Are Positivists Committed To A Particular Theory of Adjudication?
Are Positivists Committed To A Particular Theory of Adjudication?
Are Positivists Committed To A Particular Theory of Adjudication?
First, I examine the core elements of legal positivism, and argue that ‘positivist’ is a
label given to an abstract theory about the nature of law and interpretation. Second, I
examine how this abstract theory might influence choices between different theories
greatly, all positivists must be prepared to accept the possibility that in some
circumstances it would be right for a judge actively to disobey the law, and that the
scope for such judicial disobedience within positivism is somewhat wider than might
at first be thought.
The heart of positivism is a theory, not about adjudication, but about the nature of law
and legal interpretation. What positivists all agree on, is the possibility of the existence
of morally bad laws. This foundational belief carries with it the logical consequence
that in at least some legal systems, at least some of the time, it would be possible to
interpret the law in a way which is “morally sterile”.1 Holding to this belief is a defining
characteristic of positivism.
This might seem to present an artificially abstract version of positivism. The name
‘positivist’ has become so associated with a dry analytical approach that someone
could be forgiven for slipping into thinking that positivists are, by definition,
1
QGRN7
it, “nothing about positivism compels the idea that only legally pedigreed rules should
a judge in a court of law, to treating positivistic norms as the exclusive input into
between is and ought…it in no way favours the is”.4 Accordingly, the major works of
To the extent that individual positivists do have theories of adjudication, these vary
from the most staunchly originalist to the most radically activist. 6 Some variants of
positivism espouse theories of adjudication which are themselves morally sterile, and
take up a scientific and naturalistic methodological stance; but it is equally true that
adjudication,7 and some have even derived their positivist theories of law and
Studies 39 – at p.56
4 Owen M. Fiss, ‘The Varieties of Positivism’, (1980) 90 Yale L.J. 1007 – at p.1007
5 H.L.A.Hart, The Concept of Law, (2012) OUP
6 Edward A. Purcell Jr, ‘Democracy, the Constitution, and Legal Positivism in America: Lessons from
a Winding and Troubled History’, (2015) 66(4) Florida Law Review; and, Anthony J. Sebok, Legal
Positivism in American Jurisprudence, (1998) CUP
7 E.g. Will Waluchow, ‘Constitutions as Living Trees: An Idiot Defends’, (2005) XVIII(2) Canadian
(2001) OUP
2
QGRN7
These facts about how positivists in practice treat adjudication do not, however,
answer the question whether the core insight of positivism – the possibility of a “morally
adjudication. Does that abstract thesis logically commit the positivist to any particular
Unlike natural law theorists who are logically committed to treating the question ‘how
should judges act?’ as a variant of the question ‘what is the law?’, positivists must treat
“the questions, ‘what is the law?’, and ‘how should judges decide cases?’ as distinct
questions with distinct answers”.9 How a judge should proceed when confronted by a
‘gap’ in the law (which makes it impossible to determine the right answer on the basis
of law alone),10 or when confronted by a deeply immoral law is, for the positivist, an
inherently moral question – different in kind from the analytical question of what the
pre-existing law actually is. So, for any positivist, a theory of adjudication must be
based on ethical reasons rather than analytical reasons of the kind normally used to
For positivists, theories of adjudication, as Raz observes, “are justified only if they are
morally justified”.11 Hence, even a positivist who holds a morally neutral theory of
adjudication and concludes that judges should simply apply the law neutrally by
9 Julie Dickson, ‘Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning’, (2010) Stanford Encyclopaedia of
Philosophy – at p.3
10 Hart supra n.5 – at p.123–36; and, Joseph Raz, ‘Legal Reasons, Sources and Gaps,’ in The
3
QGRN7
reference to legislative intent or reliance on the text alone, must defend that conclusion
on moral grounds. Such a positivist’s reasons for holding a morally neutral theory of
It would be both surprising and interesting then, if positivists were logically committed
to a particular answer to the inherently moral question: ‘how should judges decide
the nature of law, should contain within it the logical seeds of a particular view about
There is, however, one particular feature of adjudication that is (ethically even if not
If it is true, as positivists claim it is, that there can be morally iniquitous laws which are
still properly called laws, and true also that in some legal orders judges can only
interpret those laws in a morally sterile way, then, it must also be true – as a matter of
The positivist is, in other words, logically committed to saying, as Hart said, that “the
obedience, and that, however great the aura of majesty or authority which the official
system may have, its demands must in the end be submitted to moral scrutiny”. 12 No
4
QGRN7
morally defensible case can be made for a positivist theory of adjudication which fails
to allow for the possibility of judicial disobedience and insists on an absolute judicial
“duty of fidelity to law” even in cases where such fidelity would lead to morally
abominable results.13 Indeed, at the extreme, a legal system which achieved no moral
good whatsoever would create no obligation whatsoever for judges to follow the law.
So, all positivists are bound, ethically, to conclude that judicial fidelity to the law is
dependent on the law’s content. But, although all positivists accept this ethical point
and agree that the connection between positivism and judicial obedience is content-
dependent (and hence also agree that certain circumstances ethically demand judicial
disobedience) they disagree about the particular circumstances in which such judicial
how much moral content is needed in a particular system’s laws to make a good moral
case for an absolute judicial obligation of fidelity to law. It is to those differences that I
now turn.
At one end of the spectrum are those positivists who think that the bare fact of a legal
system’s existence will give rise to strict moral obligations on the part of judges (and
citizens) to obey the law. For the Hobbesian, a judge’s fidelity to law is crucial, and so
a minimalist theory of adjudication inevitable. A judge must settle the case before him
in a way which does not “reignite, the controversies whose existence called for a
13I use ‘fidelity to law’ in the same way as both West and Raz use it in: Raz ibid.; and, Robin West,
‘Natural Law Ambiguities’, (1992) 25 Conn. L. Rev. 829
5
QGRN7
decision-procedure in the first place”.14 If judges do not have fidelity to the law, the
consequence is the inevitable ‘war of each against all’. What both ancient and
by a concern about the law’s authority – by the worry that if judges are too creative
and activist, then the stability of the legal system will be jeopardised with the
Even theories which, like those of Hobbes, argue for a strong judicial duty of fidelity to
the law, still do so in a content-dependent way. If judicial obedience to the law would
somehow result, for example, in nuclear war, then even the Hobbesian must admit
that judicial disobedience is the only option. Hobbes explains that the reason for
absolute obedience to the sovereign lasts only as long as the sovereign can prevent
anarchy – if the sovereign can no longer provide for the “protection of his
subjects…[then] every man is at liberty to protect himselfe by such courses as his own
discretion shall suggest unto him…[If] the Power of an Assembly is once suppressed,
But Hobbes was pressing his point to an extreme when he suggested that so long as
a sovereign could prevent anarchy, absolute obedience was necessary. Not every act
of judicial disobedience inevitably leads to anarchy – stable modern states can surely
is incontestably iniquitous, and in which a judge can disobey the law without provoking
14 Jeremy Waldron, ‘The Core of the Case against Judicial Review’, (2006) 115(6) Yale L.J. 1346 – at
p.1371
15 E.g. Andrei Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory, (2005) Hart – particularly Ch.8 & 9
16 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, (2012) OUP, Noel Malcolm ed. – at p.518
6
QGRN7
So, while a positivist might well accept the Hobbesian argument that judges should
obey the law enough of the time to prevent a collapse into anarchy, they are not bound
to accept the claim that judges have an absolute obligation do as the law says.
The failure of the argument from authority to establish absolute judicial obligation leads
other positivists to ground the assertion that judges should always be obedient to the
law on other values. For example, although substantively Bentham’s position “hardly
differs from that of Hobbes”,17 he also introduces an important new argument: under
democratic order as misplaced. Austin’s argument that the opinion of the “ignorant
masses”18 should be constrained by the judgement of the better educated judicial elite
now seems anachronistic. But there are more compelling arguments against
majoritarianism available. First, German history in the last century has surely taught
7
QGRN7
unconstrained expression of the collective political will of the people”, but rather, is an
So modern positivists have retreated to the much weaker claim that judges in ‘properly
functioning’ liberal democracies should always be obedient to the law. Waldron, for
example, argues that judicial disobedience would only “be appropriate in legal orders
that have not yet made the transition to liberal democracy”.20 Absolute judicial
obedience is, for Waldron, required only when a system contains laws which ensure
Other ‘ethical positivists’ have expressed similar sentiments – Campbell, for example,
argues that if judges in liberal democracies think that applying the law is an “immoral
activity, they should resign their position”.22 Campbell’s argument from deliberative
democracy invokes powerful Rawlsian ideas about just institutional design. As Rawls
says in his earlier work, “if the basic structure of society is just, or as just as it is
8
QGRN7
reasonable to expect in the circumstances, everyone has a natural duty to do his part
But even these more moderate “neo-Benthamite”24 theories have been challenged.
Thinkers like Goldsworthy, although holding quite similar views to Waldron and
Campbell about the role of judicial creativity and innovative interpretation where legal
standards are indeterminate,25 still argue that there are “limits of judicial fidelity to law”,
and suggest that even in properly functioning liberal democracies there might be
“obvious and extreme cases of injustice”,26 in which judicial infidelity to law might be
positively desirable.
Democracies
Even if Goldsworthy is right that “damage to public confidence in the judiciary seems
judge is to know when he is faced with a genuine case of injustice – how is he to know
that his own judgement is better than that of the democratically elected
representatives? If a system has not succumbed to sheer majoritarianism, and the law
in question is not one which undermines the very values on which democracy is based,
then on what moral grounds, other than the subjective dictates of his own conscience,
167
26 Jeffrey Goldsworthy, ‘The Limits of Judicial Fidelity to Law’, (2011) XXIV(2) Canadian Journal of
9
QGRN7
While Goldsworthy fails to answer these questions, other positivists have sought to do
democracy, there might be good moral reasons for judges to deviate from the law. He
lays down “guidance rules” for judges, which he argues will enable them to work out
when it will be morally right to disobey the law. 27 He argues that “in realistic legal
systems it is impossible to guarantee, a priori, that a judge will never hear a case in
argues, if judges restrict their disobedience to only a very small portion of those laws
which they think morally wrong, there is likely to be significant overlap between those
laws which they deviate from, and those laws which actually create a morally bad
outcomes.
Brand-Ballard is surely right to conclude that – within a positivist framework – the only
morally appropriate way for judges to proceed is to create for themselves rules of
guidance which allow for the possibility of deviation from the law in extreme
circumstances. The fact that a law is democratically enacted does not provide a
guarantee that it is morally justifiable. The morally right action for a judge then, is to
devise a decision procedure with a high threshold which gives his own moral
judgement some epistemic credibility, and requires him to presume that the
democratically enacted law is just unless he has very strong reasons for concluding
the contrary. The overall utility achieved by such a rule would, if it leads judges to
27 Jeffrey Brand-Ballard, Limits of Legality: The Ethics of Lawless Judging, (2010) OUP – at p.233
28 Ibid. – at p.312
10
QGRN7
disobey the law only in cases where they have great certainty both that the law before
them is unjust and that their disobedience will not result in anarchy, be greater than
Conclusion
The simple conclusion is that being committed to the positivist view that morally
iniquitous laws can exist, means one is also committed to the view that judges
I have argued, further (and more tentatively), that positivists ought to accept a theory
of adjudication which allows for judicial disobedience in less than extreme (but still
I have not explored the extent to which it is legitimate for judges who are obedient to
the law to engage in 'creative' interpretation, or to make new law when the result is
underdetermined by the text. These questions are no less important than the question
of when judges should disobey the law; indeed, in a liberal democracy with an
entrenched bills of rights, these are the most pressing questions of constitutional
theory. But they are not questions the answer to which is either logically or ethically
11
QGRN7
Bibliography
12