Fitzmaurice 1994
Fitzmaurice 1994
International Law
http://journals.cambridge.org/NYL
M.A. Fitzmaurice
M.A. Fitzmaurice
1. Introduction
1.1 What is special about the environment as a subject-matter?
1.1.1 General background
1.1.2 Particular aspect
1.2 Specific features of international environmental law covered in this article
4. 'Soft law'
4.1 What is meant by 'soft law'
4.2 The origins of 'soft law' in the economic field
4.3 'Soft law' in the environmental field
4.4 'Soft law' in the settlement of disputes
* © M. Fitzmaurice, 1994.
** Senior Lecturer in International Law, University of Amsterdam; Visiting Lecturer in
Environmental Law, King's College, London.
1. INTRODUCTION
There are, of course, many individual aspects which differentiate the environment
from other fields over which international law operates. As these are to a large
extent inter-related, it is difficult to arrive at a satisfactory comprehensive list
of individual aspects. For the purposes of this article, we shall be laying emphasis
on certain major aspects which appear to lie behind those features of international
environmental law which may be regarded as special. These are the following:
(i) The speed of development of the global environmental crisis, of our
scientific understanding of it and of the technology to remedy it, as well as its
intensity and its wide geographic scope.
(ii) The need, in relation to environmental problems, to balance complex
conflicting economic interests between States at widely different stages of
development. Of particular importance is the conflict which exits, in economic
terms, or at least short-term economic terms, between economic development
and environmental protection (for instance the conflict which exists between the
environmental interest of developed States to bring an end to deforestation, and
the economic interests of developing countries to continue logging as a major
source of earning foreign currency). The problems arising from these conflicts
influence many aspects of the development of international environmental law.
International environmental law 185
They are one of the factors lying behind the development of new methods of
negotiation, and of the structure, of treaties. They give rise to doubts as to
whether sufficient consensus, in terms of State practice or of the development
of opinio juris, can be achieved to arrive at adequate rules of international
customary law. These problems are also one of the major factors in the
development of the concept of 'sustainable development'.
(iii) The difficulty, in the case of environmental damage, of the restoration
of the status quo ante and/or payment of compensation for damage caused, which
has been the basis of traditional remedies for breach of international obligations.
Thus, while economic damage or related consequences are seen as being
relatively short-term in their effect, reversible, and capable of being compensated
in damages, damage to the environment has come to be seen as long-term in its
effect, even, indeed, irreversible, and consequently incapable of being
compensated in damages. An initial effect of this perception was the increasing
emphasis on the preventive element in the content of the obligation of States not
to cause environmental harm to other States, or to areas outside State jurisdiction.
But it has come to lie behind a number of other important areas of recent
development of international environmental law, such as the so-called
precautionary principle, the concepts of inter-generational equity and of
sustainable development.
(iv) The threat to the environment does not come solely, or even perhaps
principally, directly from the exercise of the political will of States, but from
the actions of private individuals and companies. On the other hand, the results
of those activities may either directly affect the daily lives of individuals living
in other States, or affect certain things, for instance by leading to the extinction
of species of flora or fauna, in which it is individuals essentially, rather than
States as such, who are perceived as having an interest. The result is that both
in terms of the imposition of obligations and of the exercise of rights, the
individual is perceived as an important, in some respects a necessary, player in
the environmental field.
Reflecting the urgency of these problems, environmental law has become one
of the most dynamic areas of international law, and is one within which there
is constant change and development. Much of this would easily fall within the
terms of reference we have described above and in order to remain within the
limited confines of an article such as this, to some extent we have had to be
selective.
186 M.A. Fitzmaurice
We shall, in the final section of this article, consider some of the most recent
developments in international environmental law, some of which at least are
resulting in theories and solutions which are stretching the bounds of traditional
international law. These include the development of treaty structures aimed at
global administration of the environment, the development of concepts of offence
against world order, and the attempts at integration within a single field of aspects
of environmental protection with economic factors incorporated in the concept
of 'sustainable development'. Within this section we shall also refer, by reason
solely of the limits of an article such as the present one, only very briefly to the
developments which are arising as a result of the importance of the individual
in the environmental field.
The sources of environmental law have included all of those enumerated in the
classic Article 38(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice. Of these,
at least until very recently, by far the most important in terms of both the quantity
and breadth of the rules that have derived from it, has been that of treaties.
Indeed, the history of the development of environmental law, as concerns both
the importance attached to it by the international community and the nature of
its content, can to a large extent be traced through the history of the conclusion
of international agreements concerning environmental issues. This history, and
the ways in which it has been influenced by the special features of the
environment are covered in section 3, but it may be noted here that the field of
the environment is one in which the striking role of treaties in its formation must
be noted.
One extremely important area of international environmental law, however,
has been developed largely on the basis of rules of international customary law
(deriving - as to which see below - from general principles of international
law). The principal rule of customary international law in this area is that
prohibiting States from causing transboundary harm to other States, a rule first
enunciated in the Trail Smelter arbitration, and more recently incorporated in
the important Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration. A number of other
obligations of States to other and - in particular neighbouring - States have
developed, or are in the course of developing, as rules of customary international
law in thefieldsof environmental law, or in the often related field of management
of shared resources. These include such things as obligations of prevention, the
provision of information and negotiation, as well as, in the field of shared
188 M.A. Fitzmaurice
4. See also P.W. Birnie and A.E. Boyle, International Law and The Environment (1992) pp.
9-32; A. Kiss and D. Shelton, International Environmental Law (1991) pp. 95-115.
International environmental law 189
the rapid growth of activities which could cause harm far outside the area where they
take place . . .'10
The point of this in considering the loss of confidence that has manifested itself
in international law making processes in the environmental field is that, granted
the concept of sovereign, independent and equal States, certain consequences
must, both as a matter of logic and as a matter of practical necessity, follow.
These consequences — or at least some of them - are capable of being, and have
been, enunciated in the form of legal principles relevant to environmental
protection; and these legal principles can be, and indeed under Article 38 of its
Statute must be, applied by the International Court of Justice. It is thus that the
future importance which Sir Robert Jennings ascribed to the combination of
general principles of law and judicial decision as sources of development of
international law comes about,11 an importance which he has recently reiterated
directly in relation to the environmental crisis.12
1972, the year of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment,
which led to the issue of the Stockholm Declaration and the establishment of the
United Nations Environmental Programme, is often taken as an approximate date
for the start of the modern era in international environmental law. The most
immediately obvious characteristic of the environmental field generally during
the period since that date has been the explosive growth in the awareness of the
environmental threat and political activity aimed at establishing a basis to meet
it. This political activity has been reflected in the development of international
environmental treaty law. The last two decades have been extremely fruitful in
the production of bilateral and multilateral conventional regimes aimed at
environmental protection and resource management either within a particular
geographical area, or in relation to particular activities, and now beginning to
aim at global protection of ecological systems. Thus, while in 1972 there were
10. R. Jennings and A. Watts, eds., Oppenheim's International Law, 9th edn., Vol. I (1992)
p. 408.
11. Loc. cit. n. 5, at p. 345.
12. Sir Robert Jennings, 'Environmental Policy and Law, 22/5/6' (1992) p. 312, (text of a
statement made by the author to the UNCED entitled "The role of the ICJ in the Development of
International Environment Protection law').
192 M.A. Fitzmaurice
13. E. Brown Weiss, 'Introductory Note, United Nations Conference on Environment and
Development', 31 ILM (1992) p. 814; E. Brown Weiss, International Environmental Law:
Contemporary Issues and the Emergence of a New World Order, 81 Georgetown LJ (1993) p. 675;
P. Malanczuk, Towards Global Environmental Legislation, Paper for the UN/IAF Workshop on
'Organizing Space Activities in Developing Countries: Resources and Mechanisms' (1993).
14. Brown Weiss, 'International Environmental', loc. cit. n. 13, at p. 697.
15. J.L. Sax, 'A General Survey of the Problem', in Science for Better Environment,
Proceedings of the International Congress on the Human Environment (1976) pp. 753 and 755.
16. Handl, loc. cit. n. 3, pp. 5-7.
17. T. Gehring, 'International Environmental Regimes: Dynamic Sectoral Legal Systems',
1 YIEL (1990) p. 38.
International environmental law 193
Thus there have been conventions with supplementing protocols, such as the 1979
Geneva Convention on Long-Range Transboundary Pollution. Some conventions
have been accompanied by annexes, protocols and regulations containing technical
data and may be subject to an 'opting-out' procedure whereby some States parties
to the main convention are not bound by all the detailed technical provisions.
Yet another type are so-called 'umbrella treaties' consisting of a general
framework with accompanying protocols, such as the 1976 Barcelona Convention
on Protection of the Mediterranean Sea. The purposes of these various structures
include the following:
— to delay the necessity for all States to bind themselves at the outset to detailed
or contentious standards or rules;
— to delay the necessity to formulate detailed standards or rules;
— to make provision for regular revision and amendment of treaty provisions
through procedures which are less cumbersome than those involved in a full
diplomatic conference;
— to make provision for input to the formulation and revision of detailed rules
and standards of developments in scientific knowledge;
— to make provision for special dispute settlement procedures which are less
formal than the traditional recourse to an independent tribunal (the ICJ or
an international arbitral tribunal), and which will render it easier to apply
internally-defined criteria to the process.
It should be noted that, within these various structures, detailed rules and
standards are often included in treaty protocols or annexes which, however, are
not, at least initially, binding on the parties, thus constituting one of the areas
in which a so-called 'soft law' approach is being used.
Taken to its extreme, some recent environmental treaty regimes have been said
to constitute special regimes, to some extent at least separate from mainstream
international law.IS These are regimes which have been set up under conventions
which, though they have been concluded within the framework of traditional
international law, once in operation involve systems which effectively bypass the
mechanisms of traditional law. In particular, they may be expected to involve
the setting up of some permanent forum between the parties, the functions of
which go beyond those of implementation of the rules set up in the convention,
and technical supervision, which characterise the technical commissions of more
traditional conventional regimes, but also have a rule making capacity which may
in practice even involve revision of the convention itself. A second essential
feature of such regimes is the provision of their own dispute settlement
procedures. Thus, it has been said: 'By internalising the making and application
of international law within their respective issue-areas, international
environmental regimes develop into comparatively autonomous sectoral legal
systems.'19
One may illustrate the concept by comparing two major treaty regimes in the
environmental field. The first of these, the regime under the Helsinki Convention
on the Protection of the Marine Environment of the Baltic Sea of 1992, involves
the express application of traditional methods of law making and dispute
settlement, and fairly clearly does not constitute a special regime in the above
sense. The second (the regime under the Montreal Protocol 1987) illustrates
internalisation in both these respects.
The regime under the Helsinki Convention is fairly typical, in terms of its
legal structure, of the umbrella-type convention. It sets up a Commission with
substantial capacities in the technical field, and in relation to the development
of technical rules. But it remains firmly within the framework of traditional
international law in the vital areas of amendment of the Convention itself, and
of the settlement of disputes. Thus, in particular, proposals to amend the
Convention were developed at the level of a full diplomatic conference between
the parties, rather than within the forum of the Helsinki Commission; and the
Convention itself expressly provides for the settlement of disputes between the
parties to be submitted to international arbitration or to the ICJ.
By comparison, in support of the contention that the regime under the
Montreal Protocol20 does constitute a 'comparatively autonomous sectoral legal
system' in the sense referred to above, Gehring points in the first place to a
number of ways in which the Meetings of the Parties to the Protocol effectively
arrived at amending the arrangements under it without the formalities which
would have normally been required under a traditional international law
regime.21 In the second place, he points to the emphasis in the Montreal
Protocol on the development of a procedure aimed at overcoming the difficulties
of using the traditional remedies for breach of treaty in an environmental context,
that is to say of a 'non-compliance procedure', adopted by the Second Meeting
of the Parties as an alternative to a more traditional dispute settlement procedure
involving arbitration between particular parties. Gehring points out that 'while
disputes submitted to arbitration are to be settled in accordance with international
law, submissions to the non-compliance procedure are to be considered "with
a view to securing an amicable resolution of the matter on the basis of respect
for the provisions of the Protocol"'.22
for Oil Pollution Damage (as amended by the Protocols of 1976 and 1984) do
adopt this approach.
Traditionally civil liability and State responsibility were distinct. State
responsibility was related to the wrongful acts of States, whereas the subject-
matter of civil liability was primarily that of relations between private subjects,
though with the possibility of the participation of the State.25 Civil liability
regimes contain material and procedural rules, relating to equal access, non-
discrimination, etc.26
The 1969 IMO Civil Liability Conventions channel liability to the operator.
The operator has to maintain an insurance policy to assure the availability of
funds for the compensation of victims of accidental transfrontier pollution
damage. The State, however, retains a residual responsibility. If the private
person's financial coverage is insufficient in the event of enormous claims or
when accidents involve single ship or single plant companies, the State would
be liable.27 The 1971 International Convention on the Establishment of an
International Fund for Compensation for Oil Pollution Damage28 in Article 15
obligates the contracting States to provide information on persons liable to
contribute to the Fund; and in a new 1984 Protocol (not yet in force) the residual
liability of the State is expanded so that if a contracting State does not fulfil its
obligations to submit to a Director the communication required by the convention,
and this causes financial loss for the Fund, the contracting State is to be liable
to compensate the Fund. It is submitted that even in the absence of the express
treaty provisions on the State's residual responsibility, the State, due to its control
over risk-creating activities and to the fact that it benefits from them, must be
responsible 'in the last resort'.29 Another way in which State responsibility may
come about is when a State refuses to implement a treaty-based civil liability
regime by enacting appropriate municipal law. Such refusal may amount to
breach of international obligations and thus entail State responsibility in
accordance with general rules of State responsibility.30 In practice, however,
since the establishment of the oil liability regime, States have not been prepared,
25. Ibid., A. Rosas, 'Issues of State Liability forTransboundary Damage', Nordic JIL (1991)
p. 34.
26. G. Doeker and T. Gehring, 'Private or International Liability for Transnational
Environmental Damage - The Precedent of Conventional Liability Regimes, 2 J Environmental
L (1990) pp. 1-16.
27. I. R. Pinto-Dobering,' Liability for the Harmful Consequences of Instances of Transfrontier
Pollution not Prohibited by International Law', 38 OzoRV (1987) p. 106.
28. 11 ILM (1972) p. 284.
29. Pinto-Dobering, loc. cit. n. 27, at p. 108.
30. G. Handl, 'State Liability for Accidental Transnational Environmental Damage by Private
Persons', 74 AJIL (1980) p. 525.
International environmental law 197
31. Tovlad and Cristal are private liability agreements for the oil transporting and the oil
processing industries. B. Brennan, 'Liability and Compensation forOil Pollution from Tankers under
Private International Law, Tovalop, Cristal and the Exxon Valdez', 2 Geo. Int. Env. L Rev. (1989)
p. 1.
32. Convention on Third Party Liability in the Field of Nuclear Energy (Paris Convention),
6 EY (1960).
33. ILM (1972) p. 277.
34. Doeker and Gehring, loc. cit. n. 26, at pp. 8-9.
35. T. Gehring and M. Jachtenfuchs, 'Liability for Transboundary Environmental Damage
Towards a General Liability Regime?', 4 EJIL (1993) p. 104.
198 M.A. Fitzmaurice
The Finnish-Swedish Frontier Rivers Commission (the 'FSFRC') is the body set
up under the Boundary Rivers Agreement of 16 September 1971 (the 'FSFRC
Agreement') between Finland and Sweden to manage the watercourse system
which constitutes, and lies on either side of the greater part of the border between
them. It represents what may be seen as the logical extreme of a civil liability
regime, in which both rights and obligations in relation to the environment are
accorded to individuals, thus effectively excluding the operation of State
responsibility as between the two State parties. The FSFRC is not in itself an
international body in the sense of one which applies principles of international
law between States or whose decisions are intended to be enforceable through
international law. Rather, the FSFRC embodies a merging of certain internal or
municipal law powers, of the two States which were previously administered,
with regard to the territory of each State, by that State's own organs, judicial
or administrative, but which are now administered by the single body over the
whole FSFRC area.
The FSFRC is primarily a body responsible for the management of the
international watercourse; its functions encompass, however, strong elements of
environmental protection. The FSFRC has judicial, administrative and supervisory
functions, which roughly correspond to functions of water rights courts and
licensing boards in both States. The setting up and operation of the FSFRC may
be said to involve the application by the two States of international law principles
such as the duty to co-operate, the principle of equitable utilisation, doctrines
such as sic utero tuo ut alienum non laedas and the duty of riparian States to
settle disputes relating to the shared international watercourse. But the manner
of application of these principles has its own special characteristics due to the
fact that, though set up under an international agreement, the States as such are
largely excluded from its activities. From this it follows that certain notions
related to State responsibility, such as reparations or countermeasures, simply
cannot be applied to this commission since its foundations are different and not
comparable with laws regulating relations between States.38
4. 'SOFT LAW
38. The FSFRC is one of a number of international bodies which have been set up in relation
to what are generally now referred to as international watercourses and which are also variously
described as border river and lake basins commissions. For an extensive study of the Commission
see M. Fitzmaurice, "The Finnish-Swedish Frontier Rivers Commission', Hague YIL (1992) pp.
33-67.
39. Birnie and Boyle, op. cit. n. 4, at p. 16.
40. For a general discussion of the subject, and with particular reference to the importance of
the intention of the parties in drawing the line between law and 'soft law', see G.M. Borchardt and
K.C. Wellens, 'Soft Law in the European Community Law', 14 EL Rev (1989) p. 267.
200 M.A. Fitzmaurice
As stated above 'soft law' was first used in international economic law — (where
it is also a fairly widely accepted concept,41 in particular in dealing with economic
issues which were thought to be within the sovereign power of States.42 The
nature of 'soft law' was perfect for uses such as combining collective regulations
and restraint in economic dealings with flexibility and freedom to manoeuvre
where events or changing circumstances so require. The use of 'soft law'
sometimes indicates an attempt to build a new economic structure.
'Soft law' instruments were perfectly suited for the transactions and relations
which emerged after the Second World War which left, inter alia, many
decolonised States with weak economies and developed States without assured
access to raw materials.43 International economic relations suddenly had to
accommodate almost irreconcilable differences between the approaches of
different legal systems and the different goals of a highly diverse and vastly
enlarged group of members of the international community. Thus, States were
faced with the problems of achieving an agreement on universally acceptable rules
and an unwillingness to undertake legal obligations. They were, though not averse
to collective action, not prepared to fetter their freedom of action. As a rule,
States are willing to take legal obligations when they expect to comply with
them44 and to avoid legal obligations because of technical problems involved
in forming and terminating them.45
In international environmental law, the grounds for employing 'soft law' are
similar to those in international economic law, in particular relating to the
problems of reaching agreement between States at widely disparate stages of
development and with widely differing economic interests. To these reasons may
be coupled a number of others which arise as a result of special features of the
environment, which lend themselves particularly well to 'soft law' solutions. Of
particular importance, in this respect, are the problems arising from the speed
particular importance, in this respect, are the problems arising from the speed
with which the world's perception of the environmental crisis has developed, and
the urgency of the need to find solutions. There is a desire to, as it were, run
ahead of the relatively slow process of negotiation and ratification which is
involved in the traditional treaty making process by, in the first place, agreeing
more speedily on standards and objectives, which may be contained in non-
binding declarations, for example, the Declaration on the Protection of the Marine
Environment of the Baltic Sea ('The Ministerial Declaration'),46 or resolutions
of international organisations, or, in the second place, agreeing on the outline
structure of regulatory regimes in framework treaties, while leaving the detailed
norms to be applied within them in, at least initially, non-binding form. Exactly
similar solutions may be used to meet the problems which arise as a result of
the lack of certainty which exists in relation to the scientific basis of the crisis
or of the measures to be adopted to meet it. A further reason for the use of the
many formulations of concepts and principles of a legal nature in non-binding
instruments is to stimulate State practice and provide a focus for the expression
of the opinio juris, which is needed to speed up the process of formulation of
legally binding principles through development of customary law (a matter which
has been referred to above in section 2.2).
46. Baltic Sea Environment Protection, Doc. No. 26, (1987) pp. 30-36.
47. Boyle and Bimie, op. cit. n. 4, at p. 191.
48. A. Boyle, 'International Law and the Protection of the Global Atmosphere: Concepts;
Categories and Principles', in R. Churchill and D. Freestone, eds., International Law and Global
Climate Change (1991) p. 18.
202 M.A. Fitzmaurice
We will consider this from the point of view, first, of an analysis of the ILC's
use of the terms 'responsibility' and 'liability' in the two drafts, and, second,
of their concept of a 'compound primary obligation' as propounded in the initial
version of the Liability Draft.
5.2.2.1 Terminology
The ILC reserved the word 'responsibility' to cover the whole range of
obligations involved in its work on State responsibility and the word 'liability'
to cover the whole range of obligations involved in its work on the 'liability'
project. In so doing, the ILC, simply as a matter of the use of differing
terminology, departed from what may be regarded as the most widely accepted
distinction drawn between these two words, namely, that 'responsibility' refers
to an obligation arising from a legally binding rule (often referred to as a primary
rule), while the word 'liability' refers to obligations which only arise as a result
204 M.A. Fitzmaurice
The way in which the ILC used the words might have done no more than cause
terminological confusion, had both Drafts retained the underlying concepts of
primary and secondary obligations, of obligation to act in accordance with rules
of international law and of consequences flowing from the breach of those rules.
But, while they did, indeed, retain this distinction in the Responsibility Draft,
in the first of the Liability Drafts (the Schematic Outline of Quentin-Baxter, and
his commentaries on it), the ILC abandoned the dual obligation concept and
attempted to construct a single obligation concept involving what was referred
to as a 'compound primary obligation' which was to incorporate four individual
duties, namely, to prevent, to inform, to negotiate and to make reparation. Even
the last element in this compound norm - the duty to make reparation — was
considered as a primary obligation, since it was not, unlike the duty to
compensate under the Responsibility Draft, based on any wrongful act. It was
propounded, however, that breach of this last element in the compound norm
was an international wrong which would result in State responsibility.
This article is not the appropriate place for a detailed discussion of the ILC's
reasons either for separating the two topics at all, or for adopting their novel
single compound obligation concept. These matters have been treated ably and
51. It may be noted that this distinction is, in fact, only possible in the English language;
languages such as French and Spanish, for instance, having only the single word 'responsabilite'
and 'responsabilidad', respectively, to cover both meanings.
52. L. Goldie, 'Concept of States and Absolute Liability and the Ranking of Liability in Terms
of Relative Exposure to Risk', 16 NYIL (1985) pp. 175 and 176.
International environmental law 205
53. N.L.J.T. Horbach, "The Confusion about State Responsibility and International Liability',
4 LJIL (1991) p. 47. S. Erichsen, 'Das Liability-Project des ILC, Forentwicklung des Allgemeinen
Umweltrechts Oder Kodifizierung eines Haftung fur besonders gefahrliche Aktivitaten? ',51 ZaoRV
(1991) p. 94.
206 M.A. Fitzmaurice
and convincing evidence.>54 This principle was endorsed by the ICJ in the Corfu
Channel case where the Court stated that it is 'every State's obligation not to
allow knowingly its territory to be used for acts contrary to the rights of other
States.'55 Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration also stresses die responsi-
bility of States to 'ensure that activities within their jurisdiction or control do not
cause damage to the environment of other states or areas beyond the limits of
national jurisdiction. '56 Against this background, both die basis for a separate
'liability' regime, and the basis of die regime proposed by the ILC, have been
shown to be flawed.
Brownlie doubts die academic value of the Commission's distinction and
assesses die Liability Draft as 'fundamentally misconceived'. According to him,
State responsibility (including die jurisprudence of die Trail Smelter and Corfu
Channel cases) relates to harm caused by lawful activities. The distinction
between lawful and unlawful activities is, dierefore, widiout purpose and lacks
support in eidier State practice or in jurisprudence. What is crucial is the content
of relevant rules. A similar criticism is made by Boyle, according to whom '. . .
the notion diat activities incurring responsibility for harm are unlawful and
prohibited can be seen as misconceived and oversimplified; die elements of harm,
knowledge and control are drawn direcdy from comparable use in a state
responsibility context.'57
Akehurst is also highly critical of die ILC's basic conceptual distinction
between die 'responsibility' and die 'liability' topics. In die first place, he finds
puzzling die concentration of die ILC in die Liability Draft on environmental
damage. According to him, attaching liability sine delicto to die environment is
a misunderstanding on die part of die Commission, since rules of international
law concerning die environment are phrased in terms of a duty not to damage
the environment, from which it follows diat any resulting liability for damage
to die environment is liability ex delicto not sine delicto.5i
Illustrating dieir point by reference to die Trail Smelter arbitration, Brownlie,
Boyle and Akehurst all state diat while die operation of die plant was lawful,
pollution which was caused by diis operation was not and was dius subject to
die responsibility regime. On these bases, one must conclude diat die better view
54. 3 RIAA (1941) pp. 1911 and 1965. See also the Lake Lanoux arbitration {France v. Spain)
55 AJIL (1959) p. 156.
55. ICJ Rep. (1949) p. 22.
56. 11 ILM(1972)p. 1416.
57. A. Boyle, 'State Responsibility and International Liability for Injurious Consequences of
Acts Not Prohibited by International Law: A Necessary Distinction?', 39 ICLQ (1990) p. 22.
58. M. Akehurst, 'International Liability for Injurious Consequences Arising Out of Acts Not
Prohibited by International Law, 16 NYIL (1985) p. 3.
International environmental law 207
is, firstly, that the original Liability Draft cannot be accepted as a codification
of customary law, and, secondly, that the conceptually separate regime
propounded in it does not, at least for the present, exist in international law.
This conclusion would seem to have been, to some extent at least, accepted by
the second Special Rapporteur, Barboza, who introduced significant changes in
his Draft Articles. The most important of these, in relation to the conceptual basis
of the Draft, arises in the way the two Rapporteurs differ in their versions of the
legal consequences attached to a breach of the primary compound norm:
notification, consultation, prevention. Quentin-Baxter, despite convincing
jurisprudence contained in such classic cases as the Trail Smelter and Lake
Lanoux arbitrations, put forward the argument that a breach of this norm does
not necessarily result in State responsibility. Barboza, on the other hand, accepts
State responsibility for such a breach.
This new solution by Barboza has given rise to differing opinions in the
literature on the subject. Thus it is said that Barboza, by the introduction of
corresponding State responsibility for the breach of notification, negotiation and
prevention of harm, initiated State responsibility for lawful activities in two cases:
(1) when the State does not perform the primary obligation of prevention,
information and negotiation, and (2) when it does not perform the reparation duty
(Quentin-Baxter's Draft envisaged only the second possibility). This solution
seems to be 'illogical and incompatible with the original reasons for a separate
consideration of international liability.'59 The same author also maintains that
the Draft completely blurs the distinction between primary and secondary rules
by entailing both sets of rules leading to State responsibility.60 Another author,
while welcoming this stricter approach as a '. . . return to the more convincing
thesis and avoids implausible inflation of the significance of a global distinction
between primary and secondary obligations,"51 nevertheless considers that, in
assimilating liability to the Commission's own conception of responsibility, it
makes the title of the 'Liability Draft' misleading.62 Similar reasoning is to be
found by Pinto-Dobering, who says that, under the Liability Draft:
'[t]he regime of liability does not, therefore, exist in isolation from the regime of state
responsibility, for, while international liability signifies the duty to compensate loss
or injury in the absence of internationally wrongful conduct, as provided for by a
primary rule of obligation, failure to meet this obligation will constitute a breach of
an international obligation and give effect to the secondary rules of state responsibility
for internationally wrongful behaviour.'63
Another author considers it illogical and incompatible with the original reasons
for the separate consideration of international liability and responsibility.
According to this author, co-existing responsibility only adds to confusion and
the reasons for different treatment disappear.64
Another problem in accepting the separation of the topics which survives the
latest Draft arises in connection with the question of reparation for damage.
Contrary to the Draft on State Responsibility there is, under the proposed liability
regime, no absolute obligation to discontinue the harmful activity, to restore the
status quo ante or to compensate fully for harm. Barboza's Draft, it is true, is
firmer on the question of making reparation for appreciable harm.65 However,
he also based his reasoning on the 'balance of interest' principle, which sets a
ceiling on compensation, thus maintaining the distinction between lawful and
unlawful activities by limiting the consequences of the former.66 But this actually
hides still greater confusion. According to the theory of State responsibility for
an internationally wrongful act, a State is under a secondary obligation to pay
compensation.67 According to Barboza's Draft, a breach of the primary
compound rule in the liability regime causes, surprisingly, the same outcome,
so that the question arises whether and to what extent there exists a difference
between two types of compensation. Furthermore, if a State does not pay
compensation under the Liability Draft, it is also guilty of an internationally
wrongful act giving rise to responsibility. The question of liability for
environmental damage (wrongful act) (primary norm) changes into State
responsibility (secondary norm). The final result in both cases will be to pay
compensation. The only difference may be that the compensation for the lawful
act will be lower than that for the wrongful act.68
5.4 Conclusion
In conclusion we may say that, even with the modifications now made to the
Liability Draft, a foundation in international law for the separation of the two
concepts of State liability and responsibility does not exist. Indeed, this conclusion
is even reinforced by the latest Draft.
However, even harsh critics of the ILC's work accept that it has positive
elements which include, in particular, the movement towards some level of
stricter liability in relation to environmental harm; the concept of liability
covering both the results of unforeseeable accident and of continuing polluting
activities; and the introduction of some concept of balance of interest in relation
to responsibility for environmental harm. For instance, Zemanek sees it as the
right approach to base States' obligations in the environmental field on strict
liability. Otherwise, if pollution occurs through accident, and if the unmodified
regime of State responsibility applies, the victim may well be left without a claim.
This author does not dwell, however, on the 'separateness' of the liability regime,
but rather on its practical consequences.71 The point made by other authors is
that these positive elements can as well, or better, be accommodated within the
basic concept of State responsibility, i.e., in terms of the definition of the
obligation or obligations which States owe to other States in respect of
environmentally harmful activities and of the consequences of breaching those
obligations. Thus, as Boyle says (having postulated the weakness of the
conceptual basis for separation of the responsibility and liability topics): 'it would
have been wiser to concentrate not on the topic as originally conceived, but to
approach it from the altogether more practical and less theoretically questionable
standpoint of codifying and developing a set of basic environmental obligations
for States.' It is in this spirit that we shall consider in section 6 what may now
be said to be the characteristics of such obligations in the present state of
development of international law, and what are the consequences of their breach.
Within this context, we will also consider the positive aspects of the ILC Liability
Draft to which we have referred above.
6.1 Introductory
It is the view of the majority of writers that 'there now exists in general
international law, real and binding primary obligations of states on the protection
of the environment, whose breach involves responsibility for a wrongful act.'72
The law in this area is still undoubtedly developing, but certain features of these
obligations can already be seen which are special to the environmental field, and
the need for which may be seen to arise from the special nature of environmental
problems.
Thus, in the first place, though the obligation not to cause harm to other States
falls firmly within the general field of State responsibility, there are a number
of respects in which there are, or are developing, special features relating to the
definitions of this obligation, and to the consequences of its breach, when the
harm involved is environmental. Secondly, it is now widely accepted that there
has evolved as a matter of customary law, an additional duty which may generally
be referred to as a duty to co-operate in relation to environmental matters,
though, as we shall see below, this duty is made up of a number of individual
elements.
The nature and origins of the obligation of States to refrain from causing harm
to other States has been stated in section 3.2.3 above. It is supported by two
separate, though in their result similar, principles, namely, the principle 'sic utero
tuo ut alienum non laedas', and the concept of neighbourship law (droit
international de voisinage), which comprises an obligation of States to abstain
from conduct causing physical harm to other States.73 Put another way, it has
been said to embody the rule that neighbouring States have to limit enjoyment
of their territorial sovereignty to a certain extent for the benefit of other States,
and to tolerate a certain degree of nuisance74 or that no substantial damage
should be inflicted by one State on another.75
This principle was also accepted as the basis for establishing the responsibility
of States in relation to transboundary damage in the Stockholm Declaration,
which by the ILA in the Helsinki Rules and in their 'Rules on International Law
Applicable to Transfrontier Pollution' was adopted at the 1982 meeting in
Montreal. With respect to the special field of international watercourses, the same
principle was incorporated by the ILC in Article 7 of the Watercourse Draft
which states that 'watercourse states shall utilise an international watercourse in
such a way as not to cause appreciable harm to other watercourse states.' A duty
not to cause environmental harm of various kinds has also been a feature of a
number of conventional regimes.
76. Boyle, loc. cit. n 57, at pp. 15-16; Handl, loc. cit. n. 30, at p. 541.
77. Boyle, loc. cit. n. 57, at p. 23.
78. W. Jenks, Liability for Ultra Hazardous Activities in International Law, 17 Hague Recueil
(1966) p. 99.
212 M.A. Fitzmaurice
probability of minor appreciable injury' arising from the use of things whose
physical properties, location or use make injury likely.79
6.2.3 Knowledge
The obligation of States under customary law, as illustrated in the Corfu Channel
case, is one not 'knowingly' to cause damage; and this requirement of knowledge
is also incorporated into the liability regime. Thus Article 3 of the Liability Draft
reads as follows: '[t]he source State shall have the obligations imposed on it by
the present articles, provided that it knew or had means of knowing that an
activity involving risk was being, or about to be, carried out in areas under its
jurisdiction or control.' However, the requirement of knowledge may be seen
as somewhat weaker in the liability regime in view of the terms of the second
paragraph of Article 3 which reads: 'Unless there is evidence to the contrary,
it shall be presumed that the State of origin has the knowledge or means of
knowing referred to in the preceding paragraph.'
6.3.1 In general
adverse environmental effects resulting from activities conducted in all spheres, in such
a way that due account is taken of the sovereignty and interests of all states. '81
The principle is also incorporated in the ILC Watercourse Draft, which states
that:
The duty of co-operation is set out in the Liability Draft's Article 7 which
provides that States are to co-operate in good faith among themselves, and are
to request the assistance of any international organisations that might be able to
help them, in trying to prevent any activities which risk causing transboundary
harm; if such harm occurs, they are to co-operate in minimising its effects.
81. Many international organs or organisations adopted similar principles in their resolutions
or recommendations. To name a few: the United Nations Environment Programme (UNEP) in its
1978 Draft Principles of Conduct in the Field of the Environment for the Guidance of States in the
Conservation and Harmonious Utilisation of Natural Resources Shared by Two or More States, in
17 ILM (1978) p. 1097; the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development contributed
to the development of the above-mentioned and other principles relevant to transfrontier pollution
in its 1974 Recommendation on Principles concerning Transfrontier Pollution (Doc. (74) 224), in
14 ILM (1975) p. 242 and subsequent recommendations.
82. Art. 8 of the Draft Articles on the Law of Non-Navigational Uses of International
Watercourses, Draft Report of the ILC, UN GAOR, 43rd Session, UN Doc. A/CN L.463/Add.4
(1993), hereinafter referred to as 'ILC Watercourse Draft".
214 M.A. Fitzmaurice
Chapter III of the Liability Draft specifies a number of specific instances of such
co-operation, in particular the duties of notification and to exchange information
(Article 11) and a duty to consult (Article 14). It will be seen that these duties
reflect Article 24 of the Stockholm Declaration and also to a large extent mirror
the duties elaborated in the ILC Watercourse Draft.
The Liability Draft, also, in Article 10, expressly invokes the principle of non-
discrimination and goes on to provide in Chapter V a number of specific
provisions in relation to civil liability. It should also be noted that, in Article 17,
a series of specific factors are set out which may be taken into account 'in order
to achieve an equitable balance of interests among the States concerned in relation
to' activities which risk causing transboundary harm.
The main feature of the regime proposed by Quentin-Baxter was to provide room
for a degree of negotiability as regards the obligation to repair damage in cases
where the States did not specify a specific regime before the damage occurred.85
The pivotal feature of this regime was the so-called balance of interest principle
between the parties concerned. This balance of interest principle was perhaps
derived primarily from Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration of 1972.86
This principle may be seen as a parallel to the principle of 'equitable
participation' in the field of shared resources and in particular of international
83. Draft Art. 6 of the Draft Rules on State Responsibility, ILC Yearbook (1984-11) p. 2.
84. UN Doc. A. CN/4/405 (1987) p. 17, para. 55.
85. Gehring and Jachtenfuchs, loc. cit. n. 35, at p. 95.
86. States have, in accordance with the Charter of the UN and principles of international law,
the sovereign right to exploit their own resources, pursuant to their own environmental policies,
and the responsibility to ensure that activities within their jurisdiction or control do not cause damage
to the environment of other States or to areas beyond the limits of national jurisdiction.
International environmental law 215
watercourses. This was the most important principle of the Helsinki Rules and
is also central to the ILC's work in relation to international watercourses. Though
not easy to define, it may generally be said to mean that a watercourse State is
entitled to use and benefit from the watercourse in an equitable manner, in order
to achieve the maximum benefit to each State from the utilisation with the
minimum detriment to another watercourse State.87
While the concept is well established in relation to shared resources, it is more
doubtful where it stands in relation to the causation of environmental harm. As
Boyle says: 'while a balancing of interests in environmental disputes is probably
a necessary and inevitable condition of progress in the regulation of the global
environment, this is also an issue which needs a new conceptual framework for
the subject.'88 To some extent, this may be achieved by developing the concept
of threshold of harm. Boyle also emphasises the importance in this respect of
developing appropriate remedies for breach of environmental obligations, in
particular the role of injunctions and declarations.89
Another example of a special approach to the settlement of environmental
disputes may be found in the Hague Declaration of 1989 which calls for a 'new
and more effective decision-making and enforcement mechanism'. The
establishment of such a mechanism would entail four principles: research,
assistance, enforcement and negotiation.90 The substance of solving an
environmental dispute is to find a balance between the sovereign rights of States,
the one harmed by polluting activities and the other exercising its sovereign rights
in its territory through such activities. This became particularly evident in the
Nuclear Tests case in which Australia pleaded that France by polluting its
territory, breached its sovereignty.91 The ILC Liability Draft seems to follow
the general procedural scheme and (as stated above) sets out a procedure for early
notification, negotiations and consultations in respect of harmful activities —
based on negotiations through which the 'balance of interest' principle is
implemented between the source State and the affected State.
6.4.3 Countermeasures
Countermeasures (a term which, in recent years, has replaced the term 'self-help')
can take the form of reciprocal actions, of a lawful act in response to an unlawful
87. E. Lipper, 'EquitableUtilisation' in A.H. Garretson, R.D. Haytonand C.J. Olmstead, eds.,
The Law of International Drainage Basins (1967) pp. 15-16.
88. Boyle, loc. cit. n. 57, at p. 23.
89. Ibid., p. 24.
90. 28 ILM (1989) p. 1308.
91. Nuclear Test case (1973) Pleadings I, p. 14.
216 M.A. Fitzmaurice
one and of an unlawful act which is rendered lawful by being a response to the
prior unlawful act ('reprisal'). The object of the reprisal must be to 'effect
reparation from the offending State for the offense or a return to legality by the
avoidance of further offenses.' Another condition of lawfulness of reprisals is
that they should be preceded by 'an unsatisfied demand for reparation'.92 The
latter element is, however, controversial and not uniformly supported either in
the practice of States or in doctrine.93 The reprisals must be proportional to the
prior illegal act in terms of damage.94
The ILC's Responsibility Draft, Part I Article 30 states that: 'The
wrongfulness of an act of a State not in conformity with an obligation of that
State towards another State is precluded if the act constitutes a measure legitimate
under international law against that other State, in consequence of an
internationally wrongful act of that other State.'95 For the purpose of Article
30 'countermeasures' also include breaches of treaty obligations justified in
accordance with Article 60 of the Vienna Convention and measures taken by
States in pursuance of decisions and recommendations of international
organisations.
It is said that countermeasures are rather dangerous as a tool in environmental
international law. It is difficult to be precise as to who has the right to take
countermeasures, when they are appropriate, or how they should be used.96
According to O'Connell the most common, yet in the field of the environment
sometimes inappropriate, form of reprisals are reciprocal countermeasures, such
as those envisaged in, e.g., Article 60 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of
Treaties. As an example one may postulate the suspension of an obligation not
to pollute in response to a breach of treaty obligation by another State, a solution
which seems highly unlikely.
Retorsion and reprisal are more appropriate means. Retorsion may take the
form, for instance, of suspending loan conditions on environmental protection
(e.g., within the framework of the World Bank.). The question of the application
of reprisals, due to its controversial character, is of course much more doubtful.
In case of reprisals a State must have a strong case — a treaty breach or actual
physical damage - such as in the Trail Smelter case. Environmental law, being
imprecise and developing, is not an easy field of international law to apply
reprisals and there is no certainty as to what the law in this respect is.
There is, of course, one already famous example of the application of
countermeasures in environmental law: the Yellow Fin Tuna case. In this case,
the USA used countermeasures against Mexico to support the conservation of
dolphins - prohibiting all imports of tuna from Mexico and intermediary States.
The countermeasures were aimed against the use of drift-nets by Mexican
fishermen which led to the slaughter of dolphins. The embargo on Mexican
products resulted in the alleged violation of GATT rules by the US Government
and a subsequent case before the GATT Panel which ruled against the US
measures. These measures were justified by the US Government as being taken
under an exception in the GATT rules for environmental protection. Thus, the
US Government did not plead reprisals against Mexico, but founded its ruling
on the provision of the GATT treaty. The article in question cited by the US is
XX(b) - Protection of Animal Life.97 This case raises several questions, for
example the fairness of countermeasures and the integrity of treaty regimes, i.e.,
unilateral actions, such as those taken by the US, to undermine multilateral treaty
regimes.
Another possibility for the application of countermeasures may perhaps be
found in the context of negotiations, i.e., to enforce the obligation to negotiate.98
This assumption is not, however, supported by the ILC's Draft which stated:
'[fjailure to take any step required by the rules contained in this section [context
of negotiations] shall not in itself give rise to any right of action . . . ' "
Reprisals, being an unlawful answer to a wrongful act, rendered lawful by
the actions of the wrong-doing State, could, apparently, not be used in the
framework of the State liability regime as postulated by the Liability Draft, which
is based on the notion of a permissible act. As referred to above, the better view
is that the conceptual basis of this regime is actually misconceived. But were it
to survive, it would seem that the only possible countermeasures within it would
be reciprocal countermeasures and retorsion. Overall, though the position is by
no means clear, there would seem to be grounds for doubting whether the
In general, treaties in the environmental field have not contained firm or precise
provisions on the responsibility of their parties for causing damage. For example,
the 1979 Geneva Convention on Long-Range Transboundary Air Pollution in
relation to possible damage from long-range transboundary pollution (Article 8)
contains a footnote expressly stating that the Convention 'does not contain a rule
on liability as to damage.' The same applies to the Vienna Convention on the
Protection of the Ozone Layer and the Basel Convention on the Transboundary
Movements of Hazardous Wastes. Regional conventions also fit this general
pattern (for instance the Convention on the Protection of the Marine Environment
of the Baltic Sea Area (1992), 'The Helsinki Convention') and very often only
contain a general provision such as that in the Helsinki Convention which states
in Article 25 that: '[t]he Contracting Parties undertake jointly to develop and
accept rules concerning responsibility for damage resulting from acts or omissions
in contravention of this Convention, including, inter alia, limits of responsibility,
criteria and procedures for the determination of liability and available remedies.'
The vagueness and uncertainty of such commitments breeds doubts as to their
binding force and also as to the possibility of enforcing international responsibility
for their breach. 10°
Further, the language of the Conventions (with a limited number of specific
exceptions) clearly indicates that they do not in general establish a strict
obligation not to pollute as an obligation of result, but only an obligation to
'endeavour' in accordance with the due diligence standard to prevent, control,
and reduce pollution.101 The much cited Space Liability Convention102 is
supposed to provide evidence that States have undertaken to accept a standard
of strict liability for transboundary environmental harm.103 This view, however,
is not uniformly accepted. Some authors assert that since the first of these
Conventions was negotiated simultaneously with the Outer Space Treaty, it cannot
be considered as an independent liability regime and that the two superpowers
accepted the principle of unlimited liability only in order not to endanger a
As long ago as 1966, it was said that 'a governing principle ought to be that
nothing in man's environment should be subject to the risk of large-scale change
until the natural phenomena which might be changed or obscured, have been
studied, and their nature and functions established with reasonable certainty. To
act counter to this principle is recklessness of a cataclysmic order . . . ' 106 Much
more recently, another author pointed out that there is, as part of the
environmental crisis, a risk of 'serious irreversible or cumulative effects, of an
environmental system overload, producing cascading effects throughout ecological
sub-systems. Thus international environmental law must come to reflect a much
greater emphasis on precautionary policies." 07
As a legal principle, the concept of a precautionary element in States'
obligations in respect of environmental harm has had wide acceptance in a
number of declarations. As an instance of these, one may cite the Bergen
Ministerial Declaration108 which states:
While a number of authors take the view that this embodies an important new
principle in international environmental law,109 it is submitted that the better
view is that, at least as stated in the Bergen Ministerial Declaration, and other
similar formulations, it should be seen rather as no more than an increasing
emphasis on the preventative aspect of the duty of States in relation to
environmental harm which has for some time been well established.110 Even
in the sense of the declaration quoted above, however, it is not certain to what
extent the principle can yet be said to be a principle of international law.1"
An even stronger formulation of the principle would actually reverse the
burden of proof, in the sense of restricting any actions by States unless it could
be shown that they would have no adverse effect on the environment. Though
such a principle has been adopted in certain very specific fields under treaties,
there is plainly no such general principle in international law at present. But this
formulation deserves mention as a particular example of ways in which the
advocacy of extreme measures in the protection of the environment may lead to
attempts to limit State sovereignty (see section 7 below).
6.7 Conclusions
which has, until rather recently, been principally concerned with 'transfrontier
damage to components of the environemnt; exploitation and protection of those
natural resources which are commonly shared by several states; the use and
protection of areas beyond national jurisdiction such as high seas and outer
space." 12 But international environmental law now has to face a wider problem,
namely, environmental problems of global relevance, and this calls for a different
approach in the development of obligations and treaties. Thus, it has been said
that:
'the difference between treaties for the protection of areas beyond national sovereignty
on the one hand and of treaties dealing with global environmental problems on the
other hand, is twofold: the latter oblige States to become active in their own territories
which means a substantial intervention into State sovereignty, whereas the former
require acts or omissions outside of the State territory and thus infringe to a lesser
degree upon sovereignty.'"3
It is inherent in the traditional concept that the obligations of one State are more
or less matched by the rights of another (sometimes referred to as the 'zero sum'
concept). This is no longer the case in relation to the obligations which it is
perceived need to be imposed on States to meet the challenge of the environment.
What is needed is obligations which States in general owe to die world
community, or to the environment itself. And it has been said:
'Within treaties which aim to resolve global environmental problems and impose
consequential obligations upon states in the interest of the state community, no direct
benefit or competence exists which corresponds with these obligations. To this point,
the usual interdependence between rights and duties, characteristic for international
law agreements and for the mechanisms guaranteeing their observance does not exits.'
114. R. Higgins, Problems and Process ~ International Law and How We Use It (1994) (being
the revised text of the Hague Academy General Course in International Law delivered by Prof.
Higgins in 1990) p. 105.
115. Birnie and Boyle, op. cit. n. 4, at p. 191;R.D. Munroand J.G. Lammers, Environmental
Protection and Sustainable Development (1986) p. 40.
International environmental law 223
One must, at this stage, mention in passing (the scope of this article does not
allow for more) the concept of 'intergenerational equity' which would extend the
concept of an individual human right in favour of members of the present
generation to a collective human right in favour of generations yet to come. There
is no doubt that the concept of the protection of the environment for the benefit
of future generations as a policy objective underlies much of the latest thinking
in the field, and plainly underlies the concept of 'sustainable development'. But
it has to be said that of all the theoretical, even philosophical, bases that have
been propounded to found an obligation towards future generations, as it has been
said of the Brown Weiss theory of intergenerational equity, that 'these
prescriptions for the extension of [international environmental law] to future
generations are wildly unrealistic."16 As the author of these remarks has said:
'It is already an intractable task to reconcile the environmental interests of those
here and now in a weak international legal and political system, without also
embracing the interests of the future."17
In the end, it is at least arguable that, in many respects, the interests of the
individual concerning the environment are best protected on the basis of the
private law solutions.
116. Boyle, reviewing the book In Fairness to Future Generations (1989) in 40 ICLQ (1991)
230.
117. Idem.
118. Jennings, loc. cit. n. 106, at p. 512.
119. Idem.
224 M.A. Fitzmaurice
It has been observed above that one of the features of the environment as a
subject-matter of international law has been the growing perception not only of
the global scope of the problem, but also of its scope in terms of the areas of
human activity that are relevant to its protection. This perception has resulted
in the acceptance of the proposition that the problems of environmental protection
cannot be addressed in isolation from economic matters, in particular in relation
to poverty, development and trade. The most important inter-relationship between
these subject-matters arises from the fact that, as perceived in the light of modern
understanding of the global ecosystem, environmental protection is incompatible
not only with continued unrestricted economic activities in developed countries,
but also with unrestricted development of the developing countries. On the other
hand, this realisation has come at a time when the developing countries have been
increasingly asserting their right to development, even, in an extreme view, as
a kind of collective human right. Both the existence and the complexity of the
relationship between environmental protection and development was recognised
in and forms the subject-matter of a number of the Principles of the Stockholm
Declaration. Thus, against the Principles which set out the general obligations
to preserve the environment, are those which recognise the necessity for
development, the impact of environmental protection on it, and the need to
provide assistance to developing countries to enable them to meet both their
125. S.R. Dovers and J.W. Handmer, 'Uncertainty, Sustainability and Change', 4 Global
Environmental Change (1992) p. 264.
126. Boyle, loc. cit. n. 116, at p. 231.