The Ethics of Respect For Nature - Paul W. Taylor PDF
The Ethics of Respect For Nature - Paul W. Taylor PDF
The Ethics of Respect For Nature - Paul W. Taylor PDF
Paul w. Taylor*
In this paper I show how the taking of a certain ultinlate moral attitude
toward nature, which I call "respect for nature," has a central place in the
foundations of a life-centered system of environmental ethics. I hold that a set
of nloral norms (both standards of character and rules of conduct) governing
human treatment of the natural world is a rationally grounded set if and only
if, first, commitment to those norms is a practical entailment of adopting the
attitude of respect for nature as an ultimate moral attitude, and second, the
adopting of that attitude on the part of all rational agents can itself be justified.
When the basic characteristics of the attitude of respect for nature are made
clear, it will be seen that a life-centered system of environmental ethics need
not be holistic or organicist in its conception of the kinds of entities that are
deemed the appropriate objects ofmoral concern and consideration. Nor does
such a system require that the concepts of ecological homeostasis, equilibrium,
and integrity provide us with normative principles from which could be
derived (with the addition of factual knowledge) our obligations with regard
* Department of Philosophy, Brooklyn College of the City University of New York, Bedford
Avenue and H, Brooklyn, NY 11210. Taylor's special fie1ds are ethics and theory of value. He
is the author of Normative Discourse (Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall, 1961) and Principles
0/ Ethics: An Introduction (Encino, Calif.: Dickenson Publishing Co., 1975), and has also edited
two books of readings: The Moral Judgment: Readings in Contemporary Meta-Ethics (Englewood
Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall, 1963) and Problems 0/ Moral Philosophy, 3rd ed. (Encino, Calif.:
Dickenson Publishing Co., 1971).
197
198 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Vol.3
1 The conceptuallinks between an entity having a good, something being goodfor it, and events
doing good to it are examined by G. H. Von Wright in The Varieties ofGoodness (New York:
Humanities Press, 1963), chaps. 3 and 5.
200 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Vol.3
interest without its being interested in what we are doing to it in the sense of
wanting or not wanting us to do it. It may, indeed, be wholly unaware that
favorable and unfavorable events are taking place in its life. 1 take it that trees,
for example, have no knowledge or desires or feelings. Yet is is undoubtedly
the case that trees can be harmed or benefited by our actions. We can crush
their roots by running a bulldozer too close to them. We can see to it that they
get adequate nourishment and moisture by fertilizing and watering the soil
around them. Thus we can help or hinder them in the realization oftheir good.
It is the good of trees themselves that is thereby affected. We can similarly act
so as to further the good of an entire tree population of a certain species (say,
all the redwood trees in a California valley) or the good of a whole community
of plant life in a given wilderness area, just as we can do harm to such a
population or community.
When construed in this way, the concept of a being's good is not coextensive
with sentience or the capacity for feeling pain. William Frankena has argued
for a general theory of environmental ethics in which the ground of a creature's
being worthy of moral consideration is its sentience. 1 have offered some
criticisms of this view elsewhere, but the full refutation of such a position, it
seems to me, finally depends on the positive reasons for accepting a life-
centered theory of the kind 1 am defending in this essay.2
It should be noted further that 1 am leaving open the question of whether
machines-in particular, those which are not only goal-directed, but also
self-regulating-ean properly be said to have a good of their own. 3 Since 1 am
concerned only with human treatment of wild organisms, species populations,
and communities of life as they occur in our planet's natural ecosystems, it is
to those entities alone that the concept "having a good of its own" will here
be applied. 1 am not denying that other living things, whose genetic origin and
environmental conditions have been produced, controlled, and manipulated by
humans for hun1an ends, do have a good of their own in the same sense as do
wild plants and animals. It is not my purpose in this essay, however, to set out
or defend the principles that should guide our conduct with regard to their
good. It is only insofar as their production and use by humans have good or
ill effects upon natural ecosystems and their wild inhabitants that the ethics
of respect for nature comes into play.
(2) The second concept essential to the moral attitude of respect for nature
is the idea of inherent worth. We take that attitude toward wild living things
2 See W. K. Frankena, "Ethics and the Environment," in K.E. Goodpaster and K.M. Sayre,
eds., Ethics and Problems 0/ the 21st Century (Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press,
1979), pp. 3-20. I critically examine Frankena's views in "Frankena on Environmental Ethics,"
Monist, forthcoming.
3 In the light of considerations set forth in Daniel Dennett's Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays
on Mind and Psychology (Montgomery, Vermont: Bradford Books, 1978), it is advisable to leave
this question unsettled at this time. When machines are developed that function in the way our
brains do, we may weIl come to deern then proper subjects of moral consideration.
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 201
themselves responsible for performing actions that will have this effect and for
refraining from actions having the contrary effect.
Why should moral agents regard wild living things in the natural world as
possessing inherent worth? To answer this question we must first take into
account the fact that, when rational, autonomous agents subscribe to the
principles of moral consideration and intrinsic value and so conceive of wild
living things as having that kind of worth, such agents are adopting a certain
ultimate moral attitude toward the natural world. This is the attitude I call
"respect for nature." It par(!llels the attitude of.respect for persons in human
ethics. When we adopt the attitude of respect for persons as the proper (fitting,
appropriate) attitude to take toward all persons as persons, we consider
the fulfillment of the basic interests of each individual to have intrinsic value.
We thereby make a moral commitment to live a certain kind of life in rela-
tion to other persons. We place ourselves under the direction of a system of
standards and rules that we consider validly binding on all moral agents as
such. 4
Sin1ilarly, when we adopt the attitude of respect for nature as an ultimate
moral attitude we make a commitment to live by certain normative principles.
These principles constitute the rules of conduct and standards of character that
are to govern our treatment of the natural world. This is, first, an ultimate
commitment because it is not derived from any higher norm. The attitude of
respect for nature is not grounded on some other, more general, or more
fundamental attitude. It sets the total framework for our responsibilities to-
ward the natural world. It can be justified, as I show below, but its justification
cannot consist in referring to a more general attitude or a more basic normative
principle.
Second, the commitment is a moral one because it is understood to be a
disinterested matter of principle. It is this feature that distinguishes the atti-
tude of respect for nature from the set of feelings and dispositions that com-
prise the love of nature. The latter sterns from one's personal interest in and
response to the natural world. Like the affectionate feelings we have toward
certain individual human beings, one's love of nature is nothing more than the
particular way one feels about the natural environment and its wild inhabi-
tants. And just as our love for an individual person differs from our respect
for all persons as such (whether we happen to love them or not), so love of
nature differs from respect for nature. Respect for nature is an attitude we
4 I have analyzed the nature of this commitment of human ethics in "On Taking the Moral
Point ofView," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 3, Studies in Ethical Theory (1978), pp. 35-61.
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 203
believe all moral agents ought to have simply as moral agents, regardless of
whether or not they also love nature. Indeed, we have not truly taken the
attitude of respect for nature ourselves unless we believe this. To put it in a
Kantian way, to adopt the attitude ofrespect for nature is to take a stance that
one wills it to be a universallaw for all rational beings. It is to hold that stance
categorically, as being validly applicable to every moral agent without excep-
tion, irrespective of whatever personal feelings toward nature such an agent
might have or might lack.
Although the attitude of respect for nature is in this sense a disinterested
and universalizable attitude, anyone who does adopt it has certain steady,
more or less permanent dispositions. These dispositions, which are themselves
to be considered disinterested and universalizable, comprise three interlocking
sets: dispositions to seek certain ends, dispositions to carry on one's practical
reasoning and deliberation in a certain way, and dispositions to have certain
feelings. We may accordingly analyze the attitude of respect for nature into
the following components. (a) The disposition to aim at, and to take steps to
bring about, as final and disinterested ends, the promoting and protecting of
the good of organisms, species populations, and life communities in natural
ecosystems. (These ends are "final" in not being pursued as means to further
ends. They are "disinterested" in being independent of the self-interest of the
agent.) (b) The disposition to consider actions that tend to realize those ends
to be prima facie obligatory because they have that tendency. (c) The disposi-
tion to experience positive and negative feelings toward states of affairs in the
world because they are favorable or unfavorable to the good of organisms,
species populations, and life conlmunities in natural ecosystems.
The logical connection between the attitude of respect for nature and the
duties of a life-centered system of environmental ethics can now be made clear.
Insofar as one sincerely takes that attitude and so has the three sets of disposi-
tions, one will at the same time be disposed to comply with certain rules of
duty (such as nonmaleficence and noninterference) and with standards of
character (such as fairness and benevolence) that determine the obligations
and virtues of moral agents with regard to the Earth's wild living things. We
can say that the actions one performs and the character traits one develops in
fulfilling these moral requirements are the way one expresses or embodies the
attitude in one's conduct and character. In his famous essay, "]ustice as
Fairness," John Rawls describes the rules of the duties of human morality
(such as fidelity, gratitude, honesty, and justice) as "forms of conduct in which
recognition of others as persons is manifested."5 I hold that the rules of duty
governing our treatment of the natural world and its inhabitants are forms of
conduct in which the attitude of respect for nature is manifested.
I return to the question posed earlier, which has not yet been answered: why
should moral agents regard wild living things as possessing inherent worth?
I now argue that the only way we can answer this question is by showing how
adopting the attitude of respect for nature is justified for all nloral agents. Let
us suppose that we were able to establish that there are good reasons for
adopting the attitude, reasons which are intersubjectively valid for every ratio-
nal agent. If there are such reasons, they would justify anyone's having the
three sets of dispositions mentioned above as constituting what it means to
have the attitude. Since these include the disposition to promote or protect the
good of wild living things as a disinterested and ultimate end, as well as the
disposition to perform actions for the reason that they tend to realize that end,
we see that such dispositions commit a person to the principles of moral
consideration and intrinsic value. To be disposed to further, as an end in itself,
the good of any entity in nature just because it is that kind of entity, is to be
disposed to give consideration to every such entity and to place intrinsic value
on the realization of its good. Insofar as we subscribe to these two principles
we regard living things as possessing inherent worth. Subscribing to the princi-
pIes is what it means to so regard them. To justify the attitude of respect for
nature, then, is to justify commitment to these principles and thereby to justify
regarding wild creatures as possessing inherent worth.
We must keep in mind that inherent worth is not some mysterious sort of
objective property belonging to living things that can be discovered by empiri-
cal observation or scientific investigation. To ascribe inherent worth to an
entity is not to describe it by citing some feature discernible by sense perception
or inferable by inductive reasoning. Nor is there a logically necessary connec-
tion between the concept of a being having a good of its own and the concept
of inherent worth. We do not contradict ourselves by asserting that an entity
that has a good of its own lacks inherent worth. In order to show that such
an entity "has" inherent worth we must give good reasons for ascribing that
kind of value to it (placing that kind of value upon it, conceiving of it to be
valuable in that way). Although it is humans (persons, valuers) who must do
the valuing, for the ethics of respect for nature, the value so ascribed is not
a human value. That is to say, it is not a value derived from considerations
regarding human well-being or human rights. It is a value that is ascribed to
nonhuman animals and plants themselves, independently of their relationship
to what humans judge to be conducive to their own good.
Whatever reasons, then, justify our taking the attitude of respect for nature
as defined above are also reasons that show why we should regard the living
things of the natural world as possessing inherent worth. We saw earlier that,
since the attitude is an ultimate one, it cannot be derived from a more funda-
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NA TURE 205
mental attitude nor shown to be a special case of a more general one. On what
sort of grounds, then, can it be established?
The attitude we take toward living things in the natural world depends on
the way we look at them, on what kind of beings we conceive them to be, and
on how we understand the relations we bear to them. Underlying and support-
ing our attitude is a certain belief system that constitutes a particular world
view or outlook on nature and the place of human life in it. To give good
reasons for adopting the attitude of respect for nature, then, we must first
articulate the belief system which underlies and supports that attitude. If it
appears that the belief system is internally coherent and well-ordered, and if,
as far as we can now tell, it is consistent with all known scientific truths
relevant to our knowledge of the object of the attitude (which in this case
includes the whole set of the Earth's natural ecosystems and their communities
of life), then there remains the task of indicating why scientifically informed
and rational thinkers with a developed capacity of reality awareness can find
it acceptable as a way of conceiving of the natural world and our place in it.
To the extent we can do this we provide at least a reasonable argument for
accepting the belief system and the ultimate n10ral attitude it supports.
I do not hold that such a belief system can be proven to be true, either
inductively or deductively. As we shall see, not all of its components can be
stated in the form of empirically verifiable propositions. Nor is its internal
order governed by purely logical relationships. But the system as a whole, I
contend, constitutes a coherent, unified, and rationally acceptable "picture" or
"map" of a total world. By examining each of its main components and seeing
how they fit together, we obtain a scientifically informed and well-ordered
conception of nature and the place of humans in it.
This belief system underlying the attitude of respect for nature 1 call (for
want of a better name) "the biocentric outlook on nature." Since it is not
wholly analyzable into empiricallY confirn1able assertions, it should not be
thought of as simply a compendium of the biological seiences eoncerning our
planet's ecosystems. It might best be described as a philosophical world view,
to distinguish it from a seientific theory or explanatory system. However, one
of its major tenets is the great lesson we have learned from the science of
ecology: the interdependence of allliving things in an organically unified order
whose balance and stability are necessary eonditions for the realization of the
good of its constituent biotic communities.
Before turning to an aceount of the main components of the biocentric
outlook, it is convenient here to set forth the overall structure of my theory
of environmental ethics as it has now emerged. The ethics of respect for nature
is made up of three basic elements: a belief system, an ultimate moral attitude,
and a set of rules of duty and standards of character. These elements are
connected with each other in the following manner. The belief system provides
a certain outlook on nature which supports and makes intelligible an autono-
206 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Val. 3
The biocentric outlook on nature has four main components. (1) Humans
are thought of as members of the Earth's community of life, holding that
membership on the same terms as apply to all the nonhuman members. (2) The
Earth's natural ecosystems as a totality are seen as a complex web ofintercon-
nected elements, with the sound biological functioning of each being depen-
dent on the sound biological functioning of the others. (This is the component
referred to above as the great lesson that the science of ecology has taught us).
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 207
protozoa actually predated this by several billion years.) If the time that algae
have been here were represented by the length of a football field (300 feet), then
the period during which sharks have been swimming in the world'soceans and
spiders have been spinning their webs would occupy three quarters of the
length of the field; reptiles would show up at about the center of the field;
mammals would cover the last third of the field; hominids (mammals of the
family Hominidae) the last two feet; and the species Homo sapiens the last six
inches.
Whether this newcomer is able to survive as long as other species renlains
to be seen. But there is surely something presumptuous about the way humans
look down on the "lower" animals, especially those that have become extinct.
We consider the dinosaurs, for example, to be biological failures, though they
existed on our planet for 65 -million years. One writer has made the point with
beautiful simplicity:
We sometimes speak of the dinosaurs as failures; there will be time enough for
that judgment when we have lasted even for one tenth as long.... 6
6 Stephen R.L. Clark, The Moral Status 0/ Animals (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1~77), p. 112.
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 209
To accept the biocentric outlook and regard ourselves and our place in the
world from its perspective is to see the whole natural order of the Earth's
biosphere as a complex but unified web of interconnected organisms, objects,
and events. The ecological relationships between any community of living
things and their environment form an organic whole of functionally interde-
pendent parts. Each ecosystem is a small universe itself in which the interac-
tions of its various species populations comprise an intricately woven network
of cause-effect relations. Such dynamic but at the same time relatively stable
structures as food chains, predator-prey relations, and plant succession in a
forest are self-regulating, energy-recycling mechanisms that preserve the equi-
librium of the whole.
As far as the well-being of wild animals and plants is concerned, this
ecological equilibrium must not be destroyed. The same holds true of the
well-being of humans. When one views the realm of nature from the perspec-
tive of the biocentric outlook, one never forgets that in the long run the
integrity of the entire biosphere of our planet is essential to the realization of
the good of its constituent communities of life, both human and nonhuman.
Although the importance ofthis idea cannot be overemphasized, it is by now
so familiar and so widely acknowledged that I shall not further elaborate on
it here. However, I do wish to point out that this "holistic" view of the Earth's
ecological systen1s does not itself constitute a moral norm. It is a factual aspect
ofbiological reality, to be understood as a set of causal connections in ordinary
empirical terms. Its significance for humans is the same as its significance for
nonhumans, nan1ely, in setting basic canditians for the realization of the good
of living things. Its ethical implications far aur treatment of the natural envi-
ronment lie entirely in the fact that our knowledge of these causal connections
is an essential means to fulfilling the aims we set for ourselves in adopting the
attitude of respect for nature. In addition, its theoretical implications for the
ethics of respect for nature lie in the fact that it (along with the ather elements
of the biocentric outlook) makes the adopting of that attitude a rational and
intelligible thing to do.
210 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Vol.3
This fourth component ofthe biocentric outlook on nature is the single most
important idea in establishing the justifiability of the attitude of respect for
nature. Its central role is due to the special relationship it bears to the first three
conlponents of the outlook. This relationship will be brought out after the
concept of human superiority is examined and analyzed. 7
In what sense are humans alleged to be superior to other aninlals? We are
different from them in having certain capacities that they lack. But why should
these capacities be a mark of superiority? From what point of view are they
judged to be signs of superiority and what sense of superiority is meant? After
all, various nonhuman species have capacities that humans lack. There is the
speed of a cheetah, the vision of an eagle, the agility of a monkey. Why should
not these be taken as signs of their superiority over humans?
One answer that comes immediately to mind is that these capacities are not
as valuable as the human capacities that are claimed to make us superior. Such
uniquely human characteristics as rational thought, aesthetic creativity, auton-
7 My criticisms of the dogma of human superiority gain independent support from a carefully
reasoned essay by R. and V. Routley showing the many logical weaknesses in arguments for
human-centered theories of environmental ethics. R. and V. Routley, "Against the Inevitability
of Human Chauvinism," in K. E. Goodpaster and K. M. Sayre, eds., Ethics and Problems 0/ the
21st Century (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1979), pp. 3fr-59.
212 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Val. 3
the values of human civilization, rather than by values connected with what
it is for a member of that species to live a good life? If all living things have
a good of their own, it at least makes sense to judge the merits of nonhumans
by standards derived from their good. To use only standards based on human
values is already to commit oneself to holding that humans are superior to
nonhumans, which is the point in question.
A further logical flaw arises in connection with the widely held conviction
that humans are morally superior beings because they possess, while others
lack, the capacities of a moral agent (free will, accountability, deliberation,
judgment, practical reason). This view rests on a conceptual confusion. As far
as moral standards are concerned, only beings that have the capacities of a
moral agent can properly be judged to be either moral (morally good) or
immoral (morally deficient). Moral standards are simply not applicable to
beings that lack such capacities. Animals and plants cannot therefore be said
to be morally inferior in merit to humans. Since the only beings that can have
moral merits or be deficient in such merits are moral agents, it is conceptually
incoherent to judge humans as superior to nonhumans on the ground that
humans have moral capacities while nonhumans don't.
Up to this point I have been interpreting the claim that humans are superior
to other living things as a grading or ranking judgment regarding their con1-
parative merits. There is, however, another way of understanding the idea of
human superiority. According to this interpretation, humans are superior to
nonhun1ans not as regards their merits but as regards their inherent worth.
Thus the claim of human superiority is to be understood as asserting that all
humans, simply in virtue oftheir humanity, have a greater inherent worth than
other living things.
The inherent worth of an entity does not depend on its merits. 8 To consider
something as possessing inherent worth, we have seen, is to place intrinsic
value on the realization of its good. This is done regardless of whatever
particular merits it might have or might lack, as judged by a set of grading
or ranking standards. In human affairs, we are all familiar with the principle
that one's worth as a person does not vary with one's merits or lack of merits.
The same can hold true of animals and plants. To regard such entities as
possessing inherent worth entails disregarding their merits and deficiencies,
whether they are being judged from a human standpoint or from the stand-
point of their own species.
The idea of one entity having more merit than another, and so being superior
to it in merit, makes perfectly good sense. Merit is a grading or ranking
concept, andjudgments of comparative merit are based on the different degrees
to which things satisfy a given standard. But what can it mean to talk about
one thing being superior to another in inherent worth? In order to get at what
8 For this way of distinguishing between merit and inherent worth, I am indebted to Gregory
VIastos, "Justice and Equality," in R. Brandt, ed., Sociallustice (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Pren-
tice-Hall, 1962), pp. 31-72.
214 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Val. 3
is being asserted in such a claim it is helpful first to look at the social origin
of the concept of degrees of inherent worth.
The idea that humans can possess different degrees of inherent worth origi-
nated in societies having rigid class structures. Before the rise of modern
democracies with their egalitarian outlook, one's membership in a hereditary
class determined one's social status. People in the upper classes were looked
up to, while those in the lower classes were looked down upon. In such a
society one's social superiors and social inferiors were clearly defined and
easily recognized.
Two aspects of these class-structured societies are especially relevant to the
idea of degrees of inherent worth. First, those born into the upper classes were
deemed more worthy of respect than those born into the lower orders. Second,
the superior worth of upper class people had nothing to do with their merits
nor did the inferior worth of those in the lower classes rest on their lack of
merits. One's superiority or inferiority entirely derived from a social position
one was born into. The modern concept of a meritocracy simply did not apply.
One could not advance into a higher class by any sort of moral or nonmoral
achievement. Similarly, an aristocrat held his title and all the privileges that
went with it just because he was the eldest son of a titled nobleman. Unlike
the bestowing of knighthood in contemporary Great Britain, one did not earn
membership in the nobility by meritorious conduct.
We who live in modern democracies no Ionger believe in such hereditary
social distinctions. Indeed, we would wholeheartedly condemn them on moral
grounds as being fundamentally unjust. We have come to think of class systems
as a paradigm of social injustice, it being a central principle of the democratic
way of life that among humans there are no superiors and no inferiors. Thus
we have rejected the whole conceptual framework in which people are judged
to have different degrees of inherent worth. That idea is incompatible with our
notion of human equality based on the doctrine that all humans, simply in
virtue oftheir humanity, have the same inherent worth. (The belief in universal
human rights is one form that this egalitarianism takes.)
The vast majority of people in modern democracies, however, do not main-
tain an egalitarian outlook when it comes to comparing human beings with
other living things. Most people consider our own species to be superior to all
other species and this superiority is understood to be a matter of inherent
worth, not merit. There may exist thoroughly vicious and depraved humans
who lack all merit. Yet because they are human they are thought to belong
to a higher class of entities than any plant or animal. That one is born into
the species Homo sapiens entitles one to have lordship over those who are one's
inferiors, namely, those born into other species. The parallel with hereditary
social classes is very close. Implicit in this view is a hierarchical conception
of nature according to which an organism has a position of superiority or
inferiority in the Earth's community of life simply on the basis of its genetic
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 215
background. The "lower" orders of life are looked down upon and it is consid-
ered perfectly proper that they serve the interests of those belonging to the
highest order, namely humans. The intrinsic value we place on the well-being
of our fellow humans reflects our recognition of their rightful position as our
equals. No such intrinsic value is to be placed on the good of other animals,
unless we choose to do so out of fondness or affection for them. But their
well-being imposes no moral requirement on uso In this respect there is an
absolute difference in moral status between ourselves and them.
This is the structure of concepts and beliefs that people are committed to
insofar as they regard humans to be superior in inherent worth to all other
species. I now wish to argue that this structure of concepts and beliefs is
completely groundless. If we accept the first three components of the biocentric
outlook and from that perspective look at the major philosophical traditions
which have supported that structure, we find it to be at bottom nothing more
than the expression of an irrational bias in our own favor. The philosophical
traditions themselves rest on very questionable assumptions or else simply beg
the question. I briefly consider three of the main traditions to substantiate the
point. These are classical Greek humanism, Cartesian dualism, and the Judeo-
Christian concept of the Great Chain of Being.
The inherent superiority of humans over other species was implicit in the
Greek definition of man as a rational anima!. Our animal nature was identified
with "brute" desires that need the order and restraint of reason to rule them
. (just as reason is the special virture of those who rule in the ideal state).
Rationality was then seen to be the key to our superiority over animals. It
enables us to live on a higher plane and endows us with a nobility and worth
that other creatures lack. This familiar way of comparing humans with other
species is deeply ingrained in our Western philosophical outlook. The point to
consider here is that this view does not actually provide an argument for
human superiority but rather makes explicit the framework of thought that is
implicitly used by those who think ofhumans as inherently superior to nonhu-
mans. The Greeks who held that humans, in virtue oftheir rational capacities,
have a kind of worth greater than that of any nonrational being, never looked
at rationality as but one capacity of living things among many others. But
when we consider rationality from the standpoint of the first three elements
of the ecological outlook, we see that its value lies in its importance for human
life. Other creatures achieve their species-specific good without the need of
rationality, although they often make use of capacities that humans lack. So
the humanistic outlook of classical Greek thought does not give us a neutral
(nonquestion-begging) ground on which to construct ascale of degrees of
inherent worth possessed by different species of living things.
The second tradition, centering on the Cartesian dualism of soul and body,
also fails to justify the claim to human superiority. That superiority is supposed
to derive from the fact that we have souls while animals do not. Animals are
216 ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Vol.3
mere automata and lack the divine element that makes us spiritual beings. 1
wou't go into the now familiar criticisms of this two-substance view. 1 only add
the point that, even if humans are composed of an immaterial, unextended soul
and a material, extended body, this in itself is not a reason to deern them of
greater worth than entities that are only bodies. Why is a soul substance a thing
that adds value to its possessor? Unless some theological reasoning is offered
here (which many, including myself, would find unacceptable on epistemologi-
cal grounds), no logical connection is evident. An immaterial something which
thinks is better than a material something which does not think only ifthinking
itself has value, either intrinsically or instrumentally. Now it is intrinsically
valuable to humans alone, who value it as an end in itself, and it is instrumen-
tally valuable to those who benefit from it, namely humans.
For animals that neither enjoy thinking for its own sake nor need it for living
the kind of life for which they are best adapted, it has no value. Even if
"thinking" is broadened to include all forms of consciousness, there are still
many living things that can do without it and yet live what is for their species
a good life. The anthropocentricity underlying the claim to human superiority
runs throughout Cartesian dualism.
A third major source ofthe idea ofhuman superiority is the Judeo-Christian
concept of the Great Chain of Being. Humans are superior to animals and
plants because their Creator has given them a higher place on the chain. It
begins with God at the top, and then moves to the angels, who are lower than
God but higher than humans, then to humans, positioned between the angels
and the beasts (partaking ofthe nature ofboth), and then on down to the lower
levels occupied by nonhuman animals, plants, and finally inanimate objects.
Humans, being "made in God's image," are inherently superior to animals and
plants by virtue of their being closer (in their essential nature) to God.
The metaphysical and epistemological difficulties with this conception of a
hierarchy of entities are, in my mind, insuperable. Without entering into this
matter here, 1 only point out that if we are unwilling to accept the metaphysics
oftraditional Judaism and Christianity, we are again left without good reasons
for holding to the claim of inherent human superiority.
The foregoing considerations (and others like them) leave us with but one
ground for the assertion that a human being, regardless of merit, is a higher
kind of entity than any other living thing. This is the mere fact of the genetic
makeup ofthe species Homo sapiens. But this is surely irrational and arbitrary.
Why should the arrangenlent of genes of a certain type be a mark of superior
value, especially when this fact about an organism is taken by itself, unrelated
to any other aspect of its life? We might just as well refer to any other genetic
makeup as a ground of superior value. Clearly we are confronted here with
a wholly arbitrary claim that can only be explained as an irrational bias in our
own favor.
That the claim is nothing more than a deep-seated prejudice is brought horne
to us when we look at OUf relation to other species in the light of the first three
Fall 1981 RESPECT FOR NATURE 217
I have not asserted anywhere in the foregoing account that animals or plants
have moral rights. This omission was deliberate. I do not think that the
reference class of the concept, bearer of moral rights, should be extended to
include nonhuman living things. My reasons for taking this position, however,
go beyond the scope of this paper. I believe I have been able to accomplish
many of the same ends which those who ascribe rights to animals or plants
wish to accomplish. There is no reason, moreover, why plants and animals,
including whole species populations and life communities, cannot be accorded
legal rights under my theory. To grant them legal protection could be inter-
preted as giving them legal entitlement to be protected, and this, in fact, would
be a means by which a society that subscribed to the ethics of respect for nature
could give public recognition to their inherent worth.
There remains the problem of competing claims, even when wild plants and
animals are not thought of as bearers of moral rights. If we accept the biocen-
tric outlook and accordingly adopt the attitude of respect for nature as our
ultimate moral attitude, how do we resolve conflicts that arise from our respect
for persons in th~ domain of human ethics and our respect for nature in the
domain of environmental ethics? This is a question that cannot adequately be
dealt with here. My main purpose in this paper has been to try to establish a
base point fron1 which we can start working toward a solution to the problem.
I have shown why we cannot just begin with an initial presumption in favor
of the interests of our own species. It is after all within our power as moral
beings to piace limits on human population and technology with the deliberate
intention of sharing the Earth's bounty with other species. That such sharing
is an ideal difficult to realize even in an approximate way does not take away
its claim to our deepest moral commitment.