A Non Philosophical Theory of Nature - Ecologies of Thought
A Non Philosophical Theory of Nature - Ecologies of Thought
A Non Philosophical Theory of Nature - Ecologies of Thought
Radical Theologies
Series Editors
Mike Grimshaw is an associate professor of Sociology at Canterbury
University in New Zealand.
Michael Zbaraschuk is a lecturer at the University of Washington,
Tacoma and a visiting assistant professor at Pacific Lutheran University.
Joshua Ramey is a visiting assistant professor at Haverford College.
Ecologies of Thought
Introduction 1
Notes 227
Bibliography 261
Index 271
Series Preface
the theory-jargon got too much for a critical geographer), Stuart Jesson (for
discussions about nonviolence and generally being kind enough to listen),
Alex Andrews (for discussions about general systems thinking and having
done with a certain kind of theology), Karen Kilby (for always having a
sympathetic ear and for the trust and guidance she extended to me regard-
ing teaching), and Orion Edgar (for discussions, usually whisky fueled,
about the place of religious beliefs and practices and what they mean to
him in relation to nature, ecology, and food).
Of course dear friends outside Nottingham also played a role as sound-
ing boards for ideas. Nicola Rubczak, whose brilliant work encouraged
me to consider feminist ways of thinking, was an immense help in deal-
ing with issues in the French. Daniel Whistler, whose philosophical acu-
men I greatly admire, has been a tremendous help with short but brilliant
“tutorials” (often given on buses or trains or, on one occasion, short walks
around the strange but beautiful English countryside) on Spinoza, Fichte,
Schelling, and the relationship between philosophy and religion. Marjorie
Gracieuse for all the discussions about Laruelle and Deleuze as well as
calming me down when I was anxious about my viva. Liam Heneghan,
the philosopher stuck in an ecologist’s body and codirector of DePaul
University’s Institute for Nature and Culture, who not only gave me my
first paid academic work when I was an undergraduate student in philoso-
phy at DePaul University, but also became a close friend and helped me
navigate the world of scientific ecology. Two other DePaul friends deserve
to be thanked as well, though not for any direct contribution to the book:
William Jordan III helpfully slowed me down early in my research by put-
ting forth his own ponderous questions to me; and Peter Steeves provided
not only personal encouragement but also intellectual inspiration. Then
there is Adam Kotsko, who I have to thank for creating our little online
community of support, intellectually and financially, at the blog An und
für sich.
I was encouraged to turn the original thesis into a book, first, by my
PhD examiners Dr. Steven Shakespeare and Prof. Agata Bielik-Robson,
whose tough examination humbled and emboldened me, as does our con-
tinued friendship. However, it was the prodding and counsel of Joshua
Ramey that finally allowed this book to see the light of day. I am immensely
happy that he, along with his coeditors Mike Grimshaw and Michael
Zbaraschuk, wanted to include this book in their Radical Theologies series.
Burke Gerstenschlager at Palgrave has been very supportive and made the
publishing process feel human, a rare achievement in this business and
testament to his skills as an editor.
Finally, I continue to be amazed at the openness and kindness François
Laruelle has extended to me, always patient with my broken French and
Acknowledgments xi
There is a very old philosophical story. We no longer have the full tale, but
only the ending that goes, “Nature loves to hide.” We don’t know if this
is a drama or a tragedy. If you say it with the right inflection it could even
be the punch line to a joke. But is the joke philosophical or is it a joke on
philosophy?
There is another story, even older, and this time theological. It begins
with the beginning (though whether or not it is the very beginning is up
for debate) saying, “In the beginning God created the heavens and the
earth.” The story goes on to say that at that time the earth was formless
and would go on being nothing without this God. Now, they say this story
has an ending and we see there that the earth returns, “Then I saw a new
heaven and a new earth; for the first earth had passed away, and the sea
was no more.”
This story may be epic in scope, but we still don’t know if it is a joke or
not. And we don’t know who that joke is on. For nature has become a prob-
lem. Small talk is filled with discussion of this problem, for now when we
talk about nature we know that we’re talking in part about global climate
change. Some may say that it is shameful how human beings are unable
to work in harmony with nature. That we go against the order of nature.
But this present work began with a different thought. It began with the
thought that nature has become a problem for nature. For if human beings
are natural then there is nothing unnatural about what we are doing to the
biosphere. We haven’t risen above the natural in the creation of nuclear
power any more than the beaver does when he constructs his dam. The
problems caused to other living things by human pollution are entirely
natural. For what is, is natural. There is simply no other test for it. It’s not
as if we can name something an aberration of nature by measuring how
long it can persist living. Duration of living is relative after all and we know
that those creatures living now are but a tiny percentage of those who have
lived on this planet. Yet they were natural and their extinction too was
natural. It is natural to be born, to persist, and to die and it is natural to
2 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the acts that occur during that persistence and even the “corruption,” what
we now call decomposition, that follows after death.
Nature is also a problem at the level of ideas. For the idea of nature
seems to have no direct object. I am unable to simply put nature in front
of me anymore than I can put Being or love in front of me. Rather than
attempting to think nature under this impossibility of objectification, we
instead see in the history of thought a proliferation of very different ideas
of nature. There is the Romantic understanding of nature, where one is
truly free and all is in balance, mingling openly with the pessimistic under-
standing of nature as the site of suffering, pain, and death. There is also the
theological understanding of nature as a good creation, which stands side
by side with the notion that nature is organized hierarchically such that
domination and even death is taken to be not just natural but also divine.
What interests me is not entering into philosophical and theological
debates about what nature could be. These seem to me to be intractable
debates that are more concerned with the philosophical or theological
project putting them forward rather than with thinking nature outside of
those projects. No, what interests me is rather that these projects, the pro-
liferation of strikingly different ideas concerning nature, are natural. And
so in this work I attempt to think and develop that very idea. Subsuming
thought into nature, but without becoming a naturalism or materialism,
without reducing ideas to some kind of “mere nature,” for this itself is but
one of those ideas about nature.
The method for this work is derived from François Laruelle’s
non-philosophy as he has developed it over the last three decades. This
method and the way I’ve synthesized it is explained at length in part II.
What Laruelle’s non-philosophy allows me to do is envisage a different
organization of thinking within different practices of knowledge. Rather
than the usual division of labor between a science that does not think and a
philosophy or theology that must think for science and thereby make sense
of its stumbling across reality, Laruelle fosters a democracy (of) thought
that includes philosophy and science expressed also as a unified theory
of philosophy and science. Even the way he writes this democracy (of)
thought, with the suspended “of,” speaks to this practice of a real democ-
racy as the relationship between democracy and thought is itself suspended
and becomes instead as if One. And the figure of the One is also of great
importance here, as our attempt to think a nature that brings about the
effects of the ideas of nature is also an attempt to think nature prior to
Being and Alterity. To think what Laruelle calls the radical identity of
nature as if One.
However, there is also a model for the work that I have used but
that I don’t discuss at any length. I suspect those who know it can feel
Introduction 3
the powers of this World. This only seems strange, I claim, because what
is most immanent to us is also most alien precisely because of the hallu-
cinatory transcendent structures of thought developed in philosophy and
theology. And to break from those transcendent structures I infect them
with material from scientific ecology. This mutation causing infection
should not be confused with raising science to the level of the sole arbiter
of truth. It would be counterproductive to simply reverse the hierarchy of
science and philosophy/theology as if science was to become some kind
of priest for immanent divinity. But science, I argue following Laruelle,
has a particular posture in its practice, one that is paralleled in theology
to some extent, that thinks from its object and changes its practice on the
basis of its relation to that object. This posture is an expression of radical
immanence.
So what is this immanence? What does radical immanence mean in
this work? The focus on immanence in recent Continental theory is due in
part to the importance given it in the work of Gilles Deleuze, but the term
was central for the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl as well. A focus
on immanence can be found at the heart of widely divergent thinkers such
as Alain Badiou, who understands his philosophy to be materialist, and
immanence can be found in virulent antiscience theological philosophies
such as that of Michel Henry’s. In each thinker the meaning of the word is
different, but in its most common Deleuzian form it is sometimes confused
by some English-language commentators as being a variant of naturalism.
This interpretation is shared in a hostile register by Radical Orthodoxy
theologians. Thus they take the notion of there being no absolute exterior
to immanence to mean that there can be no appeal to something other:
there is nothing but what there is.
In my view this reading of Deleuze is wrong, but dealing with those
readings and presenting a counter-reading is outside the scope of this proj-
ect, which begins instead with Laruelle’s understanding of immanence.
He himself differentiates this from what he takes to be Deleuze’s under-
standing for Deleuze, according to Laruelle, attempts to think an absolute
immanence whereas Laruelle thinks from a radical immanence. Radical
immanence is the experience or style of thinking in-One or from the
Real. Laruelle explains his theory of immanence, differentiating it from
the philosophical “misadventures” of immanence writing, “In philosophy,
Marxism included, immanence is an objective, proclamation, an object;
never a manner or style of thinking.”1 Radical immanence is different from
the Nature of naturalism; it is different from a quasi-thing above con-
sciousness or humanity. Thinking in the manner of radical immanence
is to think neither as a part in a whole, nor as a cog in a cosmic machine,
but in a manner already-manifest prior to thinking as inscribed within a
Introduction 5
system. For that system itself is produced from that immanence. Radical
immanence is prior to ontology or to the difference or alterity to ontology.
Thus we can speak of the immanence of what is, but this “what is” is never
a “merely what is.” For radical immanence is what is, but it is also what
could be and what could have been but will never be. More than this, it
is lived. It is the thought thinking more than it is the totality of thought.
It is not a system, but neither is it unknowable. It is both fleshly, because
a creatural body is radical immanence, but it is also the potential for that
body to die and to love. It is the unconcealed prior to knowledge, prior
to theory, and theory can never circumscribe it but can recognize that it
already is it. This conception of immanence avoids a kind of ideational
friend/enemy distinction between itself and transcendence. This is true
for two reasons: first, transcendence is understood as an effect or a pro-
duction of immanence from this position because, second, transcendence
is in some sense Real at the relative level. There is no reason from the
perspective of the radical immanence of a lived body that what is must
be. There is a relative transcendence at work in the life of that lived body,
but that relative transcendence must be thought in the manner of a lived
body. Nature as a transcendent, quasi-thing is thought in the manner of
radical immanence and in this way nature is thought in exile from worldly
Nature, a wandering Stranger, rather than one who is at home and content
with the mere what is.
This brings us then to the structure of the book. I have split the work
into four parts. In part I, I investigate the standard relationship between
scientific ecology and both philosophy and theology. I begin there with the
axiom: nature is perverse. This is to say it outruns thought. As a result, each
regional knowledge or knowing (the gerund is intentional) is in an equiva-
lent position with respect to nature: each remains partial and incomplete.
Beginning with this axiom already separates the work undertaken here
from classical Greek metaphysics, the transformation of that metaphysics
in Christian theology, as well as the contemporary forms of reductionist
naturalism and materialism. In this section I show how ecology’s object
is not nature as such, but the ecosystem. The ecosystem reveals aspects or
occasions of nature, but is not nature itself, for nature outruns ecological
thinking as well as philosophical and theological thinking. I then turn
to the respective relations between philosophy, theology, and ecology in
order to show the various types these dominant standard relational forms
may take. Philosophy has a subsumption type (which includes, at least
on most readings, Plato to Hegel, Husserl, and Heidegger), where science
must be subsumed into philosophy in order to think, and a bonded type
(which includes Aristotle to Schelling and Žižek), where philosophy claims
to be bonded with science in its thinking. Theology is located within the
6 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
subsumption model, but finds that it can either be a declension type (which
includes, interestingly, Karl Barth and Pope Benedict XVI), where science
can only point to its fallenness, or an inflection type (which includes most
ecofeminists and the liberation theology of Leonardo Boff), where it can
transform itself by working with what it sees as the best, most theologi-
cally fruitful science. In each case, though, there is a certain shallowness in
terms of engagement with scientific ecology. For many philosophies this is
often in the name of some kind of naturalism or materialism taken from
a bonded model with physics. Yet many of the subsumption philosophies
and theologies also purposefully avoid engagement with ecology, as with
all science, as it aims to avoid the perceived failings of both naturalism and
materialism. Even when an inflection type theology thinks with science it
does so with the aim of transcending the shortcomings of naturalism and
materialism. The theory developed in the final part of the book also aims
to avoid naturalism and materialism. Or, rather, in precise terms, I aim for
a theory of nature that is not overdetermined by naturalism or materialism
but one that can nevertheless use naturalist and materialist philosophies in
its construction of a theory of nature just as it can use those philosophies
and theologies antagonistic to naturalism and materialism in the same way.
The survey and typology provided in part I thus serves two purposes: first,
to show the failure of philosophy and theology to engage in a deep way with
the material of scientific ecology and, second, to locate the ideational fields
(philosophy, theology, and ecology) that will be our sources in parts III and
IV for the construction of a non-philosophical theory of nature.
After this survey and typology of the dominant standard relational
forms, I turn in part II to a deep explication of François Laruelle’s
non-philosophy. Laruelle’s work is renowned for its difficulty, yet that
difficulty is but an expression of an attempt to think what is very diffi-
cult—the radical immanence of the One without recourse to subsuming
it into Being or Alterity. While Laruelle’s work has been lumped in with a
general trend in Continental philosophy that sees a return to engagement
with science, sometimes given the misnomer of “Speculative Realism,” his
project differs markedly from others grouped under this name, like the
science and technology studies of thinkers such as Bruno Latour as well as
the recent “return to the Real” in thinkers such as Quentin Meillassoux.
The term “non-philosophy” often gives the reader a sense that this is a
philosophy that says no. Really though, the “non” in non-philosophy takes
its cue from the “non” in non-Euclidean geometry, and like non-Euclidean
geometry it does not negate philosophy, but thinks philosophically in a
different, more general way according to different axioms. Laruelle’s work
provides a model for how the theoretical humanities can come together
with scientific thinking while avoiding the pitfalls of positivism (which
Introduction 7
in ecological principles and concepts, derived from the study of the eco-
system, challenge some standard philosophical and theological notions of
nature. However, instead of focusing on this challenge, which in many
ways would repeat some of the criticisms already made in part I, I focus on
trying to think philosophically and theologically from within the scientific
material. So, this challenge is presented not to shut down philosophical
and theological thought, but to actually be productive of a different way
of thinking within a unified theory of philosophical theology and ecology
or immanental ecology.
This comes to fruition in part IV. Immanental ecology allows me to
treat philosophical and theological conceptions of nature as simple mate-
rial that can be reorganized into a new, more adequate theory of nature.
This comes out of a recognition of the perversity of nature as well as the
natural processes of the ecology (of) thought explored in earlier chapters.
It is important to understand that I am not claiming here that ecology
provides a more adequate understanding of nature and that philosophy
and theology need to simply explicate what ecology already thinks implic-
itly. This would again be a standard form of philosophy or theology that
understands the scientific material to be in some way separate from the
philosophical or theological practice. My claim is rather that nature, as
perverse, can never be thought fully by any single discourse and in fact
can never be thought fully. Instead I claim that the theory of nature con-
structed here is adequate to that reality, that a unified philosophical theory
and ecology can think nature otherwise than we find in naturalism. To
make that argument I first show that the various proliferating ideas about
nature are all thought under an unthought dominance of the World in
philosophy and theology. This worldliness of thinking about nature is
located as an invariant in philosophy that goes mostly unacknowledged. I
then turn to a philosopher who has made an investigation of World central
in his work, Martin Heidegger, and his use of the fourfold to think world-
liness. The fourfold, perhaps one of Heidegger’s more daunting concepts,
is treated under Laruelle’s non-philosophy (specifically a practice called
“unilateralization,” which is explained in part II) to create a single dyad
made up of two minor dyads. These dyads come to stand in for what is
commonly referred to as nature and culture, but as understood through a
relationship of veiling/unveiling and presence/absence. These relationships
are in many ways just as theological as they are philosophical, and indeed
there is a deep connection in the nature dyad with the way the relation-
ship between God and nature has played out in theology and philosophy.
I then turn to these various forms of relation that these dyads exhibit in
theology and philosophy by looking at St. Thomas Aquinas, Benedict de
Spinoza, Abu Ya’qûb al-Sijistânî, and Naīr al-Dīn al-ūsī. What is given
Introduction 9
in the presentation of these thinkers are not readings as such, but rather I
treat them as processes that can be treated ecologically precisely because
thought in general has already been shown to be ecological. I call these
processes, following Goodchild, an expression of piety. As this is a unified
theory of philosophical theology and ecology I am able to think of piety
as something ecological and ecology as being traversed by piety. For in the
unified theory both the terms of ecology and the terms of philosophical
theology are mutated. In this way I am not entering into a wider scholarly
debate, but instead I am treating these thoughts as ecosystems that have
material and energy that can be extracted.
Finally, in the conclusion, I construct a non-philosophical and
non-theological theory of nature using the materials and energies extracted.
This theory can be summarized as having a tripartite structure that under-
stands the creatural as subject of nature, the chimera of God or nature as
non-thetic transcendence of nature, and the One as radical immanence of
nature. This summary is in terms that will here, in the introduction to this
work, seem impenetrable, but by the end of the book should come to have
a determinate meaning for the reader. However, the general shape of this
theory can be understood if you consider what each aspect of the theory
avoids. For, by thinking nature as One or nature from radical immanence,
I am able to avoid both the subsumption and bonded model of philosophi-
cal and theological thinking. For philosophy and theology subsume nature
into their own ontological concerns and thus confuse nature with Being.
This may be why philosophers have claimed that nature loves to hide, for
they never actually looked for it, instead preferring to look for some matter
(materialism) or normative idea (naturalism) that nature would be reduc-
ible to. By thinking the chimerical identity of God or nature as a non-thetic
transcendence of nature I am able to avoid naturalism more fully, or rather
I am able to show that the transcendent, hypostasized conception of nature
operative in naturalism is actually a production of immanence and thus is
itself ecologically produced rather than providing metaphysical rules for
ecological processes. In this way a space for freedom is opened up. This
space is not opened up “in nature,” for freedom is natural, but is rather
opened up in the sense that the transcendent aspect of nature is ultimately
made relative to a lived immanence common to all creatures. This crea-
tural aspect of nature is what I claim is the subjectivity of nature. Nature
too has a subjectivity produced from its radical immanence such that every
creature is said to be natural. This disempowers any strong sense of nor-
mativity in “the natural” such as we find in Thomistic natural law theory.
For the perversity of nature is present as subject in the ongoing and diverse
creation of niches by species (which are immanently connected, as you
will see in chapter 9). Indeed there is a certain messianity present in this
10 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
In the introduction I said that the goal of this work is to foster a democracy
(of) thought among the disparate fields of philosophy, theology, and ecol-
ogy. This democracy (of) thought is not an end unto itself, but is neces-
sary in order to denude these discourses of any pretense to a hierarchical
posture over the others. This in turn will allow us to treat material within
these discourses as just that—simple material that can be distributed and
organized in a different ecosystem (of) thought. This chapter serves to sur-
vey these fields as they are currently organized in relation to one another.
In terms that will be discussed at length in part III, we will examine the
ecotones or the limits of their identity as they come up against one another
as already constituted, though unconsciously, as ecosystems (of) thought
(an ecotone is a transition zone between two different ecosystems, often
there will be a blending of elements from two different ecosystems and
species will be present in the ecotone that are not present in either of the
two bordering ecosystems). I will trace their limits and the spaces at their
limits where they blend (ecotone) and in these limit-ecotone spaces we will
find what remains unthought within their strict borders, what remains
presented as if unecological in being thus thought, and we will then begin
to identify the perversity of nature foreclosed to thought. As we will come
to see, it is this blindness of these discourses to the perversity of nature
foreclosed to thought, their refusal or inability to allow scientific ecology
to infect and mutate their own thinking about their own thinking, that
lies behind their remaining unecological in thinking nature.
Recognizing the perversity of nature is recognizing that nature is stranger
than any one regional knowledge, be it philosophy, theology, or scientific
ecology, can capture. Recognizing the perversity of nature means recog-
nizing the radically foreclosed character of nature to thought. In terms that
14 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
I adapt from Laruelle, “nature” becomes a first name for the Real. Laruelle
gives this definition to first names, “Fundamental terms which symbolize
the Real and its modes according to its radical immanence or its identity.
They are deprived of their philosophical sense and become, via axiomatized
abstraction, the terms—axioms and theorems—of non-philosophy.”1 A
certain term, chosen in part for its fittingness with the Real, is transformed
from its philosophical sense or meaning and thought according to certain
axioms of the Real. The sense that nature is foreclosed to thought is a
mutation of the historical philosophical stance toward nature, transmitted
through its Greek filiation, that “nature loves to hide.”2 As Pierre Hadot
has shown, this underlying idea about nature has been able to accommo-
date a variety of very different philosophical visions about nature, from
its original meaning in Heraclitus that the death of things is unavoidable,
“What is born tends to disappear,” to the modern antagonism between
the Promethean and Orphic attitudes.3 The first, combining the attitudes
of both magicians and scientists, claims that nature has hidden itself in
mechanization and that mechanics itself can unveil nature and reveal its
secrets, which are of or can be turned into human use. The second, shar-
ing much in common with the green notion of “small footprints,” seeks to
unveil the spiritual secrets of nature, to unveil nature though contempla-
tion, art, and poetry and thereby take pleasure in this knowledge without
any particular concern for its use. While there is certainly an antagonism
between these two attitudes, there is also a fundamental amphibology: for
both, nature is veiled and can be unveiled.
This is not what our axiom, that the perversity of nature is foreclosed
to thought, means. Nature itself is not veiled, nature does not “love to
hide”; no, nature is radically immanent as the Real. That is, the metaphor
of nature’s veil already beguiles one into thinking that there is something
other than nature, something we can appeal to outside of nature. Yet, if we
think nature in an ecological thought we have to recognize that the veil is
also nature! No, nature is not veiled, but thinking this allows our regional
knowledges to think that they can unveil nature, that they can touch and
circumscribe nature with thought and thereby either exploit her for our
own gain or save her. Our contemporary climate, both in the physical and
intellectual sense, is determined by a single force: the neoliberal capital-
ist ideology that demands everything reduce its value to the quantitative
measure of money so that it can produce more of this measure. Nature,
though, appears to be purposely deviating from what is accepted as good,
proper, or reasonable in capitalist society. Nature itself appears to be refus-
ing to go away, to separate itself off from “culture” and the human person,
and insists on inhering to every part of culture and within every human
person, and it resists bowing before capitalism’s demand, to be measured as
Nature Is Not Hidden but Perverse 15
something relative rather than the radical condition for any relative mea-
surement.4 This is not hidden from us; we know the perversity of nature.
It is present in our bones, the aches some get when a storm is coming and
the way that weather is no longer a matter of mere conversation but of life
and death concern.5 We are witnesses to the perversity of nature as we are
an instance of its perversity.
In other words, which will be explained in more depth in part II, the
causal relationship of nature to thought is a unilateral one. Nature, as a
name for the Real, determines all thought; in the last instance all thought is
natural. This may cause certain misunderstandings. For instance, someone
may read this and think it means that thought has no influence or causal
power in the world. This would be to confuse two levels of autonomy, the
relative and radical, for, of course, thought can affect things in the world.
An idea can lead to or participate in a change to a society. An idea can lead
us to destroy an ecosystem or to restore a degraded one. Yet, none of this
destroys or saves nature as such. The thought can never become unnatural;
it is never not a real idea and what is real is natural. Thought can have real
effects, but cannot affect the Real; thought can think the unnatural, but it
does not do so unnaturally.
Allow us to step back for a moment, before diving into the local mate-
rial of specific thinkers, and survey the whole of the field from a little
higher up. We have three distinct regional knowledges, what we call eco-
systems (of) thought: philosophy, theology, and ecology. These identities
may seem too pure in the simple separation here, for, as regards philosophy
and theology, there has been no actual purity of either that we can locate
in the history of thought and the same holds true for ecology, as it found
itself developing among and responding to philosophical and theological
notions of nature. The messy reality of these discourses gives me no offense
and it does not need to lead into mystification. After all, though Spinoza
devotes the first part of his Ethics to a treatise on God, surely a theology
by definition, no one feels all that uncomfortable calling him a philoso-
pher. In the same way Aquinas, while clearly devoting much of his work
to “pure” philosophical matters or matters that seemed removed from the
everyday problems of religious believers, he is nevertheless a Doctor of the
Roman Catholic Church and we have no difficulty referring to him as
a theologian. Finally, though Aldo Leopold’s classic 1949 work A Sand
Country Almanac bears upon certain philosophical problems, both meta-
physical and ethical, he was never a professor of philosophy but rather
was a forester and eventually became a Professor of Game Management in
the University of Wisconsin-Madison’s Department of Forest and Wildlife
Ecology and no one seems to think a professorship in philosophy was sto-
len from him.
16 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
The Christian faith, however, does not consider them as such; thus, it
regards fire not as fire, but as representing the sublimity of God, and as
being directed to Him in any way at all. For it said: “Full of the glory of
the Lord is His work. Hath not the Lord made the saints to declare all His
wonderful works?” (Eccles. 52:16–17)6
The material is reality itself, but the posture taken toward reality is deter-
mined by the development of dogma in the light of a particular revelation,
while philosophy, especially at its limits in thinkers such as Spinoza, aims
to think from a position that it takes to be more universal, unmoored by
strict boundaries (though there are of course some) and to find some kind
of secure grounding for knowledge outside of particular or local revelations.
Here the material is also reality itself, but the stance is more universal, in
varying degrees, and an attempt to think a universal ground of knowledge.
This means that philosophy can dismiss more easily certain antagonisms
between certain dogmatic statements coming out of a religious community
and what knowledge derived from “nature” or from outside of that religious
community, but it also means that philosophy tends to split up thought
itself in a way that theology does not tend to, for instance, between revela-
tion and ground. These are both incredibly schematic definitions and not
intended to bestow any kind of absolute judgment on either theology or
philosophy, but only to delineate distinct fields by way of strong tendencies
in terms of material worked with and the practice of working on that mate-
rial. As will become clear throughout this chapter I find within both fields
aspects that are problematic in terms of thinking ecologically and aspects
that are indispensable. We can, however, give a definition to ecology that is
a bit more precise. While the material of philosophy and theology is reality
itself, a necessarily abstract definition if we are to include all the various
philosophers and theologians valued as such in the history of thought, the
material for ecology is more concrete and common among ecologists. The
primary material is that of the ecosystem, discussed at more length later,
and it is from the concept of the ecosystem that working with any other
material is practiced, be it philosophical or some physical material within
a particular environment.
These then are our three distinct regional knowledges that we move
within in this work. We can speak of their limits as regards each other
because of the dominant tendencies we have located, which also avoid any
kind of naive, strict separation or desire for purity among them. What is
most at issue is not the relationship of philosophy and theology, often an
antagonistic one that every philosopher and theologian has some opinion
on. No, what is most at issue here is the relationship between science and
philosophy or theology, specifically between ecology and philosophy or
theology. Not as regards the historical relationship between science and
philosophy or theology, which has been both antagonistic and beneficial,
but as regards this specific science, ecology, and the stances that philoso-
phy and theology take toward it with regard to their own thought. First,
we will examine the relationship of ecology to philosophy or theology,
which I simply call “thought” in this section. This is important because
18 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
The most important concept within ecology is the ecosystem. This con-
cept has changed over time, but the currently accepted definition is that
the ecosystem is a physically locatable and quantifiable community formed
by a system of energy exchange between the living, the dead, and the nev-
er-living where, when energy animates the system, there is an exchange
of energy and material between the living and the dead.1 It is not often
understood that this concept, the most important and foundational within
ecology, was created in response to the overdetermination of ecology by
two schools of thought: organicism and mechanism. These schools of
thought are philosophical and theological in their make-up and concern
the reality of nature as such. The ecosystem concept is first articulated
in 1935 by A. G. Tansley in his unification of these two rival schools of
thought as they were understood and shaped by the material and stance
of ecology. The organicists, primarily developed in and from the work of
F. E. Clements, were opposed by the individualist reaction against organi-
cism of Henry Gleason and his followers. In Clements’s view the ecosys-
tem, which he named “biome,” was like a single organism where all the
parts worked toward the health of the whole. Whereas Gleason rejected
this organic view of nature and instead proposed that natural communities
of plants are simply a random grouping of individual species that existed
in that place because of the possibility of satisfying their needs, Tansley
rejected the organicism of Clements, but could not follow the coincidental-
ism of Gleason, which constituted a decisive critique of Clements’s views
but did not provide any satisfactory understanding of the relation between
plant communities. To overcome both their weaknesses Tansley forged a
new theory from the dyad of holistic organic community and individual-
istic coincidental community.2
20 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
will stand in contrast to the attempt taken later to create a unified theory
of philosophical theology and ecology.6
Botkin begins his historical survey with Nature as Divine Order.7 Under
this image, largely prior to the advent of ecological science, scientists
undertook the study of the environment under the presupposition that
nature tended toward an underlying equilibrium. This presupposition did
not rely on specific religious doctrines, but rather on what can be termed
“religious sentiment.” Any discussion of dogmatic theology is notice-
ably absent from Botkin’s overview.8 Rather, in the scientific writing of
Christian scientists, Botkin locates a reliance on the thought of Cicero,
Seneca, Plato, and Xenophon.9 Under this pregiven image scientists made
attempts to locate some sense of order (understood as equilibrium and pur-
posiveness) in nature, often in spite of observations to the contrary. This
belief in an ordered equilibrium led to an ecological theory of population
equilibrium between predator and prey, meaning that scientists assumed
there was a “natural” (meaning in actuality a truth that was transcendent
and eternal) relationship between predator and prey such that they would
always balance one another out. Botkin traced the failure of this view in
his own book through actual ecological case studies and one can see from
the practice of ecological restoration that the equilibrium theory simply
does not allow one to think the ecosystem as it really is. In other words, the
assumption of what is “natural” does not allow one to accept the actuality
or mode of existence of nature in ecosystems.
Botkin also highlights the anthropocentrism of this view. For the major-
ity whose thought persisted under this image nature has been ordered spe-
cifically for human beings.10 Botkin does not, however, discuss dominion
theory, which interprets this divine order as placing humanity at the pin-
nacle of creation as its Lord, or in more theologically respectable terms, its
Viceroy. Both views, however, present a very pernicious and ecologically
dangerous understanding of hierarchy. Everything praises the Creator of
the Divine Order through individual, dependent relations with the entities
directly higher up in the hierarchy. Thus, through the use made of nature
by human beings nature itself reaches its truest, best, and most beautiful
expression as given by its proper place in the hierarchy.
Under this image nature is ultimately only equilibrium, either as per-
fected or fallen, that is established correctly through hierarchy. Nature
22 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
thus should be static and each being in nature should express its own
static nature/essence if rightly attuned to the reality of the Divine Order as
underlying nature/essence.
Botkin moves from the Divine Order to the organic image of nature.11 This
image takes a number of different shapes depending on the cultural milieu
it develops within and is traced further back than the Judeo-Christian (one
should also add Islamic, though Botkin does not) culture prevalent in the
West today.12 Common to all these varieties, however, is the view “that the
Earth either is like a living creature or is a living creature.”13 Under this
view the Earth is seen to be an idealized or perfected version of an organ-
ism with an analogous organic structure of growth and decay.
Ecologists and other scientists outside the field of ecology largely reject
the organic view of nature today. It should also be noted that philosophers of
the so-called naturalist-materialist orientation often mock this view, while
many ecological philosophies and theologies have tried to reclaim it in the
light of the “new physics.” Despite this now ubiquitous position, there were
scientific attempts to prove the organic view, most notably the attempts
undertaken by the protoecologist and botanist F. E. Clements. Clements,
like many pre-twentieth-century thinkers, looked for the implicit order
underlying nature and saw there were associations of plants containing
discrete individual plant species that would not persist outside the wider
association of plants. This led Clements to the view that nature was like an
organism made up of particular and necessary organs that needed to work
as a whole. This was eventually disproven by Henry Gleason ultimately
relegating Clements to a minor place within the history of ecology as a
cautionary example of what not to think.
Botkin, like most ecologists, rejects the organic view of nature. He sums
up the reasons succinctly saying that the organic view of nature was depen-
dent, like the image of Divine Order, on a static understanding of plant
associations, which was extended to more general associations of organ-
isms, whereas observations show that individual species respond uniquely
to environmental factors. Further, the species that dominates a particular
environment changes continuously.14 However, Botkin is obviously not
comfortable simply mocking this view of nature. While he shows that this
view is indeed wrong from the ecological standpoint, he is also convinced
that the predominant mechanical view is also wrong and in the future
both will be thought to be equally silly and misleading.15
Ecology and Thought 23
Along with many other ecologists, Botkin clearly thinks that the mecha-
nistic account of nature is wrong. Yet, it largely remains the dominant
image under which ecology labors. He traces the outlines of this image
last and emphasizes its connection with the image of Divine Order dem-
onstrating the homology of the mechanistic and theocentric theory of the
cosmos, as well its antagonism to the organic image.16 Under this image of
thought the Earth is dead, for it is a nonliving machine instead of a living
organism.17 The death of the Earth is predicated, however, on a theologi-
cal perception of beauty: “The mechanical view is constant with the idea
of a divine order in most of its particulars and consequences, and thus
the mechanical perspective simultaneously reinforced the ideal of divine
order and was reinforced by that theological perspective.”18 The theologi-
cal perspective Botkin is here speaking of is, of course, the human search
for a static and, due to that stasis, peaceful order to the cosmos that ulti-
mately serves or can be manipulated to serve human ends. There is a deep
connection here between an ecology guided by aesthetics and theological
thinking:
Thus the problem with the mechanical image is the same as the problem
with the image of Divine Order as both attempt to locate simple, solid-state
realities in nature despite the empirical findings of ecological fieldwork.
Nature is not a great machine in the sense of an ideal, nineteenth-century
machine that works according to an outdated physical model for the pur-
poses of static predictions. The one truth that this image could give us has
largely been occluded—nature is ultimately a duality of the artificial and
the natural. From a certain perspective nature is, of course, natural but
from another it is made up of artificialities as well. In other words, human
beings can act as engineers or custodians of this machine for the benefit
of all of nature (human and nonhuman). Yet, instead, the view has tended
to see nature as a divinely constructed machine that must either be left
completely undisturbed to remain perfect as such or completely subjected
24 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Botkin then focuses his attention on two more images that are more
advanced and sophisticated: Nature as Computer or the Cybernetic image
and Nature as Biosphere or the earth as life-support system.21 These
images clearly have some origin in the preceding three, but make signifi-
cant advances on them as they are revised by ecological findings.
The cybernetic image of nature, however, does not provide an adequate
image of a nature that outstrips the biosphere or specific ecosystems, but
using computer modeling guided by mature human observation and
speculation can lead to helpful findings regarding particular ecosystems.22
This is because the computer, unlike the ideal physical machine, can help
ecologists to accurately model mathematically the stochastic reality of eco-
system development. The cybernetic model allows nature incarnated in
ecosystems to be known as they are: nondetermined (i.e., nonmechanical)
dynamic systems of complex exchange.23
This image can also be thought of alongside the other evolving image
of nature: nature as biosphere or life-support system. It should be noted
already that this image of nature is irreducibly coimplicated with the real-
ity of the planet earth as such. Botkin provides a wonderful and grotesque
description of this image by comparing it to the relationship between
a moose and the bacteria that live in the moose’s stomach and that the
moose in turn needs in order to continue living in its particular environ-
ment.24 The most well-known theorist of this image is, of course, James
Lovelock who developed the famous Gaia hypothesis. Under this theory
nature is thought of as a single system that regulates and makes possible
the development and perpetuation of life. Thus, the biosphere metaphor
says that there is some steady-state quality predicated for the planet as
a whole, but not to individual organisms, and this steady-state quality
must be understood within the wider stochastic events in large and small
ecosystems.25 It differs fundamentally from the organic image (though
obviously owing it some debts), a fact often missed in environmental the-
ology, in that the earth is not said to be alive, but is “a life-supporting and
life-containing system with some organic qualities, more like a moose than
a water-powered mill.”26
Ecology and Thought 25
Yet, this doesn’t have to be the end of ecology and thought; this failure
to bring together ecology and thought, that is, philosophy and theology, is
limited because ecology was overdetermined by these images of thought.
Ecology, perhaps for being somewhat more humble than the so-called
thinkers of Big Science in biology and physics, has yet to go on the offen-
sive against philosophy and theology; ecology has not tried to take the
place of philosophy and theology, claiming that it can provide truth better
than them.29 Yet, the concepts that ecology has created and developed
through its history of practice should be a challenge for thought, without
thereby invading and colonizing thought, but instead being a posture that
thought begins to think in or a kind of change in identity when one “goes
under,” both in the sense of going under medication for surgery and in the
sense of going under a different name. We will return to this in the next
chapter, but first we must turn to the relationship of philosophy and ecol-
ogy, both philosophy of nature and environmental philosophy, to see what
happens when philosophy refuses the challenge of ecology and the missed
opportunity to make our thought ecological by “going under” ecology.
Chapter 3
philosophy still does not draw on scientific ecology out of fear of the natu-
ral attitude, but without asking if ecology unified with philosophy can
provide a stronger thought outside of the natural attitude.
While these two strains of philosophical thought, mainstream environ-
mental ethics and phenomenological environmental philosophy, are the
dominant forms of philosophy and ecology there are some other resources
for thinking about the relationship between the science of ecology and
philosophy further afield. These thinkers do not call themselves environ-
mental philosophers, but are instead concerned with nature as understood
through the philosophy of nature. This resurgence of interest in the phi-
losophy of nature has included a renewed philosophical interaction with
physics or scientific cosmology and thus offers us another example of the
relationship philosophy may take toward science in its attempt to think
nature (understood as a first name of the Real). Here the problem of phi-
losophy’s relation to science remains. Does philosophy’s understanding of
nature change in an engagement with science or is nature still thought of
primarily in a philosophical register? Furthermore, is there a theory of the
relation between philosophy and a science other than physics?
the specifics of Leopold’s land ethic, but the very merging of the ethical and
the ontological for breaking certain philosophical rules writing, “This line
of reasoning is not sound from a logical point of view. It confuses fact and
value, ‘is’ and ‘ought.’”3 He goes on to say that ecology, as a special branch
of biology, can only provide facts that have to be taken into account when
one philosophizes about the proper way to live within the physical limits
for survival that those facts set. He goes so far as to claim, “Nothing in
ecology, for example, can tell us that it is wrong to have a wholly exploit-
ative attitude towards nature.”4 In other words, translated into terms famil-
iar to readers of Heidegger, Taylor is making the claim that science does
not think, in this case it does not think ethically. Philosophy must come
alongside it and think for it ethically, even though, in the case of Leopold,
you have a scientific thought and an ethical thought coming together in a
unified manner, while in the case of Taylor’s implicit metaphilosophy you
have two modes of thought that are at war, or at the very least not at peace,
with one another. The particular form this takes in Taylor is common
to mainstream environmental philosophy insofar as it centers on certain
philosophical problems, like the relationship of an “ought” to an “is,” and
takes these as problems that float around scientific ecology’s relationship
to ethics.
It is telling that in Taylor’s development of a theory of environmental
ethics he does not engage in a deep way with ecological concepts. Perhaps,
one might suggest, Taylor constructs such a limit to philosophy and sci-
ence owing to this philosophical commitment to a separation between
ontology and ethics. Such a notion should be able to be tested by consider-
ing a philosophy that rejects this separation. One philosophy that appears
not to suffer so acutely from this same separation of the ethical and the
ontological and metaphysical is the deep ecology or ecosophy of Arne
Naess, perhaps owing to the influence of Spinoza on his own work.5 He
recognizes that “one’s ethics in environmental questions are based largely
on how one sees reality” and thus holds that it is “important in the phi-
losophy of environmentalism to move from ethics to ontology and back.”6
Yet, though this would seem to place it at odds with Taylor’s strict separa-
tion of the ontological and the ethical, we find that both have the same
limit-structure with regards to its practice and relationship to science. The
notion of a deep ecology would appear to suggest that Naess’s philoso-
phy is developed alongside concepts from scientific ecology, yet Naess’s
real hope is to move from ecology to ecosophy. Ecology doesn’t appear
to set the agenda for the philosopher, but instead provides, as it so often
does, a litany of facts about the destructive power of contemporary human
society on the wider nonhuman world. Rather than challenge philosophy
with ecology, as we aim, Naess provides philosophy and ecology with a
30 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Naess recognizes that a true ecosophy cannot separate the ethical and the
ontological as strictly as Taylor, though he organizes ecosophy along a sim-
ilar structure such that the science of ecology is, like an “ought,” unable
to provide any principles for action. We find the same general structure of
science requiring a philosophy purified of its scientific deviations at work
in the phenomenological tradition, while providing a philosophy that is,
ironically given Naess’s aims, more “lived” or “everyday” than ecosophy.
Rather than proceeding from norms, that is, from what “ought,” phenom-
enology proceeds from the thing itself, from the essence of what appears
to us because these norms are already suspect as developing within the
natural attitude. The natural attitude names that particular way of think-
ing that we take as given, but that, if we begin to think critically about the
structures of our thought, appears instead as just a frame of reference or
meaning within a wider pregiven horizon that Husserl calls the life-world.
In this section I’ll consider the underlying structure of phenomenology’s
relationship to science as it is developed in Husserl, which is defined by the
“crisis of the sciences,” and how that is developed by the environmental
phenomenology of John Llewelyn. What will be common to all, though,
is the submission of science to phenomenology, to a form of philosophy
developed necessarily apart from science.
Philosophy and Ecology 33
it; indeed, losing life itself. Husserl’s solution to this problem is locating an
anonymous, transcendental subjectivity that is “functioning in all experi-
encing, all thinking, all life, thus everywhere inseparably involved,” but
that itself has “never been grasped and understood.”25 How he gets to that
transcendental subjectivity, however, is what is ingenious in Husserl. Notice
that he accuses science divorced from the life-world as being naive.26 Yet,
the solution to that naivety is to plunge into it intentionally, whereas before
one simply acted in it. This may become clearer if one considers this in
light of Plato’s familiar cave myth. There we have the prisoners, chained to
a wall since birth and made to watch shadows of people, animals, and the
like dance on the wall of the cave. This is their only frame of reference so
that they take, completely naturally, these shadows as truth. When one of
the prisoners escapes, whether through accident or intention, and emerges
into the “real world,” he begins to see things as they really are or, at least,
as more real than they are in the cave. Husserl, though, sees no reason to
leave the cave. In fact, we have every reason to question the notion that
outside the cave is the “real world.” What is outside the cave is just the
world beyond the cave, the cave itself is part of the real world, as are the
materials in the cave that hold the prisoners to the wall and the materials
for projecting the shadows upon the wall. No, what the usual telling of
Plato’s myth serves to do is provide a cover for a more insidious cave. If
we consider this in the Hollywood terms of the twentieth-century’s film
version of this myth, Lana and Andy Wachowski’s The Matrix, it would be
as if there was a matrix inside the matrix. So when Neo takes the red pill
he simply enters into another version of the matrix, one that chains him
ever more for his having thought that he escaped illusion. Indeed, this set
of problems is presented cinematically in the 2010 film Inception directed
by Christopher Nolan.
Husserl’s radical step is to perform an epochē, what is also called the
reduction or bracketing, on what appears. Eugen Fink, one of Husserl’s
closest students and an assistant on many of Husserl’s most important
projects, including the Crisis, describes the epochē as a radical new begin-
ning for thought. “The de-absolutizing of the world (which in the natural
attitude is absolutized ) signifies a more radical ‘Copernican revolution’
than the conversion from a geocentric to a heliocentric system—one more
radical than all the philosophical revolution in world outlook which takes
place on the basis of the natural attitude.”27 There is something radical
within Husserl’s thought, a radicality that is perhaps not available to us
now after the institutionalization of phenomenology. Yet, what Husserl’s
epochē did was take away the whole world from us, though of course he
did so in order to bring it back, but bring it back under new conditions, as
a phenomenon constituted by an anonymous transcendental subjectivity.
Philosophy and Ecology 35
Any interest in the being, actuality, or nonbeing of the world, i.e., any
interest theoretically oriented toward knowledge of the world, and even any
interest which is practical in the usual sense, with its dependence on the
presuppositions of its situation truths, is forbidden; this applies not only to
the pursuit, for ourselves, of our own interests (we who are philosophizing)
but also to any participation in the interests of our fellow men—for in this
case we would still be interested indirectly in existing actuality.32
project, who did not know what the effect of the atomic bomb would be,
but who went out to the desert, put on the their goggles, and detonated it to
find out. They did this knowing that one possible scenario could have been
the complete destruction of the atmosphere, meaning the complete anni-
hilation of all life on earth. But, though Husserl’s description is far from
the nostalgic gatekeeper of meaning that he is presented as by Brassier and
others, it does share certain less dramatic qualities with science. Consider
again ecology, where after the failures of chaining ecological science to
pre-ecological philosophical images of natures, it tended to consider the
ecosystem simply as it appears. Instead of approaching the ecosystem with
an aura of metaphysical presuppositions, presuppositions that unlike the
physicist the ecologist isn’t allowed because of the inherent complexity of
an actual object, the ecologist approaches the ecosystem naively with only
a handful of axiomatic concepts that can be revised on the basis of the
“presentation” of the object. Husserl’s philosophy attempted to do the same
thing within the field of philosophy. Throwing off the failures of meta-
physics, not to encourage some agnosticism, but to truly engage the reality
of things. Our goal, as it has been throughout this chapter, is not to assess
the success of that attempt, but only to trace philosophy’s self-constructed
limits with regard to science. In that regard it is telling that Husserl’s dis-
cussion of transcendental subjectivity, a life that runs through things, has
nothing to do with the way that science thinks life. In fact, science is now
treated on this subject antagonistically in the Crisis. We can see this clearly
when Husserl writes:
The radical consideration of the world is the systematic and purely internal
consideration of subjectivity which “expresses” itself in the exterior. It is
like the unity of a living organism, which one can certainly consider and
dissect from the outside but which one can understand only if one goes
back to its hidden roots and systematically pursues the life which, in all its
accomplishments, is in them and strives upward from them, shaping from
within.33
At the far end of the phenomenological tradition this line of thought ends
with the philosophy of Michel Henry, who has no room at all for sci-
ence in his philosophy and instead delivers his own condemnation of the
Galilean sciences writing, “In its inaugural decision, having placed sensible
life, phenomenological life in general outside its field of study, Galilean
science would assuredly not be able to discover it again through research,
even though it calls itself biology.”34 After quoting the words of Nobel
laureate François Jacob, “Biologists no longer study life today,” Henry goes
Philosophy and Ecology 37
on to declaim, “We must take [biology] at its word: in biology there is not
life; there are only algorithms.”35 In distinction to Henry, Husserl spends
most of his Crisis examining the philosophy of objectivism that philoso-
phers fall prey to, rather than engaging in polemic against the sciences as
such. The notion of being “scientific” for philosophers is the equivalent
of taking the red pill, falling into a second matrix, but falling deeper into
illusion for thinking you have escaped it: “Thus nowhere is the temptation
so great to slide into logical aporetics and disputation, priding oneself on
one’s scientific discipline, while the actual substratum of the work, the
phenomena themselves, is forever lost from view.”36
While clearly for Husserl the separation of life from biological life, or
science from the life-world, is not an error or failure of science as such, but
rather one of a certain philosophical way of thinking that pervades science,
we still see in the block quote earlier a skepticism toward science provid-
ing any specific tools for understanding this transcendental subjectivity.
How Husserl submits science to philosophy is far more interesting than
those philosophies discussed earlier, even if the general structure remains
the same. Husserl takes a certain scientific attitude toward the world,
naivety, and radicalizes it. We must still come before the world with our
metaphysical presuppositions bracketed, and even more radically bracket
the whole notion of world; so must science in such a way that it must be
placed within a new philosophical milieu before it can operate outside of
a permanent crisis. That is, only as a philosopher under a transcendental
epochē can one say with Husserl, “I stand above the world, which has now
become for me, in a quite peculiar sense a phenomenon.”37 In this way, sci-
ence is both prized and distrusted. How, though, does this work itself out
in relation to ecology?
Despite phenomenology’s abiding interest in nature, it would be unfair
to expect an explicitly ecologically informed phenomenology from think-
ers like Husserl or Heidegger. Now in the age of ecological crisis, however,
it is unsurprising to find phenomenologists engaging environmental prob-
lems. Yet, of the many books published, few environmental philosophers
take up the radical stance of Husserl’s return to the things themselves but
instead produce studies of past phenomenologists’ considerations of nature
and the environment, sometimes putting them into their historical context
and sometimes suggesting aspects that might be of use to addressing our
current situation.38 One notable exception is the Welsh phenomenologist
John Llewelyn, whose two books of ecophenomenology, The Middle Voice
of Ecological Conscience (1991) and Seeing through God: A Geophenomenology
(2004), remain the deepest phenomenological engagement with environ-
mental thought.39 In both books Llewelyn takes this radical notion of a
38 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Insofar as nature lies outside the remit of just one science, can a philoso-
phy of nature ever hope to think nature if it is eternally and necessarily
bonded to but one science, the science of physics? Of course, Grant is not
suggesting that physics as such is the final arbiter of the truth of nature,
indeed his argument is that by separating physics from philosophy it has
failed to live up to its own identity as the infinite science. That in separat-
ing the subject of physics, physis, from philosophy it has left itself blindly
conditioned by nature. A philosophy that is a compromised antiphysics
will always find itself coming up against the chiding of facile naturalism,
and what lies behind the laughter of these naturalist philosophers, who are
of course compromised as well, is what the compromised antiphysics has
left unthought.
The point here is not to say that Grant has left ecology unthought, which
would be rather silly since his work thus far has been a historical study to
set up his own forthcoming project, but to challenge the philosophical
overdetermination of nature, both as an idea and as that which is (though,
42 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Writing about theology in relation to ecology may seem strange within the
scope of a book that itself stands within no particular religious tradition,
or, more exactly, is unconcerned with its standing within any particular
religious tradition as it aims for a “secularity of thought” within its own
“non-theological” discourse.1 There may even seem to be an air of insin-
cerity or a cynical appeal to the power of a large group present in religious
communities, a group that one may disagree with because they “don’t
know any better” but that can be exploited for the same reason, an atti-
tude present in the appeal of E. O. Wilson to religious believers in his The
Creation (2006).2 There is however an ultimately realist reason for consid-
ering theology within the wider paradigm of “environmental thought”: the
form its thought takes is superior in a specific way to that of philosophy.
Theology is concerned with many of the same questions as philosophy,
and that includes the question of ethics and metaphysics raised by the eco-
logical crisis. However, unlike the environmental philosophies discussed
earlier, the works of ecotheology tend not to separate nearly as easily the
ethical and the metaphysical, even within their own self-understanding of
the discipline; these two strands are always unified within some broader
paradigm, some single, theological vision. As will become apparent in the
next chapter, this prefigures the methodology of non-philosophy; it is akin
to the “vision-in-One” that non-philosophy thinks from. Yet, theology, I
will argue, does not itself break with its own self-sufficiency, it does not
allow itself to be thought ecologically. This is clearest in its interaction
with the science of ecology.
In chapter 1, I say that the limit of theology’s relationship to science is
determined by the absolute subsumption of science into theology, though
this subsumption operates differently than philosophical subsumption
46 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the same time arguing that the modern understanding of science arises
out of Christian nominalists, rather than what he takes to be the much
richer theology explicated by earlier Medieval theologians such as Aquinas
and Augustine.14 Again, we see the transcendental choice at work here. In
one breath, Christianity is absolved of crimes against nature by referring
to Christianity’s varied form, and science is linked to deficient forms of
Christian theology.
It is possible to confuse the difference in number of theologians dis-
cussed under the declension type to that of the inflection type, one envi-
ronmental theologian to three in the next section, with a comment on the
relative influence of each type within religious communities. The reality,
though, is quite different as the relative declension model discussed earlier
is found in the official teaching of the Roman Catholic Church as outlined
in Pope Benedict XVI’s “In the Beginning . . . ”: A Catholic Understanding
of the Story of Creation and the Fall, written when he was then Cardinal
Joseph Ratzinger, and in his third encyclical, Caritas in veritate, outlin-
ing Roman Catholic social teaching. In the encyclical he sums up Roman
Catholic social teaching regarding ecology in this way:
All the elements of the declension model are present here: an overall sub-
sumption of science into the theological vision, an appeal to the real dete-
rioration of the biosphere or nature, and finally an appeal not to science, or
other seemingly rational forms of thought such as economic planning, but
to the renewal of human society, what Benedict calls “overall moral tenor,”
brought about through a return to a premodern organization of thought.
Benedict’s dismissal of science as a partner in the forming of theological
thought is, if not explicit throughout the rest of the encyclical, implicit in
his unecological splitting of “human ecology” and “environmental ecol-
ogy,” advocating some kind of strange “trickle down ecologics” whereby
if we simply respect nature certain environmentally harmful aspects of
our dwelling on the earth will, the text suggests, be alleviated or disap-
pear altogether. Never mind that part that says an ecologically informed
response to our current untenable form of life is the encouragement of
50 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
family planning, including sexual education and birth control, ideas that
go explicitly against Roman Catholic social teaching.
In short, because science is taken as fallen it isn’t even suitable as a
conversation partner beyond its being a sign of human fallenness. As we
saw with Northcott, the reader is asked to accept the varied forms that
Christian theology may take without any recognition of the varied prac-
tices at work in science. And again there is no sense that science could even
challenge theology, that, even if it is historically correct that it arises from
nominalism, it could creatively respond to the shortcomings of nominal-
ism. Thus, in the declension type, the subsumption of science is a com-
plete disempowering of science to challenge theology in any way, except to
respond to the environmental crisis as theology. That is to say, it responds
as theology bonded to its own circularity.
more radical in that she both recognizes the lack of any “golden age” from
which decline could be located and locates the underlying problem within
thought further back than McFague, and thus further entrenched in our
culture, in the way dominant global cultures “have construed the idea of
the male monotheistic God” and the subsequent “relation of this God to
the cosmos as its Creator.”18 This construction of God and the relation-
ship reality has with God has had the effect of “reinfor[ing] symbolically
the relations of domination of men over women, masters over slaves, and
(male ruling-class) humans over animals and over the earth.”19 While I
identify more closely with this model, ultimately the relationship between
theology, as one regional knowledge, and ecology, as one scientific regional
knowledge, remains overdetermined by the identity of theology and its
own circularity.
Ultimately the theologians grouped under the inflection type hold that
science provides a valuable and necessary dialogue partner for theology.
However, their understanding of how that dialogue works differs greatly.
For instance, while McFague sees promise in some contemporary cos-
mological and biological theories that emphasize a cosmic life to things,
she also holds that the earlier “picture of reality” also had, and contin-
ues to have, scientific supporters.20 There is a certain incoherence to her
understanding of the relationship of theology and science, for while she
sees within certain strands support for “the organic model,” a model she
believes fits well with a theological statement that the world is the body of
God, that God suffers in the making poor of the world, she has no reason
for thinking this statement will remain theologically or scientifically valid.
Or indeed, as could be argued, why that lack of future validity may not
be necessary. She thus provides no metatheology, no criteria for why this
aspect of science can be used as a resource for theology. This is symptom-
atically important since the book bases much of its positive project on a
model of the relationship between God and World (as one Body) that she
says “is [ . . . ] in keeping with the view of reality coming to us from con-
temporary science.”21 Why is it that the science of ecology is only used as
a resource in relation to the facts it gives us about ecological degradation?
Her own lack of attention given to ecological science is evident in her privi-
leging of the idea of wilderness present in her view that as mostly urban
dwellers we no longer know “wilderness as a yardstick,” the idea being that
we no longer know how nature really is or that we lack “a measure of how
we have changed the world.”22 Wilderness is not an ecological concept,
but a philosophical one, for the city is an ecosystem too, and often can be
understood as a viable one at that.
McFague seems less interested in engaging specifically with ecology
so much as she’s interested in thinking theology in the light of a new
52 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
exhaust gases from a bus is related to our Milky Way. My own conscious-
ness is related to elementary particles.25
to take one example, of theology’s disrespect for the body in its major
traditions. For Northcott, who expands the declension narrative, and
McFague, who allows a place in her ecotheology still for a strong declen-
sion narrative, and even in Ruether, who rejects the idea that there is some
prior good state from which a decline began, we still find an eschewing
of technology (not unlike Heidegger) as well as the urban, laying much of
the ecological blame for climate change on the lifestyles of urban dwell-
ers, even though there is a good deal of evidence suggesting that we could
continue to have an urban society, and that the required asceticism need
not take a localist bent, but may actually require a closer, more urban liv-
ing situation that involves a great deal less meat eating. This, however, is
a practical argument that does not bear directly on the problem here, it
being my own instance of a “transcendental choice” that requires a greater
theory of the “organon of selection” that undergirds the circular rigor of
the work, which I will discuss in part III. I bring up urban ecology here
only to highlight that neither theologian has internalized the ecological
outlook, for they are not even able to see that the city is an ecosystem,
that there is no coherent or meaningful discussion of wilderness (unless
one wants to go back millennia, but few are brave enough to push their
declension narratives that far), of a biosphere where humanity isn’t part
of the ecosystem.
Boff perhaps provides the best theology within the inflection type in
terms of coming closest to a unified theory of theology and ecology. This
may be in part because the declension narrative is relativized, as it is in
Ruether, but in Boff this serves to direct nearly all the attention toward the
“new paradigm” more than any diagnosis of the problem. We can likely
attribute this to the Marxist undercurrent in liberation theology, which
locates the solution to the present situation in neither some premodern
nor a preurban past, but rather through the construction of some radically
different future. The little attention given to such a task only serves to
implicate Christianity along with the other human elements responsible
for the ecological crisis.29 Yet, if we recall the quote from Boff earlier that
defines ecology as the science of relationality, we see that Boff too engages
rather shallowly with ecology. Though relationality is often seen as a main
tenant in ecology, and certainly the science is concerned with the relations
within a particular ecosystem, it is also concerned with demarcating these
relations in ecologically meaningful ways. Thus, ecologically, the slug on
the roadway, while being ecologically related to the particular ecosystem,
is not “related to everything else in all respects.” Or, to be more precise, it’s
relation to everything else differs importantly in intensity. A concept that
could prove fruitful in a theological context especially in terms of theoriz-
ing about theology’s discourse itself.
Theology and Ecology 55
All of this will be treated in part III. This “immanental ecology” is nec-
essary because under the current regime of thought we can only enter into
an already declared and ongoing war between philosophy and theology
and the various internal wars raging between philosophers and theologians.
This war of opinion is endemic to philosophical and theological thought.
We aim not primarily for propositions that can be assented to or not, but a
more generic form of thought that can respond to ecological reality. Thus,
I will not enter into discussions about the destructive essence of modernity
or whether or not the new physics is actually scientifically tenable. I agree
with Boff (drawing on Koyré and Prigogine) that nonscientific forms of
thought need to be employed within a broad response to the environmen-
tal crisis.30 Indeed, the ideology of scientism, as captured within the wider
paradigm of the capitalist drive toward ecologically untenable growth, has
resulted in a certain mystification of reason. Yet, while I agree with Boff
and others about the need for a broad but unified response to the ecologi-
cal crisis, I don’t think philosophy and theology will themselves become
an ecological thought through the same withdrawal from ideologically
determined science, which is often in practice a withdrawal from science
altogether. Rather, we aim to radicalize certain elements of the preceding
forms of thought surveyed.
As I will argue in the proceeding chapter, we must see all thought as
equivalent before the Real, dare to go further into scientific thought along-
side philosophical theology in order to radicalize the subsumption model
by subsuming thought into a generic matrix. Not to subsume all thought to
a preconceived thought, but to conceive of a model, a kind of quasi meta-
physics that Laruelle calls philo-fiction (playing on science-fiction), from
which thought moves forward denuded of its presumption to divinity, or
its belief to be speaking for divinity. At the same time, this radicalizes
the bonded model, but instead of bonding philosophy to one science, we
understand that philosophy must always be bonded to non-philosophical
thoughts within the radicalized subsumption because of the perversity of
nature. From theology we see that metaphysics and ethics, dualisms in
general, may be unified when one begins to think from that which is fore-
closed to thought, which is the highest in thought, but this too is made
generic and denuded of its particular revelation within a generic framework
of revelation. From this unified perspective we may begin to respond to the
ecological crisis as a crisis in thought by way of an ecological thought.
Part II
At the end of the preceding chapter I ventured the thesis that the envi-
ronmental philosophies and theologies discussed do not think ecologi-
cally, that is, their thought is not ecological, because the structure of their
thought makes it such that they are unable to think ecologically. In this
chapter I will develop this idea by exploring the structural relationship that
philosophy and theology have with the sciences, which includes ecology of
course, and argue that it is the self-sufficient structure of philosophy and
theology that is responsible for this inability. Part II will focus on the work
of French thinker François Laruelle who has, for the last four decades,
developed a theory he calls non-philosophy or, more recently, non-standard
philosophy. In Laruelle’s view there is an intractable war between philoso-
phies and between philosophy and other regional knowledges, in particu-
lar science. The war is intractable because, by the criteria of intellectual
labor, each form of thought operates or works. John Mullarkey discusses
this in his own reading of Laruelle, showing how particular forms of
thought that claim to be at odds with one another nevertheless all still
have some level of success sufficient to allow them to believe these forms of
thoughts should persist, that they are right and helpful. Yet, the respective
metadiscourse, in our case the metaphilosophy or metatheology, “imply
that only one should work— their own. Their claims to truth are mutu-
ally exclusive. [ . . . ] And yet they still do both work.”1 The sense of “work”
Mullarkey deploys and the sense of ecological sense of work are essentially
60 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
of the same kind. This can be seen clearly in discussions on how differing
ecosystems can be said to “work,” that is, to “operate,” without their being
a single ecosystem that is the transcendent telos of the particular ecosys-
tems. Or, to put it in clearer, less theological language, the ecologist stud-
ies and describes the desert just as much as the rainforest, identifying its
ecological relations between the living, the dead, and the never-living, its
biodiversity, its resilience to disturbance, an evaluation of each ecosystem
according to certain generic criteria without passing judgment according
to a single transcendent ecosystem. Indeed, the ecologist tells us that the
desert is a viable ecosystem that works just as much as the rainforest does,
even if there are extreme differences between the two in terms of human
utility, which includes aesthetic appreciation, and even though there are
differences in less anthropocentric terms, as in the amount of biodiversity.
In fact, within the context of an ecosystem’s resilience, biodiversity is not
a good in and of itself. Rather, biodiversity operates within an ecosystem
as “a major source of future options and a system’s capacity to respond to
change and disturbance in different ways.”2 We are unable to pass judg-
ment based on the hard number or even the percentage of biodiversity
in one ecosystem over the other, but must evaluate the strength of that
biodiversity within the particular ecosystem it exists within. The same is
true of our ecosystems (of) thought; one cannot simply discard a particular
philosophy or theology on the basis of its low quotient of diversity of “spe-
cies (of) thought.” In this way, by evaluating and identifying the ecologi-
cal status of these various theologies and philosophies, what Laruelle calls
“making them equivalent,” we end the war by not participating in it within
this thought.3
Laruelle’s identification of a war within philosophy may be a stumbling
block for those who want to engage with his work. However, even if we
bar this word “war” from our description of philosophy (and theology and
ecology) there is undoubtedly still an antagonism between philosophers,
theologians, and science. This is clear in each of the ecologies, philoso-
phies, and theologies reviewed in the preceding chapter and it would seem
that, aside from a few fits and starts here and there, neither side is seri-
ous about fostering peace, what Laruelle calls a democracy (of) thought
and even a communism (of) thought, between their disciplines.4 A remark
from Husserl on science serves to illustrate both the general philosophical
attitude toward science as well as the theological method:
One must finally achieve the insight that no objective science, no matter how
exact, explains or ever can explain anything in a serious sense. To deduce
is not to explain. To predict, or to recognize the objective forms of the
composition of physical or chemical bodies and to predict accordingly—all
Theory of the Philosophical Decision 61
this explains nothing but is in need of explanation. The only true way to
explain is to make transcendentally understandable. Everything objective
demands to be understood. Natural-scientific knowing about nature thus
gives us no truly explanatory, no ultimate knowledge of nature because it
does not investigate nature at all in the absolute framework through which
its actual and genuine being reveals its ontic meaning; thus natural science
never reaches this being thematically.5
The starting questions for a reader may simply be, why Laruelle? Why
non-philosophy? In other words, what is different about non-philosophy as
a practice of thinking and an organization of that thinking in comparison
to the general structure of philosophy and theology present in the environ-
mental theologies and philosophies reviewed in the previous chapter? Or,
at a more abstract level, what is the relationship between non-philosophy
and standard philosophical practice? The answer is that Laruelle provides a
more rigorous criticism of philosophy’s relationship to science than is pres-
ent in other philosophers I have come across. This criticism avoids being a
negation of philosophy by understanding that criticism is a way to free phi-
losophy at its most radical, which is to say at its most immanent. By free-
ing philosophy in this way it helps projects that use the non-philosophical
model to avoid the pitfalls of standard philosophical practice and in this
way allows one to step outside the arbitrary choices given in choosing
between Heidegger or Russell, Deleuze or Quine, Bergson or Badiou,
Levinas or Singer (using the names of these philosophers as an index of
their thought). Each is relative and one is freed from the necessity of judg-
ment and war and thus able to select and construct alongside of material
that lies outside of philosophy as such.
To fully answer these questions and bear out the claims I make about
the liberty given by non-philosophy we need to give some attention to
Laruelle’s theory and analysis of the philosophical decision. This aspect of
non-philosophy has largely been the focus of his reception in Anglophone
philosophy, as in the speculative nihilism of Ray Brassier. The project
developed here recognizes the importance of the theory of philosophical
decision, but it will not be the main focus of the project and I will not go
into great detail about it, in part because the theory is well explained in
64 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
both Brassier and Mullarkey.6 Instead, I understand the theory from the
perspective of the matrix given in the current phase of non-philosophy
(Laruelle calls this Philosophy V and I explain this periodization in more
depth in the next chapter). In this current phase Laruelle understands the
identification of the philosophical decision as what allows non-philosophy
to free thought, specifically in its philosophical forms and forms over-
determined by philosophy, from the illusions perpetuated by standard
philosophy, by locating its relative autonomy in the face of the absolute
autonomy of the Real. This allows for the production of new constructive
and speculative solutions to old philosophical problems. By locating this
structure of philosophy it locates philosophy as material and thus it frees
philosophy to enter into more fruitful relationships with other discursive
fields.
Laruelle claims that the philosophical decision forms the invariant
structure of standard philosophical thinking and always introduces a new
transcendence, and thus new hallucinations, even in those philosophies
that claim to be of immanence. Ultimately the theory of the Philosophical
Decision claims that
[p]hilosophy is not only a set of categories and objects, syntax and experi-
ences, operations of decision and position: it is animated and traversed by
a faith or belief in itself as if in an absolute reality, by an intentionality or
reference to the real that it claims to describe and even constitute, or to
itself as if the real.7
The point of non-philosophy is simply not to think the Real. The first
axiom of non-philosophy is that the Real is foreclosed to thought and so
it cannot think the Real in any meaningful sense, in any sense that would
change the Real, but it may only think from it. It does not aim at reviving a
prior philosophy or constructing a realist philosophy that grounds science
or that protects philosophy from embarrassment before science. Laruelle
aims to make all philosophies equivalent, to take up a scientific posture
toward philosophy, in order to leave the war between philosophers, using
them as simple material in an autonomous exercise that is thought from
the Real.
This aspect of Meillassoux’s critique, in its confusion with itself, does
not really touch on non-philosophy. Its weakness arises partly as confusion
of the order of Laruelle’s thought. The first task is to posit an axiom that
states that the Real is radically autonomous to philosophy. This axiom is
70 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Some have suggested that using the One to discuss the Real as prior to
Being and Alterity and foreclosed to both suggests that non-philosophy
is a “negative theology” of the Real. In reality non-philosophy isn’t a
negation at all, but rather takes the same pragmatic posture that science
does with regard to its own practices. It would be a mistake to call this a
naivety, as Husserl does, for rather than a negation it is actually a more
lived form of thinking. More adequate to the ways in which one actually
practices thinking in the flow of ordinary time. That is, it takes the Real
as the necessary “superstructure” for thought, rather than as that whose
being or nonbeing negates the possibility of thinking in general.29 In other
words, the realist suspension, which can be found in science, is a rela-
tionship with the Real that thinks without any recourse to a transcendent
self-founding.30 Non-Philosophy is a practice, not an account of foun-
dation, and in that way it does mirror theology and, while escaping the
critiques of Meillassoux, still requires a non-theology to supplement and
complete its practice by explaining the immanent practices and resistance
to illusion at work in the realist suspension of non-philosophy. But before
turning to that non-theology we must first explain the practice and prin-
ciples of non-philosophy that non-theology necessarily builds from.
Chapter 6
The question of the relationship between science and philosophy was cen-
tral in Laruelle’s shifting from a typical philosophical practice (what he
74 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
actual the declaration of peace to the philosopher that had been hinted
at in the previous period by way of his conception of a unified theory of
philosophy and science. This theory was unified, rather than a unity,
because of the general philo-fiction structure that theorized both dis-
cursive practices as relative before the Real. In Philosophy IV Laruelle
deploys this unified theory in a number of investigations of other non
philosophical material (in the sense that they lie outside of “philosophy
proper,” hence why I have left out the hyphen), returning to questions
about politics and turning for the first time to a serious investigation
of religion, thereby deepening his concepts and elements of style, like
heresy, that he had lifted from various religious traditions and that were
already operative in his earlier works.
In his Principles of Non-Philosophy he provides a short history of the
development of non-philosophy in relation to the way that the axioms
of non-philosophy were modified in accordance with new materials. He
claims that what changes within the structure of non-philosophy, what he
now describes as “the water of the wave,” is the axioms at play within it. Here
Laruelle locates three distinct periods of non-philosophy, Philosophy I–III,
that he thinks responds to the triadic structure of philosophy itself (under-
stood by Laruelle to find its essence in the philosophical decision).2 In his
own estimation the work of non-philosophy, where philosophy is finally
taken as a simple material that one can work with, does not truly begin
until Philosophy III and is not truly completed until his latest major work,
Philosophie non-standard. Philosophy I is characterized by what may be
described in a Deleuzian way, as Laruelle’s apprenticeship in philosophy.
In his own words this period should be understood to have “placed itself
under the authority of the Principle of Sufficient Philosophy.”3 He contin-
ues on to say, that at this stage he
already sought to put certain themes to work; themes that would only find
their definitive form, a transformed form, in Philosophy III: the individual,
its identity and its multiplicity, a transcendental and productive experience
of thought, the theoretical domination of philosophy, the attempt to con-
struct a problematic rivaling that of Marx, though mainly on Nietzschean
terrain and with Nietzschean means.4
While the work here prefigured in an indefinite form the problems that
Laruelle continued to consider well into Philosophy III, its true addition
to the project of non-philosophy was the discovery of the principle of
sufficient philosophy or the philosophical faith that everything is philoso-
phizable. In the end this faith in the sufficiency of philosophy masks a cor-
relation between philosophy and the appearance of the Real found in the
76 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Philosophy III is then the proper start of non-philosophy nearly freed from
the vicious circle of the philosophical decision. It has two major concepts
that arise from the axiomatic suspension of Philosophy II’s second axiom:
force (of) thought and unified theory.14 It is from these two concepts that
the positive project begins as differentiated from its negative and critical
forms found in Philosophy I and II.
The concept of force (of) thought is complex, but some understanding
can be had if one understands its more prevalent philosophical precursor
found in the Marxist conception of labor power. According to the Marxist
ontology labor power constitutes the movement of historical materialism
and labor power in itself is not reducible to a worker’s functions or output.
In capitalism this labor power is alienated from the worker by his creation
of a product that is then given a value outside of the product itself as crys-
tallized in the form of money. The force (of) thought is similar in that it is
the organon or means though which the Real possesses a causality of the
One that avoids alienating itself in its material. That is because the force
(of) thought is a clone of the One, rather than its production or reproduc-
tion into some material form proper to it. In this way it is productive of
thought in a circular manner, but in such a way that it contains the essence
of the Real without adding to or subtracting anything from it.15 What is
most important about the force (of) thought is its alien status. The force
(of) thought appears as an alien or, as Laruelle writes it, “Stranger” from
outside of the philosophical situation, that is to say from outside of the
structure determined by the philosophical decision, and in so doing pro-
vides an occasional solution to certain problems in philosophy. In short
the force (of) thought is, as Laruelle says, “the first possible experience of
thought.”16
Finally, there is the concept of unified theory, already discussed earlier,
but to review remember that Laruelle means by this a unified theory of sci-
ence and philosophy, of ethics and philosophy, of psychoanalysis and phi-
losophy, of religion and philosophy, and so on: “The unified theory replaces
80 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the affinity of the One and science with the unilateral equality of philoso-
phy and science, philosophy and art, ethics, etc., with regard to the One
and introduces the ‘democratic’ theme within thought itself rather than as
a simple object of thought.”17 The democracy (of) thought is ultimately an
axiom and not a conclusion. One must begin as if a unified thinking of X
and philosophies were equal in the sight of the One in order to attempt and
think outside the problems inherent to philosophy due to its enclosure in
the structure of the philosophical decision. By treating thought as if it were
democratic, rather than a thought of democracy, one begins to truly think
from the One, as the One is itself outside of any unitary discourse and is
instead the universal discourse found in regional discourses.
With the publication in 2002 of Le Christ futur. Une leçon d’ hérèsie (pub-
lished in English translation in 2010 as Future Christ: A Lesson in Heresy)
Laruelle inaugurated a new stage of non-philosophy, Philosophy IV. It is
here that Laruelle appears to have finally escaped from the self-sufficiency
of philosophy present even in Philosophy III’s constant reference to pre-
cursors in metaphysical systems such as Cartesianism and Marxism. With
Philosophy IV Laruelle has begun to produce a whole host of new concepts
from the vision-in-One (keeping in mind that this is an equivalent term
to the Real and the One itself) alongside religion, ethics, and aesthetics.
While the entire project of non-philosophy is in itself interesting, and can
be highly productive of thought outside of Laruelle’s corpus as witnessed
to by the work being carried out in wildly different ways under the banner
of non-philosophy, it is in Philosophy IV that the true worth for think-
ing from the Real becomes apparent.18 What, though, is the change in
axiom here? Does the change from Philosophy III to Philosophy IV con-
stitute a change in axiom in the same way that Philosophy II changed to
Philosophy III? The answer to this question may be found in the text La
Lutte et l’Utopie à la fin des temps philosophiques (2004), translated into
English as Struggle and Utopia at the End Times of Philosophy (2012), where
he again turns to the axioms that allow non-philosophy to function. Here
they take a slightly modified form. To be more precise, they are modified
in that they are now more generalized: “1. the Real is radically immanent,
2. its causality is unilaterality or Determination-in-the-last-instance, 3. the
object of that causality is the Thought-world, or more precisely, philosophy
complicated by experience.”19 As will be discussed in the final chapter, for
Laruelle the World and philosophy are one and the same—the World is the
form of philosophy. Whereas the move from Philosophy II to III was effec-
tuated by the suspension of the axiom of science’s privileged relationship to
the Real, Philosophy IV begins with the intensification of attention given
to the complication of philosophy in experience. That is, Philosophy IV is
concerned with what might be traditionally called philosophical problems,
Non-Philosophy—Practice and Principles 81
It is the scientific attitude that consists in entrusting to science itself the elu-
cidation of its essence, to science the recognition all way through of its radi-
cality and derive all the consequences of its autonomy: science is for itself,
at least in its cause—the Identity-of-the-last-instance—, an emergent theo-
retical object, a “hypothesis,” or an “axiom” in the “hypothetico-deductive”
sense.31
arguments and positions about reality taken to be the Real, what dif-
ferentiates Laruelle from those philosophers engaging in a war over the
status of science is that he accepts the autonomy of science, he accepts
that it is free in its practice from philosophical conditions. He opposes
this to the tripartite division discussed earlier in order to show “that
every science, ‘empirical’ or not, is also a thought; that it is absolute in
its kind [genre]; that it bears—at least ‘in-the-last-instance’—on the Real
‘itself.’”36 To quickly summarize, in this early work Laruelle rejects the
philosophical-epistemological tripartite division of labor, which results in
philosophy’s invariant approach to science or its separation of the tran-
scendental and the empirical. Rather than following some variant of this
usual philosophical approach to science, which may differ in terms of what
is valued in this split, but still accepts some form of this split, Laruelle
proposes a thought experiment where philosophy is mutated. This thought
experiment is, as I have said earlier, ethical and demands that philosophy
practice in the face of its Other. The essence of philosophy is to break up
its object and then to take this break as constitutive of the Real, rather than
localized in philosophical practice. Philosophy renders the object into a
dyad, an empirico-transcendental doublet, that is always united (not uni-
fied) by some third term, whether that term be named “transcendence” or
“immanence” and follow the different paths the chosen name determines.
The posture of science, which underlies the various scientific practices,
does not split its object, even when it breaks up an object into its constitu-
ent parts; it does so with the underlying realist thesis that the object is
One-in-the-last-instance.37 This thesis, Laruelle claims, is incomprehen-
sible to philosophy because philosophy requires some third term, some
transcendent (in its operation) unity to the object, rather than the radical
immanence of the One-in-the-last-instance. Here, the two central con-
cepts of non-philosophy appear: the One (Real-One, One-in-One, etc.)
and determination-in-the-last-instance (which is the causal equivalent to
the vision-in-One, and is also called unilateral duality).
Importantly for our project, and in accord with the reality of science,
Laruelle especially rejects the second division within the tripartite division—
the division of science into empirical and transcendental.38 This division
is the vehicle for the philosophical doublet the “empirico-transcendental,”
which is maximalized by philosophy in its splitting up of the Real-One in
the Philosophical Decision. What Laruelle locates in science, and why he
at first gives in to the temptation to simply reverse the post-Kantian hier-
archy, is its nondecisional relationship to the One, such that science prac-
tices the vision-in-One rather than the philosophical splitting of the One
into condition and conditioned, empirical and transcendental. Laruelle
therefore claims that “[e]very science, even ‘empirical’ ones called such by
Non-Philosophy—Practice and Principles 87
superstructures have effects, but they are akin to accidental effects and they
do not have any strong effect on the core form of the political-economic
realm.43 Laruelle, calling determination-in-the-last-instance the “lost axi-
omatic of materialism,” extracts and mutates determination in the last
instance from its context in historical materialism and “transfers and radi-
calizes [it] in first Science or according to the One, which gives the concept
its radical sense and allows its full use.”44 This mutation of the concept
actually places Marxist thought within a transcendental framework as
well, where its own claims to sufficiently describe reality are relativized
and its orthodoxy challenged. For no longer does the determination-in-
the-last-instance arise from the economic realm, but instead the claim
about how thought itself, even thought concerning the economic realm, is
shown to be determined-in-the-last-instance by the One.
Stated otherwise, “‘In-the-last-instance’ thus identically signifies that
the cause is not alienated in the subject of its effect or in its effect itself and
that on its side the effect retains a relative autonomy.”45 What this means is
that human thought, arising as it does from any of its regional knowledges,
has relative autonomy, but it has no strong effect on the Real-One itself.
The strong causality goes in one direction, such that the object is One-in-
the-last-instance and the thought cannot split the Real-One in itself, it
is a unilateral duality. What is interesting, then, about determination-in-
the-last-instance, for Laruelle, is that it is a double causality made up of
two terms, which Laruelle says are
the case of nature “just matter,” “just genes,” “just chance,” and so on, or
the crass reductionism of theologism, which reduces nature to “just cre-
ation” (and the double sense of “just” is intended here). Since a critique of
scientism, and other forms of reductionary “naturalism,” is ubiquitous to
environmental ethics, philosophical and theological, I do not devote atten-
tion to it here in the discussion of Laruelle but it will become important
again in part IV, while in the next chapter I will discuss the relationship
between theology and non-philosophy in order to short-circuit the theo-
logical negation of nature by way of the name “creation.” This is neces-
sary to both disclose the principle of sufficient theology and, in the last
chapter, to free the name “creation” to become a form of material that may
be used.
messianism, art, mysticism, politics, and the like, and again turns its
attention intensely toward science. Philo-fiction, the quantum, and the
generic, the three terms found in the subtitle of Philosophie non-standard,
are the important aspects of the matrix that characterizes this new phase
and attempt to address both philosophical problems and problems within
non-philosophy itself. Within Philosophy III’s attempt to render certain
“unified theories” there is a question of the particularity of the theoreti-
cal dyad chosen. One side of the dyad is always philosophy, for Laruelle,
but even here the question “which philosophy” will immediately be asked.
That is easily answered in the course of the non-philosophical construc-
tion, as non-philosophy takes all philosophies as, in some sense, true (or
true-without-truth in Laruelle’s formulation, meaning that the philosophy
is true without taking the transcendental position of truth). Mullarkey,
again, describes this aptly:
So, the claims of the particular philosophy are unimportant for the
non-philosophical operation; it merely provides philosophical material
for non-philosophy. The particular philosophy is taken as if any mate-
rial whatsoever and as any material it is universal or “generic.” The same
is true of the second aspect of the dyad, be it religion or art or science.
However, the question of this relationship between the particularity and
universality of the chosen material, especially since this material is then
changed as unified theory, had remained undertheorized until recently.
Thus, a new concept brought in to support this axiom has been that of
the generic. The concept has a mixed history, taking on different forms in
philosophy, where it is split between a kind of philosophical anthropology
and first philosophy, and in sociology.48 The philosophical split is between
the Feuerbachian conception of “generic humanity,” taken up by Marxist
thought, and the extension of this by Alain Badiou to the ontological,
92 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
where “in the algebraic model of knowledge, the generic is the acquisition
of a supplement of universal properties (those of demonstration and mani-
festation) by a subtraction and indetermination, a formalization of data.”49
The second source of the generic is to be found, Laruelle says, in societal
epistemology, and is related to what in English is called the general equiva-
lent.50 This history is then subsumed in its own operation, rendering the
historical conception of the generic as a constant within thought that has
three distinct traits, which I will shorten here. First, “being-generic tends
to present itself as a stranger.”51 In other words, the being-generic of a sci-
ence or a philosophy carries with it the same “stranger” or “alien” or “for-
eign” quality described throughout his work as the first possible experience
of thought (and treated already earlier). Second, “being-generic posseses
an a priori function without being a philosophical a priori.”52 The discus-
sion here focuses on the difference between a philosophical a priori, which
grounds knowledge of the philosophical “over-Whole,” and the notion of
an object that remains unsplit. An object, Laruelle claims, is both particu-
lar and has universal significance as One (again explained in detail earlier).
Finally, the third trait of the generic is that it “represents the chance for a
duality without synthesis, it is the outline or the matrix of every duality
as such, of the Two that structures science or its subject.”53 The generic,
Laruelle claims, holds the particular and the universal in a duality with-
out synthesis (a claim that is important to understand what science does).
This duality, for Laruelle, is always unilateral; it is always “Determined-in-
the-last-instance” by the One. Laruelle incarnates the generic as an indi-
vidual person, one that is not solitary, but universal, writing, “The generic
is the individual who has accepted her being universal but limited, who has
accepted not being the tip or expression of the absolute, and thus resists a
priori its influence.”54
Laruelle succinctly described the generic in his lecture “From the First
to the Second Non-Philosophy,” given at the University of Warwick on
March 3, 2010. There he stated, “‘Generic’ signifies that science and phi-
losophy are no longer anything more than means or predicates that have
lost their disciplinary sufficiency and autonomy; bodies of knowledge
forced to abandon their specific finality in order to take up another that is
generic, a form of universality that traverses their traditional domains of
objects as modalities of the philosophical All.”55 Let’s explicate this sen-
tence beginning from its end and work our way backward to the middle
and then explain the first half before finally bringing them together. The
philosophical All or Whole [Tout] is simply another name for the vicious
circle formed by the philosophical decision. Its other name is “World.” The
“traditional domains of objects as modalities” refers to the usual way that
philosophy transforms the material of other disciplines, for example, Alain
Non-Philosophy—Practice and Principles 93
Non-Theological Supplement
For the operation of non-philosophy upon religion does not aim to merely
describe religion any more than it aims to eliminate or protect it in the
name of either a liberated philosophy or an enslaved philosophy. Instead,
non-philosophy aims at appropriating religion: “Axioms and theorems,
these are our methods, us men-without-philosophy, so that we can appro-
priate religion and adapt the divine mysteries to our humanity rather than
to our understanding.”3
Importantly, this method does not involve blending philosophy and
religion together, but treats them as relatively autonomous within a duality
that is ultimately in a unilateral relation to the Real-One. Laruelle must
deal with religion, for religion is actual and thus Real, but also because
religion has been the occasion and material of struggle against Worldly
Authorities: “The paradox is that it is above all from the sides of the reli-
gious reality, in its dualysis, that the occasion itself is found for an emer-
gence of subjects as Futures.”4 In the construction, not of the future, but of
human Futures (like Moderns or Ancients), religion appears in world his-
tory as an instance where human beings, not gods, struggle in-immanence
with and for the World. In his Future Christ, Laruelle aims to make use
of the specificity of Christian religious material to first alter the practice
of philosophy by introducing the experience of heresy into philosophy,
and then to perform a non-philosophical operation on religion to put it to
human use. He locates what is different between philosophy and religion
via the same non-philosophical dualysis—that is, in terms of the relation-
ship between their Authorities and Strangers:
For, in the duality between Authority and Stranger, heresy becomes the
organon of radical immanence determining in-the-last-instance the human
identity of religion.
Thus, religions are not only sites of Authority, though this is their
non(-One) aspect, but they are also, in their particularity, occasional
causes for human struggle, struggles as Strangers. This aspect of religion
is obscured insofar as philosophers of religion tend to focus on the ortho-
dox aspects of any particular religion. Even when a philosopher aims for
a radical critique of religion or a radical appropriation (as in Badiou’s own
98 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
work on St. Paul), they do not look to the victims of religion, that is,
to the religious victims of religion decried as heretics by the orthodox.
Instead, they play with the orthodox material, ignoring the heretical
material, even if they are unconcerned themselves with falling into her-
esy. This is why Laruelle, in his own non-philosophical working with
religious material, gives a great deal of attention to the various strains of
thought collected under the name of Gnosticism. For, though Christian
philosophers and theologians may identify all aspects of modern Western
society with Gnosticism, there are no actual Gnostics left in the World.
The “Gnostic question” prefigures the “Jewish question” and what is fast
becoming in the West the “Muslim question” and shares with it the fact
that, for both questions, the answer from the side of orthodoxy was found
in fire. Thus, in the unilateral duality of religion, where the dualism is
one between Authorities and Strangers, orthodoxy and heresy, it is always
the heretic, as subject-in-struggle and not merely a passive victim, that
determines-in-the-last-instance the identity of the particular religion that
non-philosophy may then work with. In short, non-philosophy demands
a unilateral thinking from the subject-in-struggle, rather than the victim
or the orthodox.
Rather than philosophically working out problems inherent to certain
religious thoughts, Laruelle gives “first names” to identify these occasions
of the Real (i.e., their identity as Stranger) within a particular religion.
This, then, is the meaning of that strange appellation “Future Christ”:
from the material of religion non-philosophy removes “the future” from
its inscription in a Time-World, inscribed as it is within a philosophically
determined understanding of the future. Instead Laruelle inscribes the
future in the radical immanence of Man. The future is given its identity
only as it is “lived without purpose,” a future radically immanent (to) any-
one and thus without telos as a subject formed in that radical immanence.6
This appellation is derived from three sources that are blended within
“the-Christianity,” or Christianity as formed by the Authorities or ortho-
dox, which are separated via a non-philosophical naming of them:
In this sketch of Laruelle’s working with religion and philosophy the par-
ticular power of non-philosophy is revealed. For there is certainly a wild,
heretical freedom at work that offends the scholarly tone of philosophy
of religion and the piety of theologians patiently working out the Truth
through faith and/over reason, and this heretical freedom comes from
non-philosophy’s beginning from axioms derived from the Real-One,
rather than from the philosophical history of Being or Alterity. But,
non-philosophy’s declaration of the One also restrains non-philosophical
naming and provides it with a certain amount of theoretical rigor as that
naming must, by the very same axioms, work through the material as actu-
ally given.
In his incredibly clear introduction to non-philosophy, Jean-Luc
Rannou remarks that non-philosophy has the singular ability to respond
not only to transcendental questions such as “What is religion?” but
also to those singular questions such as “What is the Qur’an?”8
Non-Philosophy has this generic ability because it aims to think equiv-
alently as both science and philosophy, theology and philosophy, art
and philosophy, erotics and philosophy and it calls these equivalencies
“unified theories” that perform a real democracy (of ) thought.9 This is
the task before any philosophy of religion separated from its authoritar-
ian form, a philosophy of religion that is non-philosophical, to consider
both generic religion (rather than religion subsumed into a universal
category) and occasional particulars (like Christ and the Qur’an) from
within the radical immanence of Man determined-in-the-last-instance
by the Real.
At this stage I must step back from an exposition of Laruelle’s work on
religion and consider the possibility of a non-theology as both the name of
a non-philosophical philosophy of religion, as presented in his work, and
as a science of non-philosophy. The first is obvious enough and follows
Laruelle’s own limited remarks on the possibility of a non-theology. He
calls non-philosophy “a human mathematics,” a formulation he opposes
to “Leibniz’s conception of philosophy as a ‘divine mathematics.’”10 From
non-philosophy springs a number of new possibilities for thought, one of
which he calls “non-theological.” This non-theological thought appears
to be essentially what I’ve described earlier: a thinking of religious mate-
rial under the aspect of Man in his radical immanence as minority, an
“inversion of the philosophies of transcendence and of the divine call,” the
construction of a future against and for the World, and so on.11 The point
here is to use religious material to challenge philosophical practice and to
transform the material of religion so that it is no longer a golem, but once
again any material whatsoever.
100 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the “non” is not about ineffable statements such as “the One is Being
beyond Being,” but of positive practices within thought. Second, Laruelle
claims, the (non-)One is an irreversible static effect of the Real, it is a dyad
unilateralized from the perspective of the Real. The implication is that
other negative forms of theological thought posit a negation that is taken
to actually affect the Real itself, even if this goes under different names
(Hegel and Hegelian forms of theology). The question of language is cru-
cial here. While in negative theology language is always taken to be insuf-
ficient to describe God, within non-philosophy language is contingent on
the One and can then still provide the means for an adequate description
and in fact this contingency requires that it be described, but only in the
last-instance.16
This differentiation, however, does not say enough yet. Theology is
not reducible to negative theology, and the more sophisticated forms of
negative theology are always combined with a positive project. There is
a similarity between non-philosophy and theology that goes down to the
level of axiomatic practice. To see this simply replace the Real with the
name of God. Theology thinks from God and not of God (in the same
way that philosophy would think of God). Theology cannot think of God
without first thinking from God and in this way theology is an axiomatic
practice like non-philosophy. Yet it is this very axiomatic aspect of the-
ology’s practice that underlies its principle of sufficient theology where
everything is theologizable because theology’s nonobject, God, is related
or even meta-related to everything that is. In non-philosophy’s method-
ological cloning of theology, how does it avoid its own self-sufficiency?
The principle of sufficient theology is clearly in a different register than
philosophy’s self-sufficiency principle in that it does not claim to have
a privileged place in the thinking of everything self-sufficiently, but as
auto-donation or auto-givenness of Divine sufficiency from its own notion
of God that functions, with various differences, in a structurally similar
way to the Real of non-philosophy. Laruelle suggests in Future Christ that
it is the figure of the heretic that must be taken up and that the Gnostic
Christ is a model of heresy. Yet, the historical Christ reportedly wanted to
draw all things unto himself, and, as we have seen, Laruelle locates this
universal salvation as one of the sources of his appellation “Future Christ.”
Can one still have this sort of theological universal, even as cloned in non-
religion, and avoid theology’s principle of sufficient theology? If so, then
non-philosophy needs to be unified with the practice of non-theology in
order to overcome the temptation to this principle.
This practice operates along two axioms: (1) the Real is foreclosed to
authority and tradition and (2) what is true(-without-truth) in theology
is what is most generic and thus what is most secular. The operations
Non-Theological Supplement 103
The question of authority is at play throughout Laruelle’s work, but its most
mature formulation with regard to Christianity, or “the-Christianity” in
the parlance of non-philosophy, a unitary form of thought that consid-
ers itself sufficient, is found in his Future Christ. Here Laruelle takes
up a common trope in his theory, that of the privileging of minori-
ties, of the individual Man-in-person, over that of authorities, or the
World. The World is, in non-philosophy, a name for the confusion of
some form of thought with the Real (hence we saw that in Philosophie
non-standard Laruelle calls philosophy a thought-World). During the first
phases of his career, Laruelle is concerned primarily with philosophy and
thus World often refers to the confusion of philosophy with the Real.
“Worldly thought” means “auto-sufficient thought,” thought taking itself
as distinct from the Real, and thus thought that has fallen into halluci-
natory error. Mullarkey aptly sums up the World when he writes that
“all philosophical thought is really about itself, it is auto-sufficient. Its
so-called world—x—is actually a mirror of itself.”17 With regard to theo-
logical forms of thought this reflective form is complicated insofar as the
reflection is always double. This double character of theological reflec-
tion relies on its tradition. Standard theology, called thus to make room
for a non-standard, heretical, or non-theology, claims to be dependent
upon a tradition. It looks to the tradition for its content, which it echoes
in its own voice. But this tradition is itself ungrounded, is itself but an
occasion, and in reality the tradition and authority are structured as an
amphibology since the tradition is but the discourse of authority and
authority derives its power from this discourse. It is another form of the
World, of a claim to self-sufficiency, of orthodoxy, which all new forms
of thought must be plunged into. This is common to all forms of Worldly
thought, where the individual, where radical immanence, is plunged into
some other aspect of the World, never known in itself, but always medi-
ated through the structure of the World, which is to say by way of the
Authorities.18
104 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
The heretics reveal to us that man is in an ultimate way that being, the
only one, who endures crime and is characterized by the possibility of
being murdered rather than simply persecuted and taken hostage, exter-
minated as “man” rather than as “Jew.” Why ultimate? Because man is
without-consistency, he is on principle, in contrast to other beings, able to be
murdered, he is even the Murdered as first term for heretical thought and for
the struggle that it performs.19
I should note here, though without developing it further until the final
chapter, that I do not hold to Laruelle’s anthropocentric characterization
of man as such and consider it a form of philosophical determination of the
Earth that has remained within his theory. This is hardly a reason to give
up on non-philosophy, though, since it calls for a kind of “permanent her-
esy,” a constant pragmatic return to its own theory to deepen its practice.
So, from the perspective of ecology there must be some room for a “crime
against the biosphere” perpetuated, as the crime against humanity is, by
some aspect of the biosphere against itself. But, this focus on the minority
status or radical individual identity, precisely because it is without-Essence,
of the human distinct from the forms of unitary identity that are bestowed
upon human beings by the World discloses the radically foreclosed nature
of the Real to authority and tradition. Instead, the Real-One is always
a challenge to authority, always an “outside-memory” that is lost to the
Western form of memory, but that is at the same time not lost because it
is the essence of thought’s non-consistency as always insufficient to think
the Real.20
Thus, heresy is the privileged form of non-theological thinking, because
it is in its immanence always inconsistent, always the shared inconsistency
that marks the identity of the human. There are, of course, majoritarian
or authoritarian forms of heresy and concerning these Laruelle remarks,
“What is more hopeless than a Principle of Sufficient Rebellion,” but these
can be differentiated from heresy as struggle.21 Laruelle delineates this dif-
ferentiation in Future Christ, tracing the differences between war, or the
Agon of philosophical absolute immanence (what we located in the previ-
ous chapter as a simulacra of immanence), and the rebellion of historical
Non-Theological Supplement 105
and nearly 90 injured. This event preceded the Coptic Orthodox Church’s
celebration of Christmas and during the Christmas Eve service, in an act of
solidarity, Egyptian Muslims surrounded the church to provide a human
shield and assure their Christian compatriots of their safety and liberty to
worship. The next image is more recent, perhaps more melancholy consid-
ering even more recent events in Egypt, and sprung radically into reality
during the recent uprising and attempts at an ongoing revolution in Egypt.
During the tense standoff with police, many of whom were corrupt and
largely loyal to former President Mubarak, many of the occupiers of Tahir
Square still wanted to carry out their religious duties and when the call
to prayer rung out from the minarets throughout Cairo they would make
their bodies vulnerable and pray. During the early days of the struggle the
police would heap abuse upon the occupiers and often attack them (there
is an especially inspiring video of an old woman shaming a police officer
for acting without any sense of piety). To protect their Muslim compatriots
during these vulnerable periods and to give them the dignity and peace
required for prayer, the Coptic Christians of Egypt formed a ring around
those at prayer repeating the act of becoming human shields.
What do these emotive images have to do with this project though?
What do they really have to do with the generic as presented here? In short,
these images are manifestations of the Real; they are manifestations of the
secular messianity of the Future Christ as laid out by Laruelle. The generic
helps us get a grip on how this messianity is made to function in a secular
way within the theoretical practice of non-theology. Both messianity and
the secular are determined in the last instance (or find their “last-identity”)
for and in non-philosophy by the generic. In Future Christ Laruelle uses the
term “minimal” instead of generic, but the function is ultimately the same as
minimal is a way of talking about the generic determination of Christianity
as material. This is what he means when he writes poetically that “[t]he
Future Christ rather signifies that each man is a Christ-organon, that is to
say, of course, the Messiah, but simple and unique once each time. This is
a minimal Christianity. We the Without-religion, the Without-church, the
heretics of the future, we are, each-and-everyone, a Christ or Messiah.”29
While he is speaking specifically here of Christianity, theoretically (even
if Laruelle himself does not bear this out in his own practice) there could
be a cacophony, though simple, of minimal forms of religious material. A
minimal Judaism. A minimal Islam. Even a minimal Voodoo. Each time
placed within a generic matrix; not reduced to its “essence” but thought as
a simple and thus radical immanence. The generic functions as a matrix
within which thought develops; a generic matrix provides certain determi-
nations for thought (the matrix itself is determined not by a meta-matrix,
but by its in-One character).
Non-Theological Supplement 109
Ecosystems (of) thought are real. As such ideas can be explored using the
concepts operative in scientific ecology. Rather than treating the works
of philosophers and theologians as if they were words from an oracle, one
treats them as if their thought were an ecosystem. Among philosophical
work there are populations that interact with one another (to name two
dominant populations (of) thought, Being and Alterity) in a way that
either creates a healthy ecosystem (of) thought, called biodiversity in ecol-
ogy, or where a dominant species degrades the health of the ecosystem by
spreading and destroying the niches allowed other populations. Laruelle’s
non-philosophy claims that philosophy always creates a united dualism, or
a dualism that is ultimately united in the form of a philosophical decision,
but a philosophical work demands more than this simply unilateral duality
in order to operate. There are other populations (of) thought that both sup-
port this dualism of dominant species and that populate the philosophical
field as the dualism itself has needs that allow for the formation of niches
within the ecosystem (of) thought. Thus there is no account in Heidegger
of Being without a whole host of other populations (of) thought that in
turn affect that account within the unified ecosystem (of) thought. Or, to
use another example, there is no thought of God in Aquinas without other
populations (of) thought such as causality and Roman Catholic Church
doctrine. How though do these populations interact with one another and
what population can be removed from an ecosystem (of) thought while
retaining its particular vitality when proposed in a different ecosystem (of)
thought?
Every philosophy is built upon some never-living element that in
ecology forms the inorganic spatial and temporal element of the ecosys-
tem. Often philosophy, especially philosophy of nature, focuses on this
114 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
The ecology outlined here will be thought through the generic matrix of
non-philosophy. In order to avoid ecologism, a kind of positivism of ecol-
ogy, scientific ecology must be taken as immanental, a word I have been
using in the work and that I think is immediately understandable, but I
will explain it in more detail now. In his earlier work Laruelle describes the
“transcendental” as “rigorously immanent.”4 In Philosophie non-standard
Laruelle sees fit to simply coin a new term, “immanental,” which describes
the “non-relation” between immanence as such and experience.5 It is then
a posture of thought, like the transcendental, but one that happens within
(hence the nonrelation) the experience and immanence itself. My earliest
description of this project began by calling it a “transcendental ecology”
analogous to Gilles Deleuze’s “transcendental empiricism” or Laruelle’s
early description of non-philosophy as “transcendental realism” and “tran-
scendental axiomatics.”6 The point of this name was always to refer to an
idea of ecology expanded beyond its local practice and applied to philo-
sophical theology, rather than subsuming it within philosophical theology.
When the term “immanental ecology” is used, it should be kept in mind
that it still shares certain likenesses with these “transcendental” positions,
but the term “immanental” is more precise despite being a neologism
because it already refers to the posture ecology as science takes toward the
Real-One and its status as Stranger to philosophy, rather than Other or the
Same. Thus it remains relatively transcendent (to philosophical theology),
but rigorously immanent to the Real.
The point of the construction of a unified theory of philosophical the-
ology and ecology by way of this immanental ecology is not an ecolo-
gism, which would give a veneer of objectivity and scientific rigor to some
new philosophical conception of nature in exactly the way philosophy has
always exploited science as discussed in the previous chapter, but is rather
to practice a kind of “under-determination” of philosophical theology that
frees it to think nature as a first name of the Real. It does not aim to give
science a concept it requires or to force philosophical theology to recog-
nize that it is not as respectable as science. The aim is to create a way
of thinking about an abstract concept, nature, in the light of a unified
theory abstracted from both the particularities of science and philosophi-
cal theology. So, with this in mind, chapter 9 outlines six fundamental
conceptual elements of scientific ecology that bear on philosophical and
theological thought: Populations, or the diversity of species that populate
the ecosystem (biodiversity); ecological niches, which both allow for the
stability of ecosystems as well as the possibility of change; the external
energy relations of exchange that arise out of the populations interaction
with one another and is originally provided by the sun; the never-living
space and temporality of the environment; and, finally, the ecological
Real Ecosystems (of) Thought 117
Laruelle on Ecology
This ecology of fear has all the chances of developing into the predominant
form of ideology of global capitalism, a new opium for the masses replacing
the declining religion: it takes over the old religion’s fundamental function,
that of putting on an unquestionable authority which can impose limits.
The lesson this ecology is constantly hammering is our finitude: we are not
Cartesian subjects extracted from reality, we are finite beings embedded in
a bio-sphere which vastly transgresses our horizon. In our exploitation of
natural resources, we are borrowing from the future, so one should treat our
Earth with respect, as something ultimately Sacred, something that should
not be unveiled totally, that should and will forever remain a Mystery, a
power we should trust, not dominate. While we cannot gain full mastery
over our bio-sphere, it is unfortunately in our power to derail it, to disturb
its balance so that it will run amok, swiping us away in the process. This is
why, although ecologists are all the time demanding that we change radi-
cally our way of life, underlying this demand is its opposite, a deep distrust
of change, of development, of progress: every radical change can have the
unintended consequence of triggering a catastrophe.12
I suspect that Laruelle too is distrustful of political ecology, though the few
places he does mention ecology his true evaluation remains ambiguous. I
was able a pose a question to him that brought up ecology and to which he
did respond directly in Rome as he gave one of the keynote lectures at the
120 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
As I will make clearer in the next section, the purpose of engaging with
scientific ecology is not simply to accept its concepts and ideas as if the
project was simply a kind of ecological positivism. Rather, the task is to
think infect philosophical and theological thinking on nature with certain
ecological concepts that will free philosophical theology to think nature
and free our thinking from its Greek overdetermination as physis and from
its monotheistic theological determination as transcendent Other or as the
simple conceptual inverse of God (this will be discussed at length in the
following chapter). But not because ecology thinks nature better than phi-
losophy, the thinking of nature still largely belongs to the province of a
philosophical theology while, as Lévêque says, “ecology can no longer be a
reflection of nature.”18 Rather philosophico-theological thinking will itself
“go under” an immanental ecology of thought, which, in turning away
from thinking moored to a transcendent notion of the-Earth, will free it
to think nature in a nonreductive and nonspecular way. As Laruelle writes,
“Nature is given an other-than-reductive meaning in this impossible onto-
logical foundation and/or that physical powerlessness in this giving does
not have definitive limitations but inhuman misunderstandings or disori-
ented interpretations.”19 We can change the way we understand nature
philosophically and theologically by thinking from the foundation-less
posture of a scientific posture.
Laruelle has affirmed much of this in a recent lecture delivered in late
2012 in both London and New York entitled “The Degrowth of Philosophy:
Toward a Generic Ecology.” There we see him implicitly affirming many
of the ideas presented in this work, formost among them the notion that
philosophy and other forms of knowledge can be treated ecologically. Of
course, he states this in a slightly more polemical manner writing, “It is
not a question of a ‘philosophy of degrowth,’ such as we sometimes hear
of today, but of the degrowth of philosophy itself.”20 In this essay Laruelle
goes on to try and think ecology in the “quantum spirit.” This is clearly
not from the perspective of scientific ecology the challenge we are putting
forth for theology and philosophy, but as a kind of political ecology still,
and yet this quantum notion is not far from the spirit of actual scientific
ecology as I present it here. Laruelle writes,
This notion of a universe that is not the great mystical All maps neatly
onto the notion of nature presented here. For nature will turn out not to be
a physical object, not an All (this is the hallucinatory theological form of
Nature explored later), but remains where the relations of the ecologies (of)
thought play out. Laruelle also seems to be thinking something similar
when he writes, “Let’s suppose an ecology of the relations of thought, of its
highest forms of which we can make use—science and philosophy, art and
religion, relations with and within the universe.”22
Yet the lingering problem of the temptation to humanism remains in
this essay as well. Laruelle notes that “[t]o preserve the natural environ-
ment of existence, to preserve man and his survival qua species even, is
the immediate and primary aim of ordinary ecology.”23 But this goal, for
Laruelle, must submit to a more primary defense of human beings, “The
‘defence’ and the maintenance of human environments, spontaneous and
naturalist ecology, must be reordered in view of a defence of generic man
in (and sometimes against) the environment or milieu of knowledges.”24
Laruelle is not committing himself to a human chauvinism here, however,
as he does go on to write, “This new objective of ecology cannot be called
superior or meta-ecological. It is in-the-last-instance a generic usage or
epistemic milieus, the best appropriation of knowledges (including philos-
ophy itself) in view of the defence of humans against their self-destructive
drive, which has its origin in the world.”25 In other words, the problem of
human environments and even going against the environment is the same
problem that haunts this work—that nature has become a problem for
nature. Though Laruelle in some sense clearly is walking a thin line, one
that he may not successfully traverse in future works on the relationship of
the animal and the human, it is a line drawn by political ecology itself. For
all of our green consciousness
is still to presuppose that man can decide freely, in some all-powerful man-
ner, to safeguard nature or to destroy it. Whereas he does not really have this
power to transform it wholesale, since he himself belongs to every decision,
is included in it and perturbs it, puts it back into play with every decision or
repetition. He has only the power to underdetermine his decisions.26
climatology, and many others in its study of the ecosystem. In its own
openness to disciplinary perversion it is able to express in its principles and
concepts nature’s perversion.
An obvious retort to this thought experiment is that this is simply a
metaphor and reveals nothing interesting in itself. Of course the Greek
metaphora literally means “a transfer” and comes from the verb meta-
pherein meaning “to transfer, carrying over.” The charge is that this “just
a metaphor” suggests we are unduly “transferring” an idea from scientific
ecology to philosophy. In short that we are not respecting the proper bor-
ders that allow the standard division of thought to work. This is also an
economic division of thought, one relating in part to labor (so who does
what jobs) and in part to branding. Of course there is a reasonable warning
in here as well, suggesting that we should not disrespect the specificity of
practices within thought. This need not be a “Sokalism,” but can point to
the real difficulties present in both scientific thinking and philosophical/
theological thinking. Consider the outrage among theologians and schol-
ars of religion when those trained in biology or cosmology publish their
largely unlearned thoughts on religion; surely then the converse would be
true as well.
So, just as Spinoza wore a signet ring with a red rose and the Latin
caute [caution] that he used to mark his texts with, we note that we are
proceeding cautiously into the scientific material. But we are still proceed-
ing because even if it were just a matter of a simple transfer of material
from scientific ecology to philosophy it could still then be following the
principles of ecology at the level of fiction. Thus one cannot see it as a
metaphor if by that one means something “outside but like an ecosys-
tem,” for the metaphor too depends on the ecosystem for its existence since
thought is tied to actuality and actuality is ecological. One may name this
the materialist element of immanental ecology, but only if what the mate-
rial is remains open to revision. However, I want to suggest that while this
is certainly a work of “philo-fiction,” there is also a more substantial basis
for positing an ecology of thought. Consider again Morton’s remark that
thinking is one of the things damaged by modern society in addition to
actual ecosystems.2 The environment inhabited by human beings, which
to say whatever particular ecosystem different human societies have code-
veloped in, is part of development of ideas. This idea was already present
in the first attempt at universal history by Ibn Khaldûn, and contemporary
environmental historians have shown that ideas are part of ecosystems.3
But this is obvious already in everyday popular environmental discourse
on the destructive nature of certain human ideas. If these ideas are allowed
to continue they will run up against ecological limits like any other species.
So, for instance, the idea of wilderness is currently on the decline because it
Elements of an Immanental Ecology 127
Ecosystem
his textbook Odum had laid out an agenda that anticipated the direction
taken by the ecological movement over the next twenty years.11
modifies for its purposes. People often ask how ecology is different from
general systems theory, how its theory of energy differs from thermodynam-
ics, and if it is really distinct from biology in general. What is behind these
questions if not a certain kind of philosophy of science that aims to find the
science that will reveal all the required answers for a philosophy of reality.
A division of the sciences that creates a permanent war between the real sci-
ences and those sciences that depend upon them. But there is no agreement
from the philosophers on which form of science is the science and so this
war is really an internal philosophical war. What is the non-philosophical
response? A relatively peaceful one, for the way non-philosophy conceives
of the division of ideational labor locates all scientific practice and all
philosophical thought relative before the Real. Ecology is thus only dif-
ferent from those scientific practices and theories it draws upon by virtue
of its object, which is the ecosystem. The object toward which a science is
directed is immanent to the identity and posture of that science such that
the autonomy of a science is always given not by some particular practice
but by the object that produces that project. In other words, the differences
in the practices between theoretical set theory and ecology are entirely
important with regards to what can be done with the science on different
occasions, but those practices cannot be truly separated from the occasion
itself. The object brings with it the problems and practices of the science.
The problem of scientism arises when one tries to make a single science
and its object (what Laruelle calls its “research-world”) the form of thought
above all others.17 Ecology already resists this kind of overcoding of every-
thing by the very virtue of the complexity of its object. For quite simply the
ecosystem is not an abstraction that can be experimented in a laboratory,
but is a lived, immanent reality in time.
Biodiversity
What scientists like Wilson have argued, supported by more recent work
in resilience ecology, is that this diversity is necessary for and constitutive
of the stable and resilient functioning of life on Earth. Moreover, it raises
questions of a philosophical and theological character about the concept of
nature itself. Namely, what is nature in relation to life? Is one term primary
over the other? Or are they reversible with one another? Beyond these ques-
tions the field of study around biodiversity gives us tools that can be used
to disempower philosophical and theological overdetermination of ecol-
ogy and begin to treat thought as if it were ecological (which, of course, it
always already is).
If it is true that philosophy begins in wonder (one thinks of Plato) and
theology in the fear of God seen through God’s Creation (one thinks of
Paul), then it is worth noting the reported numbers of biodiversity as sum-
marized in Wilson’s The Diversity of Life (2001), which continues to be
a standard summary of debates and issues in the study of biodiversity.
According to estimates made by Wilson in 1986 and published in 1992
the number of living species was put at 1.4 million. He goes on to state
that 13,000 “new” species are discovered each year, meaning at the time
The Diversity of Life went into its second edition in 2001 the number had
gone up to 1.5 million. Of these we have catalogued 865,000 different spe-
cies of insects and 69,000 species of fungi. These are the species we have
identified, the estimate of the true number of species on Earth ranges from
3,635,000 and 111,655,000. The vast majority of these unknown species
are ones that don’t normally occur to the human being to care about. So,
while it is estimated that we know 98 percent of the living bird species,
we know only 1.5 percent of chromophyte algal species. And as fantastic
as these numbers are, literally suggesting a planet that is teeming with liv-
ing creatures and where that very teeming provides the conditions for the
remarkable creation of more species, it is estimated that 98 percent of all
species that have existed on this planet in the more than 3.5 billion years of
biological history have disappeared into extinction forever.19
Note that these numbers refer only to species. This is the unit preferred
by those who study biodiversity because of the relative stability of species as
a concept (defined by Wilson as “a population whose members are able to
interbreed freely under natural conditions”) and the relative ease in record-
ing them.20 For, the fact is, there are other organic units the biologist and
ecologist could use in their study of biodiversity, such as genes or, at the
other end of the quantitative spectrum, ecosystems. Wilson tells us,
the unit of choice in biodiversity studies remains the species, which is rela-
tively easy to diagnose and has moreover been the central object of research
for over two hundred years.21
Yet, even setting aside the difficulties of counting and identifying the
unit of species, there remain some enduring problems with the concept
of species.
The most obvious problem relating to the conceptual description of
species is simply that not all organisms are sexual and so the concept of
species doesn’t fully account for them. However, since the overwhelm-
ing majority of organisms are sexual in relative terms and furthermore
the majority of nonsexual species have evolved from sexually reproducing
ancestors, this isn’t a conceptual problem that has caused scientists to give
up on a concept that otherwise works.22 What is more problematic, and
interesting for a non-philosophical theory of nature, is the inconsistent
nature of species. As Wilson pithily states, “For species are always evolv-
ing, which means that each one perpetually changes in relation to other
species.”23 This causes a nuisance in terms of cataloguing some “sibling
species,” which are largely similar but nonetheless distinct, but more trou-
bling conceptual is hybrid species that are created within a genus.24 This is
perceived by scientists like Wilson as a problem for the concept of species
and moreover as the fundamental unit because it partly opens the gene
pool leading to the question of the identity of species as such.
However, the problem present for the ecologist is an occasion for specu-
lation for the non-philosopher. In both the standard definition of a spe-
cies as a community where the population can freely breed and in the
problem where gene pools appear to open up there is still a generic, radical
identity. In the technical language of non-philosophy this radical identity
is in-One, meaning it is Being and its Alterity or difference from other
species is secondary to its own actuality or identity, and so what we have
here is a new notion of identity than the one that Wilson is presupposing.
In the non-philosophical conception of identity the issue is fundamentally
related to actuality.25 The hybrid species is radically actual, regardless of
the inadequacy of the thought attempting to think it. This is an example
of the fundamentally unilateral relationship between the One (which is
occasional and thus not a single substance, being prior to Being, but always
manifest-without-manifestation in multiple sites) where the actuality or
identity of the hybrid species requires that thought think it, but thought
itself does not have any absolute effect (even if it may have a relative effect)
on the actuality of the hybrid. Perhaps, then, a non-philosophical solu-
tion to these enduring ecological problems could be offered by way of the
unilateral duality of identity. Keeping in mind that there is always the
134 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Niche
Biodiversity opens up to a corollary concept that ecologists refer to as the
niche. If biodiversity is the recognition that there is a principal drive to
diversification within the biosphere, niche theory is the attempt to give
shape to the functioning of biodiversity. For biodiversity is a principle
derived from the research into the proliferation (one might even say clamor)
of species that are identified by the ecologist as those populations that can
freely breed under “natural” conditions. Niche theory is able to locate the
ways that clamor comes into a stochastic harmony. This stochastic har-
mony is described by Paul S. Giller as population interaction with other
populations (this grouping of populations is called the community) and
the wider ecosystem.28 Giller clarifies the strict definition of a community
writing that a community is “a combination of plant, animal, and bacterial
populations, interacting with one another within an environment, thus
forming a distinctive living system with its own composition, structure,
environmental relations, development and function.”29
Niches are tied more closely to the community rather than the ecosys-
tem as a whole, though again the confusion with regard to scale of ecosys-
tems makes this a somewhat unclear point. Giller helps clarify the place
of the niche when he writes, “The ecological niche is a reflection of the
organism’s or species’ place in the community, incorporating not only tol-
erances to physical factors, but also interactions with other organisms.”30
In a nontechnical sense, though nonetheless true, niche refers to what lines
of sustenance are open to the organism or species. That is, a niche is that
place, within a network or mesh of interactions (these are always approxi-
mate analogies for the mathematical model of the energy exchange), where
an organism can find enough energy to continue to live while passing on
its genetic information. Now the niche of one species may be wide enough
to allow that species to spread across the ecosystem, and even, as in the case
of human beings, to dominate the ecosystems they exist within. This idea
of domination refers to the intensity of the effects that this species has on
the particular ecosystem. So the human being has obviously had a high
magnitude of effects on the ecosystems they inhabit and has even shaped
them. This limits the niches of other animals, while opening up other
niches. If the human species were to disappear the ecosystems they had
inhabited would no doubt change fundamentally, which is not necessarily
true of species who have smaller niche widths.31
In practice most organisms and species are limited or “checked” by
other organisms and species. This should not suggest a rather medieval
138 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
common ontological basis, the same basis that Negri reads into Job (while
himself not going as far to the creatural generic as we are): the experience
of immense, immeasurable pain. Here the biblical text is not a parable of
human labor alone, but of generic creatural labor.
According to Negri’s reading of Job, this figure is not pitiful as he stands
in pain against a backdrop of tragedy, but is a figure of power as ability
or potentiality against Power as constituted and oppressive. In his power
Job calls the amoral omnipotence of the divine to account for itself. Such
a demand is rhetorically complex, for the protest of Job must not make
an appeal to God simply as judge, for “God is both one of the parties and
the judge. The trial is therefore a fraud.”37 For when Job opens his mouth
he will have already condemned himself before the one who judges, as he
himself says in the text:
the human being that produces suffering. Job breaks this mismatched dia-
lectic by seeing God. By his protest Job demands that God reveal himself
and in so doing Job tears away the absolute transcendence of God. By
seeing God, through the immeasurability of God revealed as a body open
to vision, Job is able to share in the divine. The immeasurable character of
pain and grace is no longer organized hierarchically, but through a simple
vision, a knowledge that is salvific. Such vision is creation according to
Negri and it is worth quoting his ecstatic hymn to creation at length:
Job speaks of grace, of the prophecy that anticipates the Messiah. “To see
God” is certainly not a moral experience, nor is it merely an intellectual
experience. Here the interpreters of the book of Job do what Job’s inter-
locutors, form Eliphaz to Bildad, from Zophar to Elihu, had done: they
confine to a given form and measure his experience within the dimensions
of the theologically known. And yes, what an incredible experience has
unfolded to this point! I have seen God, thus God is torn from the abso-
lute transcendence that constitutes the idea of him. God justifies himself,
thus God is dead. He saw God, hence Job can speak of him, and he—Job
himself—can in turn participate in divinity, in the function of redemption
that man constructs within life—the instrument of the death of God that
is human constitution and the creation of the world. [ . . . ] The antagonism
between life and death is resolved in favor of life. My life is the recognition
of you—my eyes have seen you. I am. Man is. The backdrop is not modi-
fied. It is dominated by the great forces of destruction and death. But man
reorganizes himself so as to resist this disease. Creation is the going beyond
death. Creation is the content of the vision of God . Creation is the meaning
of life.42
still required that God answer for it, so the niche is perverse in the face of
the unlimited Power of Nature.
What is common to creatural being is pain. One species causes pain to
another in the working out of niche boundaries. But corollary to this pain
is the necessity for biodiversity that niches witness to. There is then a cer-
tain creatural sociality as universality at work in the pain of living among
one another.45 This pain is primary and emotions such as fear or anger are
but secondary effects that are contingent upon the organization of that
pain in the creatural socius. Even violence is secondary to this pain, insofar
as that violence can be turned into a peaceable force by way of creation.
It isn’t my intent to argue for an overturning of death in the ecosystem,
but simply to disempower death, just as Job disempowers God. The niche
shows that death, as well as life, is secondary to a more immanent creative
power at work as nature against Nature. Niches witness to the exile of
nature from hypostasized Nature. The refusal of the value of Nature as
hallucination of the immeasurable in the name of a grace of nature that is
witnessed to in the perverse creative power of new species producing ways
of living indifferently to death.
Up until this point I have only covered what could be referred to as the liv-
ing and dead elements of ecology as seen through the concept of the ecosys-
tem. At this point we need to transition to those elements normally called
abiotic, but which the Chicago-based Irish ecologist and philosopher Liam
Heneghan refers to as the “never-living.” These never-living elements are
outside any dialectic of life and death, a dialectic that operates as a homol-
ogy where there is a pure confusion of bodies, and this dialectic continues
to haunt contemporary philosophies and theologies of nature through their
connection to the biopolitical.46 Because of this homology the ecological
conception of the never-living can actually provide a more generic matrix
than either neovitalism or nihilistic thought, which is actually based on the
anthropocentric notion of extinction, and in so doing may avoid their mis-
takes by opening up a unified theory of philosophical theology and ecology
to a freer, more radically immanent, conception of nature.
In this section I will turn to that element that unifies the living, the
dead, and the never-living: the exchange of matter and energy. Energy
exchange, also called energy flow, is the productive force at work in the
ecosystem and is also constitutive of the ecosystem. Not in a purely unitary
way, as if one term were transcendent to the other, or in a way where the two
146 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
terms are simply reversible, but in the sense that the radical identity of the
ecosystem and energy are dual. For analysis of the ecosystem and energy
seeks “to understand the factors that regulate the pools (quantities) and
fluxes (flows) of materials and energy through ecological systems.”47 The
terms are not reversible because their identities can be located, even where
these identities are always in the midst of the others. Not in a relationship
of reciprocity, but simply and radically in-One as the biosphere. Take, for
example, the “net ecosystem production,” which is the name given to the
net accumulation of carbon by an ecosystem.48 It would be too simple,
and all too philosophical and theological, to reduce all the aspects of the
ecosystem to being in some sense “carbon.” As if all the living and dead
elements of an ecosystem could be simply thought of as flows of carbon
akin to a computer code. However, this would fail to make any sense of
the exchange of carbon, the study of which shows that individuals or actu-
alities store and transfer carbon. Without an understanding of the radical
identity of these actualities ecologists would be silent in the face of the flux
and pools of carbons and yet, against such temptation, ecologists do speak
and can trace the carbon balance as it enters the ecosystem through gross
primary production (photosynthesis) and leaves through several other pro-
cesses.49 In plain terms, plants are not “merely” carbon flows, because they
have processes that are radically separate from the identity of carbon.
We can make the claim, borrowed from Marxism and mutated in
Laruelle’s non-Marxism, that every exchange is the productive force [force
(de) production] of work in ecology and still remain scientifically inoffen-
sive. Energy is defined rather pragmatically in ecology, drawing on ther-
modynamics, as the ability to do work.50 This definition of energy was
first adapted for scientific ecology by Howard Thomas Odum, brother of
Eugene Odum discussed earlier. Howard Thomas Odum used the cyber-
netic theories of the 1950s alongside of the general laws related to energy
derived from research in theoretical physics to develop theories about and
research projects concerning energy flow.51 This definition of energy is
given alongside the two laws of thermodynamics by Odum:
thought can be treated like a real ecosystem and as part of a real ecosys-
tem. From an ecological perspective thought is also dependent upon this
single source of energy. For thought to do work it requires energy. A simple
and likely obvious statement, but one that is rarely considered when doing
philosophical or theological work. But do thoughts decompose? Do they
live and die, passing on their energy to something else? Let us hazard a yes
and let this yes be said without an appeal to crude scientism or reductive
materialism. But this yes must also be said without an appeal to pseudo-
science or narcissistic notions that our thought creates reality. What then
would it mean? An enigmatic answer: thought transfers its energy in the
everyday. What this means is that thought is an ecological process just as
respiration or the carbon cycle is. The function of this “just” needs to be
clarified. For the point isn’t that thought is “just material” as if we knew
that the value of material was low from the perspective of human freedom.
Rather, the point is that thought and the rest of the ecosystem has a certain
equivalency in terms of their relative autonomy in relation to the radi-
cal autonomy of the never-living. Thought isn’t something to deride, but
neither is it something divine that can only secure its divinity by debasing
what is taken to be beneath it. Thought carries with it energy that can be
transferred to other forms of thought, can animate wider ecosystems (of)
thought, or can be used to direct action. But in this way thought remains
relative, it has no absolute autonomy, but is unilaterally determined, at
least on this refractory planet, by the sun and so any animation or action is
always as a custodian rather than a master.
So this is not a metaphor. I am claiming that within thought there is
energy that is transferred among living thought, dead thought, and the
never-living of thought. The definition of energy inherited from general
thermodynamics guides us here: energy for thought is the ability to do work.
Thus we don’t need to make any appeals to an already existing materialist
philosophy or to a reductionist account of thinking that says thought “just
is” energy. Such claims are often incoherent for they are dependent upon a
circle of meaning that they claim to escape. For many such claims are often
pitched against the reenchantment of the World and in favor of a further
disenchantment. Consider the words of Ray Brassier who claims that
So, reducing the World to a set of “just is” propositions is supposed to bear
witness to a sign of “intellectual maturity” for they show that the thinker
is involved in thinking the truth regardless of what that truth may be. The
consequence of this rhetoric is obviously intended to turn the reductionist
into a kind of hero of truth, but surely the hero just is valorizing himself
within a circle of meaning it hasn’t been able to reduce in its practice.
Instead of playing such competing games of meaning, why not think as
the wave of energy. Disinterested in the World, whether it is enchanted or
not, but acting nonetheless. For thought clearly begins with energy. When
I sit to think about an ecosystem (of) thought my body is burning calories.
My body that is thinking requires energy; it requires that I eat if I am to
think. It requires too that I have eaten well, that I have eaten nutritious
food throughout the living action of my body. For nutrition is necessary
for my brain to form synapses correctly and allow for synaptic connec-
tions. These connections and the thought that is thought are immanent
to one another. For while these connections allow for the production of
thought, they indeed are the production of thought, they do not occur
within a vacuum. For when I think I do so with the ideas of others, with
common notions as well as with presuppositions. These play a part in the
form of whatever thought I go on to think. For example, when I sit down
to read Spinoza’s Ethics there is a transfer of thoughtful energy from the
dead thought on the page to the living thought transforming the mate-
rial of the dead thought in the midst of my thinking it. Writing is but a
material trace of the living thought that provides the material energizing
the living thought. Ideas thus exhibit an energy-like quality. When I read
the ideas of some thinker I am able to do work with my own thought. My
own thought is able to perhaps do the same for another body of thinking.
The reality of this image of thought (seen from the vision-in-One) is more
adequate to what actually happens when we think. For we do not think
with perfect understanding, simply repeating the master, but always akin
to taking some material from one world to another. Sometimes that matter
is carried on our shoe, sometimes in a new configuration of our body. But
this is how we actually think in the moment: contaminated, energized,
and without the transcendent master.
“climate, parent material (i.e., the rocks that give rise to soil), topogra-
phy, potential biota (i.e., the organisms present in the region that could
potentially occupy a site), and time.”60 Of these we have effectively covered
potential biota (biodiversity), parent material (material exchange), and to
some extent climate insofar as climate is closely linked with the energy
flow. Space and time are important elements of the ecosystem process, but
how they are important can be illuminating of the general structure of
ecosystems (of) thought generally as well as questioning the commonsense
views of time and space.
There is no real need for technical language in this section, for the
effects of space on ecosystems are relatively obvious. Ecosystems are par-
tially determined by where they are on the planet in relation to where the
sun is. That climate may also be determined in part by landform effects.
For example, mountain ranges affect local climate through what are called
“orographic effects,” simply referring to the presence of the mountain. One
example of this is what is called a “rain shadow,” or zone of low precipita-
tion downwind of the mountains caused by the cooling and condensation
of air moving up the windward side of the mountains. Deserts and steppes
often exist because of their downwind proximity to a mountain range.61
Time functions in a similar way and Chapin, Matson, and Mooney
summarize the importance of time in ecosystem processes this way: “Time
influences the development of soil and the evolution of organism over long
time scales. Time also incorporates the influences on ecosystem processes
of past disturbances and environmental change over a wide range of time
scales.”62 For organisms too there is a temporal element in their ecosystem
functioning that is important if one is to understand the overall ecological
processes at work: “Many species may change their trophic level [i.e., where
they can be placed in terms of the exchange of matter and energy] during
their life cycle. A fish may be planktivorous in the larval stage, a consumer
of invertebrates in the juvenile stage, and piscivorous in the adult stage.”63
Ecological processes take time and in time there is a certain heterogeneous
character to the ecosystem and its elements that can be witnessed.
What is common to both space and time in ecological theory is their
heterogeneity. Lévêque goes so far as to claim that there is a “consensus”
in ecology “that nature is heterogeneous.”64 He goes on to define spatial
heterogeneity as existing from either a static or dynamic point of view.
“An environment is heterogeneous if a qualitative or quantitative variable,
such as plant cover or air temperature, has different values in different
places. However, in functional terms, heterogeneity is also apparent when
there is a change in the intensity of functional processes in response to
variations in the structure of the environment.”65 He goes on to define
temporal heterogeneity writing that “[t]emporal heterogeneity, more often
Elements of an Immanental Ecology 151
Resilience
The rest of this section will focus on filling out these concepts.
Walker and Salt illustrate the thresholds theme with a simple analogy.
Imagine that the system is a ball and that ball is placed within a basin that
indexes the system’s “state” variables. A simple system could be simply the
number of fish and the number of fishers, but it is important to keep in
mind that a system is of course fractal and is thus n-dimensional. Now
within this basin the ball will tend to roll toward the bottom, that is, in
system’s terms, it tends toward equilibrium. But equilibrium is not static
and is rather always changing based on the changing external conditions
and so the shape of the basin is itself always changing as the conditions
themselves change. The shape of the basin can change so much, meaning
the conditions can change so much, that the ball can suddenly find itself
rolling into a new basin with a different fundamental organization. To put
some flesh on this example, say a particular linchpin species has a small
niche width due to some other external change. If that species continues
to be pushed out of the ecosystem functioning toward extinction, then the
system will fundamentally change. While prior to this change you could
adjust on the basis of that species, that possibility is no longer open to you
because the structure of the basin has fundamentally changed.80 Walker
and Salt summarize this thus: “Once a threshold has been crossed it is
usually difficult (in some cases impossible) to cross back.”81 Furthermore,
sustainability requires that we learn if and where thresholds exist and fig-
ure out how to manage the capacity of the system in relation to those
thresholds.82
Adaptive cycles give some organization to the changes that occur with
ecosystems. “One important aspect about cycles is recognizing that things
happen in different ways according to the phase of the cycle the system
happens to be in.”83 There are four phases to the adaptive cycle: the rapid
growth phase (or r phase), the conservation phase (or K phase), the release
phase (or Ω phase), and the reorganization phase (or α phase). The r phase
is the early period of the system where there is rapid growth “as species or
people [ . . . ] exploit new opportunities and available resources.”84 During
this phase species are exploiting every possible niche and the system is
154 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
In the previous section we traced six principles and concepts from ecology
that, when unified with philosophical theology, can change our under-
standing of nature and help us to furnish a new theory of nature. But
before we offer that theory of nature we must first deal with a two poten-
tial challenges to the project of a theory of nature formed from a unified
theory of philosophical theology and ecology. For there is another option
for philosophers than this notion of nature given from the impossibility of
foundation: one may simply reject nature altogether. Timothy Morton and
Bruno Latour have offered the strongest philosophical arguments against
the validity of the concept of nature in relation to ecology and so their
criticisms must be responded to. Ultimately I will argue that while ecology
as a science may not require the philosophical concept of nature to func-
tion, nature is still a “good name” (as Derrida said of God). The reason
nature remains a good name is, in part, because of its ability to confound
philosophical thinking, but there is always the risk that this confusion be
wielded as a weapon against human beings and other creatures. Morton
and Latour, in similar ways, attempt to decommission the weaponized form
of Nature. Nature is written here with the capital N to mean a metaphysi-
cal conception of nature, as transcendent in philosophy, but I will keep the
use of the alternating use of a capital N and lowercase n to a minimum.
So, my response to Morton’s and Latour’s criticisms will not be an outright
rejection but, in true non-philosophical style, an attempt to radicalize their
criticisms, to make them immanent, to a conception of nature for creatures
but against the World created by those creatures.
Latour’s work will be the starting point, as it is, despite Latour’s promi-
nence, the weaker argument of the two. The weakness of that argument
will be developed in relation to Morton’s own argument, because Morton,
158 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
This being the case Latour’s argument against the idea of nature
does not really touch on the specific question at issue here—that of the
relationship between the idea of nature and ecology—even if he is right
to criticize the standard philosophical form of nature. Morton’s argument
though is concerned more explicitly with a kind of “unified ecology”
that he calls “the ecological thought.”13 His theorization of the ecological
thought, which he says “is a virus that infects all other areas of thinking,”
engages specifically with concepts from scientific ecology while still argu-
ing for a kind of political ecology at the same time.14 So, his attempt to cast
an ecology without nature must then bear on our attempt to recast nature
non-philosophically and thus requires a response.
What does Morton mean by nature? Morton shares Latour’s criticism
of modernity as the site where the representatives of Science (as opposed
to the sciences) rely on a certain idea of Nature to stop thinking: “[I]n
general the scientisms of current ideology owe less to intrinsically sceptical
scientific practice, and more to ideas of nature, which set people’s hearts
beating and stop the thinking process, the one of saying ‘no’ to what you
just came up with.”15 Nature then operates in a similar way to the usual
philosophical transcendental authorities that are treated as simple mate-
rial in non-philosophy, and there is much to be sympathetic with from a
non-philosophical perspective when Morton identifies nature as that tran-
scendental object of nature that takes the environment and turns it into
a fetish object.16 Or, perhaps especially, when Morton identifies (though
with little elaboration) that there is a deep connection between environ-
mental thinkers such as Aldo Leopold, who certainly remains beholden to
a transcendental idea of nature as underlying structure and often positing
a divide between humans and nature (however minimal it may be), and
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s “new and improved” conception of
nature.17
This criticism remains philosophical and so not entirely a challenge to
our proposed rethinking of nature non-philosophically arising from an
immanental ecology (or unified theory of ecology and philosophy). Yet,
Morton goes beyond Latour because he tries to conceive of ecology with-
out nature, or rather takes it that, in its actual practice, ecology already
operates without the philosophical conception of nature: “Why ‘ecology
without nature’? ‘Nature’ fails to serve ecology well. I shall sometimes use
a capital N to highlight its ‘unnatural’ qualities, namely (but not limited
to), hierarchy, authority, harmony, purity, neutrality, and mystery. Ecology
can do without a concept of something, a thing of some kind, ‘over yon-
der,’ called Nature.”18 In short, with regard to ecology and the ecologi-
cal thought that spills over science to infect all forms of contemporary
thinking, “nature” is a bad name. It is a bad name for Morton precisely
162 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Conclusion
What is the status of the old divisions of thought after the work carried
out over the past three chapters? Theology has still not been returned as
the queen of the sciences. Science can still operate with relative ease with-
out the need of worrying about the transcendental conditions for their
thought. Philosophy still is but one way of thinking alongside a plurality.
In a certain way immanental ecology does not undermine the reality of
the divisions of thought at all, for these divisions were always contingent
forms of the organization of thinking. Immanental ecology, as a form
of the non-philosophical practice of theory, simply allows us to see that
the old divisions of thought were never true divisions. That the relative
identities we can bestow on philosophy or theology is always a matter of
tendency, a tendency in the light of the radical identity of the Real-One.
In-the-last-instance ethics, theology, philosophy, ontology, God, man,
creatures, and all of creation are One. Their identity is but an effect of
the radical immanence of the One, as the radical immanence of the lived.
These divisions of thought are only useful when they are useful. This tau-
tologous statement is not meaningless, but rather it points to the material
basis of thinking about thought. If a division of thought is productive of
thought, then divide, but if the division blocks thinking, then step back
from your fabulation and refabulate from the experience of thinking itself
rather than from a hallucination of its image.
It is worth noting again Laruelle’s notion of “under-determination” in
order to understand the status of these different regions of thought or, as
164 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
In more familiar terminology, the vision of the division of science and phi-
losophy/theology at play here is one where the two unequal forces of think-
ing are brought together into a single, new thought. The formalism for
superposition or idempotence can be expressed as 1 + 1 = 1. For Laruelle
the different forces of thoughts are like quantum waves that can meet and
form, not a combination of the two waves, but an actual new wave where
there are three distinct identities now. We’re suggesting a similar image of
thought where the forces of thought are being treated as ecosystems. The
elements of these ecosystems are brought together, not in a combination,
but as a new ecosystem of thinking.
In part IV, I will propose a theory of nature from the perspective of a
unified theory of philosophical theology and ecology that will begin to use
this immanental ecology. I will engage with a number of different ecologies
(of) thought, separating out species and weakening their self-sufficiency by
placing them within wider spatial and temporal scales. The desire is that
by doing this we will not only treat these ecosystems (of) thought as simple
material, but will do so as ecological material with the intention of deriving
a theory of nature that is immanent to that material and can be adequately
called a first name for the Real and finally what such an adequacy might
mean. While the next section arises out of this immanental ecology it does
so insofar as I am now able to treat philosophical and theological con-
ceptions of nature as an ecological material. What this means is that I
can separate out the different uses of the concept of nature as manifest-
ing a particular functional form of nature as ultimately perverse. Thus
for Aquinas nature is presented as creation or creatural, for Spinoza there
is a chimera of God or Nature, and for Abu Ya’qûb al-Sijistânî and Naīr
al-Dīn ūsī there is recognition of the fundamental Oneness of nature
prior to Being or Alterity.
Part IV
A Theory of Nature
Chapter 11
Introduction
All that was covered in the preceding chapter bears on a new practice
of reading the histories of philosophy and theology. Such a practice of
Separating Nature from the World 169
takes place in a variety of ways. Ecology as a way of thinking that takes the
posture of thinking from the Real or from a perspective prior and disinter-
ested in the transcendence of Being and Alterity. So what do these claims
do? What does this theory add? They model thought ecologically and this
then makes certain illusions of the Principles of Sufficient Philosophy
and Theology more difficult to hold as well as those illusions of what we
could term the Principle of Sufficient Ecology, for it shows that a thought
that has finished thinking ecologically would be impossible. Thought is
understood not outside ecological practices, but as part and parcel of them.
There is a drive to deal with the ecological crisis by way of something
called ecological awareness, but this seems all too often to remain unaware
of its actual ecological complexity as a drive toward ecological awareness.
Thus, the claim at work here is not something I aim to prove as such.
So, while I suspect that one could do the analysis of thought and ideas in
the way I’m suggesting, I’m not trying to undertake such a purely scien-
tific inquiry. Rather my unified theory of philosophical theology and ecol-
ogy is directed in this instance toward the philosophical and theological
ideas of nature, to bring them back from the circularity of their faith and
self-sufficiency and show that they are but simple materials. Not “mere”
materials, for as material they are still powerful, but that as materials they
can be used to construct a theory of nature that is both philosophical/theo-
logical and ecological. A theory that does not aim to master nature, but to
show how nature can function in thought in different ways.
To see how a certain population (of) thought or exchange of energy can
happen consider the common practice in both philosophy and theology of
producing “readings” of other thinkers. Many scholars make their careers
on offering some kind of reading of a historical thinker that allows the
rest of us to read that figure differently than we were able to before theirs.
What happens there ecologically? As already stated, we will not aim to pro-
vide the usual history of philosophy, because we can locate the common
practice in philosophy and theology of producing readings as an ecologi-
cal process. For the reading is the extension of a kind of ecosystem (of)
thought to another locality. The particular shape of that ecosystem will be
different, but its general form will be identifiable. So, for example, the wars
that rage between various forms of Thomisms is not of particular interest
here. While some readings will obviously be wrong in some uninteresting
way, say based on some error of translation or something in the same reg-
ister, the dominant forms are still populated by populations (of) thought
that find their original organization in the thought of Thomas himself.
At a simple level, the different ecological forms of Thomism exist because
they work, because they can create some niche. In what follows here I will
call this creation of a niche “piety.” Piety should here be understood as an
Separating Nature from the World 171
within which his life and thought were productive. I will begin by follow-
ing Goodchild’s own analysis of Spinoza’s piety. Goodchild begins that
analysis by quoting from the Theological-Political Treatise where Spinoza
locates “the following manifestation of Hebrew piety” writing:
And here at the outset we must note that the Jews never specify intermedi-
ate or particular causes and take no notice of them, but owing to religion
and piety, or (in the common phrase) “for devotion’s sake,” refer everything
back to God. For example, if they have made some money by a business
transaction, they say that God has stirred their heart; and if they think of
something, they say that God has said it to them.12
our use of these figures, but that expert cannot challenge that use on the
basis of a reading. I’m treating each figure minimally as a generic name for
particular ecosystems (of) thought. Obviously this does not absolve me of
scholarly rigor, which I hope the citational apparatus will witness to, but it
does free this work as non-philosophy to experiment with their thoughts
for a project that is more concerned with a disempowering of the specular
culture of reading in the service of the creation of a theory of nature. Not a
reading of nature as Aquinas or Spinoza or al-Sijistânî understood nature,
but a theory of nature derived from philosophies and theologies as imma-
nent ecological material.
work here that even determines this “as a whole,” and that is the popula-
tion of “being.” For, “[t]his is where we are driven in our homesickness: to
being as a whole.”26
It is in the course of this lecture series that Heidegger touches on a
claim he makes in various other writings: that the Greek conception of
physis does not intend the same meaning as the Latin natura.27 Rather, he
claims that for the Greeks the word originally intended sense of physis was
the “self-forming prevailing of beings as a whole.”28 If the World is “as a
whole” and physis, which we translate as nature, is “self-forming prevailing
of beings as a whole,” then nature is subsumed into the notion of World.
In order to develop this notion of World Heidegger famously drew on the
German biologist Jacob von Uexküll, an early protoecological thinker, and
his theory of different Umwelts for different animals. This was an early
conception of the ecological concept of niche that has been greatly sur-
passed with the discovery of different relations and intensities that form
niches, yet the earlier conception of Umwelt has captured many philoso-
phers’ attention.29 But of course the metaphysical concept of World does
not suddenly appear in the midst of this lecture course, but is of funda-
mental importance in his 1927 Being and Time as well. There, Heidegger
shows himself to be a worldly philosopher in the construction of a philoso-
phy ultimately concerned with the worldliness of thought. This is a very
different view of his philosophy than he himself put forward, for in his
view his philosophy, like all true philosophy, was dealing with the question
of ontology, of Being qua Being or the Beingness of beings and so on. In
order to get to the discussion of Being, however, he has to pass through
the World. Dasein, a first name for human being, has to disclose itself in
a World. Heidegger, in his attempt to overturn Platonism, can not simply
think Being in the abstract, or as an Ideal subtracted from its actuality, and
so his philosophy must quickly come to terms with the World, if not with
the state of the World as horizon of Dasein, as that into which Dasein is
thrown. Incidentally, it is in this way that Heidegger’s thought, as is often
noticed, gives itself over to certain environmental concerns. Dasein, the
being of human being, does not exist separated from the wider whole of
beings, indeed Dasein is said to be in-the-World. Dasein is split between
a comportment toward its own Being and “which in each case I myself
am.”30 But what is important is not Dasein, but what grounds Dasein and
allows it to take on a “definite character” in both modes. Heidegger him-
self says, “[T]hey must be seen and understood a priori as grounded upon
that state of Being which we have called ‘Being-in-the-world.’ ”31
What this “being-in” consists of, according to Heidegger, is not a deter-
mination of Dasein, but the being-in is a state of Being of Dasein. Thus
Dasein is not “side-by-side” with the World, for Dasein is not a thing that
Separating Nature from the World 179
that structure. Badiou holds that the true significance of the Greek birth
of philosophy is not poetry, for poetry is more universal and found in
prephilosophical societies (China, India, and Egypt are named), but rather
what constitutes the Greek event is the interruption of the poem with the
matheme. The poem that is interrupted is the same poem that Badiou
“willingly admits” is the site of the letting-be of appearing a letting-be
that is sutured to the “theme of nature.” Thus, by implication, the Greek
event of ontology interrupts nature as the site of appearance, untying the
“thought of Being from its poetic enchainment to natural appearing.”48
This need to find at philosophy’s origin a fundamental privileging of
Being and the matheme over nature and poetry discloses the hierarchical
structure, which is to say worldly structure, of Badiou’s philosophy. Now,
it would be misguided, especially within an ecological context, to simply
reject hierarchy, for the concept is used though not in the absolute form
found in philosophy and theology. But it remains important to note that it
is that hierarchical structure that mediates the thinking of the particular
“concept of nature,” as Badiou calls it.49 We can extrapolate from here to
a kind of formal explanation of his system of philosophy: philosophy is
conditioned by truth events that arise from one of the four domains, but
philosophy must show how the truth-event is compossible within the other
truth-procedures (thus the domain has a fundamentally double structure,
both as a world where a truth occurs and as a discourse that pronounces
that truth or makes its appearance intelligible); thus the object taken for
philosophical analysis (as analysis via the conceptual framework of com-
possibility) will manifest itself distinctly and fully within this framework
and philosophy will pronounce the conjuncture of this object. However,
it is clear from the overall form of Badiou’s work, especially in his major
philosophical books, that, though philosophy is not to be sutured to the
mathematical, it is not to take a democratic form between the conditions
either. Mathematics, and thus ontology, is thus of ultimate regard and one
can almost say, slipping into Laruelle’s conceptual vocabulary, that in the
last instance the object is mathematic.50
This is what plays out in relation to the concept of nature in his analy-
sis. Some aspect of nature remains within the truth-procedure of poetry,
though Badiou does not elaborate on what that is and his main interest
remains ontological asking, “What happens—for that part of it which
has not been entrusted to the poem—to the concept of ‘nature’ in this
configuration [ . . . ] the framework of mathematical ontology? [ . . . ] is
there a pertinent concept of nature in the doctrine of the multiple?”51 The
answer is a subtraction from the Heideggerian discussion of nature, where
nature as physis names that which comes to stand and remain standing in
itself, but this ultimately must still be translated into Badiou’s own terms
182 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
Let us return now to the question posed earlier: why is it that the World, as
the name Heidegger claims is closer to the intention of the Greeks’ mean-
ing of physis, must be subsumed into the Being of Dasein in order to be
revealed? And doesn’t this turn nature, as subsumed into the World, into
yet another thing in the World? The answer seems to me to be yes, but
there is an important corollary to this thingness of nature subsumed into
World: there is a reversibility between the World and Dasein’s Being, which
is in fact the genesis of the thingness of nature at work here. For the World
is the appearance of Being and Being is what produces the appearance
such that Heidegger’s thought continually comes to turn around these two
terms throughout his work.60 This becomes clearest, perhaps ironically,
in Heidegger’s conception of the fourfold. The potential irony arises from
the fact that, of all Heidegger’s concepts, the fourfold is the most poetic
and thus the biggest distraction for Continentalists in their attempts to
have mainstream Anglophone philosophers take seriously the work of
Heidegger. For what does it mean to say that “[t]he fouring presences as
the worlding of world”?61 Especially when that meaning is dependent upon
the “fouring” of “earth and sky, divinities and mortals”!62
Yet, while of course the fourfold is indeed strange at first glance, it still
works as a way of thinking about the presence of things. It is through this
fourfold that one who is thinking is able to presence the thingness of some
thing, to speak Heideggerian. The power, in terms of its ability to produce
thought, may become clearer if one thinks of the fourfold as a particular
184 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the earth is what is seemingly absent in its closeness, while the sky is where
the unveiling of transcendence happens. Climate becomes clear to us not
as a whole, but in our experience of weather as manifest in the unexpected
storm on the horizon or the haze of an especially hot Chicago summer
day. The second axis is the life and death that are sustained by this first
axis, yet also constitute its actuality. For the mortals are those who “are the
human beings. They are called mortals because they can die. To die means
to be capable of death as death.”69 The divinities are those who provide the
measure of that unthinkable moment, a moment that mortals witness, but
do not experience in that witness. That is, the divinities are the measure of
this moment through their absence, which Heidegger calls their default,
which presences a hidden fullness.70 This hidden fullness is only experi-
enced because of mortal finitude, for Heidegger, because of the fact that an
individual human being is not the fullness of being.
This then creates an interesting new set of binaries that are more abstract
and that are lacking in the three commentators we’ve discussed: that of
earth and divinities and sky and mortals. For there is a deep connection
between the veiled character of the earth and the default absence of the
gods at work in the fourfold, just as there is a deep connection between the
presence of mortals and the unveiling of the sky. For, as we stated earlier,
the fourfold is ultimately concerned with individuation by way of mea-
sure. Consider Heidegger’s words when he writes, “What is the measure
for human measuring? God? No. The sky? No. The manifestness of the
sky? No. The measure consists in the way in which the god who remains
unknown, is revealed as such by the sky.”71 Thus, contra Young’s sugges-
tion that earth and sky form the axis of nature and mortals and divinities
form the axis of culture, it is actually that the quarter (rather than axis)
formed by earth and divinities is where nature is given as absent and veiled
and the quarter produced by sky and mortals as present and unveiled is
where culture is: culture reveals nature as such for Heidegger.
Following this quarterial vision we can thus see the fourfold not as
fourfold but another duality of identity expressed as (earth and divinities)
and (sky and mortals).72 If, following Laruelle, an identity is always what
is One in-the-last-instance, then this duality must be thought unilaterally.
But since this duality is in actuality a set of two dualities, the act of uni-
lateralization will require three operations. First unilateralize the duality
of the two sets ([earth/divinities] and [sky/mortals]) and then deal with
the real identities at work in these two sets. In-the-last-instance the set of
sky and mortals is determined by the set of earth and divinities. That is,
culture is determined in the last instance by nature and culture has no real
effect on nature as such. For, even if culture plays its part in the destruction
of the biosphere, it does so naturally. Nature remains perverse in the face
Separating Nature from the World 187
of culture and quite explicitly nature’s perversion is found in the very exis-
tence of culture as it is at work naturally in the biosphere. Yet the thinking
of nature in this dyad is caught. Always a thought of two terms in rela-
tion: earth and divinities in Heidegger’s terminology. These two terms can
stand in for a number of different terms in the history of thought and the
relationship between the two terms varies depending on the system at play.
The idea of “Nature,” with the capital N intended, is often aligned with
Heidegger’s earth. This is Nature of philosophies of immanence as well as
naturalism. It is often thought in relation to God, aligned with Heidegger’s
divinities in this case, and is the God of theological thinking as well as any
form of philosophical transcendence that claims to be outside of the condi-
tions of what is (so of course simple change is not transcendent in this way).
It is by looking at these terms, Nature and God as understood to be generic
terms related to Heidegger’s earth and divinities, that we will unilateralize
this dyad or think nature as in-One. We will begin thinking through the
relations of these two terms ostensibly by looking at the way they func-
tion in St. Thomas Aquinas, before turning to Benedict de Spinoza and,
breaking with what might seem like a historical survey, turning to Ismaili
thinkers Abu Ya’qûb al-Sijistânî and somewhat on Na īr al-Dīn ūsī. But
by engaging with these historical thinkers I am not aiming to provide a
definitive reading. While I have made traditional studies of these think-
ers in preparing for this chapter, I do not present these as studies as such.
Instead, those studies have allowed me to treat these thinkers minimally,
as occasions that provide simple material with which to work.
Thus the theory I put forth here is neither Thomist, Spinozist, nor
Ismaili. What we have done here is change the fourfold from where the
“World worlds” and turned it into an n-dimensional ecosystem. We have
shown that the World, an image of representation, is separate from the
ecosystem, which is always an identity of flowing energy amid identities
that are radically immanent in the ecosystem. For now the claim is that the
set of earth and divinities is unilaterally related to the axis of earth and sky
(biosphere), while recognizing that an element of this set is found in the
axis. By unilateralizing the fourfold in this way we have actually treated
it as an ecosystem such that the set of earth and divinities operates as the
living, the dead (earth), and the never-living (divinities) aspect of the eco-
system. This thesis will appear as if it were standard reductive naturalism,
and this is why there is a need to work out the real identities of earth and
divinities as they are found at work in other philosophical and theological
attempts to think nature. In a certain way what we’re practicing here is an
ideational “forcing” or forçage in the French. This is usually ascribed to
a technical aspect in set theory related to showing how all terms can be
generic without having to do the infinite equations required to actually
188 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
derive such a result. But the term also refers to a more obviously ecological
practice of forcing a particular plant to grow when it wouldn’t be able to.
This may involve planting and growing the roots late in the season, as in
the summer, and then taking the roots out in the fall to be forced or grown
indoors out of season. Or, more commonly, greenhouses are another exam-
ple of forcing. In each case the plant is removed from its wider ecosystem,
such that the soil it grows in is not the same soil that grows in the front
garden and so it is not using the nutrients in the same way it would. In the
next chapter we will practice this in relation to the four terms discussed
before turning to bringing these newly identified terms together again.
Chapter 12
unified in their cause, which is that simple being.3 Thus, at the heart of his
doctrine of God is creation.
With regard to the human capacity to understand God, analogy allows
one to recognize the epistemological limits in thinking about God as tran-
scendent, but also to locate what can be known through an investigation
of God’s effects. This doctrine takes its mature formulation in the Summa
Contra Gentiles where, before moving into the argument for the doctrine
of analogy, Aquinas affirms the negative theology of Pseudo-Dionysius at
the same time as he affirms that names can be predicated of God.4 He does
this through a differentiation of meaning and signification. The mode of
signification, thinking of God in relation to other things we call good, is
imperfect for those good things are never good in themselves. They are
related to God as cause or as that by which they are as effect. This means
that when we predicate God by the name “good” we have predicated an
imperfection in the mode of signification. The term that has the status of
creation in the analogy is imperfect, as its being good is dependent on the
other term of the analogy—God.5 In this way the thinking of any created
thing relates us immediately back to God via their imperfection as effect
and not cause in itself. To understand how something is good we have to
transcend what they are and move to that by which they are. Then, in order
to understand God at all we recognize that the imperfection of the thing
that has goodness does not befit God, but the meaning in some eminent
way does befit God. With regard to such names that hold in their positive
nature imperfection, such as a good thing, Aquinas writes, “such names,
therefore, as Dionysius teaches, can be both affirmed and denied of God.
They can be affirmed because of the meaning of the name; they can be
denied because of the mode of signification.”6
There are other names that Aquinas says are said of God alone, as
they express perfections unavailable to creatures, and belong to him
through the mode of supereminence.7 This mode of supereminence can
only be expressed through negation, as when we say that God is in-finite,
un-composed, im-mutable, or un-divided.8 These supereminent expres-
sions were not thought by Aquinas to be found in the sensible world and in
that sense they cannot be investigated for a further understanding of God’s
being. We may even go so far as to suggest they are but a matter of fact,
but a fact that stands against further positive knowledge and only allowing
knowledge as wonder. The desire caused by this wonder may be assuaged
by recourse to an investigation of the relation creation has to God, “as
when [God] is called the first cause or the highest good.”9 This is the indirect
way of understanding God, through the divine action in creation. Thus we
are given the full apophatic structure of Aquinas’s thought in the preamble
to his discussion of analogy: “[W]e cannot grasp what God is, but only
192 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
what [God] is not and how other things are related to [God].”10 This is
then a two-pronged apophaticism—a negative knowledge of what God is
not and an indirectly positive knowledge of God that devastates the idea
that creatures have positive being in themselves.
For analogy to work as a tool of piety it must have both aspects of this
apophaticism. Only in this way can it form thought and direct attention
in a way that satisfies the demands placed upon Aquinas by his situation.
It must give attention to the dependency of humanity, as well as the rest
of creation, on a God who is perfect being itself. At the same time it has
to give attention to the true understanding of God of which humanity,
and perhaps the rest of creation, must have some access other than (non-
existent) pure revelation. As Aquinas understands them, the other gram-
mars or conceptions of how human persons may name and thus think
about God, as qualified by the Christian creeds and Church Fathers, do
not give sufficient attention. Thus univocal predication is not sufficient in
Aquinas’s view because it both implicitly denies the radical otherness of
God and attempts to give access to knowledge of God through some third
term. The radical otherness of God is not respected in univocal predi-
cation because it attempts to find some commonality between God and
creatures through either a genus, a species, a difference, an accident, or
a property.11 The third term that allows access to a certain knowledge of
God also removes the difference between God and creation by subjecting
them to a concept that is simpler than the other two. Aquinas affirms
the demands of orthodoxy on this point and writes, “Now, there can be
nothing simpler than God either in reality or in concept.”12 If there were
a concept simpler than God it would mean there was a concept that has a
perfection that, by ontological definition, can only be said to belong, via
supereminence, to God.
Equivocal predication gives insufficient attention to the relationship
of God and creatures, as it allows no understanding of an order of cause
and effect between two terms.13 For there to be such an understanding a
thing must have some understanding of its own identity, what Aquinas
calls “likeness,” in itself, whereas equivocal predication erases this iden-
tity through the unity of the name.14 This identity, or likeness to God
through the relationship of a cause to its effects, is necessary for there to be
any reasoning of God at all. Since creatures are not God and thus cannot
know God as Godself they must proceed in their reasoning from crea-
tures, which share a likeness to God as God’s effects, to God, as cause.15
In this way equivocal predication of God, as Aquinas understands it, gives
no access to any knowledge of God in much the same way that univo-
cal predication does not. Equivocal predication tells us nothing because
it posits a unity of name that erases the relationship of creatures to God,
Materials for a Theory of Nature 193
read in the light of his later works. After running through defining expla-
nations of the three principles of nature (matter, form, and lack of form)
Aquinas turns to writing on “ultimate matter” or “first matter.”27 Ultimate
matter is defined paradoxically by Aquinas in this way: “Only material
subject to form and lack of form but having no particular form or lack of
form in itself can be called ultimate matter, because it presupposes no other
material; and another name for it is [hyle].”28
In Aquinas’s account of nature’s three principles ultimate matter appears
as a remainder, in that it cannot be thought rationally like the other three,
but can nevertheless be argued for as underling reality. The only reason
that ultimate matter may be thought at all is because of analogy. He writes,
“But since we define and know things by way of their forms, ultimate
matter can’t be known or defined as such, but only by an analogy, as that
which relates to all forms and lack of forms as bronze does to statues and
to shapelessness, and so is ultimate.”29 That is, as Aquinas shows us the
principles of nature through analogy with intentional human produc-
tion like statue making, the mind may easily begin to think that there is
some ultimate kind of potential matter like bronze is for the statue. Some
would suggest that this is an illegitimate anthropomorphism of nature, but
Aquinas is being quite ecological here as human beings are also natural and
thus their actions can be understood to be part of wider natural causation.
On a further ecological note, ultimate matter cannot be known directly as
what it is in itself but only through its relations with other things. Analogy
may then be defined as knowing through relation. Ultimate matter can
only be speculated about via an analogy with material that does have par-
ticular form and lack of form and thus Aquinas can make claims about it,
but nothing about it in itself other than what is given by logical necessity.
These claims are ultimately speculative, even little leaps of faith, for we
know individuation or generation through forms and thus, Aquinas leads
us to think, within our own limited ability to know, we have to say that
“[n]othing actually existent then can be called ultimate matter.”30
But to return to the question of whether this relational knowledge
occurs through some agreement only in one’s understanding or in the
wider reality outside that understanding, we note that to know that some-
thing is “implies some vague knowledge of what ” it is.31 Aquinas is using
the notion of analogical knowledge, where knowledge is always connected
to the truth of its being true, to mediate between totalizing knowledge and
equally totalizing ignorance. Furthermore it suggests that knowledge
through analogy implies the truth of being analogically. All knowledge,
in Aquinas’s thought, must ultimately follow the vacillation of theologi-
cal knowing—between knowledge that leads to possession of being by
its being known and ignorance, which leads to vice. In this way all true
196 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
real, constant exceeding of matter. Nature can thus be given the apophatic
name “creation” to express this reality.
As an apophatic name of nature, creation bequeaths a powerful notion
to the thinking of nature in philosophy and theology in ontologically sig-
nificant apophaticism. However, as purely Thomistic such ontologically
significant apophaticism has its own limits, which are located in its think-
ing from analogy. While this section attempts to show the strength of
Aquinas’s thinking from analogy it must also return to the use of Aquinas
by the police (again, following Jordan’s terminology) and ask what makes
Aquinas’s thinking so easily amenable to such reactionary use. The
trade-off for giving a certain divine dignity to creation through apophati-
cally thinking it as God’s effects is that God’s transcendence as limit to
violence is undermined, though not destroyed. That is, in non-theological
terms, thinking from analogy suffers from its own version of the natural-
ist fallacy. Analogy must proceed from what is in order to understand the
nature of the divine. In doing so it lacks any kind of organon for selection
and thus may select, as Aquinas himself did, an analogy of monarchy:
“[W]hatever is in accord with nature is best, for nature always operates for
the best. But in nature government is always by one. [ . . . ] Among the bees
is one king bee, and in the whole universe one God is the Maker and Ruler
of all.”35 Here Aquinas proceeds not from an understanding of nature to a
properly analogical understanding of God but from what human govern-
ment is to a misunderstanding of what government in nature is and then
to a conception of God’s governance. Bees, we now know, do not have any
one ruler as the queen of a particular hive does not direct the action of that
hive; the hive, rather, proceeds in a way altogether unlike human govern-
ment from monarchy to democracy. Indeed, what is in nature may be best,
because it is what is, but what is in nature is varied. Its organization is not
reducible to any one organization and thus analogy may not find a secure
position from any one part of nature and may not be able to think from the
whole of nature in ways that allow it to remain orthodox.
The problem with analogy is then that the entire process of analogi-
cal predication is unable to function outside of the purely metaphysical.
In terms of a doctrine of God the apophaticism of creation is productive,
but it is only productive on the basis of a second-order negation of nature.
I have shown that when one selects from what is (nature) to know God,
subsequently, that which is (the natural thing) is shown to truly be relative
to the ipsum esse per subsistans. We first know by way of something natural,
but that knowledge is then perfected in the abstract thinking of God thus
negating the autonomy of what is natural in the light of its cause. This
apophatic thinking of creation ultimately pulls the ground out from under
the one thinking, for what the perversity of nature resists is the selection
198 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
those who knew he didn’t really believe in God, why would he come right
out into the open and write, in perhaps the clearest section of his Ethics,
“[t]hat eternal and infinite being we call God, or Nature, acts from the same
necessity from which he exists.”42 For this is actually the productive power
of Spinoza’s philosophy. Consider that the general formula of Spinoza’s
ontological scheme can at first appear to be a kind of rationalist reworking
of Neoplatonism. From that perspective, the Ethics begins with a single
substance not unlike the Neoplatonic One and like it this substance must
be one since it is that which is in itself and conceived in itself. Therefore
substance, like the One, does not require the concept of another thing
for it to be formed.43 This substance is God (or nature) and from God (or
nature) attributes can be located, which are what the intellect takes to be
the essence of substance.44 Spinoza holds that there are an infinite num-
ber of these attributes, but that the intellect can have knowledge of two:
Thought and Extension.45 There are then also modes that are finite actuali-
ties or “affections of a substance, or that which is in another through which
it is also conceived.”46 A cursory reading of Spinoza could confuse this
schema with a kind of poor Neoplatonic emanationism where substance =
the One (not to be confused with the non-philosophical One), attributes
= Nous, and the World Soul and its divisions with the modes. But what
is productive in Spinoza’s thought is the way that emanation is completely
changed through the equivocation of God, nature, and substance by way
of immanent causality.47 But what happens through this equivocation is
not an overcoding of one term by the other, a kind of secular determination
to counter the prevailing theological determination of Spinoza’s time, but a
complete change in the understanding of both terms.
So, while Levene does not fully deal with Spinoza’s Marrano foundation,
Strauss and Wolfson aim to overcode the population (of) thought called
God with an all-too-easy conception of nature as assumed by the myth
of Enlightenment reason. They miss out that both God and nature are
changed in Spinoza’s thought. As Nancy Levene writes, “From a religious
standpoint, God is eternal and nature is made; from a non-religious stand-
point, God is made and nature is eternal. Both, to Spinoza, are right.”48
Or as Blayton Polka writes, “Deus sive natura. God is (infinitely) natural.
But nature is also (infinitely) divine.”49 The minimal difference between
these two quotations discloses something important about Spinoza’s prac-
tice of thought. For Levene’s statement it is a question of standpoint, of the
thinker thinking the thought, and for Polka’s statement it is a question of
ontology, what God and Nature really are. The reality of Spinoza’s practice
is that both statements are true, for the standpoint of a thinker thinking
a true idea and the being of that idea are the same. This is commonly
called parallelism, though as Deleuze reminds us we should be somewhat
Materials for a Theory of Nature 201
cautious with this terms since it was not Spinoza’s own but appears to
come from Leibniz.50 But Deleuze goes on to say that “Spinoza’s doctrine
is rightly named ‘parallelism,’ but this [is] because it excludes any analogy,
any eminence, any transcendence. Parallelism, strictly speaking, is to be
understood neither from the viewpoint of occasional causes, nor from the
viewpoint of ideal causality, but only from the viewpoint of an immanent
God and immanent causality.”51 In other words what parallelism really
concerns is three forms of identity rather than difference: an identity of
order or correspondence between modes of different attributes, identity
of connection or equality of principle, and identity of being or ontological
unity.52 In other words, to say that there is a parallelism between the modes
of the attributes Thought and Extension is to say that they are the same
thing or as Spinoza himself puts it, “So also a mode of extension and the
idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways.”53
One could even take Laruelle’s vocabulary and say that in-last-instance
they have the same identity and they are distinguished only by the other
attributes that their idea involves.54
This focus on identity arises in response to a problem. For it would
appear that in Spinoza’s universe there can be no causal interaction between
ideas and bodies. This has to do with the relationship between knowledge
of causes and effects, rather than the in-itself reality of those causes and
effects. For, with regard to Substance what we can know is actually very
little, but we can have knowledge of its essence as expressed in the attri-
butes Thought and Extension. Yet Spinoza states that “[t]he knowledge of
an effect depends on, and involves, the knowledge of its cause.”55 Different
modes fall under different attributes, that is, they are necessarily conceived
in relation to something other than themselves.56 But since each attribute
of a substance must be conceived of through itself, as the essence of the one
substance, then a mode falling under one of the attributes cannot affect a
mode falling under the other.57 Yet, just because these finite modes under
different attributes cannot causally affect one another does not mean they
are unrelated. Instead they share an identity under the three forms Deleuze
located and that are discussed earlier. For “[t]he order and connection of
ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.”58
In the Ethics this form of thought is only discussed in relation to the
modes. But, as Deleuze says, “it is grounded in substance and the attri-
butes of substance.”59 Thus parallelism of modes only makes sense insofar
as there is a principle of identity at work. Again, Deleuze captures this
point with aplomb:
God produces all things in all attributes at once: he produces them in the
same order in each, and so there is a correspondence between modes of
202 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
different attributes. But because attributes are really distinct this correspon-
dence, or identity of order, excludes any causal action of one on another.
Because the attributes are all equal, there is an identity of connection
between modes differing in attribute. Because attributes constitute one
and the same substance, modes that differ in attribute form one and the
same modification. One may in a sense see in this the triad of substance
“descending” into the attributes and communicating itself to the modes.60
the cause, which is God, through its effects, which is nature or creation,
because, “since knowledge of an effect through a cause is simply to know
some property of the cause,” then “the more we learn about natural things,
the more perfectly we come to know the essence of God (which is cause of
all things); and thus all our knowledge, that is, our highest good, not only
depends on a knowledge of God but consists in it altogether.”62
There is then an identity of correspondence again between the cause and
effect here. Unlike in Aquinas this bears itself out in a political and social
thought that moves from the selection of the variance of nature rather than
from particulars and this has implications for Spinoza’s understanding of
natural right. His notion of natural right follows from nature’s perfection,
which refuses reason demanding anything contrary to Nature and thus
demands that “everyone love himself, seek his own advantage, what is really
useful to him, want what will really lead a man to greater perfection, and
absolutely, that everyone should strive to preserve his own being as far as
he can.”63 This is sometimes taken by readers to mean that the strong can
do what they will, by their natural power, to the weak who cannot resist
by their natural power. Conor Cunningham hyperbolically makes the
ridiculous and offensive claim that the equivocation of God, nature, and
substance “has therefore enabled Spinoza to rid the world of all substances
(and eventually of all substance)” such that “in the world of Spinoza there
can be no difference between a Holocaust and an ice-cream.”64 According
to this view Spinoza would hold that if one can perpetuate a Holocaust as
easily as they produce and eat an ice cream, then there is no reason by right
why they should not.
But here we find the Christian theistic theologian Cunningham making
the same mistake as atheists like Nadler, whereby he confuses a preexisting
concept of nature as the same conception of nature at work in Spinoza. While
ultimately this conception is still caught in a dyad with God, it nonetheless
suggests a truly radical conception of nature that can be elucidated by put-
ting it in dialogue with the Catholic debate over pure nature. This debate is
as complex as it is tedious, but we can distil the doctrine to the idea that says
there is some part of God’s creation independent of a desire for God. This
would mean that there would be some part of nature that was free from
the desire for the grace of God and thus sets up a hard dualism between
nature and grace, or nature and the supernatural (God), whereas those who
stand against pure nature would prefer a softer, grammatical dualism gener-
ated by the analogy of being that recognizes only God as true Being. Yet,
Spinoza’s conception of the relationship between God and nature, even as
natura naturata, is nothing like “pure nature.” Indeed, Spinoza critiques
the theology of miracles that contains the seeds that lead to the conceiv-
ing of something like “pure nature” within Christian doctrine itself. The
204 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
[S]ince the virtue and power of nature is the very virtue and power of God
and the laws and rules of nature are the very decrees of God, we must
certainly believe that the power of nature is infinite, and its laws so broad
as to extend to everything that is also conceived by the divine understand-
ing. For otherwise what are we saying but that God has created a nature so
impotent and with laws and rules to feeble that He must continually give it
a helping hand, to maintain it and keep it going as He wills; this I certainly
consider to be completely unreasonable.67
is proven by nothing more clearly than from what they perceive as nature
failing to follow its natural course. [ . . . ] They evidently hold that God
is inactive whilst nature follows its normal course and, conversely, that
the power of nature and natural causes are superfluous whenever God is
active.”68 The position Spinoza is here arguing against is the same under-
standing, though in a crude mode, that the neo-Scholastics gave to the
split between the natural and the supernatural. Spinoza rejects this on the
basis of knowledge of nature, as opposed to the theologically orthodox
understanding of the revelation of Scripture, but knowledge of nature is
taken to be revelatory for questions of metaphysics in the same way that
Scripture is taken to be revelatory for questions of true piety (charity and
justice) and in this way the two are not opposed.
Consider how Spinoza mutates Hobbes’s conception of natural right as
explained by Deleuze through his explication of four theses that come out
of this mutation. The first is that the law of nature refers to an initial desire
and not a state of final perfection. The second thesis is that reason is only
secondary to conatus, or the will to persevere in one’s being. The third the-
sis states that power or right is primary and unconditional, which is to say
prior to reason. The final thesis has two parts: (1) regardless of their powers
of reason every person in the state of nature judges what is good, bad, and
necessary for their preservation; and (2) no one gives up their natural right
due to some recognition of the authority of a wise person, but from either
fear of a greater evil or hope of a greater good. The consequence of these
theses is that the principle of consent, whether pact or contract, replaces
authority as first principle for political philosophy.69
Let us return to the second thesis where Deleuze says, “[No]body is born
reasonable. Reason may perhaps apply and preserve the law of nature, but is
in no sense its principle or motive force. Similarly, nobody is born a citizen.
The civil state may preserve the law of nature, but the state of nature is in
itself presocial, precivil. Further still, nobody is born religious.”70 Deleuze is
here referencing Spinoza’s discussion of the state originating in the natural
and civil right of individuals by way of pact with sovereign powers found
in Chapter 16 of the Theological-Political Treatise where we find Spinoza
responding to a potential criticism that there is a contradiction between the
claim that everyone who is without the use of reason has the sovereign natu-
ral right in a state of nature to live by the laws of appetite and the claim that
all are responsible before the revealed divine law. Spinoza states that this is
true only with respect to humanity’s ignorance in the state of nature:
We can easily deal with this objection simply by examining the state of
nature closely. For this is prior to religion both by nature, and in time.
No one knows from nature that he is bound by obedience towards God.
206 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
There could be only one way of making the state of nature viable: by striv-
ing to organize its encounters. Whatever body I meet, I seek what is use-
ful. But there is a great difference between seeking what is useful through
chance (that is, striving to destroy bodies incompatible with our own) and
seeking to organize what is useful (striving to encounter bodies agreeing in
nature with us, in relations in which they agree). Only the second type of
effort defines proper or true utility. [ . . . ] There is in Nature neither Good
nor Evil, there is no moral opposition, but there is ethical difference.74
Therefore the greatest virtue of the mind, that is, the mind’s power, or
nature, or its greatest striving, is to understand things by the third kind of
knowledge.78
But the ignorant may also find salvation in simple obedience to the require-
ments of grace and charity demanded of them by religious revelation.79 In
each case, however, the point is that salvation happens in the midst of the
earth. The equivocation of God and nature directs attention toward the
earth, rather than toward some transcendent beyond, and yet it is able to
so without recourse to pure nature. And it does so by making of the earth
a form of transcendence produced by what is immanent. For what is taken
as revelation of transcendence, religious revelation, is revealed in nature.
This is what we will go on to call a non-thetic transcendence or a transcen-
dence that is an effect of immanence, but still expresses the real kernel of
transcendence in actuality.
Do you not see that the human being, in whom the most subtle quintes-
sence of the two universes has been concentrated, lives on the earth? His
subsistence is on the Earth. His return is a returning to the Earth, and his
resurrection is a resurgence from the Earth. From these premises it follows
that we have shown that the Earth is not inferior to heaven in dignity and
merits the presence of the angels, since a great number of potentialities
[ puissances] are achieved in the Earth that are in harmony with the angels.
Understand this.83
the One to thought as that which is beyond Being and Alterity, but which
manifests itself as lived in-Person. In terms whose meaning is more directly
understandable, instead of treating Deus sive natura as a relation between
two terms, treat the equation as itself relative to the radical autonomy of
the Real-One. This radicalizes the Spinozist response to the Thomist fail-
ure of selection, for instead of selecting the whole of nature as the best way
to think God, the non-theologian selects the whole of the dyad of God and
nature in order to think the cloned One.
Jambet shows how this conception of nature is dependent on being
thought from the paradoxical One of Ismaili Islam. Thus al-Sijistânî’s con-
ception is helpful for our theory of nature because it moves thinking from
the perspective of Being to a thinking in-One. Ismaili Islam, whether or not
Laruelle himself knows this, appears as a kind of proto-non-philosophical
conception of the One, though couched in terms of a radical transcen-
dence rather than a radical immanence. Yet the formalism of the One, as
discussed in chapter 6, can be seen “in-person” so to speak when we think
it alongside of the Ismaili experience of liberty, which was actually lived
in the proclamation of the time of Resurrection (qiyâmat) in the twelfth
century, after the collapse of their Fatimid caliphate that ruled over the
Islamic world.85 The story of the Ismailis of Alamût is fascinating and
should be of interest to anyone interested in messianism, but the historical
details are not of particular interest here.86 Rather, it is the relationship
between this messianic act and the One that is important. Jambet explains
this necessary connection and mutation of the Neoplatonic One and the
messianic act in Ismaili thought writing:
But, conversely, this creative spontaneity will also explain the creation of
the existent, the ordained and hierarchized formation of universes. Just as
much as with the unjustified liberty, the One will be able to justify the pro-
cession of the intelligible and sensible, and the gradation of the spiritual and
bodily worlds. Avoiding dualism, all while thinking the duality between
the One and the order of Being which it interrupts; conceiving, on the other
hand, of the unity of order and creative spontaneity—all while preserving
the dualist sentiment—without which the experience of messianic liberty
was impossible: this is what neo-Platonic thought offered to the Ismaili.87
In short, the One allows the Ismaili to think the pure formalism of the
Real—there is the non-thetic transcendence found in the negation of
Being, interrupting the order of Being and beings, and the immanence of
(non-)One or the existant that is beyond any totality, that is pure fissure
itself.
The immanental aspect of the Real-One, which is carried in each One,
simply cannot be reduced to a totality, to some kind of idea of number. It
exists without any ground whatsoever, and this is its source of liberty or
autonomy from any attempt to capture it within philosophical or theologi-
cal structures:
It is necessary that the Angel come. And so that he comes, being invisible,
he must have been visible in his works, he must have been announced in
history, he must have been there, not two objects of desire, that is where
the Fathers were lost, but two desires. Or rather, a desire, that is to say a
sexual desire, and a desire that has nothing to do with sex, not even the
desire for God: rebellion. On the one hand pleasure, jouissance, and on the
other not even beatitude. Something still unnamed, that we have called
desire under the pressure of language, which we must force into delivering
a name to us. But the Angel is anonymous, or polynymous. We only call
it that by way of negative metaphors. That’s how pseudo-Dionysius wants
to speak about that which is God. Negative theology. Speaking about the
world before the break from which it will be born, we can say nothing
except from the negative. I do not see how else to hold on to the hope of
revolution.90
the angels, the Gnostic Christ is the Envoy charged with delivering men
from their enslavement in this world by liberating in them the knowledge
of their origin and the means of getting back to the place from which
they have been exiled: Christos Angelos frees by the knowledge which gives
men the means of rebellion that they are, against all humility, fundamen-
tally driven by.”).106 So in order to understand Christ as generic subject we
must understand him as radically separate from Christianity. What better
way to do considering Christ from the perspective of a Gnostic-Islamic
Christology as present in Ismaili thought?107
Non-Philosophy is a practice of liberty from philosophy, from the struc-
ture of the World, and not an account of foundation and is thus messianic.
By taking the relatively transcendent pole of the fourfold and negating the
veiling and absence of the dyad of God or nature, we are able to free the
earth from unmessianic divinities. This choice then gives us a conception
of nature that unifies a scientific stance toward nature as the One of what
appears and the condition of that appearing and an ancient philosophical
problem of nature that has all too often ended in a conception of an over-
determining nature. Nature, in this middle place between the One and the
Future Christ as Resurrector, does not provide any of the usual limitations
to human and creatural liberty. Nothing in this conception is “unnatural,”
for nature is itself perverse here. As the condition for the appearance of
messianity of the human and other creatures it stands against what simply
is, against the sékommça. And it is ultimately here, when nature can be
turned against the natural, that we see the unified theory of messianism
and nature. Yes, let everyone say with Jambet and Lardreau “let the Angel
come!” but understand that the Angel can only come to the earth; it can
only overturn the World by overturning the absoluteness of both Being
and Alterity. For the earth, like the Angel, has no Master and is everywhere
and always already in revolt.
Conclusion
Theory of Nature
The ideas sketched in the chapters in this book are simple materials.
Understood under the immanental ecology put forth in chapter 9, aspects
may be extracted from their ecosystem and put into a relationship with
other materials. By way of a conclusion I will now present a theory of
the identity of nature constructed from these materials. I remind the
reader of the ending that we already gave away in the introduction, for
this theory of nature understands the creatural as subject of nature, the
chimera of God or Nature as non-thetic transcendence of nature, and
the One as radical immanence of nature. In that same introduction I
claimed that this theory would come to have a determinate meaning by
the end of the book and indeed what has thus far been discussed has been
necessary for the production of this theory. For this theory of nature has
grown out of the ecosystems (of) thought studied in the last chapter by
way of a unified theory of philosophical theology and ecology (which is,
of course, itself part of an ecosystem (of) thought as well) developed in
part III. This unified theory would not have been possible without the
reconception of the division of labor between philosophy and science that
Laruelle constructed in his non-philosophy as explained in part II, espe-
cially chapter 6. So, in this conclusion I will simply act as an ecologist of
thought. Ecologists are able to take people into a field and show them the
teeming drama of what seemed hidden before. I will do the same now for
this theory of nature.
218 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
For what is meant by creation in Aquinas’s defense is not the act of cre-
ation, which belongs in his view to God alone as cause, but rather to the
whole of the effects of the act of that cause. The creatural is the realm of
effect. Standard contemporary forms of what could be termed “Speculative
Thomism” (a title that would apply to those who use Aquinas as Jacques
Maritain and John Milbank do, as well as, to a lesser extent, Michael
Northcott, who was discussed in chapter 4), in an attempt to safeguard
Thomism and the humiliation of creatures it produces in its apophaticism
of nature, might object that I have made a category error here. Rather than
bestowing creatures with subjectivity, they could suggest, all subjectivity,
at least all real subjectivity, is retained for God. But this is exactly what
reveals the unmessianic character of Thomism, its deep connection with
secular naturalism and a worship of the sékommça. While the messianity
of creatures might seem like it could only be taken on faith, it is supported
by the loop of analogy that, without any organon of selection, constantly
loops upon itself producing this same sékommça. It also opens up to the
mistakes of positing some pure nature, which is anathema to these same
Speculative Thomists, but which they are unable to avoid when they insist
on the lack of positive existence for nature as creatures. Creatures, how-
ever, are always in the midst of fabulating messianity.
The creatural as subject of nature is expressed in the ecological concepts
of niche and biodiversity (chapter 9). For each of these is a fiction, or what
Bergson and Deleuze call a fabulation, a kind of story as effect of the One
that produces Being and Alterity. It is important that this notion of fabula-
tion not be confused with something unreal or even with Husserl’s irreal.
But the fabulation is the radical immanence of nature as One, a radical
immanence that is the lived bodily existence beyond transcendence of a
creature. Yet, importantly, this fabulation is created without there being a
reciprocal effect on the radical immanence of that Real-One. For there is
a finitude at work in the creatural. No creature is eternal within the orga-
nization fabulated into the World, yet each manifests as in-One and thus
is nature-in-person. When someone appeals to save creation, to save the
creatural, what they are appealing to is the salvation of the subject, of this
particular finite fiction that is how the earth or biosphere is lived. Again,
such a fiction is real, but is real as an effect of the Real and is thus said to
be in-One.
Treating creation as a population (of) thought we are able to remove
it from the wider system. This system is entrenched in Being as such, but
by removing it from the Greek and Christian ontological system, a goal of
non-philosophy in general as discussed in chapter 5, we are able to move
beyond the infinite loop of analogy. Here, where the creatural is the name
of nature’s subjectivity, there is no absolute apophaticism of creation in
220 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
the name of the Creator’s lone claim to Being used to chain and treat the
creatural as nothing. Rather analogy can come to function as a kind of
energy that is exchanged between and connects various creatures to one
another in terms of fabulative likeness. That is, rather than a complete
rejection of anthropomorphism, we can begin to think of the relative anal-
ogies between human beings and other creatures as an effect of the Real.
The complete rejection of anthropomorphism is a commonality between
theologians and radical ecotheorists, which even seeps into more popular
“Green” discourse. But this actually ends up putting a barrier between
human beings and other creatures as it sets up the old division between
humans and Nature. Human beings are part of the biosphere, they are
natural, and as such there are things in nature that have the form [morphe]
of human beings. That form will have commonalities with other creatures,
while of course having limits as well, but by thinking this kind of relative
analogy between creatures, creative of not just anthropomorphism but also
arbormorphism or elephamorphism. This relative form of analogy is pro-
ductive of an inconsistent and open ethic. Such an ethic operates through
the direction of attention to the suffering and exile common to all crea-
tures. This ethic of attention needs no other reason than their existence to
care for others. By way of a certain productive analogy of beings with the
human we can begin to change our attention. But this attention is always
guarded from being misdirected from suffering by way of a recognition of
its ungrounded character as a fabulation. Thus, when we speak of the bees
and think of them democratically (for this is closer to the actual organiza-
tion of bees than monarchy), we are free to do so in terms of a mass crea-
tural subject that includes the human alongside of the bee, but we do not
move from there away from this to a conception of the Real as such.
whom many in Ismaili Islam claimed was the “Hidden Imam” or, again,
the Messiah. This epistle, translated into English under the title The Case
of the Animals versus Man Before the King of the Jinn, details a protest made
by the animals against humanity and their violence against them because
of their belief “that the animals were their runaway and rebellious slaves.”8
Here we can see that in messianic traditions, albeit ones confusing radi-
cal immanence with an absolute transcendence, there is already a move-
ment toward this kind of open and inconsistent ethic of attention toward
the creatural, rather than the toward closed-species or what could even be
called the family, if taken in an enlarged sense.
The Aesopian element at work in theological and philosophical fables
like this fascinated Spinoza. For this Aesopian element is a version of the
general issue of metamorphosis, which fascinated Spinoza because once he
defined substance as being singular it seemed to him that we could then
think of bodies changing to such an extent they may not be considered to
be of the same nature as they were before. This in turn had important phil-
osophical consequences for thinking through what happens to a human
being in the change from infancy to adulthood.9 This interest in meta-
morphosis, really in what could be termed the supernatural, goes deeper
than a passing literary fancy for Spinoza, for it lies at the heart of the strat-
egy of the chimera discussed in the previous chapter. That strategy of the
chimera is of special interest to us when it creates the impossible equation
of God, or nature. Remember how Zourabichvili defines the chimera as
“whose nature veils [enveloppe] an open contradiction” and that which “by
its nature, cannot exist,” going on to write that “[t]he chimera is not a thing
but, if we can put it this way, a non-thing, a non-nature.”10
Here what we find is a conception of nature that is expressed as
non-thetic transcendence or what has been expressed as the non(-One)
in Laruelle. Though it seems oblique, it refers to “the real kernel of tran-
scendence” or rather transcendence understood as an effect of the radical
immanence of the One.11 As such it is a transcendence that is produced as
an effect of transcendence and yet gives itself nonreflexively as the support
for philosophical and theological thinking. A thetic statement is tautolo-
gous, like A = A, and as such fuses the idea of the posited and positing.
Paradoxically, then, even a thetic statement is a kind of chimera, an impos-
sible equation like God = nature. The power of a thetic statement lies in
the fact that they locate an identity outside of relativity and so do not take
into account the directionality of thought. Consider that if a river were
to suddenly reverse course, like the Chicago River was forced to do by
civil engineering in 1887, it does not cease being a river even though that
change in course radically alters its ecological make-up. What is non-thetic
about this transcendence is that it is relationally determined while also
222 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
strategy and in relation to the fourfold I still think this phrase works, but
it is more rigorously expressed as the One is prior to the World. The reason
that the earth isn’t a proper name for the Real within a unified theory of
philosophical theology and ecology is because the earth is actually part
of a wider relationality for its identity or, in other words, it is an effect
of nature. There is a kind of reversibility at work, as we say in chapters 8
and 9, between the earth and the flows of energy and material that make it
up, to the degree that the earth really is but a name for a certain organiza-
tion as One. In the same way the oceans and the atmosphere could also
be said to be prior to the World, but only because they too are a certain
organization as One.
So what does it mean to claim the One as the radical immanence of
nature? It is very different from the naturalisms and materialisms of phi-
losophy presented in chapter 2. Rather, the answer to this is found in
thinking together the lived subjective experience of nature as creatural as
well as its non-thetic transcendence as Nature as produced by this radical
immanence. For the radical immanence of nature as One unifies these two
modes of nature. As a creature I experience nature in-person as my body.
This is true of the lived experience of my body (of which I see no reason to
separate mind, since body is here taken in the sense of an effect rather than
a reductive materialist definition). For as a creatural body I am a certain
ecological organization of matter and energy. I produce in an ecological
sense. Yet, there is also a transcendent element at work in my experience
of this body in the sense that there is something separate from me, tran-
scending in a relative sense, that I may also call nature. I think of the way
an affliction, genetically coded, like gout, may suddenly come upon my
body and change my bodily relations, physical and mental, with the rest of
creatural nature. And yet, in the immediacy of practice and experience, I
don’t take this transcending ailment as a parameter set by Nature. That is
a secondary move and even a poor fabulation. Rather, what I can fabulate
as a creature, like Spinoza, is a cynical equivocation that locates within this
same transcending Nature the site of the appearance of the Messiah or a
great number of potentialities achieved on this body. So, within creatural
nature there are others who offer me help. Still others who create medicines
or research into the phenomenon and provide new knowledge about what
to do. So in the midst of this Nature, already disempowered for us now,
we see the appearance of love and charity. We may also see violence, but
such violence is always struggled against (as has already been discussed in
chapters 7 and 9).
Thus the Unicity of nature as One is not something that shall be
thought, if by this we aim to circumscribe and affect nature as One. For
that is impossible and only hallucinates either nature as subject or Nature
224 A Non-Philosophical Theory of Nature
The one who is faithful names from within the midst of the cage natu-
ralism attempts to put around creatures with its sékommça. It does so by
merging the radical apophaticism productive of creatural subjectivity with
the epiphany of radical immanence productive of a chimerical transcen-
dence. One is faithful when one submits to the One, which is a promiscu-
ous fidelity. Again following the Ismaili this is not a legalistic submission,
as if here we must submit to “laws of nature” and the limits it places on
human beings.16 Rather it is a submission to nature as name of the Real,
not as simple Power, but as knowledge and recognition of the freedom
inherent in radical immanence and productive of subjectivity. This allows
us to create a better fabulation of Nature and its relation to creatural sub-
jects, a fabulation that is able to find a joy in creating a different way of
living as creatures, respecting what may be called limits, but which turns
them into something other than negations. We turn nature into a first
name of the Real because this changes a hallucinatory, philosophical, and
theological Nature that loves to hide into a nature that, while foreclosed
to thought, reveals itself in our experience of the everyday. Ontology and
ethics are not treated separately here, for this form of nature as the Real,
as a radical immanence that we ourselves are the lived subjects of, requires
a kind of submission in the form of a certain kind of knowledge, a gnosis
that is salvation from the fabled war between humanity and nature. For
both are rootless. Both are abstract. Both are exiled such that home itself is
always something stranger than it seems.
Notes
Introduction
8. Ibid., pp. 10, 13. Nancy K. Levene argues persuasively that Spinoza trans-
forms and expands the meaning of revelation to something universal, rather
than something held within a particular religion. See her Spinoza’s Revelation:
Religion, Democracy, and Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2004).
9. Within the scope of this work, specifically in the chapters collected under
part I, the majority of the theology dealt with will be Christian, largely
Roman Catholic, and while there are important reasons to consider Islamic,
Jewish, or other forms of theology at greater length, I nonetheless limit myself
and consider this a necessary limitation due to time and space. However,
Islamic theology comes to have a privileged place in part IV.
8. Coates does discuss some theological themes within the specificity of the
attitude toward nature in the Middle Ages. This, however, is limited in that
Coates does not connect these themes to actual scientific practices. See Coates,
Nature, pp. 40–66.
9. Botkin, Discordant Harmonies, p. 82.
10. Ibid., p. 87.
11. Ibid., pp. 91–99.
12. Ibid., p. 93.
13. Ibid., p. 92; emphasis, as always unless noted, in original.
14. Ibid., p. 98.
15. Ibid., p. 99.
16. Ibid., pp. 101–110.
17. Ibid., p. 103.
18. Ibid.
19. Ibid., p. 109.
20. Cf. Ibid., p. 108.
21. Ibid., pp. 113–131, 133–151.
22. Ibid., p. 120.
23. Cf. Ibid., pp. 125–127.
24. Ibid., p. 136.
25. Ibid., pp. 146–147.
26. Ibid., p. 151.
27. Ibid., p. 110.
28. See Alain Badiou, The Century, trans. Alberto Toscano (Cambridge: Polity,
2007), pp. 48–57. There he suggests that this passion is what differentiates
the twentieth century from preceding ones, a claim that would suggest my
drawing on this notion to explain images of thought from prior centuries is
misplaced, but his own claim is undercut by calling on forebearers for this
passion such as Hegel.
29. Ecology has taken great pains to legitimate its scientific character, though
against doubts cast upon it by the wider scientific community because of its
ties with political issues. The question of the relationship between environ-
mentalism or political and scientific ecology is an interesting one with regards
to this legitimation crisis. See L évêque, Ecology, pp. 3–4, 8–9.
1. Some anecdotal evidence for this majority position of ethics and aesthetics can
be had by comparing the amount of Google hits one gets, at least in August
of 2009, for “environmental ethics” (about 1,180,000) and “environmental
aesthetics” (about 26,900) compared to “ecological metaphysics” (241) and
“metaphysics of ecology” (9). (Out of curiosity I reran this search in June of
2011 as I was preparing to submit the final version of my thesis and found that
230 Notes
all had increased by nearly double. “Environmental ethics” then had about
2,250,000 hits, followed by about 64,800 for “environmental aesthetics,”
while “ecological metaphysics” had about 468 and “metaphysics of ecology”
jumped to about 336. As of December 2012 these numbers had increased
again, though not as dramatically.) Both environmental ethics and environ-
mental aesthetics also have entries in the major encyclopedias of philosophy,
whereas ecological metaphysics does not. Further to this anecdotal evidence
there is a major journal dedicated to environmental ethics (Environmental
Ethics), but there is a complete absence of a journal that focuses on the meta-
physics of ecology. Even the more far-reaching Journal of Environmental
Philosophy tends to focus on ethics and aesthetics (largely from a phenomeno-
logical perspective), while metaphysics figures very marginally.
2. Paul W. Taylor, Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), pp. 50–51.
3. Ibid., p. 51.
4. Ibid.
5. See Arne Naess, “Spinoza and Ecology,” Philosophia 7:1 (March 1977): 45–54.
6. Arne Naess, Ecology, Community and Lifestyle: Outline of an Ecosophy, trans.
David Rothenberg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 66, 67.
7. See Ibid., pp. 171–182.
8. Ibid., p. 36.
9. Ibid., p. 39.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., p. 34.
12. Ibid., p. 27.
13. Cf. Ibid., p. 38.
14. Ibid., pp. 57, 57–63.
15. Ibid., pp. 26–28. Though it isn’t as if Naess is wrong here; since writing this
over two decades ago governments have not appeared to become any wiser.
16. Ibid., p. 41.
17. Ibid., p. 48.
18. See Ray Brassier, Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction (Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), Chapter 1; and Quentin Meillassoux, After
Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, trans. Ray Brassier
(London and New York: Continuum, 2008), Chapter 1. It is quite pos-
sible that Meillassoux’s conception of correlationism, the idea that nearly all
post-Kantian philosophy suffers from an antirealism that holds matter and
some form of mind necessarily exist together, was developed after reading §46
of Husserl’s The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy:
An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy, trans. David Carr (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1970).
19. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 5.
20. Ibid., p. 6.
21. For his attack on meaning, see Brassier, Nihil Unbound, p. 239.
22. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 51.
23. Ibid., p. 50.
Notes 231
24. Ted Toadvine makes the same argument regarding Nature and environmen-
tal sciences with special reference to Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. See Ted
Toadvine, Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy of Nature (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 2009).
25. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 112.
26. See ibid., p. 59.
27. Eugen Fink, Sixth Cartesian Mediation: The Idea of a Transcendental Theory
of Method, trans. Ronald Bruzina (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
1995), p. 144.
28. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 135.
29. Ibid., p. 148.
30. Fink, Sixth Cartesian Mediation, p. 32.
31. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 150.
32. Ibid., p. 175.
33. Ibid., pp. 113–114.
34. Michel Henry, I Am the Truth: Toward a Philosophy of Christianity, trans.
Susan Emmanuel (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), p. 38.
35. Ibid.
36. Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences, p. 120.
37. Ibid., p. 152.
38. I provide here just a sampling of the texts. Bruce V. Foltz’s Inhabiting the Earth:
Heidegger, Environmental Ethics, and the Metaphysics of Nature (New Jersey:
Humanities Books, 1996) provides a study of Heidegger’s considerations of
the environment and nature. Toadvine’s Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy of Nature
does the same with regard to Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. The edited collec-
tion Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself, eds. Charles S. Brown and
Ted Toadvine (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003), includes a
number of essays on particular phenomenologists, and a few, notably by David
Wood and John Llewelyn, on the general notion of an ecophenomenology,
but these both fail to engage with the ecosystem concept. There are a number
of books that engage with related ecological issues, including the edited col-
lection Nature’s Edge: Boundary Explorations in Ecological Theory and Practice,
eds. Charles S. Brown and Ted Toadvine (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 2007), which considers different ideas of boundaries, human/
animal, living/dead, but does not include any essays that engage with the eco-
system concept. Brett Buchanan’s Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments
of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze (Albany: State University
of New York Press, 2008) provides an interesting study of the of protoecolo-
gist Jacob von Uexküll’s notion of the Umwelt and the differing forms of
influence it had on Heidegger, Merelau-Ponty, and Deleuze, who of course
was not a phenomenologist. While this doesn’t provide much in the way of an
ecological philosophy, it does provide a resource for bridging the gap between
animal-philosophy and ecological philosophy. In terms of the structure we’re
tracing here, the limit of philosophy and science, none of these works moves
beyond the phenomenological drive to subsume science into itself. There is,
however, Robert Frodemen’s Geo-Logic: Breaking Ground between Philosophy
232 Notes
and the Earth Sciences (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003),
which is a work that, while sharing a different theoretical orientation, is in the
same spirit as this work. Instead of a unified theory of philosophical theology
and ecology Frodemen present a kind of unified theory of phenomenology
and geology. While his work is then not of particular use here, it does give wit-
ness to the perversity of nature and the infinite task of thinking from nature.
39. John Llewelyn, The Middle Voice of Ecological Conscience (Basingstoke:
Macmillan, 1991); and Seeing through God: A Geophenomenology (Bloomington
and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2004).
40. Llewelyn, Seeing through God , p. 22.
41. John Mullarkey makes this point about Llewelyn’s philosophy writing, “Each
and every being has a claim on me on account of the ‘that it is’ rather than
the ‘what it is’ of each; the ontological rather than the ontic. There need be
no qualitative similarity (having consciousness, sentience) between us, and
yet there remains an ethical responsibility all the same.” John Mullarkey,
“A Bellicose Democracy: Bergson on the Open Soul (or Unthinking the
Thought of Equality),” in After the Postsecular and the Postmodern: New
Essays in Continental Philosophy of Religion , eds. Anthony Paul Smith and
Daniel Whistler (Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing,
2010), p. 178.
42. Llewelyn, Seeing through God, p. 21.
43. On the status and use of the Gaia hypothesis within scientific ecology, see
Felix Baerlocher, “The Gaia Hypothesis—A Fruitful Fallacy,” Experientia
46.3 (1990): 232–238.
44. Meillassoux uses this phrase in his After Finitude, saying that contemporary
philosophy has forgotten the “great outdoors” and that he aims to mark a
return to it. Meillassoux, After Finitude, p. 7.
45. See Iain Hamilton Grant, “The ‘Eternal and Necessary Bond between
Philosophy and Physics’: A Repetition of the Difference between the Fichtean
and Schellingian Systems of Philosophy,” Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical
Humanities 10:1 (April 2005): 43–59.
46. Grant, “The ‘Eternal and Necessary Bond between Philosophy and Physics,’” 44.
47. Ibid., 46–47.
48. Ibid., 50.
49. For Žižek’s criticism of the ideology of ecology and his own attempt to recast
the problem of nature alongside of ecology, see “Unbehagen in der Natur,” in his
In Defense of Lost Causes (London and New York: Verso, 2008). For Žižek’s indebt-
edness to Schelling, see his reading in Slavoj Žižek, The Indivisible Remainder:
On Schelling and Related Matters (London and New York: Verso, 2007); and
for an account and criticism of that reading, see Iain Hamilton Grant, “The
Insufficiency of Ground: On Žižek’s Schellingianism,” in The Truth of Žižek, eds.
Paul Bowman and Richard Stamp (London and New York: Continuum, 2007),
pp. 82–98. For an interesting comparative study of Žižek’s and Heidegger’s
thoughts on nature, which argues that they share a vision of a fundamentally
not-whole nature, see Michael Lewis, Heidegger beyond Deconstruction: On
Nature (London and New York: Continuum, 2007), pp. 105–127.
Notes 233
19. Ibid.
20. McFague, Body of God, p. 29.
21. Ibid., p. 3.
22. Ibid.
23. Ruether, Gaia & God, p. 39.
24. Both Ruether and McFague make reference to the Gaia hypothesis. McFague
in relation to her understanding of ecology as concerned with “unity”
(McFague, Body of God , pp. 29–30) and Ruether introduces Lovelock very
early on (Ruether, Gaia & God, p. 4).
25. Leonardo Boff, Ecology and Liberation: A New Paradigm, trans. John
Cumming (Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1995), p. 10.
26. Ruether, Gaia & God, pp. 1–2.
27. Boff, Ecology and Liberation, pp. 9–12.
28. See McFague, Body of God , pp. 27–63; Ruether, Gaia & God, pp. 32–58; Boff,
Cry of the Earth, pp. 140–157.
29. Boff, Ecology and Liberation, pp. 43–45.
30. Boff, Cry of the Earth, p. 10.
places the reader of Laruelle in a gilded cage here perhaps to present his own
reading of Laruelle as a critical use of non-philosophy, but this forecloses the
third possibility of attempting to understand and use non-philosophy. To
one who is hostile to Laruelle’s non-philosophy this may already look like
“uncritical emulation,” and though Brassier himself is passing judgment here,
he does not provide us with any metaphilosophy for judging what uncritical
emulation looks like. It is important to keep in mind, as I will try to show
later in the essay, that there is a difference here between method and con-
tent. One can “emulate” the method of non-philosophy and reject, even on
non-philosophical grounds, the content Laruelle constructs much as Brassier
himself does, albeit Brassier does so on standard philosophical grounds. My
own positive non-philosophical project will, for instance, take a very different
form from Laruelle’s humanism (or, rather, non-humanism) on the basis of
an understanding of nature that is neither purely Greek (cosmos, physis) nor
purely Jew (creation) and that does not aim to bring them together into some
kind of Christian Jew-Greek synthesis as World.
20. Meillassoux, “Speculative Realism,” p. 427.
21. Meillassoux defines the thing-in-itself as the thing “independently of its rela-
tion to me” (Meillassoux, After Finitude, p. 1). He goes on from here to say “all
those aspects of the object that can be formulated in mathematical terms can
be meaningfully conceived as properties of the object in itself” (p. 3).
22. Meillassoux, “Speculative Realism,” p. 419.
23. Cf. Laruelle, En tant qu’Un, p. 37.
24. Laruelle, Philosophie et non-philosophie, p. 16.
25. Cf. Laruelle, Philosophies of Difference, pp. 152–155; Les philosophies de la dif-
férence, pp. 169–172.
26. Bufalo, Deleuze et Laruelle, p. 17.
27. Meillassoux, “Speculative Realism,” pp. 417–419. The argument appears
popular and convincing among readers of Meillassoux, though it is far from
clear that these are also readers of Laruelle based on their presentation of his
work. Cf. Graham Harman, Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics
(Melbourne: re:press, 2009), pp. 177–178.
28. Brassier, Nihil Unbound, p. 128.
29. Laruelle, Philosophie et non-philosophie, pp. 176–177.
30. François Laruelle, Théorie des identités. Fractalité généralisée et philosophie arti-
ficielle (Paris: PUF, 1992), p. 59.
(Paris: Kimé, 2010). Even though Laruelle aims not to separate the practice
of non-philosophy from its material some of his books do develop the practice
of non-philosophy with more clarity and attention. His most recent book is to
be counted among these alongside of (in chronological order of original pub-
lication) Philosophies of Difference: A Critical Introduction to Non-Philosophy,
trans. Rocco Gangle (London and New York: Continuum, 2010); Philosophie
et non-philosophie (Mardaga: Liege-Bruxelles, 1989); Théorie des identités.
Fractalité généralisée et philosophie artificielle (Paris: PUF, 1992); Principles of
Non-Philosophy, trans. Nicola Rubczak and Anthony Paul Smith (London and
New York: Bloomsbury, 2013); Introduction au non-marxisme (Paris: PUF,
2000); and Future Christ: A Lesson in Heresy, trans. Anthony Paul Smith
(London and New York: Continuum, 2010).
2. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 33; Principes de la non-philosophie
(Paris: PUF, 1995), pp. 38–39.
3. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 33; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 39.
4. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 33; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 39.
5. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 33; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 39.
6. See the entry “Vision-en-Un (Un, Un-en-Un, Réel)” in Laruelle et al.,
Dictionnaire de la non-philosophie (Paris: Kimé, 1998), pp. 202–205.
7. Laruelle, Philosophie et non-philosophie, p. 38.
8. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 34; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 39.
9. “In philosophy, Marxism included, immanence is an objective, a proclama-
tion, an object, never a manner of thinking or a style” (Laruelle, Introduction
au non-marxisme, p. 40).
10. See Erik del Bufalo, Deleuze et Laruelle. De la schizo-analyse à la non-philosophie
(Paris: Kimé, 2003), p. 40.
11. Laruelle, Philosophies of Difference, pp. 198–202; Les philosophies de la dif-
férence, pp. 215–219. See also Laruelle, Philosophies of Difference, pp. 219–
223; Laruelle, Les philosophies de la différence, pp. 237–240 for an early formal
schema of the One. Cf. Laruelle, Dictionnare, pp. 202–205; and Principles
of Non-Philosophy, 119–146; Laruelle, Principes de la non-philosophie,
pp. 168–192.
12. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 34; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 38.
13. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 34; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 40.
14. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, pp. 34–34; Principes de la non-philosophie,
pp. 40–41. I read the parentheses framing the “of ” to suggest that this is a
unified relationship between force and thought rather than one being primary
over the other. Thus the substantial meaning of the “of” is suspended. In my
own creation of the population (of) thought and ecosystem (of) thought I
make use of this parenthetical, recognizing as I do so that it can appear dis-
tracting and pretentious. I can only ask the reader’s charity in reading it as a
technical use of syntax that indicates this suspension.
15. See the entry “Force (de) pensée (sujet-existant-Étranger)” in Laruelle,
Dictionnaire, pp. 76–79.
16. Ibid., p. 77.
17. Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, p. 35; Principes de la non-philosophie, p. 41.
Notes 239
7 Non-Theological Supplement
25. François Laruelle, Struggle and Utopia at the End Times of Philosophy, trans.
Drew S. Burk and Anthony Paul Smith (Minneapolis: Univocal Publishing,
2012), p. 250; La Lutte et l’Utopie à la fin des temps philosophiques (Paris: Kimé,
2004), p. 204.
26. John Milbank, “Knowledge: The Theological Critique of Philosophy in
Hamann and Jacobi,” in Radical Orthodoxy: A New Theology, eds. John
Milbank, Catherine Pickstock, and Graham Ward (London: Routledge,
1999), p. 21.
27. Talal Asad, Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2003), p. 5.
28. Laruelle, Philosophie non-standard, p. 125.
29. Laruelle, Future Christ, p. 117; Le Christ futur, p. 145.
30. Zachery Luke Fraser, Draft of “Entry for ‘Generic,’” in The Badiou Dictionary,
ed. Steven Corcoran (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, forthcom-
ing). Draft available online: http://formandformalism.blogspot.com/2011/03
/generic-entry.html (accessed March 25, 2011).
1. On this, see Daniel Colucciello Barber, Deleuze and the Naming of God:
Post-Secularism and the Future of Immanence (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, forthcoming) and my own essay, which builds upon Barber’s
work to describe Deleuze and Guattari’s ecological philosophy of nature,
“Believing in this World for the Making of Gods: On the Ecology of the
Virtual and the Actual,” SubStance 38.3 (April 2010): 101–112.
2. Christian L évêque, Ecology: From Ecosystem to Biosphere (Plymouth, UK:
Science Publisher, Inc., 2003), p. 29.
3. Brian Walker and David Salt, Resilience Thinking: Sustaining Ecosystems and
People in a Changing World (Washington and London: Island Press, 2006),
p. xiii.
4. François Laruelle, Théorie des identité s (Paris: PUF, 1992), p. 56.
5. François Laruelle, Philosophie non-standard. Générique, Quantique, Philo-fiction
(Paris: Kimé, 2010), p. 54.
6. See Anthony Paul Smith, “Philosophy and Ecosystem: Towards a Transcendental
Ecology,” Polygraph 22 (2010): 65–82.
7. Rocco Gangle, “Translator’s Introduction,” in François Laruelle’s Philosophies
of Difference: A Critical Introduction to Non-Philosophy, trans. Rocco Gangle
(London and New York: Continuum, 2010), p. vi.
8. Laruelle, Philosophie non-standard, p. 490.
9. Ibid.
10. L évêque, Ecology, p. 8.
11. Cf. ibid., p. 9. Which isn’t to say that management falls outside of ecology as
such, just that the management itself should be subordinated to knowledge
rather than the demands of quick and popular policies.
Notes 243
while narrow niches mean that the species tends to concentrate on only some
resources (p. 13).
36. Pierre Hadot, The Veil of Isis: An Essay on the History of the Idea of Nature,
trans. Michael Chase (Cambridge, MA, and London: The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 2006), p. 10.
37. Antonio Negri, The Labor of Job: The Biblical Text as a Parable for Human
Labor, trans. Matteo Mandarini (Durham and London: Duke University
Press, 2009), p. 27. As is common with translations of Negri and Deleuze and
Guattari, when power is spelled with a lowercase p it is translating the French
puissance or the Italian potenza and when it is spelled with an uppercase P it
translates the French pouvoir or the Italian potere.
38. Ibid., p. 28.
39. Ibid., p. 59.
40. Ibid., p. 75.
41. Ibid., p. 81.
42. Ibid., pp. 96–97.
43. Ibid., p. 52.
44. Cf. Ray Brassier, Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction (Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), p. 25.
45. cf. Negri, Labor of Job, pp. 50, 73, for a discussion of this idea as it is found in
the Book of Job.
46. Cf. Giorgio Agamben, The Open: Man and Animal, trans. Kevin Attell
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004). Agamben’s short text provides
a succinct summary of the biopolitical elements at work in philosophy of
nature. It should be noted that the emphasis on Jacob von Uexküll, found
in Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and to a lesser extent Deleuze, as well as their
interpreters, is out of proportion to the actual legacy he has left on scientific
ecology. His name, e.g., is not mentioned in any of the major histories I have
read for this project and yet Agamben mistakenly credits him as one of the
“founders of ecology” (p. 39).
47. Chapin, Matson, and Mooney, Principles of Terrestrial Ecosystem Ecology, p. 4.
48. Ibid., p. 140.
49. Ibid., pp. 97, 140.
50. Golley, A History of the Ecosystem, p. 81.
51. Ibid., pp. 67–69.
52. Howard Thomas Odum quoted in ibid., p. 81.
53. L évêque, Ecology, p. 246.
54. Chapin, Matson, and Mooney, Principles of Terrestrial Ecosystem Ecology, p. 10.
55. Ibid.
56. L évêque, Ecology, p. 247.
57. Chapin, Matson, and Mooney, Principles of Terrestrial Ecosystem Ecology, p. 8.
58. L évêque, Ecology, pp. 247, 249.
59. Brassier, Nihil Unbound, p. xi.
60. Chapin, Matson, and Mooney, Principles of Terrestrial Ecosystem Ecology, p. 10.
61. Ibid., p. 31.
Notes 247
1. Bruno Latour, Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy,
trans. Catherine Porter (Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University
Press, 2004), p. 245.
2. Ibid., p. 249.
3. Ibid., p. 248.
4. Ibid., p. 54.
248 Notes
differences between the early and later work of Heidegger, the concept of
World and Being are continually at play.
61. Martin Heidegger, “The Thing,” in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert
Hofstadter (New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics, 1971), p. 178.
62. Ibid., p. 175.
63. Cf. Lewis, Heidegger beyond Deconstruction, p. 10.
64. Harman, The Quadruple Object, pp. 86–87.
65. Cf. ibid., pp. 96–99.
66. Julian Young, “The Fourfold,” in The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, ed.
Charles B. Guignon, 2nd edition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2006), p. 375.
67. Lewis, Heidegger beyond Deconstruction, p. 10.
68. Young, “The Fourfold,” p. 374. Cf. Heidegger, “ . . . Poetically Man Dwells . . . ,”
pp. 149, 178.
69. Heidegger, “ . . . Poetically Man Dwells . . . ,” p. 148.
70. Ibid., p. 182.
71. Ibid., p. 220.
72. Now, bringing to mind Laruelle’s focus on the ocean discussed in chapter 8,
here the term “earth” refers really to the biosphere, which includes all the
wave-like aspects of energy flowing in ecosystems through the materials that
make them up.
1. Rudi te Velde, Aquinas on God: The “Divine Science” of the Summa theologiae
(Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006), p. 85.
2. St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica (literal English translation), trans.
Fathers of the English Dominican Province (Westminster, MD: Christian
Classics, 1981), Ia, q. 4, a. 2.
3. Velde, Aquinas on God, p. 85.
4. St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles, trans. A. C. Pegis, James F.
Anderson, Vernon J. Bourke, and Charles J. O’Neil, 4 vols. (Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), I/30; hereafter SCG.
5. SCG I/30.3.
6. Ibid.
7. SCG I/30.2.
8. SCG I/30.4. In this passage Aquinas only lists “infinite.” Cf. Velde, Aquinas
on God, p. 80, for a discussion of the other three in the Summa Theologica.
9. Ibid.
10. Ibid.
11. SCG I/32.4. The argument against univocity is philosophically weak as it is
worked out from a position where the metaphysics of God have already been
decided theologically through the demands of the creeds and the Church
Fathers.
Notes 253
36. François Zourabichvili, Spinoza. Une physique de la pensée (Paris: PUF, 2002),
p. 255.
37. Ibid., p. 220.
38. Rocco Gangle, “Theology of the Chimera: Spinoza, Immanence, Practice,”
in After the Postsecular and the Postmodern: New Essays in Continental
Philosophy of Religion, eds. Anthony Paul Smith and Daniel Whistler
(Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars’ Press, 2010), p. 27.
39. Ibid.
40. For example, Steven Nadler’s biography of Spinoza, Spinoza: A Life
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), which presents a radically
atheist Spinoza, as does Stephen B. Smith’s Spinoza’s Book of Life: Freedom
and Redemption in the Ethics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003).
This view is shared to a lesser extent by Jonathan I. Israel in his Radical
Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650–1750 (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2001).
41. Nancy K. Levene, Spinoza’s Revelation: Religion, Democracy, and Reason
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 10–12.
42. Benedict de Spinoza, “Ethics,” in A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other
Works, ed. and trans. Edwin Curley (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1994), IVPref.
43. Ibid., ID3.
44. Ibid., ID4.
45. Ibid., IIP13. It isn’t entirely clear from the text why we can only have knowl-
edge of these two and no more, though this doesn’t seem really to be at issue
for our understanding of the process of his thought.
46. Ibids., ID5.
47. This is the argument of Deleuze who places Spinoza among other authors
steeped in Neoplatonism and developing various theories of expression and
explication. He writes that the goal of these thinkers “was to thoroughly
transform such Neoplatonism, to open it up to quite new lines of develop-
ment, far removed from that of emanation, even where the two themes were
both present” (Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans.
Martin Joughlin [New York: Zone Books, 1990], p. 19).
48. Levene, Spinoza’s Revelation, p. 3.
49. Blayton Polka, Between Philosophy and Religion: Spinoza, the Bible, and
Modernity, Vol. I: Hermeneutics and Ontology (Lexington: Lexington Books,
2007), p. 6.
50. Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p. 108.
51. Ibid., p. 109.
52. Ibid., p. 107.
53. Spinoza, Ethics, IIP7S.
54. Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p. 109.
55. Spinoza, Ethics, IA4.
56. Ibid., IP23.
57. See ibid., IP9.
58. Ibid., IIP7.
Notes 255
87. Christian Jambet, “The Paradoxical One,” trans. Michael Stanish, Umbr(a):
A Journal of the Unconcious (2009): 141; Jambet, La Grande résurrection
d’Alamût, p. 142 [translation slightly modified].
88. Jambet, “The Paradoxical One,” p. 142; La Grande résurrection, p. 143.
89. al-Sijistâ nî, Le Dévoilement des choses caches, p. 77.
90. Christian Jambet and Guy Lardreau, L’Ange. Pour une cynégétique du sem-
blant, Ontologie de la révolution 1 (Paris: Grasset, 1976), p. 36.
91. Cf. ibid., pp. 213–224.
92. Cf. ibid., p. 92.
93. Ibid.
94. Ibid., p. 84.
95. Ibid., p. 87.
96. Ibid., p. 100.
97. Ibid., p. 109.
98. Ibid., p. 20.
99. Of course, it may also give birth to the barbaric Angel. See Christian Jambet
and Guy Lardreau, Le Monde. Reponse à la question: Qu’est-ce que les droits
de l’ homme? (Paris: Grasset, 1978), p. 187. Lardreau is more direct about
this in his own work of negative philosophy entitled La véracité, where he
argues for a Kantian sublime within politics defined as “a politics that makes
a finality sensible to us that is completely independent from nature” (Guy
Lardreau, La véractié. Essai d’une philosophie négative [Lagrasse: Verdier,
1993], p. 237). Lardreau again invokes the Angel in his development of the
concept of the political sublime, this time as the “political name for the
desire for death” (p. 241). Within a negative philosophy this desire for death
is limited, it is a desire for the self-referential play of the correlative images
of the self and the other. In the terms laid out in my “The Judgement of
God and the Immeasurable” it is the desire for the death of the play between
friend and enemy. For Lardreau, within a negative philosophy, this desire
is checked by way of a negative presentation of the Real (ibid). Death is
always a form of transcendence as limit for philosophers and Lardreau is no
different (Lardreau, La véractié, p. 243. Cf. Philip Goodchild, Capitalism
and Religion: The Price of Piety (London and New York: Routledge, 2002),
pp. 148–155). The barbarous Angel, for Lardreau, comes when there is a pos-
itive presentation of the Real, a presentation that threatens to topple the sub-
lime over (Lardreau, La véractié, p. 241). See Anthony Paul Smith, “Nature
Deserves to Be Side by Side with the Angels: Nature and Messianism by way
of Non-Islam,” in Angelaki (Forthcoming, 2014) for a longer discussion of
this angelology.
100. Jambet, Le Grande resurrection, p. 362.
101. Francois Laruelle, Future Christ: A Lesson in Heresy, trans. Anthony Paul
Smith (London and New York: Continuum, 2010), p. 17; Le Christ futur.
Une leçon d’ hérèsie (Paris: Exils Éditeur, 2002), p. 33.
102. Laurelle, Future Christ, pp. 39, 40; Le Christ futur, pp. 58, 59.
103. Laruelle, Future Christ, p. 6; Le Christ futur, p. 20.
104. Laruelle, Future Christ, p. 117; Le Christ futur, p. 145.
Notes 257
105. François Laruelle, “A Science in (en) Christ,” trans. Aaron Riches, in The
Grandeur of Reason: Religion, Tradition and Universalism, eds. Peter M.
Candler, Jr. and Conor Cunningham (London: SCM Press, 2010), p. 318.
106. Gilles Grelet, Déclarer la gnose. D’une guerre qui revient à la culture (Paris:
L’Harmattan, 2002), pp. 119f50, 119f49.
107. Interestingly al-Sijistâ nî develops an Islamic Christology by way of a kind
of fourfold, since he uses the image of the cross as a hermeneutic for under-
standing Christ. See Abu Ya’qûb al-Sijistâ nî, “The Book of Wellsprings,” in
The Wellsprings of Wisdom, ed. and trans. Paul E. Walker (Salt Lake City:
University of Utah Press, 1994), pp. 37–111. In the editors’ introduction to
After the Postsecular and the Postmodern, Daniel Whistler and I differentiated
between a postsecular event and the appropriation of that event in the name
of a theologization of philosophy or what we called “imperial secularism.”
The event marked a break with Western imperialism, which used Christian
forms of thought to develop a post-Christian secularism in an attempt to
separate the oppressed colonial subjects internally—a separation of the
political and their religious identity, whereas the appropriation of the event
is often an attempt to reinstate (at best) a war at the ideational level and (at
worst) a new form of imperial war in the name of the clash of traditions.
The postsecular event, we claim there, was located largely with Islamic
countries throughout the Middle East and North Africa and though the
response to the postsecular event is not an Islamic turn in Continental phi-
losophy, there should be more engagement with forms of thought outside of
the Christian tradition. There are two clear non-theological reasons for this:
(1) if the generic is to be located in a way that avoids the shortcomings of
Hegelian philosophy and its continuing influence on the practice of philoso-
phy of religion, where European Christianity comes to be the name for uni-
versalism as the only consummating historical religion, then it must take the
infinite task of working with any material whatsoever in order to locate the
power of the generic that lies there; (2) non-theology always begins from
the perspective of the murdered, and thus from the perspective of heretical
material, which is to say that there is within non-theology a principle of
minority or preferential option for the poor as immanent to generic human-
ity. With regard to the second, in a very real sense, a very bodily sense, a
certain appearance of the power of poverty, what Negri calls the “force of the
slave” in regard to Job, has coalesced around the name “Muslim” (though, of
course, not just the name “Muslim”). In Europe the Muslim has become the
exception that grounds the law, both political law and the economic law of
class difference. As this structural aspect in-person the Muslim is, as Mehdi
Belhaj Kacem has argued, the contemporary form of pariah: “The pariah
is at once captured and delivered, locked within its exclusion and banished
by inclusion” (Mehdi Belhaj Kacem, La psychose françiase. Les banlieues: le
ban de la République [Paris: Gallimard, 2006], p. 18). The reality of the
pariah is manifested clearly in the collusion of the institutional Left with the
establishment Right of Europe regarding these “places of the ban” (Belhaj
Kacem makes a clever play on the name of the suburban ghettoes of France,
258 Notes
7. See Roger D. Sorrel, St. Francis of Assisi and Nature: Tradition and Innovation
in Western Christian Attitudes towards the Environment (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1988), pp. 55–97.
8. Brethren of Purity, Epistles of the Brethren of Purity: The Case of the Animals
versus Man before the King of the Jinn, eds. and trans. Lenn E. Goodman and
Richard McGregor (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 102.
9. IVP39S and see François Zourabichvili, Le conservatisme paradoxal de Spinoza.
Enfance et royauté (Paris: PUF, 2002), pp. 95–177.
10. François Zourabichvili, Spinoza. Une physique de la pensée (Paris: PUF, 2002),
p. 220; my emphasis.
11. François Laruelle, Philosophies of Difference: A Critical Introduction to
Non-Philosophy, trans. Rocco Gangle (London and New York: Continuum,
2010), p. 202; Les philosophies de la différence (Paris: PUF, 1986), p. 219.
12. Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New
York: Modern Library, 1995), p. 13.
13. Christian Jambet, “A Philosophical Commentary,” trans. Hafiz Karmali, in
Paradise of Submission: A Medieval Treatise on Ismaili Thought, ed. and trans.
S. J. Badakhchani (London and New York: I.B Tauris, 2005), p. 181.
14. Naīr al-Dīn ūsī, Paradise of Submission: A Medieval Treatise on Ismaili
Thought, ed. and trans. S. J. Badakhchani (London and New York: I.B Tauris,
2005), p. 16.
15. Jambet, “A Philosophical Commentary,” 181.
16. Cf. ibid., p. 178.
Bibliography
Agamben, Giorgio. The Open: Man and Animal. Translated by Kevin Attell.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004.
al-Dīn ūsī, Na īr. Paradise of Submission: A Medieval Treatise on Ismaili Thought.
Edited and translated by S. J. Badakhchani. London and New York: I.B Tauris,
2005.
al-Sijistâ nî, Ya’qûb. “The Book of Wellsprings,” in The Wellsprings of Wisdom.
Edited and translated by Paul E. Walker. Salt Lake City: University of Utah
Press, 1994.
———. Le Dévoilement des choses cachées (Kashf al-Mahjûb). Translated by Henry
Corbin. Lagrasse: Verdier, 1988.
Althusser, Louis. For Marx. Translated by Ben Brewster. London: Verso, 2005.
Aquinas, St. Thomas. “Commentary on Boethius’ De Trinitate [Selection],” in
Selected Philosophical Writings. Edited and translated by Timothy McDermott.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
———. “On Kingship or the Governance of Rulers (De Regimine Principum,
1265–1267),” in St. Thomas Aquinas on Politics and Ethics. Edited and translated
by Paul E. Sigmund. London and New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1988.
———. “On the Principles of Nature,” in Selected Philosophical Writings. Edited and
translated by Timothy McDermott. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
———. Summa Contra Gentiles. Translated by A. C. Pegis, James F. Anderson,
Vernon J. Bourke, and Charles J. O’Neil. 4 Volumes. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1975.
———. Summa Theologica (literal English translation). Translated by the Fathers of
the English Dominican Province. Westminster, MD: Christian Classics, 1981.
Asad, Talal. Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2003.
Badiou, Alain. Being and Event. Translated by Oliver Feltham. New York and
London: Continuum, 2005.
———. The Century. Translated by Alberto Toscano. Cambridge: Polity, 2007.
———. Interview with Ben Woodward. The Speculative Turn: Continental
Materialism and Realism. Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek, and Graham
Harman. Melbourne: re.press, 2011.
———. Logics of Worlds: Being and Event II. Translated by Alberto Toscano. New
York and London: Continuum, 2009.
———. Manifeste pour la philosophie. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1980.
262 Bibliography
Badiou, Alain. “Mathematics and Philosophy: The Grand Style and the Little
Style,” in Theoretical Writings. Edited and translated by Ray Brassier and
Alberto Toscano. London and New York: Continuum, 2004.
Baerlocher, Felix. “The Gaia Hypothesis—A Fruitful Fallacy.” Experientia 46.3
(1990): 232–238.
Balibar, Étienne. Spinoza and Politics. Translated by Peter Snowdon. London and
New York: Verso, 2008.
Barber, Daniel Colucciello. Deleuze and the Naming of God: Post-Secularism and the
Future of Immanence. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, forthcoming.
Barth, Karl. Church Dogmatics III.4. Translated by A. T. Mackay, T. H. L. Parker,
H. Knight, H. A. Kennedy, and J. Marks. Edited by G. W. Bromiley and
T. F. Torrance. London and New York: T&T Clark, 2004.
Belhaj Kacem, Mehdi. La psychose françiase. Les banlieues: le ban de la R épublique.
Paris: Gallimard, 2006.
Bell, Jr., Daniel M. “Only Jesus Saves: Toward a Theo-political Ontology of
Judgment,” in Theology and the Political: The New Debate. Edited by Creston
Davis, John Milbank, and Slavoj Žižek. Durham: Duke University Press, 2005.
Benedict XVI, Pope. Encyclical Letter, Caritas in veritate: Charity in Love. Rome:
St. Peter’s, 2009. Available online: http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi
/encyclicals/documents/hf_ben-xvI_enc_20090629_caritas-in-veritate_En.html
(accessed June 13, 2010).
Boff, Leonardo. Cry of the Earth, Cry of the Poor. Translated by Philip Berryman.
Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1997.
———. Ecology and Liberation: A New Paradigm. Translated by John Cumming.
Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1995.
Botkin, Daniel B. Discordant Harmonies: A New Ecology for the Twenty-First
Century. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Brassier, Ray. Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction . Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2007.
Brassier, Ray, Iain Hamilton Grant, Graham Harman, and Quentin Meillassoux.
“Speculative Realism,” in Collapse III. Falmouth: Urbanomic, 2007: 307–449.
Brethren of Purity. Epistles of the Brethren of Purity: The Case of the Animals versus
Man Before the King of the Jinn. Edited and translated by Lenn E. Goodman
and Richard McGregor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Brown, Charles S., and Ted Toadvine, editors. Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the
Earth Itself. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003.
———. Nature’s Edge: Boundary Explorations in Ecological Theory and Practice.
Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007.
Buchanan, Brett. Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexk üll, Heidegger,
Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze. Albany: SUNY Press, 2008.
Bufalo, Erik del. Deleuze et Laruelle. De la schizo-analyse à la non-philosophie. Paris:
Kimé, 2003.
Chapin III, F. Stuart, Pamela A. Matson, and Harold A. Mooney. Principles of
Terrestrial Ecosystem Ecology. London: Springer, 2002.
Choplin, Hugues. De la phénoménologie à la non-philosophie. Lévinas et Laruelle.
Paris: Kimé, 1997.
Bibliography 263
Grant, Iain Hamilton. “The ‘Eternal and Necessary Bond between Philosophy and
Physics’: A Repetition of the Difference between the Fichtean and Schellingian
Systems of Philosophy.” Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 10:1
(April 2005): 43–59.
———. “The Insufficiency of Ground: On Žižek’s Schellingianism,” in The Truth
of Žižek. Edited by Paul Bowman and Richard Stamp. London and New York:
Continuum, 2007.
———. Philosophies of Nature after Schelling. London and New York: Continuum,
2006.
Grelet, Gilles. Déclarer la gnose. D’une guerre qui revient à la culture. Paris:
L’Harmattan, 2002.
Hadot, Pierre. The Veil of Isis: An Essay on the History of the Idea of Nature.
Translated by Michael Chase. London and Cambridge, MA: The Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press, 2006.
Harlingue, Olivier. Sans condition. Blanchot, la littérature, la philosophie. Paris:
L’Harmattan, 2009.
Harman, Graham. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. Melbourne:
re:press, 2009.
———. The Quadruple Object. Winchester, UK: Zero Books, 2011.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward
Robinson. New York: HarperSanFrancisco, 1962.
———. The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude.
Translated by William McNeill and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1995.
———. “Modern Science, Metaphysics, and Mathematics,” in Basic Writings.
Edited and translated by David Farrell Krell. New York: HarperSanFrancisco,
1993.
———. “ . . . Poetically Man Dwells . . . ,” in Poetry, Language, Thought. Edited and
translated by Albert Hofstadter. New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics,
1971.
———. “The Question Concerning Technology,” in Basic Writings. Edited
and translated by David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco,
1993.
———. “The Thing,” in Poetry, Language, Thought. Translated and edited by
Albert Hofstadter. New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics, 1971.
Henry, Michel. I Am the Truth: Toward a Philosophy of Christianity. Translated by
Susan Emmanuel. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003.
Husserl, Edmund. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Translated by
David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970.
Israel, Jonathan I. Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity
1650–1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Jambet, Christian. La grande ré surrection d’Alamût. Les formes de la liberté dans le
shî’ isme ismaélien. Lagresse: Verdier, 1990.
———. “The Paradoxical One.” Translated by Michael Stanish. Umbr(a): A
Journal of the Unconcious (2009): 139–163.
Bibliography 265
Primavesi, Anne. Sacred Gaia: Holistic Theology and Earth System Science. London
and New York: Routledge, 2000.
Radkau, Joachim. Nature and Power: A Global History of the Environment.
Translated by Thomas Dunlap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2008.
Rannou, Jean-Luc. La non-philosophie, simplement. Une introduction synthétique.
Paris: L’Harmattan, 2005.
Rogers, Eugene F. Thomas Aquinas and Karl Barth: Sacred Doctrine and the Natural
Knowledge of God. Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press,
1995.
Ruether, Rosemary Radford. Gaia & God: An Ecofeminist Theology of Earth
Healing. London: SCM Press, 1992.
Schmid, Anne-Françoise. “Le problème de Russell,” in La Non-philosophe des con-
temporains. Paris: Kimé, 1995.
Smith, Anthony Paul. “Believing in this World for the Making of Gods: On the
Ecology of the Virtual and the Actual.” SubStance 38.3 (April 2010): 101–112.
———. “Philosophy and Ecosystem: Towards a Transcendental Ecology.”
Polygraph 22 (2010): 65–82.
———. “What Can Be Done with Religion?: Non-Philosophy and the Future
of Philosophy of Religion,” in After the Postsecular and the Postmodern:
New Essays in Continental Philosophy of Religion . Edited by Anthony Paul
Smith and Daniel Whistler. Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars
Publishing, 2010.
Smith, Stephen B. Spinoza’s Book of Life: Freedom and Redemption in the Ethics.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003.
Sorrel, Roger D. St. Francis of Assisi and Nature: Tradition and Innovation in Western
Christian Attitudes towards the Environment. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1988.
Spinoza, Benedict de. “Ethics,” in A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other Works.
Edited and translated by Edwin Curley. Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1994.
———. Theological-Political Treatise. Translated by Michael Silverthorne and
Jonathan Israel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Tansley, A. G. “The Use and Abuse of Vegetational Concepts and Terms.” Ecology
16.3 (1935): 299–303.
Taylor, Paul W. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986.
Thacker, Eugene. After Life. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 2010.
Toadvine, Ted. Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy of Nature. Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 2009.
Torrell O. P., Jean-Pierre. Saint Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Robert Royal. Vol.
I: The Person and His Work. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
Press, 1996.
———. Saint Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Robert Royal. Vol. II: Spiritual
Master. Washington D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2003.
Toscano, Alberto. Fanaticism: On the Uses of an Idea . London: Verso, 2010.
Bibliography 269
Velde, Rudi te. Aquinas on God: The “Divine Science” of the Summa theologiae.
Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.
Walker, Brian, and David Salt. Resilience Thinking: Sustaining Ecosystems and
People in a Changing World. Washington and London: Island Press, 2006.
Whistler, Daniel. “Language after Philosophy of Nature: Schelling’s Geology
of Divine Names,” in After the Postsecular and the Postmodern: New Essays in
Continental Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Anthony Paul Smith and Daniel
Whistler. Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2010.
Wilson, Edward O. The Creation: An Appeal to Save Life on Earth. New York:
W. W. Norton & Company, 2006.
———. The Diversity of Life. London: Penguin Books, 2001.
Worster, Donald. Nature’s Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas. 2nd Edition.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Young, Julian. “The Fourfold” in The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Edited
by Charles B Guignon. 2nd Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2006.
Žižek, Slavoj. “Censorship Today: Violence, or Ecology as a New Opium for the
Masses.” Available online: http://www.lacan.com/zizecology1.htm (accessed
September 10, 2010).
———. In Defense of Lost Causes. London and New York: Verso, 2008.
———. The Indivisible Remainder: On Schelling and Related Matters. London and
New York: Verso, 2007.
Zourabichvili, François. Le conservatisme paradoxal de Spinoza. Enfance et royauté.
Paris: PUF, 2002.
———. Spinoza. Une physique de la pensée. Paris: PUF, 2002.
Index
cosmos 23, 47, 51–2 ecological crisis 3, 27, 37, 45, 47–8,
creation 1, 16, 21, 45–9, 52, 79, 87, 50, 53–6, 163, 170
90, 132, 135, 139–40, 142–5, ecological degradation 48, 51
163–4, 170, 175, 190–4, 197–9, ecological imperialism 151
203, 210, 218–20 ecological restoration, practice of 21, 151
act of 218–19 ecologism 30, 52, 116
Creator 21, 51, 190, 209–10 ecology
creatural 9, 164, 167, 217–21, 223 deep 29–30, 39
creatures 1, 9–10, 16, 142, 144, 157, ecosystem 127–8
163, 167, 172–3, 190–3, 198, history of 22, 53
209, 216, 218–20, 223, 225 human 49, 121
culture 8, 14, 22, 49, 51, 106, 136, ecosophy 29, 31–2
185–7, 209 ecosystem 7–9, 13, 19–21, 24–5, 31,
Cunningham, Conor 203 36, 43–4, 53–5, 60, 113–17,
125–32, 134–9, 144–51, 153–5,
Dasein 177–80, 183 162–4, 169–70, 175–6, 182–4,
death 2, 14–15, 23, 101, 139–45, 147, 187, 196
162, 185–6, 209, 214, 224 analogical 198
decision 64–5, 67, 96, 100, 123, 152 concept 19–20, 55, 127–30, 182
declension type 6, 18, 46–7, 49–50, 53 individual 25, 135
Deleuze, and Félix Guattari 62, 83–4, philosophical 114–15
114, 224 single transcendent 60
Deleuze, Gilles 3–4, 39, 63, 66, 78, structure 149, 151
82–4, 96, 114, 136, 201, 205–6, energy
219 definition of 146, 148
democracy flows 42, 114, 129–30, 145–7, 150,
real 2, 99 223
(of) thought 2, 13, 59–60, 80, 99, energy exchange 19, 31, 114–15, 127,
115, 159 137, 145, 147, 170, 176, 182
Derrida, Jacques 66, 157, 162 environment 20–1, 30–2, 37, 47, 116,
determination 77–8, 88, 114, 159, 178 121, 123, 126, 129, 137, 147, 150,
-in-the-last-instance 80–1, 86–7, 89 159–61, 183
theological 101, 122, 200 environmental thought 37, 39–40, 45,
theological over- 129, 132 47, 152, 168, 176
dualism 56, 78, 89, 98, 113, 136, 152, epochē 34–5
214 equilibrium 21, 153–5
duality 23, 89, 92, 97, 107, 129, 134, equivocation 199–200, 207–8, 222
186, 212 essence 32, 42, 66, 75–6, 79, 84–5,
dyad of God and nature 208–9, 211 104, 108, 162, 180, 194, 200–3,
207, 210
earth 1, 10, 22–5, 36, 47–51, 104, essence of philosophy 65, 86
119–21, 128, 132, 135, 143–4, ethics 15, 27–9, 39, 45, 47, 56, 79–80,
147, 175, 183, 185–7, 208, 210, 83, 110, 136, 140, 199–202, 220,
213, 216, 222–4 225
Index 273
Man, radical immanence of 98–9, negation 69, 72, 78, 101–2, 162, 191,
101, 215 193, 198, 212, 225
material Negri, Antonio 140–4, 214
ecological 38, 62, 164 niche 46, 113, 136–41, 144–5, 153,
quasi-ecological 38 170, 173, 176, 178, 182–4, 219
religious 62, 97–9, 108 non-philosophy
theological 55, 62, 100, 167 method of 7
materialism 2, 5–7, 9, 110, 143, 167, practice of 7, 62, 69, 73–4, 78, 81, 96
208, 223 waves of 90, 93
speculative 67–8 non-religion 102, 105–6
matheme 177, 180–2 non-theology 7, 62, 72, 99–100,
matter 102–3, 107–8, 174
exchange of 145, 149–50, 196, 198 non-thetic transcendence 167–8, 208,
ultimate 195–6 212, 221, 223–4
McFague, Sallie 50–2, 54 normativity 9, 135–6
Meillassoux, Quentin 39, 64–5, Northcott, Michael 47–8, 50, 52–4
67–72, 95 nouvelle théologie 204
Messiah 108, 143, 215, 220–1, 223
messianic act 211, 214 object
messianism 91, 93, 209, 211–12, 216 of knowledge 85, 122, 213
metaphilosophy 59, 62, 73, 83, 118 real 71
metaphysics 5, 7, 28, 36, 39, 45, 56, Odum, Eugene and Thomas 128–9, 146
68, 70, 73–4, 83, 177, 180, 205, ontology 5, 29, 76, 82–3, 85, 93, 139,
218 163, 178–81, 190, 199–200, 225
Milbank, John 106, 219 organicism 19, 83, 128
Morton, Timothy 7, 117, 126, 157,
160–3, 222 parallelism 200–2
Mullarkey, John 59 phenomenology 4, 18, 32–4, 38
philo-fiction 7, 56, 70, 73, 77, 91,
Naess, Arne 29–32, 125 110, 118, 126
naturalism 2, 4, 6–10, 90, 125, 139–40, philosophical decision 7, 59, 61–71,
144, 167, 187, 189, 198, 202, 209, 75–6, 79–80, 86–8, 92, 100,
223–4 107, 113
nature theory of 63, 68
creatural 222–3 philosophy
ecological 20, 39 Christian 84, 105
ecology without 161–2 environmental 18, 20, 26–9, 38–9,
perversity of 8–9, 13–15, 25, 41, 45–6, 55, 59, 66, 151
44, 55–6, 61, 144, 167, 197 first 27, 85, 91
philosophy of 18, 26, 28, 39, 41, philosophy and ecology, unified
55, 62, 67, 113, 168, 180, 183 theory of 115
real identity of 183, 210 physis 41, 178–9, 183, 210
theological conceptions of 8, 46, piety 3, 9, 99, 108, 170–4, 189, 192, 207
135, 164 Plato’s cave 34, 159–60
Index 275
political ecology 117, 119–20, 122–3, dominant 113, 138, 175, 182–3
131, 158–61 hybrid 133
Popper, Karl 43–4 Speculative Realism 6, 67
protest 10, 139–41, 214, 221 Spinoza, Benedict de 3, 8, 15–17, 29,
pure nature 202–4, 207–9, 219 66, 87, 164, 168, 173–5, 187,
198–208, 215, 221, 223
radical immanence of nature 9, 217, substance 40, 136, 194, 200–3
219, 223–4 immaterial 194
Radkau, Joachim 152 suffering 2–3, 142–4, 162, 220
Real 4–5, 14–15, 25, 28, 30, 55–6, sufficient philosophy, principle of 64,
64–81, 84, 86–7, 91, 93, 95–104, 70, 74–5, 100
107–8, 110, 116–18, 129, 136, sufficient theology, principle of 66,
174, 218–20, 222–5 90, 100–2, 189
-One 77–8, 81, 86, 89, 93, 95, 97, supernatural 203–5, 221
99, 104, 106, 115–16, 134, 163, suspension, realist 70–2
210–12, 219 system of energy exchange 19, 147
realism 204
rebellion 104–6, 213, 216 Tansley, Arthur 19–20, 128–30
regional knowledges 5, 13–14, 51, 55, Taylor, Paul W. 28–9, 31–2
59, 81, 89, 93 theology
resilience 60, 115, 117, 135, 151–2, 163 eco- 45, 54–5
thinking 152, 154–5 environmental 18, 24, 46–7, 63,
resurrection 101, 209–11 66, 95, 175
revolution 108, 213–14 Islam 172
Ruether, Rosemary Radford 52, 54 liberation 6, 54
natural 47, 218
Salt, Brian 115, 152–4 negative 72, 102, 162, 191,
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm 213
Joseph 5, 40–2 thought
science divisions of 163
autonomy of 84, 86 ecological perspective 148
division of 86, 164 generic form of 56, 93
modern 177, 179 image of 20, 23, 149, 164
philosophy of 33, 44, 82–3, 100, 131 immanental 90
posture of 65, 86 non-philosophical 88, 101
scientism 56, 73, 87, 89–90, 117, 131, 161 non-theological 99
secularism 105–8 Toscano, Alberto 258f107
sékommça 209, 214, 216, 219, 224–5 tradition 54, 102–5, 174
Sijistânî, Abu Ya’qub al- 8, 164, 168, transcendence 5, 47, 65–6, 78, 86,
175, 209–213, 224 99, 107, 114, 117, 144, 168, 170,
social-ecological systems 152–3 172, 186, 197–8, 201, 208, 219,
species 9, 13, 22, 43, 123, 126–7, 130, 221–2
132–5, 137–9, 145–6, 150, 153, absolute 143, 221
163–4, 169, 182, 192 relative 5
276 Index
transcendent 5, 9, 21, 65–6, 78, 86, unveiling 184, 186, 190, 198
105, 114, 116, 122, 136, 145, 157,
173, 187, 191, 208 Velde, Rudi te 190
transcendental 35, 40, 61, 65, 75, 77, violence 10, 47, 61, 107, 139–40,
84, 86–7, 109, 114, 116, 212 144–5, 197, 221, 223
transcendental epochē 35
truth-procedures 180–2 Whistler, Daniel 233f53
ūsī, Na īr al-Dīn al- 8, 164, 187, Wilson, Edward O. 42–5, 132–4
224 world
metaphysical concept of 168, 178
unified theory 7, 9, 54, 73, 75, 79, natural 28, 50, 152, 171, 173
90–1, 99, 107, 110, 116–17, 125,
161, 216–17 Žižek, Slavoj 5, 40–3, 119, 138
univocal predication 192–3 Zourabichvili, François 199, 221