 Kroner, 227
Index 287
logic, 16, 44, 46, 77, 89, 137, 139 male sex, 203
inversion, 97, 152 marble, 190
logical deciency, 131 mathematical
logical forms, 127 cognition, 261
of appearances, 137 proof, 98
luminous object mathematics, 77, 207
displacement of, 182 postulates and theorems of, 89
two branches of, 223
magnet, 171, 176, 184, 165, 185, 186, mathesis, 18, 78, 79, 87, 88
255, 257, 258 mathesis of mathesis, 87, 244
as a totality in reference to itself, 190 mathesis of mind, 102
degree of coherence in dierent points mathesis of reason, 89
of, 177 philosophical, 79
empirical magnet (also see iron), 171 matter, 16, 133, 137, 138, 140, 162,
negative side, 170 163, 163n, 167, 196, 222, 254,
of the two electricities, 186 260
opposite sides of, 171, 172 animated, 201
organic, 203 as externally dierent, 185
positive side, 170 as identity under the form of the line,
total-magnet, 171, 187 169
universal magnet, 171 as internally identical, 194
magnetic as magnet, 169
attraction, 254 as real, 163n
line, 177 as relatively indierent, 185
moment, 259 as simply nothing, 163n
needle, 170, 177 common features with the innite,
poles of, 177 163n
process, 194 construction of, 166, 256, 261
repulsion, 254 depotentiation of, 196
magnetism, 47, 139, 140, 169, 170, essence of, 256
185, 187, 190, 180n, 256, 257, ideality-reality of, 166
259 imponderable, 192
as cohesion actively conceived, 169 inorganic, 201
contained in electricity, 189 primordiality of, 163
moment of, 191 posited under quantitative dierence
M, 172 in the individual, 178
+M, 172 posited under quantitative indierence
only indierent bodies magnetized, in the universe, 178
190 potentiation of matter, 196
propagation of, 184 potency-less state of, 185
two forms of, 179 quantity of, 179
magnitude terrestrial, 178
absolute, 179 matters [chemical elements], 171
discrete, 180 Mayer, 228, 263
extensive, 180 mechanism, 250
Maimonides, 8, 228 mediation, 187, 220
Index 289
Schelling (continued) 41, 43, 50, 59, 68, 69, 70, 231,
122133, 135, 136, 137, 137138, 232, 233, 234, 236, 240, 242
138, 141205, 223, 230, 236, 237, Critical Yearbooks of German Litera-
238, 239, 247, 249, 250, 264 ture proposed, 19, 29, 35, 232,
outline of, 139, 140 234
System of Philosophy in General and Outline for a Critical Institute, 29,
Philosophy of Nature in Particular, 233
13, 229 Schlegel, Caroline, 36, 77, 230, 233,
System of Transcendental Idealism, 16, 240, 242
20, 22, 24, 28, 40, 44, 67, 81, 82, Schlegel, Friedrich, 5, 10, 29, 30, 31,
86, 119120, 137, 141, 143, 157, 32, 34, 35, 36, 37, 40, 42, 43, 48,
158, 166, 224, 231, 237, 244, 246 50, 70, 233
Zeitschrift fr spekulative Physik, 22, Schleiermacher, 1, 25, 29, 35, 39, 48,
40, 42, 47, 82, 122, 135, 157, 223, 231, 233, 234
231, 232, 234, 235, 236, 247, 248, Schlosser, 245
258, 261 Schulz, 227
Schelling and Hegel, Critical Journal of Schulze, 4, 227
Philosophy, 68, 70, 72, 229, 239, Schtz, 231
240, 241 science, 4, 44, 61, 91, 92, 95, 141, 144n,
Schellings 211, 212, 219, 220, 223, 225
conception of a separate philosophy of absolute, 261, 262
nature, 100, 120 absolute character of, 217
conception of the absolute, 83 body of a science, 216
relation to Wissenschaftslehre, 132, 242 empirical, 136
schema rst principles of, 216
of basic forms of dynamic process, scientic
189 certitude, 83, 87
of change, 126 reductionism, 249
of chemical process, 196 second existent (see also organism), 200,
of cohesion, 180 260
of magnetism, 172 seeing, 56, 61, 73, 121
of relative duplicity, 172 indierence within dierence, 206
of the angle, 162 the evidence in all evidence, 207
of the line, 160 the innite in the nite, 206
of the manifold, 126 the truth in all truth, 207
of the potencies, 161, 162 universal in particular, 206
schematism, 224 self-activity, 139
original, 214 self-cognizing, 151
particular, 215 absolute self-cognition, 161
Schiller, 29, 43, 47, 50, 71, 137, 234, innite self-cognition, 161
235 self-comprehension, 112, 211
On the Aesthetic Education of Man in a self-consciousness, 17, 19, 47, 82, 96,
Series of Letters, 8 98, 112, 115, 120, 257
Xenien, 144n, 236 ideal, 114, 115
Schlegel, August Wilhelm, 24, 25, 26, immediate, 101, 108, 111, 112, 114
28, 29, 30, 33, 34, 35, 37, 38, 39, real, 114
Index 297
Voltaire, 6 wiling, 8, 11
wisdom, 211
warming, 183 Wissenschaftslehre, 8, 11, 15, 16, 19, 42,
water, 177, 178, 179, 184, 185, 186, 44, 45, 46, 48, 54, 55, 58, 59, 61,
187, 195, 196, 197, 204, 205, 258 63, 66, 72, 73, 74, 79, 88, 90, 91,
as uid magnet, 191 102, 109, 117, 116, 118, 135, 136,
can be introduced in any conductive 144, 233, 235, 243
process, 184 and Kants critical philosophy, 77, 88,
deoxidization of, 186 243
incapable of enduring polarity, 179 and mathematics, 77, 79, 89
potentiated by E (oxidized), 193 as logic, 243
potentiated by +E, 193 as mathesis of mathesis, 79
separated into oxygen and hydrogen, as science of science, 245
191 Woltmann, 27, 29, 34, 35, 231, 232
transformations of, 179 word, 95, 98, 108
weight, 259 world
Werner, 245 actual, 223
whole, the (see also totality) 132, 151, ideal, 257
153, 155, 162, 166, 176, 177, 198, material, 257
215 particular, 218
absolute whole, 185 sensible, 261, 264
whole-part, 192 world-intuition, 214
will, innite (see also God), 11 world-totality, 218
This page intentionally left blank.
This page intentionally left blank.
This page intentionally left blank.
PHILOSOPHY
Also published by SUNY PRESS Also published by SUNY PRESS
The Philosophical
delve further into this area, whether it is to learn
The Berlin Lectures Vater and Wood have given us a real gift: a strong and philosophically provocative edition of this
more about Schelling or to investigate Freydbergs
F. W. J. Schelling indispensible exchange. A thoughtful and very helpful essay that puts many of the issues into a fresh
interpretations. German Studies Review
Translated and with an Introduction and philosophical perspective precedes the letters, and some of the important primary texts germane to this
Notes by Bruce Matthews debate follow them. For lovers of German idealism, this is a text of great interest and its appearance
THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN
Rupture between
The rst English translation of Schellings nal calls for celebration.
FICHTES AND SCHELLINGS
existential system. Jason M. Wirth, author of The Conspiracy of Life: Meditations on Schelling and His Time
SYSTEM OF PHILOSOPHY
Michael G. Vater is Associate Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Marquette University. He translated An English Translation of G. W. F. Hegels
PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS and edited Schellings Bruno or On the Natural and Divine Principle of Things, also published by SUNY Differenz des Fichteschen und Schellingschen
INTO THE ESSENCE OF
SUNY
P R E S S Life as the Schema of Freedom
State University of
New York Press Bruce Matthews
www.sunypress.edu
Locates in Schelling a new understanding of our
relation to nature in philosophy.