Damodaram Sanjivayya National Law University Visakhapatnam, A.P., India

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 21

DAMODARAM SANJIVAYYA NATIONAL LAW

UNIVERSITY
VISAKHAPATNAM, A.P., INDIA

PROJECT TITLE

Public Goods

SUBJECT

Economics

NAME OF THE FACULTY


ABHISHEKH SINHA

Name of the Student: J. Bhanu


Roll No. 2016042
2nd semester

1
Acknowledgement

I would sincerely like to put forward my heartfelt appreciation to my respected professor, Prof.
Abhishekh Sinha for giving us a golden opportunity to take up the project regarding Public Goods
. I had tried my best to collect information about the project in various possible ways to depict
clear picture about the given project topic

2
Table of Contents
1.Introduction
2.Terminlogy and types of goods
3.Economic and Political Solutions
4.Free Rider Problem
5.Conclusion

3
Introduction:

In economics, a public good is a good that is both non-excludable and non-rivalrous in that
individuals cannot be effectively excluded from use and where use by one individual does not
reduce availability to others. Gravelle and Rees: "The defining characteristic of a public good is that
consumption of it by one individual does not actually or potentially reduce the amount available to
be consumed by another individual." In a non-economic sense, the term is often used to describe
something that is useful for the public generally, such as education and infrastructure, although these
are not "public goods" in the economic sense. This is in contrast to a common good which is non-
excludable but is rivalrous to a certain degree.

Public goods include fresh air, knowledge, official statistics, national security, common language(s),
flood control systems, lighthouses, and street lighting. Public goods that are available everywhere
are sometimes referred to as global public goods.There is an important conceptual difference
between the sense of 'a' public good, or public 'goods' in economics, and the more generalized idea
of 'the public good' (or common good, or public interest), the public good is a shorthand signal for
shared benefit at a societal level [this] (philosophical/political) sense should not be reduced to the
established specific (economic) sense of a public good.

Many public goods may at times be subject to excessive use resulting in negative
externalities affecting all users; for example air pollution and traffic congestion. Public goods
problems are often closely related to the "free-ride" problem, in which people not paying for the
good may continue to access it. Thus, the good may be under-produced, overused or degraded.
[6]
Public goods may also become subject to restrictions on access and may then be considered to
be club goods or private goods; exclusion mechanisms include copyright, patents, congestion
pricing, and pay television.

There is a good deal of debate and literature on how to measure the significance of public goods
problems in an economy, and to identify the best remedies.

Terminology and types of goods:

Paul A. Samuelson is usually credited as the first economist to develop the theory of public goods.
In his classic 1954 paper The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure, he defined a public good, or as he
called it in the paper a "collective consumption good", as follows:

4
[goods] which all enjoy in common in the sense that each individual's consumption of such a good
leads to no subtractions from any other individual's consumption of that good...

This is the property that has become known as non-rivalry. In addition a pure public good exhibits a
second property called non-excludability: that is, it is impossible to exclude any individuals from
consuming the good.

The opposite of a public good is a private good, which does not possess these properties. A loaf of
bread, for example, is a private good; its owner can exclude others from using it, and once it has
been consumed, it cannot be used again.

A good that is rivalrous but non-excludable is sometimes called a common-pool resource. Such
goods raise similar issues to public goods: the mirror to the public goods problemfor this case is
sometimes called the "tragedy of the commons". For example, it is so difficult to enforce restrictions
on deep sea fishing that the world's fish stocks can be seen as a non-excludable resource, but one
which is finite and diminishing.

Definition Matrix:

V. Ostrom and E. Ostrom proposed additional modifications to the classification of goods to identify
fundamental differences that affect the incentives facing individuals (1) Replacing the term rivalry
of consumption with subtractability of use. (2) Conceptualizing subtractability of use and
excludability to vary from low to high rather than characterizing them as either present or absent.
(3) Overtly adding a very important fourth type of goodcommon-pool resourcesthat shares the
attribute of subtractability

with private goods and difficulty of exclusion with public goods. Forests, water systems, fisheries,
and the global atmosphere are all common-pool resources of immense importance for the survival of
humans on this earth. (4) Changing the name of a club good to a toll good since many goods
that share these characteristics are provided by small scale public as well as private associations.

Challenges in identifying public goods:

The definition of non-excludability states that it is impossible to exclude individuals from


consumption. Technology now allows radio or TV broadcasts to be encrypted such that persons
without a special decoder are excluded from the broadcast. Many forms of information goods have
characteristics of public goods. For example, a poem can be read by many people without reducing

5
the consumption of that good by others; in this sense, it is non-rivalrous. Similarly, the information
in most patents can be used by any party without reducing consumption of that good by
others. Official statistics provide a clear example of information goods that are public goods, since
they are created to be non-excludable. Creative works may be excludable in some circumstances,
however: the individual who wrote the poem may decline to share it with others by not publishing
it. Copyrights and patents both encourage the creation of such non-rival goods by providing
temporary monopolies, or, in the terminology of public goods, providing a legal mechanism to
enforce excludability for a limited period of time. For public goods, the "lost revenue" of the
producer of the good is not part of the definition: a public good is a good whose consumption does
not reduce any other's consumption of that good

Debate has been generated among economists whether such a category of "public goods"
exists. Steven Shavell has suggested the following:

when professional economists talk about public goods they do not mean that there are a general
category of goods that share the same economic characteristics, manifest the same dysfunctions, and
that may thus benefit from pretty similar corrective solutions...there is merely an infinite series of
particular problems (some of overproduction, some of underproduction, and so on), each with a
particular solution that cannot be deduced from the theory, but that instead would depend on local
empirical factors

Common confusion is that public goods are goods provided by the public sector. Although it is often
the case that government is involved in producing public goods, this is not necessarily the case.
Public goods may be naturally available. They may be produced by private individuals and firms,
by non-state collective action, or they may not be produced at all.

The theoretical concept of public goods does not distinguish with regard to the geographical region
in which a good may be produced or consumed. However, some theorists such as Inge Kaul use the
term "global public good" for public goods which is non-rival and non-excludable throughout the
whole world, as opposed to a public good which exists in just one national area. Knowledge has
been held to be an example of a global public good but also as a commons, the knowledge
commons.

Graphically, non-rivalry means that if each of several individuals has a demand curve for a public
good, then the individual demand curves are summed vertically to get the aggregate demand curve
for the public good. This is in contrast to the procedure for deriving the aggregate demand for a
private good, where individual demands are summed horizontally.

6
Social goods are defined as public goods that could be delivered as private goods, but are usually
delivered by the government for various reasons, including social policy, and funded via public
funds like taxes. Note that some writers have used the term "public good" to refer only to non-
excludable "pure public goods" and refer to excludable public goods as "club goods".

Examples

Common examples of public goods include: defence, public fireworks, lighthouses, clean air and
other environmental goods, and information goods, such as official statistics, software
development, authorship, and invention. Some goods, like orphan drugs, require special
governmental incentives to be produced, but can't be classified as public goods since they don't
fulfill the above requirements (non-excludable and non-rivalrous.) Law enforcement, streets,
libraries, museums, and education are commonly misclassified as public goods, but they are
technically classified in economic terms as quasi-public goods because excludability is possible, but
they do still fit some of the characteristics of public goods.

The provision of a lighthouse is a standard example of a public good, since it is difficult to exclude
ships from using its services. No ship's use detracts from that of others, but since most of the benefit
of a lighthouse accrues to ships using particular ports, lighthouse maintenance can be profitably
bundled with port fees (Ronald Coase, The Lighthouse in Economics 1974). This has been sufficient
to fund actual lighthouses.

Technological progress can create new public goods. The most simple examples are street lights,
which are relatively recent inventions (by historical standards). One person's enjoyment of them
does not detract from other persons' enjoyment, and it currently would be prohibitively expensive to
charge individuals separately for the amount of light they presumably use. Official statistics are
another example. The government's ability to collect, process and provide high-quality information
to guide decision-making at all levels has been strongly advanced by technological progress. On the
other hand, a public good's status may change over time. Technological progress can significantly
impact excludability of traditional public goods: encryption allows broadcasters to sell individual
access to their programming. The costs for electronic road pricing have fallen dramatically, paving
the way for detailed billing based on actual use.

Some question as to whether defense is a public good. Murray Rothbard argues, "'national defense'
is surely not an absolute good with only one unit of supply. It consists of specific resources
committed in certain definite and concrete waysand these resources are necessarily scarce. A ring
of defense bases around New York, for example, cuts down the amount possibly available around
San Francisco."[16] Jeffrey Rogers Hummel and Don Lavoie note, "Americans
7
in Alaska and Hawaii could very easily be excluded from the U.S. government's defense perimeter,
and doing so might enhance the military value of at least conventional U.S. forces to Americans in
the other forty-eight states. But, in general, an additional ICBM in the U.S. arsenal can
simultaneously protect everyone within the country without diminishing its services".

Public goods are not restricted to human beings Indeed, it is one aspect of the study of cooperation
in biology.

Free Rider problem

Public goods provide a very important example of market failure, in which market-like behavior of
individual gain-seeking does not produce efficient results. The production of public goods results in
positive externalities which are not remunerated. If private organizations do not reap all the benefits
of a public good which they have produced, their incentives to produce it voluntarily might be
insufficient. Consumers can take advantage of public goods without contributing sufficiently to their
creation. This is called the free rider problem, or occasionally, the "easy rider problem" (because
consumers' contributions will be small but non-zero). If too many consumers decide to "free-ride",
private costs exceed private benefits and the incentive to provide the good or service through the
market disappears. The market thus fails to provide a good or service for which there is a need.

The free rider problem depends on a conception of the human being as homo economicus: purely
rational and also purely selfishextremely individualistic, considering only those benefits and costs
that directly affect him or her. Public goods give such a person an incentive to be a free rider.

For example, consider national defense, a standard example of a pure public good. Suppose homo
economicus thinks about exerting some extra effort to defend the nation. The benefits to the
individual of this effort would be very low, since the benefits would be distributed among all of the
millions of other people in the country. There is also a very high possibility that he or she could get
injured or killed during the course of his or her military service.

On the other hand, the free rider knows that he or she cannot be excluded from the benefits of
national defense, regardless of whether he or she contributes to it. There is also no way that these
benefits can be split up and distributed as individual parcels to people. The free rider would not
voluntarily exert any extra effort, unless there is some inherent pleasure or material reward for doing
so (for example, money paid by the government, as with an all-volunteer army or mercenaries). The
free-riding problem is even more complicated than it was thought to be until recently. Any time non-

8
excludability results in failure to pay the true marginal value (often called the "demand revelation
problem"), it will also result in failure to generate proper income levels, since households will not
give up valuable leisure if they cannot individually increment a good. This implies that, for public
goods without strong special interest support, under-provision is likely since benefit-cost analyses
are being conducted at the wrong income levels, and all of the ungenerated income would have been
spent on the public good, apart from general equilibrium considerations.

In the case of information goods, an inventor of a new product may benefit all of society, but hardly
anyone is willing to pay for the invention if they can benefit from it for free. In the case of an
information good, however, because of its characteristics of non-excludability and also because of
almost zero reproduction costs, commoditization is difficult and not always efficient even from a
neoclassical economic point of view.

Economic and political solutions:

An assurance contract is a contract in which participants make a binding pledge to contribute to


building a public good, contingent on a quorum of a predetermined size being reached. Otherwise
the good is not provided and any monetary contributions are refunded.

A dominant assurance contract is a variation in which an entrepreneur creates the contract and
refunds the initial pledge plus an additional sum of money if the quorum is not reached. (The
entrepreneur profits by collecting a fee if the quorum is reached and the good is provided.) In game-
theoretic terms this makes pledging to build the public good a dominant strategy: the best move is to
pledge to the contract regardless of the actions of others.

Coasian solution

A Coasian solution, named for the economist Ronald Coase, proposes that potential beneficiaries of
a public good can negotiate to pool their resources and create it, based on each party's self-interested
willingness to pay. His treatise, "The Problem of Social Cost" (1960), argued that if the transaction
costs between potential beneficiaries of a public good are lowthat it is easy for potential
beneficiaries to find each other and organize a pooling their resources based upon the good's value
to each of themthat public goods could be produced without government action.

Much later, Coase himself wrote that while what had become known as the Coase Theorem had
explored the implications of zero transaction costs, he had actually intended to use this construct as
a stepping-stone to understand the real world of positive transaction costs, corporations, legal
systems and government actions.,

9
I examined what would happen in a world in which transaction costs were assumed to be zero. My
aim in doing so was not to describe what life would be like in such a world but to provide a simple
setting in which to develop the analysis and, what was even more important, to make clear the
fundamental role which transaction costs do, and should, play in the fashioning of the institutions
which make up the economic system.

and,

The world of zero transaction costs has often been described as a Coasian world. Nothing could be
further from the truth. It is the world of modern economic theory, one which I was hoping to
persuade economists to leave. What I did in The Problem of Social Cost was simply to shed light
on some of its properties. I argued in such a world the allocation of resources would be independent
of the legal position, a result which Stigler dubbed the Coase theorem. [...]

Thus, while Coase himself appears to have considered the "Coase theorem" and Coasian solutions
as simplified constructs to ultimately consider the real 20th-century world of governments and laws
and corporations, these concepts have become attached to a world where transaction costs were
much lower, and government intervention would unquestionably be less necessary. Is there room in
the 21st century for something closer to this ideal?

A minor alternative, especially for information goods, is for the producer to refuse to release a good
to the public until payment to cover costs is met. Author Stephen King, for instance, authored
chapters of a new novel downloadable for free on his website while stating that he would not release
subsequent chapters unless a certain amount of money was raised. Sometimes dubbed holding for
ransom, this method of public goods production is a modern application of the street performer
protocol for public goods production. Unlike assurance contracts, its success relies largely on social
norms to ensure (to some extent) that the threshold is reached and partial contributions are not
wasted.

One of the purest Coasian solutions today is the new phenomenon of Internet crowdfunding. Here
rules are enforced by computer algorithms and legal contracts as well as social pressure. For
example, on the Kickstarter site, each funder authorizes a credit card purchase to buy a new product
or receive other promised benefits, but no money changes hands until the funding goal is
met. Because automation and the Internet so reduce the transaction costs for pooling resources,
project goals of only a few hundred dollars are frequently crowdfunded, far below the costs of
soliciting traditional investors. Other crowdfunded projects have raised over a million dollars, like
the Arkyd-100 space satellite telescope funded on Kickstarter in June 2013. It would seem to be a
clear instance of a Coase solution when a public good that always required government sponsorship
10
in the 20th century can be efficiently organized from 18,000 individuals' self-interest (including
rewards such as an orbital "selfie", and five minutes of observation time donated in their name to
find potential killer asteroids).

Government provision

If voluntary provision of public goods will not work, then the obvious solution is making their
provision involuntary. This saves each of us from our own tendency to be a free rider, while also
assuring us that no one else will be allowed to free ride. One frequently proposed solution to the
problem is for governments or states to impose taxation to fund the production of public goods. This
does not actually solve the theoretical problem because good government is itself a public good.
Thus it is difficult to ensure the government has an incentive to provide the optimum amount even if
it were possible for the government to determine precisely what amount would be optimum. These
issues are studied by public choice theory and public finance.

Sometimes the government provides public goods using "unfunded mandates". An example is the
requirement that every car be fit with a catalytic converter. This may be executed in the private
sector, but the end result is predetermined by the state: the individually involuntary provision of the
public good clean air. Unfunded mandates have also been imposed by the U.S. federal government
on the state and local governments, as with the Americans with Disabilities Act, for example.

Regardless the role of the government is provide vital goods to all individuals, some of which they
cannot obtain on themselves. In order to ensure that government services are properly funded taxes
and other government controlled entities are enforced. Although enforced taxes deter the free-rider
problem many contend that some goods should be excluded and made into private goods. However,
this not possible with all goods such as pure public goods that are inseparable and inclusive, thus
require "provision by public means". In short, the government has a responsibility to ensure that the
social welfare of individuals is met as opposed to privatized goods

Subsidies and joint products

A government may subsidize production of a public good in the private sector. Unlike government
provision, subsidies may result in some form of a competitive market. The potential
for cronyism (for example, an alliance between political insiders and the businesses receiving
subsidies) can be limited with secret bidding for the subsidies or application of the subsidies
following clear general principles. Depending on the nature of a public good and a related
subsidy, principalagent problems can arise between the citizens and the government or between the

11
government and the subsidized producers; this effect and counter-measures taken to address it can
diminish the benefits of the subsidy.

Subsidies can also be used in areas with a potential for non-individualism: For instance, a state may
subsidize devices to reduce air pollution and appeal to citizens to cover the remaining costs.

Similarly, a joint-product model analyzes the collaborative effect of joining a private good to a
public good. For example, a tax deduction (private good) can be tied to a donation to a charity
(public good). It can be shown that the provision of the public good increases when tied to the
private good, as long as the private good is provided by a monopoly (otherwise the private good
would be provided by competitors without the link to the public good).

Privileged group

The study of collective action shows that public goods are still produced when one individual
benefits more from the public good than it costs him to produce it; examples include benefits from
individual use, intrinsic motivation to produce, and business models based on selling complement
goods. A group that contains such individuals is called a privileged group. A historical example
could be a downtown entrepreneur who erects a street light in front of his shop to attract customers;
even though there are positive external benefits to neighboring nonpaying businesses, the added
customers to the paying shop provide enough revenue to cover the costs of the street light.

The existence of privileged groups may not be a complete solution to the free rider problem,
however, as underproduction of the public good may still result. The street light builder, for
instance, would not consider the added benefit to neighboring businesses when determining whether
to erect his street light, making it possible that the street light isn't built when the cost of building is
too high for the single entrepreneur even when the total benefit to all the businesses combined
exceeds the cost.

An example of the privileged group solution could be the Linux community, assuming that users
derive more benefit from contributing than it costs them to do it. For more discussion on this topic
see also Coase's Penguin.

Another example is those musicians and writers who create music and writings for their own
personal enjoyment, and publish because they enjoy having an audience. Financial incentives are
not necessary to ensure the creation of these public goods. Whether this creates the correct
production level of writings and music is an open question.

12
Merging free riders

Another method of overcoming the free rider problem is to simply eliminate the profit incentive for
free riding by buying out all the potential free riders. A property developer that owned an entire city
street, for instance, would not need to worry about free riders when erecting street lights since he
owns every business that could benefit from the street light without paying. Implicitly, then, the
property developer would erect street lights until the marginal social benefit met the marginal social
cost. In this case, they are equivalent to the private marginal benefits and costs.

While the purchase of all potential free riders may solve the problem of underproduction due to free
riders in smaller markets, it may simultaneously introduce the problem of underproduction due
to monopoly. Additionally, some markets are simply too large to make a buyout of all beneficiaries
feasible this is particularly visible with public goods that affect everyone in a country.

Introducing an exclusion mechanism (club goods)

Another solution, which has evolved for information goods, is to introduce exclusion mechanisms
which turn public goods into club goods. One well-known example is copyright and patent laws.
These laws, which in the 20th century came to be called intellectual property laws, attempt to
remove the natural non-excludability by prohibiting reproduction of the good. Although they can
address the free rider problem, the downside of these laws is that they imply private monopoly
power and thus are not Pareto-optimal.

For example, in the United States, the patent rights given to pharmaceutical companies encourage
them to charge high prices (above marginal cost) and to advertise to convince patients to persuade
their doctors to prescribe the drugs]. Likewise, copyright provides an incentive for a publisher to act
like The Dog in the Manger, taking older works out of print so as not to cannibalize revenue from
the publisher's own new works.

The laws also end up encouraging patent and copyright owners to sue even mild imitators in court
and to lobby for the extension of the term of the exclusive rights in a form of rent seeking.

These problems with the club-good mechanism arise because the underlying marginal cost of giving
the good to more people is low or zero, but, because of the limits of price discrimination those who
are unwilling or unable to pay a profit-maximizing price do not gain access to the good.

If the costs of the exclusion mechanism are not higher than the gain from the collaboration, club
goods can emerge naturally. James M. Buchanan showed in his seminal paper that clubs can be an
efficient alternative to government interventions.

13
On the other hand, the inefficiencies and inequities of club goods exclusions sometimes cause
potentially excludable club goods to be treated as public goods, and their production financed by
some other mechanism. Examples of such "natural" club goods include natural monopolies with
very high fixed costs, private golf courses, cinemas, cable television and social clubs. This explains
why many such goods are often provided or subsidized by governments, co-operatives or volunteer
associations, rather than being left to be supplied by profit-minded entrepreneurs. These goods are
often known as social goods.

Joseph Schumpeter claimed that the "excess profits", or profits over normal profit, generated by the
copyright or patent monopoly will attract competitors that will make technological innovations and
thereby end the monopoly. This is a continual process referred to as "Schumpeterian creative
destruction", and its applicability to different types of public goods is a source of some controversy.
The supporters of the theory point to the case of Microsoft, for example, which has been increasing
its prices (or lowering its products' quality), predicting that these practices will make increased
market shares for Linux and Apple largely inevitable.

A nation can be seen as a club whose members are its citizens. Government would then be the
manager of this club. This is further studied in the Theory of the State.

Altruistic solutions
Social Norms

If enough people do not think like free-riders, the private and voluntary provision of public goods
may be successful. For example, a free rider might come to a public park to enjoy its beauty, yet
discard litter that makes it less enjoyable for others. More public-spirited individuals don't do this
(they might even pick up existing litter) why? There could be several reasons. Perhaps they have
lived nearby for years and derive pleasure from helping their community, or at least would feel
ashamed if their neighbors or friends saw them. Perhaps they are emotionally attached to the
environment, or the park is a national treasure; littering it would offend their patriotism. To the
extent that most people behave like this (for any reason), a public good is produced: everyone
enjoys a clean park, without the government needing to spend tax money on maintenance crews.

Good or bad social behavior is contagious: people unconsciously adapt their behavior to that of their
peers. Even people who engaged in free-riding by littering elsewhere are less likely to if they see
others hold on to their trash.

Social norms can also be observed everywhere people interact, not only in physical spaces but in
virtual communities on the Internet. Lawrence Lessig describes how social norms can regulate

14
behavior in cyberspace: through an individual's perceptions from the (physical or virtual)
surrounding community. For example, if a disabled person boards a crowded bus, everyone expects
that some able-bodied person will volunteer their seat. The same social norm, although executed in a
different environment, can also be applied to the Internet. If a user enters a discussion in a chat room
and continues to use ALL CAPITAL LETTERS or make personal attacks ("flames") when
addressing other users, the culprit may realize he or she has been blocked by other participants. As
in real life, users learning to adapt to the social norms of cyberspace communities provide a public
goodhere, not suffering disruptive online behaviorfor all the participants.

Social sanctions (punishment)

Experimental literature suggests that free riding can be overcome without any state intervention.
Peer-to-peer punishment, that is, members sanction those members that do not contribute to the
public good at a cost, is sufficient to establish and maintain cooperation. Such punishment is often
considered altruistic, because it comes at a cost to the punisher, however, the exact nature remains to
be explored Whether costly punishment can explain cooperation is disputed Recent research finds
that costly punishment is less effective in real world environments. For example, punishment works
relatively badly under imperfect information, where people cannot observe the behavior of other
perfectly.

Voluntary organizations

Organizations such as the Red Cross, public radio and television or a volunteer fire
department provide public goods to the majority at the expense of a minority who voluntarily
participate or contribute funds. Contributions to online collaborative media like Wikipedia and
other wiki projects, and free software projects such as Linux are another example of relatively few
contributors providing a public good (information) freely to all readers or software users.

Proposed explanations for altruistic behavior include biological altruism and reciprocal altruism. For
example, voluntary groups such as labor unions and charities often have a federated structure,
probably in part because voluntary collaboration emerges more readily in smaller social groups than
in large ones (e.g., see Dunbar's number).

While both biological and reciprocal altruism are observed in other animals, our species' complex
social behaviors take these raw materials much farther. Philanthropy by wealthy individualssome,
such as Andrew Carnegie giving away their entire vast fortuneshave historically provided a
multitude of public goods for others. One major impact was the Rockefeller Foundation's
development of the "Green Revolution" hybrid grains that probably saved many millions of people

15
from starvation in the 1970s. Christian missionaries, who typically spend large parts of their lives in
remote, often dangerous places, have had disproportionate impact compared with their numbers
worldwide for centuries. Communist revolutionaries in the 20th century had similar dedication and
outsized impacts. International relief organizations such as Doctors Without Borders, Save the
Children and Amnesty International have benefited millions, while also occasionally costing
workers their lives. For better and for worse, humans can conceive of, and sacrifice for, an almost
infinite variety of causes in addition to their biological kin. Reciprocal altruism that leads a vampire
bat to regurgitate blood to feed a few others in its colony who fed it on previous nights when it flew
back hungry, motivates humans to build lifelong careers in huge multinational corporations and
lubricates vast systems of banking and trade and production between hundreds or thousands of
actors worldwide.

Religions and ideologies

Voluntary altruistic organizations often motivate their members by encouraging deep-seated


personal beliefs, whether religious or other (such as social justice or environmentalism) that are
taken "on faith" more than proved by rational argument. When individuals resist temptations to free
riding (e.g., stealing) because they hold these beliefs (or because they fear the disapproval of others
who do), they provide others with public goods that might be difficult or impossible to "produce" by
administrative coercion alone.

One proposed explanation for the ubiquity of religious belief in human societies is multi-level
selection: altruists often lose out within groups, but groups with more altruists win. A group whose
members believe a "practical reality" that motivates altruistic behavior may out-compete other
groups whose members' perception of "factual reality" causes them to behave selfishly. A classic
example is a soldier's willingness to fight for his tribe or country. Another example given in
evolutionary biologist David Sloan Wilson's Darwin's Cathedral is the early Christian church under
the late Roman Empire; because Roman society was highly individualistic, during frequent
epidemics many of the sick died not of the diseases per se but for lack of basic nursing. Christians,
who believed in an afterlife, were willing to nurse the sick despite the risks. Although the death rate
among the nurses was high, the average Christian had a much better chance of surviving an
epidemic than other Romans did, and the community prospered.

Religious and non-religious traditions and ideologies (such as nationalism and patriotism) are in full
view when a society is in crisis and public goods such as defense are most needed. Wartime leaders
invoke their God's protection and claim that their society's most hallowed traditions are at stake. For
example, according to President Abraham Lincoln's Gettysburg Address during the American Civil
16
War, the Union was fighting so "that government of the people, by the people, for the people, shall
not perish from the earth". Such voluntary, if exaggerated, exhortations complement forcible
measurestaxation and conscriptionto motivate people to make sacrifices for their cause.

Efficient Production Levels Of Public Goods

The Pareto optimum provision of a public good in a society is at the level where the combined sum
of the marginal rate of substitution between private goods and a given public good of all individuals
is equal to the marginal rate of transformation. This contrasts to the Pareto optimality condition of
private goods, in which each consumers' marginal rate of substitution is equal; as is the societies
marginal rate of transformation.

When should a public good be provided? Take, for example, a community of just two consumers
and the government is considering whether or not to build a public park. Arthur is prepared to pay
up to $200 for its use, while Julia is willing to pay up to $100. The total value to the two individuals
of having the park is $300. If it can be produced for $225, there is a $75 gain on its production since
it provides services that the community values at $300 at a cost of only $225.

Regardless of the method of providing public goods, the efficient level of such provision is still
being subjected to economic analysis. For instance, the Samuelson condition calculates the efficient
level of public goods production to be where the ratio of the marginal social cost of public and
private goods production equals the ratio of the marginal social benefit of public and private goods
production.

"If the amount of a public good can be varied continuously, the optimal quantity to produce is that
quantity for which the marginal cost of the last unit is just equal to the sum of the prices that all
consumers would be willing to pay for that unit." This equilibrium guarantees that the last unit of
the public good costs as much to produce as the value that it gives to all of its consumers.

Ownership

An important question regarding public goods is whether they should be owned by the public or the
private sector. Economic theorists such as Hart (1995) argue that ownership matters for investment
incentives when contracts are incomplete. The incomplete contracting paradigm has been applied to
public goods by Besley and Ghatak (2001).]They consider the government and a non-governmental

17
organization (NGO) who can both make investments to provide a public good. Who should be the
owner of the public good, the government or the NGO? Besley and Ghatak show that the party who
has a larger valuation for the public good should be the owner, regardless of whether the
government or the NGO has a better investment technology. This result contrasts with the case of
private goods studied by Hart (1995), where the party with the better investment technology should
be the owner. However, more recently it has been shown that the investment technology matters also
in the public-

good case when a party is indispensable or when there are bargaining frictions between the
government and the NGO.

Conclusion:

a public good is a good that is both non-excludable and non-rivalrous in that individuals cannot be
effectively excluded from use and where use by one individual does not reduce availability to
others. Gravelle and Rees: "The defining characteristic of a public good is that consumption of it by
one individual does not actually or potentially reduce the amount available to be consumed by
another individual." In a non-economic sense, the term is often used to describe something that is
useful for the public generally, such as education and infrastructure, although these are not "public
goods" in the economic sense. This is in contrast to a common good which is non-excludable but is
rivalrous to a certain degree. There is a good deal of debate and literature on how to measure the
significance of public goods problems in an economy, and to identify the best remedies.

18
19
20
21

You might also like