Doran
Doran
Doran
www.bloomsbury.com
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any
form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or
any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the
publishers.
ISBN: 978–1–4411–4553–6
1 History as Fulfillment 35
Hayden White
11 Comment 209
Hayden White
Notes 215
Index 251
Editor’s Note
I would like to thank Hayden White for his support during the preparation
of this volume and for his “Comment,” which appears at the end. I would
also like to thank the University of Rochester, where I currently teach, for its
generous sponsorship of the 2009 conference, “Between History and Narrative:
Colloquium in Honor of Hayden White,” where the early versions of five
contributions to this volume were first presented. Many thanks to Margaret
Brose, for her elegant translation of Gianni Vattimo’s essay, and to Ana Torfs,
for permission to reproduce photographs of her work. Finally, I am grateful to
Camilla Erskine, my editor at Bloomsbury, for her kind and careful attention to
this project.
Contributors
Mieke Bal, a cultural theorist and critic, has been a Royal Netherlands Academy
of Arts and Sciences Professor. Her interests range from biblical and classical
antiquity to seventeenth-century and contemporary art, modern literature,
feminism, and migratory culture. Her recent books include: Of What One
Cannot Speak: Doris Salcedo’s Political Art (2011), Loving Yusuf (2008), A
Mieke Bal Reader (2006), Travelling Concepts in the Humanities (2002), and
Narratology (3rd edition 2009). She is also a video-artist, making experi-
mental documentaries on migration. Her first fiction feature, A Long History
of Madness, was made with Michelle Williams Gamaker. She is currently
working on a series of video installations, later to be turned into a feature film,
titled Madame B, based on Flaubert’s Madame Bovary. She occasionally serves
as an independent curator.
Karyn Ball is Professor of English and Film Studies at the University of Alberta.
Her areas of research and teaching interests include Holocaust studies, theories
of memory, trauma, narrative, and film. She is the author of Disciplining the
Holocaust (2008, paperback 2009) and the editor of Traumatizing Theory: The
Cultural Politics of Affect in and Beyond Psychoanalysis (2007). She has also
edited a special issue of Parallax (2005) on “Visceral Reason” and a special
x Contributors
Death: The British and Irish Quakers in the Democratic Transition, 1650–1900
(1991). He is the co-editor of Historical Understanding, by Louis Mink (1987),
History and Theory: Contemporary Readings (1998), and World History:
Ideologies, Structures, and Identities (1998). Among his important essays is “The
Reception of Hayden White” (History and Theory, 1998).
1973 was a fateful year for historical studies and in particular for the much-
maligned genre of philosophy of history. It was the year Hayden White’s
Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe appeared:
“the book around which all reflective historians must reorganize their thoughts
on history,” wrote Louis Mink just a few weeks after its publication. The feeling
was prescient: forty years later, Metahistory has lost none of its power to
provoke controversy or inspire new thinking. It has so transformed the philo-
sophical view of history that one of the contributors to the present volume,
F. R. Ankersmit, has written that “[Metahistory] has been the unparalleled
success story of all twentieth century philosophy of history”1 and that “contem-
porary philosophy of history is mainly what [Hayden] White has made it.”2
Though White’s thought is certainly not reducible to Metahistory—three subse-
quent collections of essays amplified, developed, and recalibrated the ideas put
forth in his magnum opus (a fourth volume, published in 2010, brought together
White’s major uncollected essays spanning his entire career)—his contribution
to the philosophy of history genre is generally considered to be his 1973 tome.3
The present volume examines “philosophy of history after Hayden White”
in two senses of the preposition “after”: 1) philosophy of history according to
White—namely, how White completely redefined the concept of philosophy of
history in his many books and essays; and 2) what philosophy of history has
become as a result of White’s interventions: how his reconception has had, and
2 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
ground in its insistence on the ways in which the philosophy of history is still a
vibrant mode of intellectual inquiry, even if its influence is often imperceptible
and despite the fact that many of the traditional (i.e. metaphysical) aims of
philosophical history have been abandoned.6
fund of inspirational models and the common wisdom. This all changed when
Leopold von Ranke (1795–1886) sought to professionalize the study of history
by grounding it in a rigorous, empirical approach to the past, that is, one based
on primary sources and archival research. On the one hand, Ranke aimed to
separate history from the literary genres, in particular from the popular form of
novel, and, on the other, from all generalizing propositions, especially those of
the so-called “speculative” philosophy of history (e.g. Hegel and Marx), but also
of the positive sciences of the era, which subscribed to mechanistic theories of
explanation. As Ranke famously stated, the historian should aspire to present
the past “as it really was,” which meant restricting oneself as much as possible
to the particulars, to the “facts,” while purging historical writing of all fictional,
dilettantish, and extrinsic elements. This objectivist vision (value-neutral
historical knowledge), which lent to the study of history a quasi-scientific aura,
led directly to the establishment of history as an academic discipline such as we
know it today. However, as White would point out in his Metahistory, Ranke’s
objectivism was in fact an implicit “philosophy of history.” That is to say, the
“objective” view of historical practice was not neutral or commonsensical
but presupposed a particular—and rather dubious—ontological view, namely
the idea of an absolute, mind-independent “historical reality” that could be
conjured, judged, and communicated as such in its immediacy. Furthermore,
as White noted, Ranke’s advocacy of the narrative form as the most “natural”
or “transparent” medium of representation borrowed heavily from the mimetic
techniques of novelists, particularly writers of historical fiction, whom Ranke
disparaged as fabulists.
Largely due to Ranke’s intervention, philosophy of history and professional
historiography developed along divergent paths, with little or no cross-fertili-
zation. Philosophers such as Marx and Nietzsche viewed professional historians
as naïve or servile, whereas historians, following Ranke’s model, saw philosophy
of history as a threat to their putative objectivity and to their monopoly over the
proper way of ascribing meaning to history; for theirs was a minimalist meaning
that cleaved as closely as possible to the “facts.” The explicit aim of philosophy of
history, on the other hand, was to give an overarching meaning to history, under
which it subsumed the particulars unearthed by the historian; it thus considered
history as a whole. In its classical, “speculative” form, that is, as practiced by
Hegel and Marx, and more recently by Croce, Spengler, and Toynbee, this
meant describing the grand shape of history, often taking into account huge
swaths of historical time. Speculative history believed that history’s direction-
ality could be discerned and humanity’s fate predicted; in short, it offered a
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 5
historians today are in revolt against the metahistory of Hegel and Croce and
Collingwood, not because it is metahistorical, but because they feel it to be the
expression of a philosophical attitude that is no longer valid; just as the liberal
historians of the eighteenth century revolted against the theological metahistory
of the previous period.14
In an essay published the same year as his Metahistory entitled “The Politics
of Contemporary Philosophy of History” (1973), White echoes this sentiment,
contending that “the term metahistorical is really a surrogate for ‘socially
innovative historical vision.’ What the philosophers and the historians themselves
call ‘straight’ history is the historical vision of political and social accommoda-
tionists.”15 In other words, according to both Dawson and White, the distinction
between so-called “straight” history and metahistory is really a distinction
between a conformist and a radical-revolutionary approach to history, with
“metahistory” (used pejoratively) referring to a radical-revolutionary approach
that had either failed or simply been abandoned. Straight history, then, was
successful metahistory.
This explains, in part, the very negative view evinced by many twentieth-
century Anglo-American philosophers toward metahistory or “speculative
philosophy of history.” Thus Karl Popper dedicated his The Poverty of Historicism
(1936/57) to the “memory of the countless men and women of all creeds or
nations or races who fell victim to the fascist and communist belief in Inexorable
Laws of Historical Destiny.”16 Popper was referring to Oswald Spengler’s
influence on National Socialism (Nazism) in Germany, Marx’s influence on
the Bolshevik Revolution in Russia, and Hegel’s influence, via Benedetto Croce
and Giovanni Gentile, on Italian Fascism (it should be noted, however, that
while Gentile was a self-avowed “philosopher of fascism,” Spengler and Croce
overcame initial enthusiasm to become severe critics of the fascist regimes in
their respective countries). Though Popper ranked history rather low in the
hierarchy of intellectual endeavors, he nevertheless pined after “old-fashioned
history,” which, precisely by being conformist, carried none of the politico-
ethical risks engendered by metahistory.
However, in 1942, a seminal article by Carl Gustav Hempel, “The Function
of General Laws in History,” reinvigorated the debate around the viability of
philosophy of history in Anglo-American, and more specifically Analytic,
thought. Hempel’s intervention in historical studies must be seen against
the backdrop of his endeavor to unify the natural and the “human” sciences:
Naturwissenschaft and Geisteswissenschaft (literally “sciences of spirit”) as they
were known in Germany since Hegel. Their strict separation had been an
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 7
article of faith for the anti-positivists, in particular Wilhelm Dilthey and Max
Weber; but under the aegis of a logical-empirical model of explanation, the
“covering law model” (i.e. a law that explains or “covers” the relation between
two or more discrete events),17 Hempel effectively circumscribed philosophy
of history according to a more austere, formal concept of explanation (“expla-
nation sketches”) that did not permit prediction (what Arthur Danto dubbed
“historical foreknowledge”),18 as had the speculative form of philosophy of
history.19
Arthur Danto later differentiated between “substantive” and “analytical”
approaches to philosophy of history, the latter being “philosophy applied to the
special conceptual problems which arise out of the practice of history as well
as out of substantive philosophy of history.”20 Danto claimed that “substantive”
philosophy of history was much closer to history than to philosophy, thereby
replacing the distinction between history and metahistory with a distinction
between analytic philosophy of history, on the one side, and history/specu-
lative philosophy of history (metahistory), on the other. Thus, according
to this view, analytical philosophy of history is the only true philosophy of
history. Nevertheless, one could certainly characterize the approach Danto
was advocating as “metahistorical” in the strict sense of this term. In fact,
White, though an admirer of Danto, would later reject Danto’s opposition: his
Metahistory would be both an epistemological critique of historical practice and
a philosophy of history in its own right.
A few years after Hempel’s seminal essay, a competing vision within
Anglo-American philosophy of history emerged in R. G. Collingwood’s The
Idea of History, posthumously published in 1946 and popularized by W. H.
Dray.21 Whereas Hempel had advocated methodological unity in the sciences,
Collingwood promoted Dilthey’s and Weber’s Verstehen (understanding) model
of the human sciences, as contrasted with the Erklären model (objective scien-
tific explanation) then in vogue, thereby preserving the separation between
Geisteswissenschaft and Naturwissenschaft. Collingwood held that history
involved understanding the thought processes of historical actors rather than
explaining events according to causal laws. History was thus a product of
interpretation, and it required the exercise of one’s imagination. (The section of
Collingwood’s book entitled “The Historical Imagination” may have inspired
the subtitle for White’s Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-
Century Europe.) While Collingwood rejected the scientization of history,
he was not anti-scientific, and he cast a long shadow over Anglo-American
philosophy of history, in such figures as W. H. Walsh, Patrick Gardiner, W. B.
8 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Gallie, and Alan Donagan.22 Collingwood was also an early influence on White.
One of White’s first essays (1957) was entitled “Collingwood and Toynbee:
Transitions in English Historical Thought.”23 White saw Collingwood as a “crack
in the armor of a historiographical tradition that ha[d], heretofore, avoided
all connections with Continental historicism and philosophy of history”24—a
“crack” that White himself would continue to widen in the ensuing years.
A third watershed development in the Anglo-American attitude toward
philosophy of history, Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
(1962), with its theory of “paradigm shifts,” belatedly delivered the death-blow
to Hempel’s logical-empirical approach to historical explanation. Kuhn showed
that science was in fact subject to the same kind of interpretative framing it
had criticized in the “sciences of spirit” (Geisteswissenschaft). This book thus
effectively obliged analytic philosophers to choose between a “softer” historical
approach or a “harder” philosophy of science approach. Not surprisingly, they
chose the latter, though a few renegades, such as Richard Rorty, extolled Kuhn
as a welcome corrective to a philosophy of science gone awry.25 Thus, after a
lively, twenty-year debate, analytic philosophers abruptly lost interest in the
philosophy of history. Danto’s Analytical Philosophy of History (1965) turned
out to be the last major intervention in the field. In a 1995 essay entitled
“The Decline and Fall of the Analytic Philosophy of History,” Danto wistfully
observes:
The same year as Foucault’s Les mots et les choses an obscure professor of
medieval history at the University of Rochester publishes an article that would
soon become a kind of clarion call for a revolution in historical studies. This
article, “The Burden of History” (1966), which appeared in the recently founded
journal History and Theory, established Hayden White as a fiery polemicist
who quixotically challenged the basic conventions of his field. Though White’s
piece generally avoided discussing philosophy of history per se, focusing
instead on the present state of academic historiography, the goal of the essay
was nevertheless to show how the “antihistorical attitude” or “the revolt against
historical consciousness” that characterized much early twentieth-century
writing amounted, in effect, to a positive philosophy of history.
Sartre’s influence was particularly in evidence.29 The section of Being and
Nothingness entitled “My Past” was no doubt the prime inspiration for what
would become one of the defining ideas of White’s work, that of “choosing
one’s past.” Sartre’s philosophy revolves around a fundamental dialectic between
10 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
past, as the past whose spirit it wishes to embody and perpetuate, but it does not
thereby deny the facticity of Nazism or the Holocaust, which would be a form of
bad faith, i.e. revisionism or negationism.34 In Sartre’s formulation, transcending
one’s past does not at all involve its denial.
This operation is best illustrated by what Sartre says about the personal past
and the existential “project”:
Now the meaning of the past is strictly dependant on my present project. […] I
alone in fact can decide at each moment the bearing of the past. I do not decide
it by debating over it, and in each instance evaluating the importance of this or
that prior event; but by projecting myself toward my ends, I preserve the past
with me, and by action I decide its meaning. Who shall decide whether the
mystic crisis in my fifteenth year “was” a pure accident of puberty or, on the
contrary, the first sign of a future conversion? I myself, according to whether I
shall decide—at twenty years of age, at thirty years—to be converted.35
Sartre’s point here—a point first illustrated in his novel Nausea—is that the past
is meaningless in itself; it only takes on meaning when it is volitionally related
to the present, that is, to present choices, which, for Sartre, entail a choice of
being (according to Sartre, we are defined by our actions, not by a preexisting
“essence”; existence precedes essence). Sartre in effect collapses the distinction
between an internal (subjective) and an external (objective) perspective in
historical studies (i.e. Verstehen versus Erklären), for the historian is in the
same predicament as the historical actor; both are effectively making history in
both the literal and figurative sense.36 Sartre notes that “the historian is himself
historical; that is… he historicizes himself by illuminating ‘history’ in the light
of his projects and of those of his society.”37 In other words, whether under the
guise of “professionalism” or of “objectivity,” the historian cannot escape the
fundamental freedom that inheres in every individual’s and society’s relation
to the past and the ends towards which the individual or collective projects
itself as a function of its project. The irreducible element of futurity in choice is
another factor in the blurring of the distinction between history and philosophy
of history: all history is essentially a projection into the future through the past,
even if only philosophy of history does so explicitly (i.e. in good faith).38
Summarizing Sartre’s view in “The Burden of History,” White writes: “we
choose our past in the same way we choose our future. The historical past
therefore, is, like our various personal pasts, at best a myth, justifying our
gamble on a specific future, and at worst a lie, a retrospective rationalization
of what we have become through our choices.”39 White will effectively adopt
12 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
to honor the Roman past as their past, the Roman sociocultural system ceased to
exist.”44 Though White does not mention it in this essay, his idea of the historical
system stems from his early fascination with Martin Luther’s revolt against the
Catholic Church, which replaced an almost millennium-and-a-half tradition
with a return to textual Christianity and the simplicity of origins. Protestants
thus do not regard Catholics as their progenitors, but instead see themselves as
coinheritors of the original Christianity of the Gospels and of the ministry of
Peter and Paul in the first century a.d.
At the end of the essay, White sums up his argument in terms that recall the
Sartrean language of “The Burden of History”: “In choosing our past, we choose
a present; and vice versa. We use the one to justify the other. By constructing our
present, we assert our freedom; by seeking retroactive justification for it in our
past, we silently strip ourselves of the freedom that has allowed us to become
what we are.”45 It was traditional historical inquiry that White saw as “stripping
[us] of our freedom,” since, in its bad faith, it refused to see its justification of
the present as the result of a choice of (historical) being.
At this point I think it would be helpful to recall the discussions of this
problematic in Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time—a strong influence on
Sartre—which will allow us to better elucidate the stakes involved in the idea
of “choosing the past” from the perspective of existentialist philosophy.46 In
Division II of Being and Time, Heidegger uses the Kierkegaard-inspired concept
of “repetition” or “retrieve” (Wiederholung) to describe the constitutive histo-
ricity of Da-sein (human existence):
Retrieve is explicit handing down, that is, going back to the possibilities of
Da-sein that has been there. The authentic retrieve of a possibility of existence
that has been—the possibility that Da-sein may choose its own heroes—is
existentially grounded in anticipatory resoluteness… The retrieve of what is
possible neither brings back “what is past,” nor does it bind the “present” back
to what is “outdated.” […] Rather retrieve responds to the possibility of existence
that has-been-there. […] Retrieve neither abandons itself to the past, nor does
it aim at progress.47
been” (Gewesenheit)—that is, a past that retains its relation to the present—as
opposed to the “outdated” (i.e. objectified) past (Vergangenheit) severed from
the present; 3) repetition/retrieve is also a response to the past; in other words,
it is the manifestation of an interpretative attitude, which is not a desire to
relive the past, to merely identify with past actors (retrieve/repetition does not
“abandon itself to the past”), but to make it new, open-endedly, that is, without
thereby assuming a particular teleology (such as progress or decline). This, for
Heidegger, constitutes an authentic relation to one’s past.48
In his essay for this volume, Gianni Vattimo offers a lucid reinterpretation of
Heidegger’s concept of authentic historicity:
There is no history of Being other than that of human praxis; and there is no
objective structure other than that of history considered as previous, that is, as
interpreted for and by the present, a history that, as Being and Time teaches, is
never vergangen (gone) but always only gewesen (what has been). That is, the
past is not an immutable datum… but a call, a message that always addresses
itself to the projectural capacity of the one who receives it and who actively
interprets it. What is “real” is not in any way objective Being, but only that
which has been produced by other beings existing before us, themselves active
interpreters, involved in a process that might have developed differently.
Vattimo contrasts the notion of the past as objective Being with the past
conceived as praxis (a move that leads Vattimo in a recent book to link Heidegger
to Marx),49 thereby recalling Heidegger’s cardinal distinction (elaborated in
Division I of Being and Time) between Vorhandenheit (“presence-at-hand” or
“objective presence”) and Zuhandenheit (“readiness-to-hand” or “handiness”).
On this conception, the past is primarily Zuhandenheit, a practical past, a past
always already interpreted in the context of its relationality to the present and
the future, and only secondarily or derivatively Vorhandenheit, the objective
apprehension of the past, i.e. the past of the traditional, Rankean historian
(whose ideology, for Heidegger, would entail an impoverished vision of the past,
because of its detachment from being-in-the-world).
In his most recent work (2010), White has sought to develop a similar
distinction, that between the “practical past” and the “historical past,” a
distinction he derives from the British philosopher and political theorist
Michael Oakeshott.50 The concept of the “historical past” matches up with
Heidegger’s critique of scientific objectivity, of the primacy accorded to “theory”
as a mental activity that detaches objects from their practical contexts, consid-
ering them in isolation and for their own sake, existing by and for themselves.
White writes:
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 15
In short, the “historical past” has no edifying purpose, even if it has a scholarly
one. However, White’s notion of the “practical past,” unlike Heidegger’s
concept of practical utility, stems from a more Kantian conception of the
“practical,” with its ethico-political implications (without losing sight, of
course, of the Nietzschean-Sartrean conception of the past as not something to
be merely studied, categorized, examined, etc., but rather as something to be
used for distinctively human ends): “The practical past is made up of all those
memories, illusions, bits of vagrant information, attitudes and values which
the individual or the group summons up as best they can to justify, dignify,
excuse, alibi, or make a case for actions to be taken in the prosecution of a
life project.”52 Here again we find the existentialist language of the “project,”
thereby connecting White’s current thinking with the impulses that came out
of the writing of “The Burden of History” and “What is a Historical System?”
in the mid-1960s.
Not surprisingly, White associates the “practical past” with the philosophy
of history, thus underscoring the fact that for White all authentic history is
philosophy of history, that is, “socially innovative historical vision.” Aligning
philosophy of history with literary genres such as the historical and realist novel,
which also bear a “practical” relation to the past, White observes:
It has to be said that, whatever else it may be, philosophy of history belongs to
the class of disciplines meant to bring order and reason to a “practical past”
rather than to that “historical past” constructed by professional historians for
the edification of their peers in their various fields of study.53
Now the idea of the “practical past” is certainly not a new thought in White’s
work, even if it does effectively bring philosophy of history back into the
forefront of White’s reflections, after having languished for some time in the
background.54 In fact, the idea of the practical-historical is rooted in White’s
earliest university studies, in the example of his undergraduate mentor William
J. Bossenbrook at Wayne State University, an inspiring figure who also taught
two other contributors to the present volume, Arthur Danto and Harry
Harootunian. Describing the intellectually formative (and not merely inspira-
tional) influence of his teacher, White recounts:
16 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
[Bossenbrook] consistently sustained the illusion that the study of history was
the most important intellectual task that a morally responsible man could
undertake. Perhaps this was because he always portrayed the great historians of
the past as actors in the dramas of culture, not as mere passive commentators on
events that had already run their courses. […] We concluded that thought and
action were not mutually exclusive alternatives, but only different aspects of the
single seamless web of human involvement.55
This passage, written in 1968, before any of the books for which he is now
famous had been published, offers what I consider to be the best succinct
statement of White’s philosophy of history: historical writing as praxis—as the
shaping both of historical reality and of the community that historical writing
serves. White’s insistence on the activity of the heroic historian/philosopher of
history, versus the passivity of the traditional, objectivist historian is simply a
somewhat romanticized version of a leitmotif that runs throughout his oeuvre.
(In his essay for this volume, “History as Fulfillment,” White criticizes the idea
of historians as “the passive receivers and forwarders of [historical] messages.”)
For White’s philosophy of history is inextricable from a philosophy of life: that
is, from an understanding of the role of history in individual and collective self-
making and self-transcendence.56
One has to keep in mind that White wrote “The Burden of History” during a
transitional moment in twentieth-century intellectual history: a few years after
Thomas Kuhn’s seminal text appeared but a few years before the poststructuralist
explosion with which White, rightly or wrongly, would come to be identified.
Thus White’s examples of avant-garde, anti-historicist French thought in that
essay are Sartre and Camus rather than Foucault and Derrida. Nevertheless,
“The Burden of History” was anthologized in the popular textbook collection
Critical Theory Since 1965, published in 1986, in effect canonizing White as one
of the progenitors of the “theory” movement in literary and cultural studies,
which, in the mid to late 1980s, had hit its high-water mark (though it has
survived in various forms up to the present day).57
A new phase in the reception of White’s thought was opened up with the
publication of Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century
Europe in 1973, which is still White’s best-known and most controversial work.58
From the perspective of the philosophy of history, to which Metahistory was
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 17
history and philosophy of history are one (“the possible modes of histori-
ography are the same as the possible modes of speculative philosophy of
history”).68 But, of course, only a metahistorical approach can account for this
fact, thereby surreptitiously establishing its priority. White’s Metahistory was
in effect a meta-metahistory,69 since it involved the condition of possibility of
(historical and philosophical-historical) discourse itself, even if this condition
was conceived as tropological rather than as logical-conceptual.70 (White’s move
was not unlike Jacques Derrida’s deconstruction of the opposition between
speech and writing: both terms of the opposition are shown to inhere in a
common structure, a structure that can only be described by one of the terms,
“writing” or “arche-writing,” though Derrida’s “arche-” sounded paradoxically
more transcendental than White’s “meta-.”) As Harry Harootunian observes
in his contribution to this volume, White “[laid] to rest the claims of the
philosophy of history by shifting its ground to linguistic protocols that would
demonstrate how ‘empirical history’ was no more exempt from the mediations
of linguistic prefiguration than was philosophy of history.”
Thus, in his preface to Metahistory, White argues that the differences
between straight history and philosophy of history are more superficial than
essential, that “there can be no ‘proper history’ which is not at the same time
‘philosophy of history,’”71 meaning that, in addition to the common tropological
structure, all history writing inevitably embodies theoretical presuppositions
that concern history-in-general and that condition any elaboration of the
historical particulars. Proper or straight history is philosophy of history that
does not recognize itself as such (because of its unconscious conformity
to prevailing norms); philosophy of history, on the other hand, “contain[s]
within it the elements of a proper history,” choosing rather to emphasize the
“conceptual construct” over the historical data.72 Thus, from the perspective of
each of the opposing poles, straight history is criticized for its insufficiency of
meaning and philosophy of history for its excess of meaning. However, for White,
the idea that Marx apprehended historical reality Metonymically and that
Ranke apprehended historical reality Synecdochically was a more important
distinction than that between the philosophy of history embodied by the former
and the straight history exemplified by the latter.
Though White’s tropological grid appeared at first glance to be rigid and
deterministic, it was actually meant as a corollary to Sartre’s dictum that we
are “condemned to be free.” For once we see the tropological apprehension of
historical reality as constituted by a choice (among different tropological appre-
hensions) that we are condemned to make (“condemned” because we cannot
20 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
think discursively and thus historically outside of the tropes), we can then
unburden ourselves from the idea of corresponding to a non-linguistic reality,
from the illusion of representing historical reality “as it really was.” White writes
that “we are indentured to a choice among contending interpretative strategies
in any effort to reflect on history-in-general; […] the best grounds for choosing
one perspective on history rather than another are ultimately aesthetic or moral
rather than epistemological.”73 The “we are indentured to a choice” is clearly a
paraphrase of Sartre’s “we are condemned to be free.” However, White’s superim-
position of the moral and the aesthetic dimensions that inform and ultimately
constitute any “choice of interpretative strategy” already transcends the Sartrean
problematic (at least insofar as it was developed in Being and Nothingness).74
As the reader of Metahistory knows, the tropes are aligned with modes
of emplotment (Romantic, Tragic, Comic, Satirical), argument (Formist,
Mechanistic, Organicist, Contextualist), and ideological implication (Anarchist,
Radical, Conservative, Liberal). The choice of tropological apprehension, then,
cannot be motivated by purely epistemological or empirical reasons, but is
rather a function of the historian’s or philosopher’s ethical and aesthetic predi-
lections. This skeletal structure of the tropes is fleshed out, as it were, by the
other modes, which are subject to a virtually inexhaustible number of combi-
natory possibilities; these constitute for White a “historiographical style.”
One of the most important and enduring of White’s ideas put forward in
Metahistory is the aesthetic concept of “emplotment,” a term of his coinage.
Though it sounds as if it were hatched by a literary theorist, the term is in fact
designed to reveal something that is specific to historiography (for it would be
a redundant concept in literary theory). By “emplotment,” White meant that
the historian and the philosopher of history use conventional (i.e. preexisting
and culturally conditioned) narrative forms to organize and tell a story about
the past—or, to put it more succinctly, stories are made, not found. Traditional
historiography, on the other hand, had always held that the story is to be
discovered or uncovered in the amassed data, that the facts tell their own story.
But this view, if carried to its logical conclusion, presupposes that there are
an infinite number of possible stories, none of which bear any formalizable
(i.e. plot) resemblance to any other. White holds that this is an illusion, that
it is impossible to construct (or, if you like, reconstruct) a narrative, whether
composed of real or imagined elements, utterly bereft of conventional form
(plot type) or of “storiness” itself (i.e. as having, as Aristotle said, a beginning,
a middle, and an end). In other words, there is no such thing as narrative-
in-general, only particular kinds of stories, which White reduces, following
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 21
White thus contends that there is a “content of the form,” as one of his later
collections (1987) was titled, that the aesthetic form inevitably conveys a
moral, conceptual, and ideological content, forming a totality with the putative
“content,” with which it is in the end indistinguishable.
The rapprochement White effected between historical and fictional narrative
on the level of form was, unsurprisingly, considered a threat to the quasi-
scientific objectivity that historians saw as legitimating their discipline as
the search for the truth of the past. The idea that every narrative contains an
inexpugnable element of fiction (the very conventionality of form that preexists
and conditions any narrative process) appeared to strip history of its status as
an empirical, fact-driven discipline.75 If “all stories are fictions,” as White liked
to say, then how could the historian effectively separate his activity from that
of the novelist? And if fictionality (which, for White, is simply another name
for figuration) is fundamental to historicity, then how are we to conceive of
22 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Figural causation is thus a kind of “reverse causation”; and in this sense, all
history, like the Sartrean “project,” is an act of redemption: one redeems the past
by choosing it, by choosing to actualize it in and for the present, thereby making
it “new,” or making it anew.
The difficulty for the modern historian in countenancing such an idea of
“reverse causation” is succinctly addressed by Gabrielle Spiegel in her essay for
this volume, where she observes that White is
I turn now to a brief discussion of the essays that comprise this volume. The first
chapter features a previously unpublished essay by White. Originally given as a
keynote address, “History as Fulfillment,” is an excellent introduction to White’s
later thought as well as one of the few essays in which White explicitly defines
how his notion of figuralism relates to historical studies, a topic that White had
addressed in the article on Auerbach cited above. Unlike the latter essay, however,
White here develops the notion that narrative itself—“plot-meaning”—is a
manifestation of the prefiguration-fulfillment dynamic, thereby connecting
his earlier philosophy of history with his later thought (a unity I have sought
to describe in this introduction according to the idea of “choosing the past”).
“Emplotment,” the key-term of White’s Metahistory, can therefore be seen as a
kind of figuralism. In addition, White reiterates that, despite structuralist and
pseudo-scientific attempts to reduce history to its conceptual content, narrative
is essential to history, not merely as a discourse genre, but as a discipline:
“history, anthropology, and psychoanalysis are, I believe, the only disciplines of
the human sciences that still treat narrativization as a legitimate means of expla-
nation, rather than as an instrument of vulgarization by which to introduce
findings to a lay audience.” This is because, when it comes to human events,
such as those that history recounts, “the figure precedes the concept, rather than
the reverse.” It would not be an exaggeration to say that the working out of this
deceptively simple idea is the guiding thread of White’s philosophy of history.83
F. R. Ankersmit’s essay, “A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s
Tropology,” treats the question of how White’s theory of tropes can represent a
“contribution to historical rationality.” Ankersmit thus diverts White’s tropology
from its original purpose in Metahistory (which was to examine historical
discourse in terms of the structuring effects of the most basic tropes), thereby
26 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
developing White’s thought in ways that are suggested by but not explicitly
elaborated in Metahistory.84 Specifically, Ankersmit seeks to address how the
referential or truth value of historical writing can be assessed according to
the logic of tropes. Ankersmit notes that since White’s main purpose was to
show how historical meaning was generated, White gives scant attention to
the truth value of the tropes. Given that the tropes are, by nature, negations of
literal truth, and that historical texts do not, of course, present themselves as
negations of literal truth, but, on the contrary, as facts strung together in some
coherent form, the question arises as to what happens to this literal truth—i.e.
its cognitive status—as the structuring and ordering function of the tropes
take over, as it must in any discursive rendering of historical reality. Therefore,
Ankersmit seeks to establish which tropes best capture the cognitive relation
between historical discourse and historical reality. In his tour through the four
tropes, Ankersmit begins by eliminating Irony and Metonymy from contention:
the first because it transcends or frustrates any cognitivist account; the second
because the “trope itself remains outside of any effort to make sense of the
world.” He concludes that only Synecdoche and Metaphor can constitute a
specifically cognitive relation to historical reality or historical truth—a finding
that will demonstrate, according to Ankersmit, “how Whitean tropology may
shed some new light on the cognitivist aspects of historical writing.”
In her essay “Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians,”
Mieke Bal also tackles the question of truth in historical scholarship, but from
a very different perspective. She describes her first encounter with White’s
Metahistory as a seminal moment in her own intellectual formation, for it
offered a way out of the rigid formalism-historicism binary that characterized
the critical discussions of that time. Those in the formalist camp (like Bal) were
invariably accused of ahistoricism, of refusing to acknowledge the relevance of
historical meaning. White’s philosophy of history, however, had demonstrated
how all history, philosophical or straight, is inevitably structured and hence
subject to formalist analysis. But Metahistory also showed that formalism, far
from being ahistorical, is firmly rooted in time, specifically in the way in which
the present frames the past. Bal observes that “by endorsing the present as a
historical moment in the act of interpretation itself, one can make much more of
the object under scrutiny.” Bal notes how her notion of non-linear history, which
she calls “preposterous history” (“the impact the present has on the past”), can
be considered in a similar light as White’s figuralism (i.e. as reverse causation),
except that she separates her account from any suggestion of redemption. In
the second part of her essay, Bal takes White’s work to an area where it is not
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 27
often applied (Stephen Bann’s work being an important exception), that is,
to visual art. Bal analyses at length a slide instillation by Belgian artist Ana
Torfs entitled Du Mentir-Faux (Concerning Lying-Falsehood), which purports
to thematize questions of historical truth and reality by analogizing the
photographic image of a contemporary woman with the historical figure of
Joan of Arc. Unlike most of White’s interpreters, Bal does not see White’s
philosophy of history as undermining the idea of historical truth, but rather as
recasting it beyond the fact-fiction, true-false dichotomies—an operation she
sees embodied in Torfs’s installation. According to Bal, by “explicitly bracketing
the question of truth,” White “leaves it and the desirability of its pursuit intact.”
Karyn Ball’s essay, “Hayden White’s Hope, or the Politics of Prefiguration,”
seeks to reconcile the seeming transcendentalism of White’s philosophy
of history, i.e. the “precritical” function of tropic prefiguration, with “his
commitment to recapturing the potential for visionary politics forsaken by a
disenchanted historical profession.” In her investigation into White’s transcen-
dentalism, Ball invokes Kant’s distinction between the transcendent (that
which is beyond experience) and the transcendental (necessary condition
of experience), to show how the objectivist historian, by treating historical
reality as existing apart from historical discourse, falls prey to what Kant calls
the “transcendental illusion”: the confusion of a noumenal idea of history,
what history is in itself, with objective reality and knowledge. This Kantian
distinction allows Ball to “shed light on White’s ‘transcendental narrativism’
as an ‘aestheticist’ approach to the critique of historiography.” Ball’s resulting
rapprochement between the aesthetic and the political dimensions in White is a
welcome corrective to commentaries that miss the inherently political nature of
White’s formalist-aestheticist approach to philosophy of history, or the aesthetic
nature of White’s politics. In this vein, Ball notes how White’s association (in his
essay “The Politics of Historical Interpretation”) of the aesthetic category of the
sublime with a visionary philosophy of history “amplifies what is at stake in his
politics of interpretation: a potentially mobilizing recognition of the negativity
of history—its dynamic withdrawal from the totalizing presumptions of the
understanding.”
As mentioned above, Arthur Danto had also been inspired by the teaching
of William J. Bossenbrook at Wayne State University. He thus begins his essay,
“Hayden White and Me: Two Systems of Philosophy of History,” with a tribute
to Bossenbrook, whom he credits with having taught his students “to think
grandly about history,” but also with stressing the importance of narrative in
historiography, something that became central to both Danto’s and White’s
28 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Nobody ever actually lived or experienced the historical past because it could
not have been apprehended on the basis of whatever it was that past agents
knew, thought, or imagined about their world during their present. Historians,
viewing the past from the subsequent vantage point of a future state of affairs,
can claim a knowledge about the past present that no past agent in that present
could ever have possessed.87
In his essay, Danto thus unwittingly reveals more commonalities than diver-
gences between his and White’s philosophies of history. Both see historical
understanding as an irreducible fusion between past and present against the
illusion of a fixed and autonomous past.88
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 29
The Executioner’s Song, and Thomas Keneally’s Schindler’s Ark, all of which
inhabit the ambiguous space between history and fiction. In the second part of
his essay, Vann examines truly experimental works of historical writing: those
of the medieval social historian John Hatcher, whose account of the Black Death
uses fictional characters “to provide a framework for the facts,” as Hatcher
himself claims; and of Keith Hopkins, a social and demographic historian of
ancient Rome, whose A World Full of Gods: The Strange Triumph of Christianity
(2001) purports to be academic history, though it features time-travellers and
an imagined “confession” of Saint Augustine. Vann concludes that these are
“hybrid” works, presenting themselves as both historical (a contribution to
historical scholarship) and fictional (with invented characters and events),
without being reducible to either pole (unlike, say, the historical novel, which
is first and foremost a novel). These hybrid works serve a singular critical
function, according to Vann, since “thoroughly fictionalized historiography
can also complicate the notion of historical knowledge that is presupposed by
uncritical acceptance of the fiction/non-fiction binary.” Vann concludes his
essay by observing that such a complication of historical knowledge has in fact
been White’s unquestioned legacy.
Finally, Gianni Vattimo, in his essay “From the Problem of Evil to Hermeneutic
Philosophy of History,” shows how White’s critique of the objectivist credo of
traditional empirical historiography, which presupposes a stable and immutable
historical reality, can be considered in light of Heidegger’s cardinal idea of
the “ontological difference,” that is, Heidegger’s critique of metaphysics as
the confusion of beings (objective being, scientific realism) with Being (the
self-revelation of what is)—for in both cases it is a matter of a “hermeneutic
philosophy of history” transcending a narrow-minded and socially oppressive
objectivism.91 Vattimo begins his essay by noting how Heidegger’s ontological
difference or the “destructuring of the ontological tradition” (i.e. of the history
of ontology)92 is a “direct consequence of the traditional reflection on the
problem of the ‘reality’ of Evil.” That is, how can Evil, traditionally understood
as non-being, exist? This polemic is transformed, in Heidegger’s thought, into
a new ontological thesis: “‘a being that exists does not exist,’ but happens.” In
this formula, Vattimo implicitly collapses the theory of historicity articulated
in Heidegger’s Being and Time (which I analyzed above) into Heidegger’s
later idea of Being as happening or “event” (Ereignis). Vattimo thus proposes
a “radical reading of Heidegger,” which translates into a “radical historicism,”
that is, a historicism that results from an “ontology of the present” and from
its triple function of “inheriting-interpreting-transforming.” As we have seen,
Choosing the Past: Hayden White and the Philosophy of History 33
***
It is now—and perhaps abundantly—clear that the one theme that runs through
virtually all of the essays in this volume is that of figuralism. Moreover, one
could say that all of the essays contained in Philosophy of History After Hayden
White represent, in their own eclectic ways, fulfillments of White’s oeuvre,
fulfillments that will, in turn, serve as figures for new interpretations. If all great
thought is measured by its capacity to create new meanings, White’s philosophy
of history is certainly no exception.
1
History as Fulfillment
Hayden White
How are historical pasts constructed? That historical pasts have to be constructed
seems self-evident. To be sure, historians speak of their work as reconstruction
rather than construction. For historians, the past preexists any represen-
tation of it, even if this past can be accessed only by way of its shattered and
fragmentary remains. Historians speak of their work as reconstruction in
order to distinguish their object of study from the constructions of fabulists,
novelists, and poets who, even though they may invoke the historical past,
refer to it, and make statements about it, are licensed to ignore the available
evidence about the real past and to make of its elements whatever the imagi-
nation and their powers of poetic creativity might wish it to have been.
Historians work with the remains (ruins and relics) of past forms of life,
and their aim is to restore and display, as accurately as possible, the original
forms of life of which these remains, even in their state of decay, are tokens
and manifestations. But as anyone knows who has studied the restoration
of artistic, architectural, or archeological artifacts, every reconstruction—of
a painting, a building, a wall, a document, a tool, or weapon—requires not
only a great deal of original construction but also a considerable amount of
destruction of the original as well. Putting back together what God, time, man,
or nature has damaged is a delicate technical matter, but also a matter of profes-
sional ethics hinging on the difficult question of living men’s responsibility to
their predecessors. This is why the ancient Greeks and Romans believed that
any kind of bridge-building activity, indeed any building at all, was a sacred
enterprise, to be attended by sacrifices and rites of propitiation to the gods for
presuming to wish to join together what fate and the gods had put asunder.
If the aim of historical research is reconstruction of the past as it really
was or had been, if it is a bridge spanning the gap between any past and the
present from which a historical inquiry is to be launched must be constructed,
36 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
History, or rather, historical studies, remains the least scientific—in both its
achievements and its aspirations—of all the disciplines comprising the human
and social sciences. Ever so often, there is a move to make historical studies
more scientific, either by providing it with a theoretical basis such as positivism
or dialectical materialism, or by importing into it a methodology from one
or another of the “social sciences.” But these efforts seldom succeed, largely
because of the way that the principal object of historical study—the event—is
defined. Historical events are considered to be time- and place-specific, unique
and unrepeatable, not reproducible under laboratory conditions, and only
minimally describable in algorithms and statistical series. This is why efforts to
transform history into a science typically take the form of attempts to redefine the
event or eliminate it altogether as a proper object of scientific study. Nonetheless
(or possibly therefore) history continues to enjoy a status as foundational
vis-à-vis the other human and social sciences. As Michel Foucault pointed out
in Les mots et les choses (The Order of Things), since the mid-nineteenth century,
history has occupied a place both intimately related to but only contiguous with
(rather than integrated into) the other human sciences. History serves as both
basis and antitype of the other human sciences—in virtue of its continuing
commitment to an idiographic (analogical) method for the description of
singular events and its conviction that the establishment of a relationship of
temporal successivity between events is explanatory of them. This manner of
construing events by describing or otherwise representing them (mimetically,
History as Fulfillment 37
could be truthfully represented in the form of the kinds of stories met with
in myth, fiction, and drama. The task of the researcher was to discover these
structures or stories in the data—the documentary, monumental, and archeo-
logical record—and to choose and apply (rather than construct) the modes
of description best suited to their truthful (or intelligible) representation in a
written discourse. To be sure, some structuralists believed that the narrativists
were inventing their stories and imposing them upon the facts, and most narra-
tivists believed that the structuralists were imposing upon the data conceptual
schemes or models that deprived events and processes of their concreteness
(“concreteness” being defined as the indissociability of form and substance).
But these differences were thought to be reconcilable by analytical procedures
that discriminated among levels of historical integration (natural, social, and
political) at which different temporal durations (long, medium, and short) and
intensities of occurrence (cold, lukewarm, and hot) could be discerned.
But this was before the “linguistic” or more specifically the “discursive” turn
struck the human sciences, and analytical attention shifted from the object (or
referents) of historiological research to the products of that research, the written
texts in which historians presented their findings. Here the issue soon devolved
into a discussion of what György Lukács was wont to call “the philosophy of
composition.” The conventional view was that the research phase of an historical
investigation could be kept relatively distinct from the phase of composition.
Indeed, it was thought that the establishment of the facts could be kept distinct
from the analysis of their status as evidence in a particular causa or the inter-
pretation of their significance as elements of a structure of meaning. As the great
historian of Italian Fascism, Renzo de Felice, often stressed: “First the facts, then
the interpretation.”
The canonical view was that the competent historian would always first
discover the facts and martial his thoughts about them, and only then sit down
and compose a discourse in which he presented both the facts and his thoughts
about them in a “literary” or “scientific” manner. In many respects, this view
of the relation between research and composition resembled the relation
that historians had to presume existed between the past and the present; the
research phase of the historian’s labor was both disjoined from and continuous
with the phase of composition. The historical account was a report about the
events established as facts in the research phase and the historian’s thoughts
(explanations and interpretations) about the facts subsequently composed and
presented in the form of a written prose narrative. On this view, the form of the
historian’s discourse (its form as a story) was conceived to be contingent and
History as Fulfillment 39
their accounts of the past raised the threat of formalism, anathema to both
the Left and the Right of the ideological spectrum. If a historical process was
identifiable by its form and if this form was that of the narrative, how could
one distinguish between historical and fictional, or for that matter, “mythical”
narratives? The response of the leading professional historians was to moot
this question by appeal to the authority of the rules and procedures honored
as properly historiological in nature by “the community of professional histo-
rians.” The relativism implied in this investiture of authority in “the” community
of professional historians to decide what was and what was not a properly
historical method or mode of representation was to be blocked by the culti-
vation of a “critical” historiography—an openness to all theories of history that
did not feature a frivolous or nihilistic approach of the kind supposedly caused
by “the linguistic turn” in the human sciences.
This phrase “the linguistic turn” refers to a conception of history as a
constructivist enterprise based on a textualist conception of the relation
between language and reality. Textualism presumes whatever is taken as
the real is constituted by representation rather than preexists any effort to
grasp it in thought, imagination, or writing. The representation of anything
whatsover—whether in visual, auditory, haptic, or verbal imagery—establishes a
site whereon the difference between a reality and its forms of manifestation can
be discerned. But, at the same time, the representation of a state of affairs (such
as a historical event) in a given medium (such as a historical narrative) invites
attention to the difference between the thing represented and its representation.
It is this difference that makes possible the critical comparison between one
representation of “the past,” or any aspect of it, and another. The belief in the
commensurability of different representations of any aspect of the past hinges
on the prior belief in a past to which all representations of it can be referred and
differentially assessed as to their validity and their status as contributions to our
knowledge of it. But the real past is not, of course, accessible except by way of
its representations—indexical, iconic, or symbolic, as the case may be.
It is, of course, a commonplace of traditional historical studies that the
past represents itself in the remains—documentary, monumental, and archeo-
logical—that it has left behind. According to this view, a historian’s work is like
that of an archeologist, which is to find a past hidden in rubble and requiring
only the clearing away of accumulated detritus for it to present itself as it really
was in its more or less pristine condition. As thus envisaged, the compositional
task of the historian is that of a transcriber rather than that of a translator
between past and present. The messages lying dormant in the ruins of the past
History as Fulfillment 41
do not have to be reconstructed but only decoded for reception by their present
and future receivers. Historians are the passive receivers and forwarders of
these messages, not co-composers thereof. The validity of their transmissions
are assessable on the basis of what the “community of professional historians”
regards as the rules and procedures for handling evidence of a particularly
historical kind. Thus, the representation of the past, its elements, and the
relations among these is not a problem, because the objects of historical interest
have been self-constituted by the actions of past agents and agencies. It is all
a matter, not even of interpretation or explanation, but of description and the
inscription of the description in a written discourse that displays the historicity
of the objects described.
Now, from the perspective of a textualist conception of representation,
description is a means of constituting states of affairs as possible objects of a
historical interest and as candidates for inclusion among the class of objects
deemed worthy of being inscribed in a historical discourse. If the discourse
in question is to be cast in the mode of a narrative, then the objects to be
represented must be described simultaneously as possessing the attributes of
historicity and narratability. The historicity (historical substance) of an object
is to be established by the description of the object according of the rules
of evidence prevailing in “the community of historians” at a particular time
and place. But its narratability is quite another matter. There are no rules of
narration similar to the rules of evidence (unless it be admitted, as I believe, that
the rules for processing historical materials in order to constitute them as data
relevant to a given causa are as conventional, and therefore as socially specific,
as the rules of narration). And this is because narration requires that historical
agents, events, institutions, and processes be not so much conceptualized as
enfigured (mise en figure) in a twofold way. First, they must be imaged as the
kinds of characters, events, scenes, and processes met with in stories—fables,
myths, rituals, epics, romances, novels, and plays. And secondly they must
be troped as bearing relationships to one another of the kind met with in the
plot-structures of generic story types, such as epic, romance, tragedy, comedy,
and farce. The description of past entities as figures of stories located in specific
times and places produces the chronicle type of historical representation. The
endowment of these figures with plot-functions endows the trajectory of their
life-courses with plot-meaning. Plot-meaning is a way of construing historical
processes in the mode of a fulfillment of a fate or a destiny considered, not
as an instance of mechanical or teleological causality, but as contingent on
the interplay of free will (choice, motives, intentions), on the one hand, and
42 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
historically specific limits imposed upon the exercise of this free will, on the
other. Fulfillment (Erfüllung) is understood as an exfoliation of all the possi-
bilities for action contained in the “situation” (the context enfigured as a
scene of possible action). The enfiguration of agents, agencies, actions, events,
and scenes as elements of dramatic conflicts and their resolutions (either as
victories or defeats) is the means by which narrative interpretations of historical
processes are constructed. Emplotment (mise en intrigue) is the means by which
a specific set of events, initially described as a sequence, is de-sequentiated and
revealed to be a structure of equivalences—in which earlier events in the chain
are shown to be anticipations, precursors, or prototypes of later, more fully
“realized” instantiations thereof. (In Tacitus’s account of Nero’s rule, the events
of his “quinquennium,” the first five years of his rule, in which he appeared to
be a “good” emperor, are shown to be “figures”—incomplete, partial, or masked
anticipations—of the “bad” emperor he subsequently revealed himself to have
been.)
It is the fulfilled figure that casts its light back—retrospectively and, in the
narrative account, retroactively—on the earlier figurations of the character
or process being related. It is the figure-fulfillment model of narrativity that
lends credence to the commonplace that the historian is a prophet, but one
who prophesies “backward.” It is what justifies the notion that the historian,
as against the historical characters he studies, occupies a privileged position of
knowledge in virtue of the fact that, coming after a given set of events have run
their course, “he knows how events actually turned out.” But what can “actually
turned out” mean here? It can only mean that the historian has treated his enfig-
uration of a given set of events as an “ending-as-fulfillment” that permits him
to “recognize” in earlier events in the sequence dim and imperfect anticipations
of “what will have been the case” later on. The meaning-effect of the narrative
account of the sequence is produced by the technique of relating events in the
order of their occurrence but construing them as “clues” of the plot-structure
which will be revealed only at the end of the narrative in the enfiguration of
events as a “fulfillment.”
There is much more to be said about the figure-fulfillment model of narrativity
and the different forms it takes in Classical, Christian, and post-Renaissance
writing and historiography. Above all, we should note its function as the model
of every historical account of the past cast in a celebratory or redemptive mode.
What Andreas Hillgruber and Ernst Nolte called “the pleasures of narration”
was advanced in the cause of redeeming a “portion” of the German past deemed
worthy of being narrated and narrated as a drama of fulfillment rather than
History as Fulfillment 43
other regimes more or less genocidal known to history, but also on the possibly
cosmeticizing effects of a “narrative” of the actions of any group in any way
connected with the Final Solution. Andreas Hillgruber was turned into lamb
or goat to be sacrificed on the altar dedicated to both science and justice for
deigning to call what happened to Germany during the last two years of the
War “die Zerschlagung des Deutschen Reiches (“the shattering of the German
Reich”) and what happened to the Jews “das Ende des europäischen Judentums
(the end of the European Jewry)” You will recall how Hillgruber was pilloried
for daring to suggest that a specific group of historical agents—units of the
Wehrmacht defending the Eastern Front in the final year of World War II—
could plausibly be represented in a narrative account that would redeem their
status as heroes of a kind and thereby redeem something of German national
honor from the ashes of a general disgrace. In other words, Hillgruber was to
have been run out of the profession for doing what historians have always done:
try to legitimate the national past and tell stories about it—or rather, by telling
stories about it.
In this debate, it was taken as given that everybody knew what was being
referred to by Germany, the Soviet Union, the Gulag, the Second World War,
the Holocaust, the Final Solution, the Eastern Front, not to mention the Turks,
the Armenians, Pol Pot, Himmler, and so on—and so they did. These were or
had been real things, events, persons, programs, places, peoples, what have
you. There was no denying their once or present reality. What was only dimly
perceived, or if perceived, not stressed, was that what was being compared or
held to be “incomparable,” “unique,” or “incommensurable” were the different
descriptions of these entities that had been “laid down” (posited) and enfigured
as possible objects of comparison, explanation, or moral judgment prior to the
bringing to bear upon them the specific methodologies, conceptual tools, and
technical terminologies that were supposed to fix them as “facts” in a specific
zone of “the past.” (In this case, the “recent” past, itself less a concept than
“figure” of temporality of a peculiarly ambiguous kind.) The debate turned on
questions of evidence and on how to assess the remains of the past available
in the documentary record, and consequently took the form of charges of
bad faith, special pleading, or political prejudice, on both sides. And this even
though, as everyone admitted or professed to believe, the litigants were profes-
sional historians with impeccable credentials of professional achievement. The
cause of this paradoxical situation, as I see it, was the fetishism of literalness
that has burdened the historians’ profession since it cut itself off from its
tradition as a literary or discursive practice and began to aspire to the status of
History as Fulfillment 45
a “science” of the “concrete.” I will not go into this history at this time, except to
say that, by this move, historical studies became systematically blinded to the
fact of its own discursive nature, its status as a practice of “composition,” and its
irredeemably tropological methods of constituting its objects of study. By this I
mean that because of the nature of the historian’s object of study—as an object
located in “the past” and by definition no longer an object that can be defined
by ostention, i.e. an object that can be indicated or referred to only by way of
its remains—the historian must and can only indicate it as a figure, a verbal
image, a simulacrum of a thing that might be viewed, a virtual thing, a thing
therefore that admits of different notions of what it might have been or might
have consisted of in its formerly realized state. And this sets a limit on not only
the possibility of reducing contending interpretations of the thing to the best or
most plausible interpretation, but also on the possibility of reducing contending
notions of “what are the facts” to the best or most accurate representation of the
facts. For the facts are figurations posing as predications, images posing or being
represented as manifestations of conceptual contents of utterances governable
by a logic of identity and non-contradiction. But the logic of narrative repre-
sentations of the world—whether of its past or of its present or of the relations
between them—is a logic of figures and tropes, which is not a logic at all unless
an assemblage of images can be said to be a structure of meaning logical in kind.
I think that Walter Benjamin perceived this when he wrote that “History
does not break down into stories; it breaks down into images”—in response
to Theodore Adorno’s criticism of his work as a mélange of “mysticism and
positivism” because it lacked a “theory.” Benjamin tried to theorize what he
called the “dialectical image,” which captured the contradictory nature of every
specifically “historically significant” event of the past. For him, the images that
we can find “caught” in the record like a fly in amber are not those that figure
forth an unambiguous and internally consistent social reality, but those that
capture, as in the still photograph, a moment of tension and change, an inter-
mittency between two moments of putative presence. I am not sure about this,
but I think that in his attempts to theorize the “dialectical image,” Benjamin
betrayed an insight expressed in the observation I noted above: that “history
does not break down into stories; it breaks down into images.” The truth is—and
I speak only figuratively rather than literally—that all images of the past are
“dialectical,” filled with the aporias and paradoxes of representation. And that
they can only be “fulfilled” by narrativization: as stories.
2
Introduction
Metahistory was not only Hayden White’s magnum opus; it was also by far
the most important work published in philosophy of history since World War
II. No book was more lengthily and intensively discussed; no book was more
prominent in debates around philosophy of history in the almost forty years
since its publication in 1973.
Discussion of Metahistory mostly focused on the structuralist grid it
proposed—too well known to be rehearsed here. And in course of time,
discussion concentrated on the role of the four tropes—metaphor, synecdoche,
metonymy, and irony—in historical writing. Self-evidently, this was wholly in
agreement with Metahistory itself, insofar as the book mainly consisted of a
close analysis of the oeuvre of eight nineteenth-century historians and philoso-
phers of history, whereas only the introduction and the conclusion dealt with
the tropes in a more technical and systematic way. In fact, this was precisely
one of the principal merits of Metahistory. For whereas pre-Whitean philoso-
phers of history often got lost in the mists of theoretical abstraction, White
firmly rooted his theory in the practice of historical writing. He thus achieved
a rapprochement of philosophy of history and historiography (i.e. the history of
historical writing), and this is still where the emphasis is, down to this day.
The result was, however, that relatively little attention was paid to the tropes
as such, and, especially, to the question of how tropological utterances—
metaphors, synecdoches, metonymies, and ironies—relate to the world, the
question of what kind of knowledge of, or insights into, the world is expressed
by them and of how this may contribute to a better understanding of the ways
48 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
in which the historical text relates to the past of which it claims to be a verbal
image. In a word: what is the cognitivist function of the tropes in the context of
historical writing? This will be my topic in this essay.
White’s tropology
In 1998, Richard Vann published in History and Theory a most perceptive and
informative essay on the Rezeptionsgeschichte of Hayden White’s work up until
that time. The essay carefully retraced how White’s philosophy of history made
its way in the intellectual world—at first slowly, then ever and ever faster and
in ever more fields, beginning with the discipline of history itself and then
anthropology, geography, law, literary studies, psychology, and so on; even
extending its influence to such unlikely and remote fields as communications
and administration science.1 It has been the unparalleled success story of all
twentieth-century philosophy of history.
Three things stand out in Vann’s account. In the first place, though the
triumph of White’s philosophy of history self-evidently started with history,
curiously enough interest for his work increased faster outside of historical
studies than within that discipline. It was as if the provocation of his ideas was
often part of its impact, as if the intellectual shock produced by his writings
went apace with its spreading from one discipline to another. His oeuvre
attacked by surprise, so to speak. And so it still is the case, for White rarely sat
down to carefully re-elaborate previous insights; instead he typically preferred
to present his readers with ever new and still unexplored possibilities. His
oeuvre is a wellspring of ideas. This is why his work still has the same freshness
and originality that it did in the 1970s.
Secondly, Vann argues that there has been “a common tendency to emphasize
White’s adaptation of Northrop Frye’s four plot-types, often to the exclusion of
his more radical view of the underlying tropes,”2 though Vann went on to say
that, as time passed, the interest moved in the opposite direction, so that now
the tropes are generally regarded as the heart of White’s philosophy of history.
Part of the explanation is that the tropes were far harder to relate to actual
historical writing than were Frye’s modes of emplotment—or those of argument
and of ideological implication, for that matter.
This is so since tropes such as metaphor, synecdoche, metonymy, and irony
will typically be found in sentence-like utterances; and it is not easy to see how
to relate them to (historical) texts taken in toto. We know what it means to say
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 49
that the utterance “John is a pig” is a metaphor; but what makes a (historical)
text metaphorical? You do not have in a (historical) text an obvious counterpart
to the semantic tension or deviance typical of metaphorical utterances such
as “John is a pig” and requiring us to think how to combine what we could
associate with John, on the one hand, and with pigs, on the other, in some
meaningful way. On the contrary, the historical text is ordinarily a long string
of statements, organized to relate to each other as smoothly and as naturally
as possible, and thus to minimize as much as possible any semantic friction.
For only this will guarantee the text’s coherence. Much the same can be said of
the other three tropes (synecdoche, metonymy, and irony). In all cases, tropes
begin by deliberately creating semantic friction in order to make clear that the
utterance in question should not be read as an assertion claiming propositional
truth for itself. Whatever “truth” the figural utterance conveys can only be estab-
lished on the condition that it be recognized as literally false.
Hence our perplexity about how the relation of the semantic friction of
metaphor to the semantic “smoothness” and continuity of the (historical) text
is to be reproduced by synecdoche, metonymy, and irony. All of the tropes
start with semantic friction, and all of the tropes then require us to make sense
somehow of the figural utterance. Hence, all of them raise this problem of how
to reconcile the semantic friction of figural language with the absence of friction
in, and the smoothness of, the (historical) text.
As far as I know, White never addressed this problem. Perhaps because there is
an obvious answer to it. Think, for example, of climbing a mountain; after you reach
the summit, you can contrast the start of your itinerary with its end—where there
may well be hundreds of yards between the former and the latter. But, next, you may
think of the itinerary itself—where you move from one step via the next, from the
beginning to the end, and where you gradually and almost imperceptibly make your
way to the top of the mountain. Having these two images in mind, one might say
that what figural utterances achieve at a single stroke (moving from the beginning of
your itinerary to its end) is achieved in (historical) texts only step by step; in figural
utterances you only become aware of the semantic journey you have travelled when
comparing not individual steps with their previous ones, but the very first with the
very last. Then you can maintain, first, that (contrary to appearances) historical
texts are semantically identical to figural utterances, such as metaphor, metonymy,
synecdoche, and irony—notwithstanding the fact that prima facie there seems to be
no semantic friction in historical texts. The semantic friction is truly there—though
we recognize it only if we contrast the beginning with the end. And, second, you
can maintain that there are always different ways to climb a mountain, e.g. from the
50 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
South, the North etc., and that this corresponds to how each of the four tropes might
achieve historical meaning in a way that is specific to itself.
The fact that all tropes announce themselves by means of semantic friction
could be used in support of the idea that there is a dimension of irony in all of
White’s tropes. This would explain—and justify—why White considers irony to
be, in some way or other, a “master-trope” that is superior to and more basic
than the other three. For in all tropes there is a dimension of denial, of denying
that what is said should be literally true. In all cases there is semantic friction,
urging us to deny or to negate the literal truth of an utterance. And this is,
of course, what we primarily associate with irony. So irony is what all tropes
have in common. Irony is what separates figural or tropological utterances
in general from their literal counterparts. Though, again, tropology makes us
aware of the fact that the denial—or negation—may take different forms. It is
the shortcoming, or naivety, of Aristotle’s law of the excluded middle to suggest
that there should be just one form of denial or negation—i.e. the one we would
primarily relate to irony. So denial can take different forms: there is irony, but
also metaphor, metonymy, and synecdoche as “variants of irony.” Put differently,
tropology requires that we recognize that there is not a vacuum between truth
and its denial but, instead, a continuum, which is best explored with the help of
tropology and the “variants of irony” thereof.
And if you wish to know more about these “variants of irony”—about how
they all achieve irony in their own inimitable way and about how each of them
finds its own way in the territory between truth and its denial—one need only
look at the (historical) text. For there, what is done step by step is what ironical,
metaphorical, synecdochical, and metonymical utterances do in one single
(but unanalyzable) stroke. It is the (historical) text that will enlighten us about
the finer details and differences between irony, metaphor, synecdoche, and
metonymy and, thus, also of all the variants of negation on the level of literal
language of which we have hitherto been unaware.
Speaking more generally, when analyzing the relationship between the
statement and the text, we always moved from the former to the latter.
Admittedly, this seems to be the most natural thing to do. But tropology, and
White’s successful application of tropology to the text, invites us to explore,
for a change, the opposite route as well and to ask ourselves how the text may
affect sentential meaning. This would add a new dimension to contemporary
philosophy of language.
Finally, this brings us to a third problem that was, according to Richard
Vann, occasioned by White’s tropology. Historical texts consist of statements
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 51
about the past, and if the historian has done his homework properly, each of
them expresses some (literal) truth about the past. But, as we saw a moment
ago, when you have such a very long string of literally true statements about
the past as is offered by historical texts, then you may find, after having moved
from one to the other, that you have defined your position to the past in a
way that is captured by one of the tropes. So what happens to truth when you
move from the level of the literally true individual statement about the past to
the historical text relating to the past in a tropological way? Is (literal) truth
lost then somewhere on that trajectory? Can (literal) truth be recaptured if we
closely analyze what happens on that trajectory, or does some wholly new, and
still unnoticed, kind of (tropological) truth arise in the course of that trajectory?
This is a difficult problem—all the more so if we try to deal with it within the
framework of White’s own philosophy of history. For it is one of the peculiarities
of White’s approach to the philosophy of history that he does not himself much
warm up to issues of historical truth and to the cognitivist dilemmas occasioned
by it. As Vann observes, White “has bracketed considerations of historical
knowledge, as he has bracketed treatments of referentiality.”3
It is not hard to explain why this kind of issue, traditionally at the center
of philosophy of history, was relegated to the background in White’s work.
Metahistory’s main message has been that the historical text should not be seen
as a transparent medium through which we can observe the past, as if we were
looking through a window to the landscape outside it. The historical text is not
something that we look through, but something we look at, in much the same
way that we always look at paintings and not through them, as if they were mere
transparent windows. It is true that both the historical text and paintings evoke
the illusion of looking at something lying beyond, or behind, the text or the
paintings themselves. This is the miracle of representation. So our real question
must be how the historical text may succeed in representing the past, in much
the same way that we do when we unproblematically grant paintings this
capacity. And this will compel us to investigate how the historical text, as such,
can generate historical meaning; again, much in the same way that paintings
generate pictorial meaning.
So if philosophical semantics traditionally investigates truth, reference,
and meaning, and if philosophy of history traditionally focuses on issues of
truth and reference, White reversed this by privileging meaning to truth and
reference. Thus a wholly new set of questions was put on the philosopher of
history’s agenda, and whatever the future of philosophy of history will look like,
it is simply inconceivable that these questions might be struck again from it. It is
52 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
unthinkable that we should ever return to the naivety with regard to the text that
was characteristic of pre-Whitean philosophy of history. In this way, Metahistory
can be seen as a contribution to our insight into the nature of historical writing
that will never be questioned again. And if this ever happened, we would surely
see it as a sign that we had returned to historiographical barbarism and that the
Middle Ages had returned in our discipline.
However, rearranging the field of forces between truth, reference, and
meaning in favor of meaning does not automatically imply that the other two,
then, should now lose all significance for a correct understanding of historical
writing. It is true that White himself was not much interested in the question
of how his revolution in the hierarchy between reference, truth, and meaning
might affect the (cognitivist) issues of the referentiality and truth claims of
historical writing. He even seemed to go so far as to imply that the question of
the cognitivist value of the tropes is basically misguided. Think, for example, of
his notorious claim that historical writing is “fictional.” The claim is undoubtedly
correct insofar as historical writing is something that is “made” and not “found”
by the historian. The same is true of scientific theories, since you will never
encounter these in reality itself, but only in the scientist’s treatises; and, as we all
know, this does not stand in the way of the scientist’s cognitivist pretensions. So
why should it be different with history? However, when speaking of the “fiction-
alism” of historical writing White also wished to claim that historical writing
is closer to fiction, i.e. to the novel, than to science—which certainly seems to
discourage a cognitivist approach to historical writing.
However, by no means does this does rob the question of its urgency! All
the more so, since White has often been criticized for suggesting that there are
no good (epistemological) reasons for preferring one representation of some
part of the past to some other, whereas one need only look at the review pages
of historical journals to recognize that historians are ordinarily very capable of
finding out what is weak and unconvincing in some historical representations
and what deserves approval in others. And the scope of historical rationality
is emphatically not restricted to the more elementary level of factual truth,
but also includes how the past is represented in all of the historical texts on,
say, the Industrial Revolution or the American Civil War. Hence, the level on
which White’s tropes are active and structure the historical text (as a whole).
Which raises the question as to what contribution to historical rationality can
be expected from White’s tropes.
Finally, it is true that philosophers of language and of science were rarely inter-
ested in synecdoche, metonymy, and irony. But metaphor has been intensively
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 53
discussed and its cognitive potentials widely recognized and explored since Max
Black’s influential essay on metaphor.4 The philosopher of science Mary Hesse
even reversed the whole traditional argument about metaphor by arguing not
that metaphor conveys literal truth but that there is a metaphorical dimension
to what at first sight seem to be true literal statements. In this way metaphor
can be said to take over what used to be seen as the literal statement’s unique
prerogative, namely the capacity to express propositional truth. Metaphor
then penetrates right into the cognitive heart of the sciences themselves. So
if metaphor can be argued to be so central in the acquisition of scientific
knowledge, why would we then recoil from attributing to metaphor (and to the
tropes generally) a cognitive faculty in our effort to represent and understand
the past?
that is somehow more, or “deeper,” than knowledge: the former is what we may
achieve with the help of the structuralist grid, but there is a superior kind of
knowledge, reminiscent of the effort to grasp the Kantian noumenon, which
may be our paradoxical reward for sinning against the structuralist grid. Let us
call this historical insight.
Now, White’s tropology accounts for all of this. And it does so by means
of the trope of irony. As White himself emphasizes, the trope of irony
stands a bit apart from the other three. It is, as he says, a kind of “master-
trope,” for it continuously reminds us of the provisional character of all
historical knowledge. Elsewhere White most perceptively characterizes irony
as a “metatrope”; hence, a trope expressing a message about the other three,
namely that the historical knowledge produced under their aegis will always
be provisional and always in need of correction. Or, rather, the past as given
to us by the other three tropes is always a merely phenomenal past, the past as
it appears to us, and whose rights must give way immediately to the noumenal
past, to the past “as such.”
The trope of irony is meant to make us aware of this. But for a proper under-
standing of White’s intentions a few comments must be added. To begin with,
when saying that irony makes us aware that historical knowledge is always in
need of correction, White does not invite us to liken the feats of irony to Karl
Popper’s “trial and error,” or to his model of “conjecture and refutation.” This is,
indeed, how science grows—but without ever leaving the domain of the strictly
phenomenal. And this surely has its counterpart in historical writing: historians
often correct each other, but without questioning the most basic assumptions of
their approach to the past. However, the historians that White is interested in
attack precisely these most basic assumptions. All our most basic assumptions
about how we relate to the past are then at stake. And such a total challenge to
accepted historical knowledge can only happen in the name of the past itself, of
the “quasi-noumenal” past.
Next, we should not radically exclude or separate irony from metaphor,
synecdoche, and metonymy, as if there were a time for metaphor, one for
synecdoche, one for metonymy, and then the night arrives where irony, like
the Penelope of historical writing, undoes what had been achieved by the other
three. For irony, being a metatrope, is at work all of the time, as we might have
expected already, because each trope—metaphor, synecdoche, and metonymy,
no less than irony itself—contains in itself a moment of denial, namely, the
denial of a literal truth. This is the metatropological insight conveyed by irony
(which we discussed already in the previous section).
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 55
This also is where irony must remind us of Friedrich von Schlegel’s notion of
“romantic irony,” best characterized as the “deferral” of all trust in final truths about
the world. It need not surprise us, therefore, that Jacob Burckhardt was White’s
crown-witness for the case of irony. For Burckhardt succeeded in his provocative
effort to openly incorporate irony in his writings, by eliminating all emphasis from
his expositions of the past. Normally the statement “p” is said to be equivalent to
the statement “p is true.” Burckhardt’s text, however, reminds us of someone saying
“p” but without wishing to commit himself to “p is true.” This comes close to what
Schlegel had in mind with his romantic irony. Romantic irony is dialectical, but it
is essentially different from Hegel’s dialectics. For Hegel, dialectics is the process
that carries you more or less automatically from one stage to the next. But in
romantic irony, the dialectical process is suspended, in the sense that the shift
from one stage to the next is denied to you. It is as if, while watching a movie, the
movie suddenly stops so that you get stuck with one image only. Of course such a
thing is possible only with movies and not with reality itself—reality always moves
on and on. This is why romantic irony provoked Hegel’s ire. He rightly suspected
romantic irony to be an ironization of his dialectical understanding of the past, by
particularizing it into ever smaller bits that gradually fade out of existence and by
thus suggesting that the most supreme wisdom is that there is no wisdom.
As White puts it, commenting on Burckhardt:
Burckhardt’s manner of representing the Renaissance was that of the
connoisseur beholding a heap of fragments assembled from an archaeological
dig, the context of which he divines “by analogy” from the past. But the form
of the context can only be pointed to, not specified. It is like those “things in
themselves” which Kant maintained we must postulate in order to account for
our science, but about which we cannot say anything. The voice with which
Burckhardt addressed his audience was that of the Ironist, the possessor of a
higher, sadder wisdom than the audience itself possessed. He viewed his object
of study, the historical field, Ironically, as a field whose meaning is elusive,
unspecifiable, perceivable only to the refined intelligence, too subtle to be taken
by storm and too sublime to be ignored.5
So, indeed, irony has its origins in Burckhardt’s awareness of the past as a quasi-
Kantian “thing in itself,” and his genius was to be able to express this awareness
in his text on the Renaissance. For that is certainly not an easy thing to do (as
White’s brilliant exposition of Burckhardt amply demonstrates). The quote is
also of interest, since White explicitly refers here to the sublime in a way that
seems to anticipate his later and much-discussed essay on the historical sublime,
in which he writes the following:
56 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Here, too, the sublime and sublime meaning are presented as the “ironic” result
of the apperception of history’s intrinsic meaninglessness. Here, too, the pivot
on which White’s argument turns is the contrast between history as science (the
counterpart of Kantian beauty) and the encounter with history in its quasi-
noumenal manifestation (the counterpart to the Kantian sublime).
In sum, when White discusses irony he does not have in mind its more
pedestrian variant such as “Bush’s war on Iraq was a stroke of political genius,”
where clearly the opposite of the utterance’s literal meaning is meant. This
variant of irony never leaves the domain of meaning. White’s irony, however,
always implies a moment of the mirroring of meaning in the meaninglessness
of a (past) reality’s quasi-noumenal manifestation. Perhaps I may add that I feel
the greatest sympathy for White’s proposal.7 In fact, when writing some time
ago a book on sublime historical experience, I had something similar in mind. I
therefore consider White’s conceptualization of irony and the historical sublime
to be one of the most fascinating aspects of his oeuvre.
The only comment I would have, though, is that the term “paradox” would
probably have been more appropriate here than “irony.” Surely, paradox and
irony have much in common, so in the end this is certainly a mere debate about
terminology. Nevertheless, this openness can also be attributed to paradox,
to the aforementioned quasi-noumenal past, whereas irony must necessarily
remain blind to it, since it never requires us to leave the domain of linguistic
meaning. Paradox is ordinarily defined as a statement that the language in
which it is stated prevents us from recognizing as true, and yet we must recognize
it to be true if we look at the facts. Think of Bernard de Mandeville’s paradox that
private vices are public virtues: all that we associate with vices and virtues—
hence what these concepts mean to us!—militates against this equalization. And
yet (supposing Mandeville to be right about this) reality can be said to confirm
the truth of this statement.
This, then, is the essence of paradox: our trust in language and in its capacity
to subject reality to our aims and purposes is suddenly tripped up. A hole
reveals itself in the complex and infinitely fine mesh-work that language has
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 57
woven around all of reality and through which we then may momentarily
perceive naked reality itself and without the concealing linguistic clothes
in which it normally presents itself to us. All the efforts (and successes!) of
language to “domesticate” reality and to conform to the well-bred etiquette of
language are suddenly and momentarily found to be glaringly inadequate and
helpless—so that we have to encounter reality without the shock-absorbers
of language. The encounter is therefore inevitably painful—and the technical
term of the sublime is meant to express exactly this. In this way, the notion of
paradox certainly comes closer to White’s relevant intentions than does irony.
Or, to put it in words close to White’s own intentions, paradox makes us aware
that the revelations of historical Truth and the deepest insights are to be found
in the holes and fissures between the categories of the historical understanding,
as exemplified by the structuralist grid. So, perhaps, the notion of paradox better
captures what White had in mind than that of irony. But, again, this is a matter
of mere terminological detail. And I do wholly agree with White with regard to
the substance of the issue and with what he expects from irony.
At the same time, however, this is also what would effectively discredit irony
(and paradox) as tropes furthering a strictly cognitivist account of historical
understanding. As a “metatrope,” irony deliberately transcends the effort to
achieve an understanding of the past that satisfies cognitivist requirements.
So if we ask ourselves the question of the cognitivist dimensions of Whitean
tropology, we shall have to put irony aside. The “beauty” of the scientific
approach to the past requires us to avoid the sublimity of irony (and paradox),
even though the two belong together like day and night—and I leave it to the
reader to decide which corresponds to which.
This leaves us thus with metonymy, synecdoche, and metaphor.
In 1525 a medal was struck to commemorate the victory at Pavia of the German
Emperor Charles V over King Francis I of France in that same year.8 On this
medal, we see a crowned cock in the claws of a crowned eagle, and around this
battle of the birds it says: “Gallus succumbit aquilae, anno 1525” (The cock
succumbs to the eagle, in the year 1525).
To begin with, there is a referential obscurity here: do the words “gallus” and
“aquila” refer to France and Germany, or to their respective monarchs? The fact
that both the cock and the eagle are crowned seems to suggest that the words
58 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
were meant to stand for the two monarchs actually wearing these crowns. On
the other hand, it seems odd to depict Francis I as a cock (though his reputation
as a womanizer would give some support to the idea to do so) and Charles V as
an eagle. It is hard to see what message one might wish to convey by presenting
them in this way. So probably we had best take the words “gallus” and “aquila” as
standing for France and Germany respectively—all the more so since the French
cock and the German eagle were often used to refer to France and Germany,
regardless of who their monarchs happened to be.
Self-evidently, there is a great deal of mere coincidence and arbitrariness
here, even though a historical explanation can be given of why France was
often represented by a cock and Germany by an eagle.9 This also is why we
would say that France is represented by, rather than as, a cock (and the same
would be true of the German eagle). “Representing as” is to be distinguished
from “representing by”; when you represent A “as B” you wish to suggest that B
intimates some important truth about A, whereas in the case of “representing
by” the link between A and B is purely coincidental. And it was a matter of pure
linguistic coincidence that the Latin word “gallus” could mean both “cock” and
“an inhabitant of Gallia” (i.e. France). This is what Napoleon failed to recognize
when rejecting the proposal made by a commission of councilors of state to use
the cock as the nation’s emblem. Napoleon pointedly objected that “the cockerel
has no strength; in no way it can stand as the image of an Empire such a France.”
So, instead, he chose the (German) eagle, while, at roughly the same time, the
Austrian Emperor Francis I also imported the German eagle from Germany
into Austria.
Using words like “cock” or “eagle” to stand for France or Germany respec-
tively resembles the arbitrariness of proper names; for is it not a matter of pure
coincidence that you have the name you happen to have? What difference
would it make to you if your parents had decided to call you “William” instead
of “John”? Or think of Shakespeare’s “What’s in a name? A rose if called by
any other name would smell as sweet.” However, there may well be something
more to this that we must take into account when we recall Gottlob Frege’s
contrast between 1) “Phosphorus is identical with Hesperus” and 2) “Hesperus
is identical with Hesperus.” Both statements are true, but 1) is empirically true,
whereas 2) is a logical truth. The asymmetry can only be explained, says Frege,
if we assume (against what John Stuart Mill and, for that matter, common
sense, would make us believe) that proper names not only refer, but also have a
meaning. For example: “Phosphorus” also means the star you see in the morning
at some place in the sky, whereas “Hesperus” also means a star in the evening
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 59
sky (in both cases Venus). For if “Phosphorus” and “Hesperus” had no such
meaning and possessed only the capacity to refer (i.e. to the planet Venus),
statement 1) would be just as much a logical truth as 2). Thus there would be no
difference between the two of them. Only because these two proper names each
have a meaning of their own can 1) express an empirical truth of some minor
(astronomical) interest.
But perhaps this does have a certain basis in how we do intuitively think
about proper names. I have in mind here the fact that in daily life the use of our
own proper name leaves us indifferent, whereas when concentrating intensly
on one’s own proper name, when we start thinking “I am … (fill in your own
proper name),” an odd feeling of vertigo tends to take over that is suggestive of
our proper name throwing us into the unfathomable depth of the person we are.
Our proper name then becomes suffused with meaning. And this seems to be
in agreement with Frege’s account of proper names rather than that of common
sense (and Mill).
The phenomenon deserves our interest, since something similar also happens
with proper names for collective entities, such as institutions, organizations,
and, above all, nations. We may use the proper names Germany, France, or
America disinterestedly and where these proper names have no other function
than to refer to a certain nation. But we may also use them in contexts such as
“Deutschland, Deutschland über alles,” “la gloire de la France” or “God bless
America,” and then these proper names also get suffused with nationalist or
even chauvinist meaning. Much the same will be true of French “cocks,” British
“lions,” or American “eagles.” The mere sight of these cocks, lions, and eagles
may make the heart of Frenchmen, Englishmen, and Americans leap for joy
or instill fear and hatred in the minds of the victims of their past and present
actions outside their borders. The tendency of the relevant proper names and
the way nations are symbolized to have this effect on us has been an autonomous
historical factor of great historical significance during the past two centuries. In
sum, Frege’s logical point goes a long way to explain why we rarely experience
proper names as wholly arbitrary sounds merely standing for what is designated
by them and why hosts of pleasant or sinister meanings tend to cluster around
or cling to them.
Put differently, it takes quite an effort to keep these meanings at bay and to
assure that proper names remain semantically “clean.” Doing so goes against
our nature and our natural inclinations and, if Frege is right, even against the
nature of signs themselves. Reference and meaning naturally go hand in hand.
All this can be reformulated in terms of the distinction between metaphor and
60 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
metonymy. The French cock, the British lion, etc., can all be said to function like
metaphors. There is semantic friction, as is the case with metaphor, for France is
not a cock and England not a lion. But these words invite us to project what we
associate with cocks and lions onto France and England, just as the metaphor
“John is a pig” invites us to project piggishness on John.
However, there are contexts where getting rid of these associations is
absolutely necessary. Think of mathematics. Thus David Hilbert (1862–1943)
had argued that the symbols and primary terms used by mathematicians should
have no meanings other than those attributed to them in the axioms pertaining
to them. For example, from concepts like points, lines, and planes we must
remove all that we ordinarily associate with these words, so that we are left only
with what is said concerning their use in the axioms of Euclidian or Riemannian
geometry. A point, line, or plane can then just be anything, be a model of them,
as that term is used in mathematics and the sciences, if it satisfies what is said
about them in the relevant axioms. So reality can then be a model of calculus,
and not the reverse, as the notion of model is ordinarily understood. Ordinarily
the model is said to be a model of something existing in reality—think of the
models one builds of actual aeroplanes in order to find out about their aerody-
namic properties in wind tunnels. Here models are simulations of reality. But
in mathematics and in the sciences it is exactly the other way round: there you
have, first, the abstract calculus and you can then inquire, next, what aspects of
reality can be explained in terms of it. The relevant aspects of reality are then
said by the mathematician and the scientist to be a “model” of the calculus.
This comes close to White’s understanding of the trope of metonymy. Think
of how White defines metonymy:
So you have certain phenomena (in reality), and the relationship between
the symbol naming them and these phenomena is purely “functional.” The
meaning of these symbols is then not defined by their referential ties, but by
how they function in an abstract system or calculus. And in order to get to that
metonymical meaning of these symbols we must wipe them clean, so to speak,
from all associational meaning that we might project on them. This, then, is
where metonymy is the very opposite of metaphor. For whereas metaphor
always invites us to take best advantage of all the associations we happen to
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 61
have (rightly or wrongly) with certain words, metonymy requires us to avoid all
such associations. This is precisely why we must agree with White when arguing
that metonymy is the trope having an innate affinity with the sciences, for the
sciences can only achieve their impressive results when they carefully avoid the
contamination of the concepts used in scientific theory with meanings origi-
nating outside that theory.
As White himself emphasizes, socio-scientific historical writing best
exemplifies the metonymical approach to history. For then the facts of the past
are made sense of by explaining them with the help of socio-scientific laws and
theories that have been established on the basis of facts quite different from
the historical facts they are applied to. Think of using John Maynard Keynes’s
General Theory of 1936 for explaining the economic growth of eighteenth-
century England. Observe that in this instance White is playing a nice trick on
his socio-scientific opponents. Metonymy makes it clear that tropology is not in
the least opposed to the socio-scientific approach to history, as the advocates of
that approach always complain. Metonymy and the scientific (or, rather, scien-
tistic) approach to history is certainly not irreconcilable with White’s tropology.
In fact, it is just one of the options the historian has in his effort to make sense
of the past.
At the same time, however, this compels us to remove metonymy, too, from
the list of tropes to be studied for their cognitive value. For, as the foregoing
makes clear, all that is of cognitive interest only takes place after one has decided
to make use of that trope. But the trope itself remains outside of any effort to
make sense of the world. Its role is restricted to the choice of a certain method
of making sense of the world. But it could never itself be part of that method,
just as the decision to play a game of chess is not part of the game itself.
So that leaves us with synecdoche and metaphor. Unlike irony (or paradox),
synecdoche and metaphor do have cognitivist aspirations and, unlike metonymy,
they are undoubtedly part of the cognitive machinery for the acquisition of
historical knowledge and understanding. So let us now have a closer look at
these.
With regard to the cognitivist pretentions of synecdoche, it will be sufficient
to recognize how close it comes to what the so-called “Ideen-Lehre,” the doctrine
of the “historical ideas,” under whose banner historicists such as Leopold von
62 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Ranke and Wilhelm von Humboldt hoped to explore and map the past. Ranke’s
and Humboldt’s “historical ideas” are best compared to the Aristotelian notion
of entelechy. Entelechy is a principle of development inherent in all things of
nature. And we should recall that the Greek word for nature is phusis, derived
from the verb phuein meaning “to grow” (part of Aristotle’s metaphysics has its
origin in this etymological fact). Thus the suggestion is that the development,
growth, or evolution of all things in nature is determined by an entelechy
inherent in them—in the way that there is an entelechy in an acorn making it
grow into a huge and mighty oak. So if we wish to explain the miracle of a puny
acorn developing into an oak in the course of time, we will have to discover
that entelechy. This is more or less how we should conceive of Ranke’s and
Humboldt’s “historical ideas.” And then the main insight is that it is the histo-
rian’s task to discover a nation’s, a people’s, or a civilization’s “historical idea.” If
the historian has got hold of that, this will enable him to explain the history of
that nation, people, or civilization.
We have all been taught to reject this as nineteenth-century metaphysical
rubbish—if not worse. As opposed to this almost unanimously shared communis
opinio, I see instead the beginning of all wisdom about historical writing;
however, I would emphasize that it is “the beginning” and certainly not “the last
word”—for it requires a great deal of logical refinement to demonstrate where
the historicists were basically right and where they irreparably erred.
Self-evidently, this is not the appropriate place for addressing that issue. So
I restrict myself to recalling the close agreement of the historicist’s doctrine
of the historical idea with the way in which almost every historian conceives
of what historical writing is all about. Will every historian not express his
enthusiastic and spontaneous assent with the view that it is the historian’s
task to discover “the essence” of the past and that he has explained the past
in the way we expect this from him when he has given a convincing account
of this “essence”? Now, replace “essence” by “historical idea,” and then you
have the message that Ranke and Humboldt wished to convey to us. If we
translate Ranke’s doctrine of the historical idea from a theory about historical
phenomena into a theory of historical writing (i.e. into an exhortation to the
historian to present in his text what he considers to be the essence of the past),
we shall have a theory that seamlessly agrees with how historians conceive of
their practice.11
As White made clear in the introduction to Metahistory, synecdoche is the
trope that will give us the essence of things. The synecdoche “he is all heart”
reduces the immense complexity of someone’s personality to that part of it
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 63
problem. For if both synecdoche and metaphor claim to give us the “essence”
of part of the past, they do so in different ways. For, as we have seen in the case
of synecdoche, we get to that essence by getting hold of something that is part
of the object of historical understanding itself—just as the heart is part of an
organism; whereas metaphor finds the essence by having recourse to something
outside the object of understanding—just as hearts and pumps, or minds and
computers, are different things, and are not parts of one and the same kind of
thing. And yet, both synecdoche and metaphor have been found to capture
adequately how historical understanding comes into being and what we should
recognize as its cognitive pivot point. So we may now begin to worry whether
there is, perhaps, something ineradicably schizophrenic about historical under-
standing and whether we have inadvertently hit here upon one of the intrinsic
weaknesses of all historical writing.
However, there is no reason to despair about historical writing and its disci-
plinary coherence and solidity, for the problem is not hard to solve. Ordinarily
metaphor is seen as a purely linguistic phenomenon. Take a metaphor like
“the heart is a pump,” which is a falsehood if taken literally, since the heart is
not a pump. So the metaphor invites us to manipulate the literal meanings of
the words “heart” and “pump” in such a way that some illuminating insight
emerges. But this is a play with meanings and firmly keeps us within the domain
of language—though, admittedly, the ultimate purpose of this interplay of
meaning is a better understanding of the world. But the world itself is not an
ingredient in the production of metaphorical meaning.
But now consider the claim that a historical text is an invitation to see a
certain part of the past in terms of that text. That preserves the basic form of
metaphor; hence the form of “see A as if it were B” is the form of the statement
“see the heart as if it were a pump.” However, in this case, A stands for a part of
the past, for the world itself, whereas B stands for the historical text. In that case,
we shall have pulled the world itself, or part of past reality itself, into metaphor.
Metaphor, then, is no longer an interplay of mere meanings but an interplay
between language and the world. And in this interplay, metaphor then singles
out a certain part or aspect of the past that we should consider to be its essence,
insofar as this essence is not something outside what it is the essence of, but part
of it.
Now, obviously, this is what synecdoche does. Think of White’s own example:
“he is all heart”; here someone’s “essence” is situated in what is part of him, i.e.
his heart. So if metaphor is redefined as it was above—a redefinition of metaphor
that is wholly in agreement with the practice of historical writing—metaphor
A Plea for a Cognitivist Approach to White’s Tropology 65
and synecdoche can be reconciled with each other and be shown to be indis-
cernible from the perspective of the practice of historical writing itself.
Conclusion
Finally, one may ask oneself what is the point of theoretical speculations such as
these. Let me put it this way. Traditional cognitivist and epistemological analysis
somehow resembles a young man who spoils his love-affair with a girl by making
his intentions too obviously clear. Traditional epistemology is too much focused
on its purpose—the definition of Truth—to remain open to how knowledge
may arise out of other endeavors. But knowledge is no less a work of art than
art itself. Hence the enveloping movements of tropology may yield unexpected
insights—as is the case here, when discussing how Whitean tropology may shed
some new light on the cognitivist aspects of historical writing.
In historical writing we have to pass through tropology in order to achieve
historical truth; and this is how we should conceive of the cognitive faculties of
the tropological or figural use of language in historical writing.
3
Introduction
It must have been decades ago, and regretfully, I do not remember the details.
In a daily newspaper that was rarely interested in academic pursuits, I read
a brief article stating that a National Endowment for the Humanities-funded
project conducted by an interdisciplinary team of researchers had found the
answer to the question: “Was Joan of Arc really a woman?” Triumphantly—
and predictably—the answer was “no.” She must have been a man disguised
as a woman disguised as a man… I never heard about the project again, never
mustered the interest to look into it. Perhaps it was only a dream. What stayed
with me from that fleeting moment was the flabbergasting question itself.
Who would wish to spend time, energy, intelligence, and money on finding
out whether the one woman hero of Western history was “really”—meaning
what, exactly?—female? For someone like myself, who always worries about
the relevance of my research questions, this was a shocking little piece of
press. Rather than the answer, it was the question (both in its futility and the
confusion of female and woman) that has always stayed with me as a caricature
of historical inquiry, as well as of the funding agencies that decide on the fate of
academic projects. Not a caricature by which I would judge that discipline, of
course, but an example of excess in its obsession with “truth.”
“Truth” is the name of the pursuit of scholarship and science, and it epito-
mizes in particular the discipline of history. When, in 1973, Hayden White’s
Metahistory appeared, I was working exclusively in literary theory and, with my
structuralist bent, not too versed in considerations of history. What I studied
was the imagination; a richer field I could not imagine. But we literary theorists
68 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
were somewhat embattled by those who did not believe that the imagination
had anything to do with reality and could therefore not be subjected to the test
of “truth.” I countered that the imagination is part of reality, even if the worlds
it produces may not exist.
I remember vividly how colleagues came into the building waving this
new miracle book. For those of us on the far side of the historical vs. struc-
tural approaches, the appearance of this spectacular book was, indeed, a bit
of a miracle. It vindicated our supposition that those colleagues who contra-
dicted everything we said about literature with the injunction “Historicize!
Historicize!” and scolded us for “formalism,” and, worse, “interpretation,”
were proven wrong. They were just blind to their own interpretative and
formal choices. The word “imagination” in the subtitle, yoked to the qualifier
“historical,” made our case.
Those were days of fierce polemics, when we had not yet learned to be
nuanced and to refuse to be locked up in binary oppositions. You either did
history, or you were “a-historical” and, hence, dismissed. My sense of “form”—of
the aesthetic side of the artifacts I studied, the influence of form on meaning—
was too strong to compromise, and I happily called myself a “formalist.” When
I started to work on visual art and realized that, simultaneously with White’s
“formal,” indeed, literary turn in historiography, the contextual turn was
beginning to rage in art history, and there “formalism” rapidly became a fresh
taboo.
And then, here was a book about the historical imagination—something that
seemed almost inconceivable by definition. This book told us that historians
too adopt a form, interpreting their alleged “data” after first selecting these
according to principles of form. As Metahistory bluntly stated on one of its
first pages: “My method, in short, is formalist”1—something that I would never
have dared say out loud. At the time—and I see this as a historical moment—to
adopt a formalist methodology was to endorse a certain universalism of forms.
Indeed, one of the constructive critics, Ernst Van Alphen, criticized White on
that very point: he did not appear to historicize his own categories of analysis.2
For me, this was not so clear. Not that Van Alphen was wrong in arguing
that White did not historicize his categories. But I believed then, and still
believe, that historicization is both possible and beside the primary point.
Universalizing formalism has never been the only possible alternative to what
we, alleged formalists, sometimes labeled a bit easily as “naïve historicism.” I did
not see White as stepping over from one side of the picket fence to the other.
For me, the book that made White famous across the disciplines overnight
Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians 69
would even go so far as to say that over-categorization helps rather than hinders
a liberation from taxonomy’s straitjacket, that it is the over-categorization that
allows for a bold amount of messiness in the analyses. This is manifest in appli-
cations of Peirce’s categories.6
Thus, Peirce’s threesomes only work if one deploys them to map overlaps and
crossings. To cite a well-known example: the sign that indicates the exit of, for
instance, a train station pertains to the symbolic, indexical, and iconic grounds
all at once. The interrupted square iconically represents the exit; the arrow
indicates it by continuity, and the convention by which we recognize this sign
makes it readable. The brilliant philosopher knew very well that not everything
in the universe or the human mind can be divided into three possibilities—on
the contrary. In my view, he made them threesomes for reasons other than a
systemic (over-)drive. If I may speculate by taking the effect for the cause, he did
so, firstly, to deliver us from the domination of binary opposition; secondly, to
establish a dynamic, a temporal element that later even the brilliant semiotician
Umberto Eco was not able to build into his revised Peircean theory; and thirdly,
to make it possible, indeed indispensable, to keep moving from one point of
the triangles to another, none of them ever being satisfactory on its own as a
label that would characterize a single phenomenon. In short, one system was
mobilized to beat another, so that in the end, users of his theory were given tools
to make up their own combinatoire.
For me, White’s book had a similar effect. His categories are so clearly
readerly devices, hints for establishing contexts and connections, rather than
rigid grids, that I would venture to say that his “system” of foursomes, in its
invitation to disobey it, virtually contains its own historicization, but one that
is established in the present. The casual language in which he introduces these
foursomes already indicates this.7 And, even when he is on his best academic
behavior and leaves his tongue out of his cheek, his discourse cannot be locked
up in an either/or (formalist or historicist) camp.
In the sentence right before the one referred to above, White characterizes
historical writing as follows: “a verbal structure in the form of a narrative prose
discourse that purports to be a model, or icon, of past structures and processes
in the interest of explaining what they were by representing them.”8 In the first
half of the description, formalist terms abound: a historical work is a (verbal)
structure, in a particular form, espousing a semiotic mode—narrative—and
a discourse that, as we have learned from Michel Foucault, produces what
it analyzes; namely, a model to be followed or an icon to keep the work
protected from change. In the second half, however, we encounter the terms
Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians 71
that are contested at the other side of the formalism/historicism divide. The
structures are now in the past, even if they remain structures and, hence, are
“contaminated” by the formalism of the first half. The term “interest” stipulates
a goal-orientedness that, after Habermas,9 we cannot take lightly either. If this is
formalism, then there is no opposite easily captured.10
In this, White remains abreast of those who come after him. Fellow historiog-
raphers Hans Kellner and Frank Ankersmit—co-editors, with Ewa Dománska,
of a recent volume devoted to White’s influence11—characterized Metahistory
as debunking the traditional conception of history. Kellner saw it as an
attempt to “challenge the ideology of truth.”12 Ankersmit called it “postmod-
ernist.”13 Both of these responses remain—given the academic climate at the
time, understandably—bound to a binary opposition in which “truth” is one
thing, and form, or relativism, another. It almost seems a question of personal
preference. Ankersmit’s later book on historical experience explicitly makes this
an acceptable choice for a historian.14
Detractors and, as the recent volume mentioned above testifies, admirers
alike have kept their loyalty to the pact of binary opposition, with truth on one
side, and myth (Stephen Bann), language (David Harlan), narrative (Nancy
Partner), or rhetoric (Allan Megill) on the other, even if they admire and
approve of the mix. Yet, all these terms are complicated in White’s hands. Myth,
in White’s vision, becomes “remythification”;15 language becomes poetic or “a
verbal structure”;16 narrative, story and “emplotment”;17 and rhetoric, signs.18
None of these alternative terms can be opposed to truth. Instead, as some of
White’s articles demonstrate, the problem is binary opposition itself.
Although he does not give much explicit attention to it in his groundbreaking
book Metahistory, binary opposition is what White’s theory undermines; not
“truth” in whatever sense one wishes to impute to that notion. Indeed, in
the article “The Forms of Wildness: Archaeology of an Idea,” he unpacks
in detail the effects of binarization. In the same move, he demonstrates the
relevance of questioning a form of thought that may well be the most universal
structure in the mind. He does this by showing, through the deployment of an
eminently useful rhetorical concept, that the idea of “the wild man” serves as
an “ostentatious self-definition by negation” throughout history.19 That concept,
or as he calls it, “device,” is a tool for groups of humans, bound together by
nationality, citizenship, or other collective identities, to assert who they are
without having to bother to come up with contestable descriptions. Even the
rejected other needs no definition; all it takes is to point at him or her, and
assert: “I am not like that.”20
72 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
truth and the relative merit of the discourses he examines as conveyors of truth,
he leaves it and the desirability of its pursuit intact. The opponent his approach
targets, if any, I contend, is binary opposition itself, and this is also the thrust of
Ana Torfs’s artwork that engages with Joan of Arc. That the contested historical/
mythical figure of Joan of Arc is at the heart of that work is no coincidence. Like
White, Torfs declines to invest in decisions about truth and falsehood, but rather
thematizes them, probing the difficulty of access to truth and exploring ways of
enabling that access. Like White, Torfs has not chosen truth or falsehood as
her object of examination, but the cruelty and, more generally, the beside-
the-pointedness of classical ways of getting at the truth. These include torture,
intimidation, insistent repetition, and other forms of extortion that prove that
truth is, precisely, what is not being pursued.
manner. This refusal of both opposition and unity is suggested by the hyphen
that connects the two elements. On closer inspection there seems to be an
imaginary hyphen that connects the elements within each pair, as well as the
pairs to one another. More than in the content of the words, what matters lies in
that specific kind of duality, as well as in the connection. Of these potential but
not actualized oppositions, the primary one is lying, as in fiction, accompanied
by false, as in untrue, deceptive. But fiction cannot lie. Then, there are words and
images, sound and vision, space and time, black and white, light and darkness,
surface and depth, history, with all its mentir-faux, and the present.23
In the current thought climate, one would expect the pairs to be deconstruc-
tions of the oppositions they reference. But this is not the case either. Rather
than deconstructing each other, the elements of each of these pairs begin a
composition together. Take history and the present—not as history versus the
present, but rather as history in the present. The messiness of that truth about
history—its “presence” in the present makes a bird’s eye view of it impossible—
is overdetermined by another messiness. The story of which Du mentir-faux
presents a glimpse is historical as well as mythical: a reality no longer acces-
sible, and a fiction we must believe in. It is part of the history of violence and its
complexities, of which the character of Joan of Arc is one of the most intriguing
examples. The question of gender is crucial to understanding this particular
kind of violence, in which the State and its representatives, the notables, were
invested in determining the truth of Joan’s obedience to their laws of gender.
Whether Joan was a woman or a man was less important than the fact that she
went around performing her revolutionary militantism as a woman dressed as
a man.
The question of medium is related to (hence, neither opposed nor separated
from) it. Not only was Joan’s gender, in a way, a medium unto itself, since her
dressing up as a man was one of the reasons put forward for sentencing her to
death at the stake, but also Torfs’s work is part of the history of the medium
of photography, into which it inserts itself on different levels. This medium
promises access to reality and hence, to reliable documents of history. Once we
see the past not as the opposite but as a companion of the present, we realize
that the present is characterized by its own incidences of violence and its own
disbelief in and disregard of women’s voices.
The pair of history and the present also casts its light, or shadow, on the work
itself. The present of contemporary art is, as Torfs’s work tells us, entangled in
its own history. This insight underlies the deployment of black-and-white still
photography in an age of the moving image and of color photography. Reverting
76 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Instead, the artist makes a new work, for which the raw material is a set of
historical streams, such as misogyny, photography, violence, and grief.
Due to its forceful, implicit, multiple arguments, as much as its formal
beauty, Ana Torfs’s Du mentir-faux remains, for me, one of the most gripping
and meaningful works of contemporary art. On a large projection surface of at
least four and a half by three meters, portraits of a single woman appear and
disappear—another one of those intricate pairs. The timer gives the image, and
takes it away.28 Disappearance makes us grateful for appearance; appreciative
of the time allotted to seeing, in a robust form of montage. In a twenty-minute
loop, the length of each slide’s presence varies between seven and fifteen
seconds, so that neither haste nor visual laziness compelled by routine can enter.
The historical device of the slide show allows this work to be just as much time-
based as it is space-based. The brief periods of silence and darkness between
images are interrupted by the click of the slide falling into the carousel. With
each falling slide, silence retrospectively becomes a form of sound, an effect that
permeates the entire work.
More intertwined dualities creep in, further defeating binary thinking.
What silence does to sound, white does to color—even if, strictly speaking,
white consists of all colors. The images are so similar in light, composition,
and distance that one is irresistibly drawn to take in the subtleties of the hues
Photography as history
All these defeated dichotomies join forces when we consider photography itself.
Photography, itself a medium of mentir-faux, allows the artist to create a fiction
that lies all the more forcefully as we are compelled to suspend our disbelief. As
photography proves for us, this woman is alive in the present. But the medium
did not exist at the historical time she invokes. So, even if this woman is real,
the figure she represents is not. Photographing the fifteenth-century figure of
Joan of Arc is a foolproof method of declaring her fictional. What is more—
something that I would refrain from even mentioning if it were not so directly
relevant for this discussion—like the figure she represents, this woman was
seriously ill at the time these photographs were taken, and she is no longer alive
today. Like Joan, she was aware of her imminent death. This makes the issue of
representation and the confused realities dealt with here even more troubling.
Also, visually, qua image, she is just out of reach, not only in terms of
distance, but also as per her own volition. The woman in the photographs never
confronts us; her eyes are averted even when the image is almost, but not quite,
Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians 79
frontal. In each set of photographs, the relations between face and picture plane
vary slightly, visible only through tiny shifts in the light as time glides through
the day. Throughout the cycle of the installation, it is as if she turns slowly, from
gazing to the left in the beginning, to half-right toward the end, always in the
direction of the light. In all these portraits, she is engrossed in a mood that we
can almost grasp, but not quite. It is tempting to say that the images express
grief; as if to sustain that claim, a tear sometimes appears on her face as the
images are screened.30
But “express” is the wrong word, and that is where the trouble begins. We
cannot “read” her anguish. We can only surmise it on the basis of that intricate
combination of an image and a face, a history and a myth, that constitutes the
imagination. There is no exact match between the two-dimensional image and
the three-dimensional face. The gap of visual imagination stubbornly remains,
even if both the medium of photography and the slow pace of her appearances
conspire to make the figure believable. The photographs’ high visual quality
surrenders the grain of the surface, easily called “skin.” But it is as if the skin
of the face and the surface of the image were trading places, so that we cannot
distinguish them from each other. The white of the skin of the photograph
becomes the surface of the face. The woman’s face withholds the nature of her
80 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
grief, hence, the (historical?) cause of it. The tears that appear so sparingly are
symptoms of something to which we have no access.31
Just like the story of Joan of Arc, often taken as the story of a heroic and
strong-faithed young woman, what I mentioned above about the woman posing
in the photographs might easily entice a sentimentalist view of the work. Not
only is such an appeal rigorously avoided, but I even speculate that the work
seems to skirt that temptation, in order to dismiss it more forcefully. As many
have argued, sentimentalism encourages forms of identification based on
emotional appropriation, absorption of otherness within the self, and vicarious
suffering. These three movements encourage neither reflection nor action
within the political present-with-past, but, on the contrary, its evasion.32
These three emotion-based entrapments hang together in the following
way. The first movement, or the trap that seduces viewers to that movement, is
the primary problem of sentimentality; of an identification that either appro-
priates someone else’s pain or exploits it to feel oneself feeling, in a time when
the overflow of visual representations of suffering tends to inure one to the
confrontation—and thus feel good about oneself. The joy is in the feeling itself;
in feeling that one has regained the capability of feeling. The emotional realm in
which such identification may occur most easily is that of suffering. The identi-
fying viewer may appropriate the suffering of others in a more bearable form
and feel good about it.
This entails the second trap, frequently discussed within trauma studies,
which involves the model of a cannibalizing form of identification. The
viewer identifying with other people’s (represented) suffering appropriates the
suffering, cancels out the difference between self and other, and in the process
makes cheap of the suffering. Vicarious suffering, thirdly, is obviously an
extremely lightened form, and if this lightening comes with the annulling of
difference, in the end the suffering all but disappears from sight, eaten up by the
commiserating viewer.
To remedy this triple danger, Dominick LaCapra proposes a response he calls
“empathic unsettlement.”33 Through this concept he attempts to articulate an
aesthetic based on both feeling for another and, as Jill Bennett phrases LaCapra’s
view, “becoming aware of a distinction between one’s own perceptions and
the experience of the other.”34 With all these qualifications in mind, I propose
to read the appearing and disappearing face of Torfs’s woman as an affection-
image that steers away from these traps. Gilles Deleuze seems to share this
reluctance to endorse the centrality of the face in the humanistic sense, the
sense that is seducing us to sentimental identification. Instead, as Mark Hansen
Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians 81
argues in a different but related context, the philosopher identifies the affection-
image—which, in order to avoid all conflation of Deleuzian affection with the
realm of the emotions, I will call from now on affect-image—that he spotted in
the close-ups of classical cinema not only with but as the face. Deleuze writes:
There is no close-up of the face. The close-up is the face, but the face precisely
in so far as it has destroyed its triple function [individuation, socialization,
communication]. . . . [T]he close-up turns the face into a phantom… The face
is the vampire.35
The view of the close-up image qua face, standing in as face instead of the
human face, becomes increasingly relevant as the installation continues and no
image other than this face is forthcoming. This unique face is a close-up of and
to the viewer that collapses subject and object.
For Hansen, this Deleuzian view leads affect away from the viewer’s body. In
contrast, in what Hansen calls “digital-facial-images” (DFI), the viewer’s body
is directly addressed and hence mobilized, not into action, but into affective
response. Regardless of the relevance of oppositional reasoning here, the
viewer’s body, although not forced into motion as in interactive video, is swept
into the motion that is observed and within which the two-screen installation
has positioned it.36
The face we see in each photograph is indeed a close-up. If the close-up is
the face, then the face is also the close-up. Hence, the slight distance built into
the dispositif (material and spatial) of the installation, by which the work avoids
locking the viewer up and denying the woman any space at all; it avoids both facile
conflation and an appeal to the sentimentality described above. It gives the face a
frame within which it can exercise its mobility and agency—here, its relation to
the light. That slight distance, then, provides the space for a freedom that can be
called “critical,” a freedom à la Spinoza.37 Such a freedom is “critical” because it
stimulates the imagination.38 Critical freedom is the practice of seeing the speci-
ficity of one’s own world as one among others. Intertemporally, this freedom sees
the present as fully engaged with a past that, insofar as it is part of the present,
we can rewrite a little more freely. For me, this is the key consequence of White’s
allegedly formalist approach to the writing of history, as well as of Torfs’s dispo-
sition of the face on the image. The white around the face, then, in addition to the
obvious homonymy with Hayden White’s name, is an active part of the image as
“writing in the middle voice”; it provides the playing ground for critical freedom.
It is equally crucial that the woman withholds her gaze; we cannot look her
in the eye. This, too, is a visual version of the middle voice. It is not imposing a
82 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
gaze into which, once locked, we cannot but let ourselves be seduced to identify.
Instead, it leaves us with the “burden of history”—to recycle the title of an essay
White wrote in 1966—which is, here, to decide what to believe of the signs we
see. For, just as White delivered us scholars in the arts from the indictment of
a-historicism, so Umberto Eco delivered us from the burden of submission to
what our eyes see. His statement “The sign is everything that can be used in
order to lie” is congenial to the title and thrust of Torfs’s artwork; linked to it, so
to speak, by a hyphen.39 Since her woman figure withholds her gaze, she cannot
tell us to believe her; neither is it possible to assign an intention to her facial
“expression” or even to the scarce tear.
This is yet another mode in which modesty is brought to the table. Symptoms
are involuntary signs, as distinct from signals, which are signs sent out
intentionally. Whether caused by profound grief, as in fiction, or by the cutting
of onions, as in Torfs’s studio, the crying subject—historical figure or model—
cannot call up tears at will. This questioning of intention as well as of expression
is yet another of the many levels at which this work glosses the way we tend to
think. For, as I have argued many times, most extensively in Travelling Concepts
in the Humanities,40 intentionalism, the interpretation of art through the artist’s
intention, is perhaps art’s worst mentir-faux. I see in the argument against
intentionalism in art interpretation the key to a kind of history that I have called
“preposterous” and that I see as the backdrop of White’s analysis of history.
When we are standing before a work of art and we admire it, are touched,
moved, or even terrified by it, when a work of art somehow seems to do
something to us, the question of artistic intention loses its obviousness, for
the artist is no longer there to direct our response. Something happens in the
present, whereas what the artist did happened in the past. That act, we may
suppose, was willful, intentional. What is not so clear is that between the event
in the present and the act in the past the same intentionality establishes a direct
link. While it would be futile to doubt that an artist wanted to make her work
of art and that she proceeded to do so on the basis of that intention, the control
over what happens between the work and its future viewers is not in her hands.
But that later event is still, logically, a consequence of that act—the doing of an
agency. Torfs was not there when I experienced her work. And even if she had
been, she would not have been able to control that experience. But what she, or
rather her work, could do was make that distinction clear. In this way, art, not
the artist, is the historian, of a history beyond the opposition to formalism.
Present–past. It is history’s mission to be attentive to change over time. It is
a cultural commonplace, in the present, that art has the remarkable capacity
Deliver Us from A-Historicism: Metahistory for Non-Historians 83
all multiply indirect; syntactically, they are indirect questions, like “Interrogated
if she had seen or made any images…” No answers are included in the slides. In
the book that is part of the work the artist explains the historical indirectness of
these testimonies. They are severely belated, since they were written down from
memory decades after the trial took place. As a gloss, or parody of the use of
historical sources, these indirect questions do their “lying” up-front.
The indirect half-questions and the absence of answers make the discourse
a hovering, anonymous threat. The selection of the indirect questions overde-
termines the violence done to the young woman. Since she cannot answer, it
is obvious that she does not stand a chance. It is clear, then, that control is as
impossible as unambiguous truth. All dualities are thus resolved in a time-based
oscillation instead of a merging. As a result, rather than unifying in a false
harmony at the cost of complexity, this work retains all tensions as precious,
but, along with the answers to Joan’s interrogators, refuses the structure of
opposition. What remains, instead, is an infinitely rich fabric of possibilities.
The middle voice is nested in this fabric; it is there that experiencing-with
becomes possible, without encouraging the forms of identification I have above
imputed to sentimentality and its traps.
obliges you to do theory but also furnishes you with the means of doing it.
Thus, if you agree to accept it on theoretical terms, it will produce effects
around itself… [and it] forces us to ask ourselves what theory is. It is posed in
theoretical terms; it produces theory; and it necessitates a reflection on theory.43
object, its viewers, and the time in which these come together, accompanied
by the off-white space that surrounds both, a compelling thought process
emerges. This process concerns primarily, I have argued, the suspension or
even annihilation of binary opposition. This cancellation of opposition leaves
the relationship between the two sides of each pair unspecified. It is the need to
consider the nature of such a relationship further that constitutes the theoretical
activity Damisch describes.44
Since I propose to establish a partnership here between White’s academic
work and Torfs’s artwork, the term “theoretical object” suits my approach better
than the simpler one of “case.” The theoretical activity is the work viewers and
readers do, in an ongoing performativity. This performativity is significant for
work that is still—mute and unmoving—photography. Thanks to its performa-
tivity, it cannot stand still; it is also, and will always be, “becoming.” By that
Deleuzian term I mean something quite specific. The becoming of an artwork
implies a retrospective temporal logic according to which each new moment
of viewing recasts the terms in which the previous encounter with the work
could be understood. Each new phase of that becoming is informed by a later
work that retrospectively glosses an earlier work. Each work puts a spin on the
ensemble of what came before it. It is this retrospective impact that is the point
of my discussion.
These aspects, moves, or strategies through which I juxtapose and intertwine
Metahistory and Du mentir-faux form a kind of rhizome, parts of which pop
up above ground while others stay underground, yet continue to grow and
work.45 Here, I will limit the root system of that rhizome to the one feature
through which these two works are primarily connected: their vision of the past.
For White, this is his primary concern. Early on in Metahistory, when White
interrogates the diachronic process characteristic of a history conceived as an
account of change over time, his formulation demonstrates the entanglement of
history and the present, as when he writes:
When a given set of events has been motifically encoded, the reader has been
provided with a story; the chronicle of events has been transformed into a
completed diachronic process, about which one can then ask questions as if he
were dealing with a synchronic structure of relationships.46
the seventeenth century. That is not what “meta-” means to me, or, I think, to
most scholars of historical objects. If anything, “meta-” means “about,” as in
“critical examination of.” Metahistorical, therefore, would be the perfect term
for a critical examination of what historicity means—and can mean—both for a
reappraisal, say, of the “old” Baroque and for a critical examination of our own
position in reconstructing it. Something similar can be said of Du mentir-faux.
The indirect questions have a function comparable to White’s categories. They
are artificially streamlined, given the same form, so that they can be meaning-
fully compared, both to one another and to any other document of juridical
proceedings. A universal present, in contrast, is literally “the end of history.”
Mutidirectional history
The difficulty of a historical approach to the present is, precisely, the absence of
tools for “emplotment,” White’s term for the establishment or construction of an
understandable coherence, as opposed to one that is “found.” In this sense, the
present is structurally analogous to trauma: the incapacity to interpret or, indeed,
experience what does not fit in any known framework.51 And this incapacity to deal
with the present outside of established frameworks can either lead to the kind of
universalizing paronthocentrism I see Calabrese as unwittingly espousing or to an
impulse to radical innovation. If White’s book, in spite of the well-known categories
it deploys, has had such innovative impact, it may well be because of the unusual
framework he proposed for history. Conversely, Torfs, as an artist, experiments
with, and probes, not the present that is her starting point, but the past to which she
knows from the start she cannot have access. Yet, she will not give up on this past,
since history, as all good artists know, is where art and its subjects must be inscribed.
The concept of preposterous history I have developed acknowledges the
impact the present has on the past. White’s term “historical imagination”
also captures this and, in my view, better than Frank Ankersmit’s “historical
experience.”52 The difference is the status of experience, which in common
parlance suggests a kind of authority of knowing. The experiencing subject
“knows better” “what it feels like” to be in the experienced situation; one can
thus be considered an “experience expert.” Historical thinking and represen-
tation are better off staying aloof of such authority. The point is not that anyone
knows better, but that anyone, given a sufficiently serious commitment to the
historical object, is able to contribute from her own present the specific, always
subjective but potentially intersubjective view that is the imagination.
88 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Since “The Burden of History” was first published in 1966, Hayden White
has been accused of many crimes. In the eyes of mediocre moralists, he is the
unrepentant relativist whose linguistically turned emphasis on the poetics
of historiography has opened the door to Holocaust deniers. To the stalwart
defenders of objectivity, he is the saw-toothed murderer of historical truth,
vampirically gorging on facticity’s innocent blood. To the post-anti-founda-
tionalists, he is a nihilist trapped in the ironist’s cage, or a “secular creationist”
who endows historians with an unlimited power to construct meaning.1 For
his fans, he remains the revolutionary scourge of naïve positivists, calling them
to account not only for the self-proclaimed transparency of their scientific
methods, but also for the gratuitousness of their unacknowledged desires.
Indeed, as Dirk Moses aptly observes: “The picture we have of White is
curiously bifurcated: on the one hand, the wayward historian under Nietzsche’s
spell with the consequent dubious politics and seeming inability to safeguard
the historical integrity of the Holocaust’s facticity; on the other, the lopsided
formalist whose analyses of historical rhetoric appear as intellectually sterile as
they are politically impotent.”2 A recent collection entitled Re-Figuring Hayden
White (2009) counters a narrow-minded polarization of White’s critical incli-
nations with fresh perspectives on the wily metahistorian’s adventures in the
course of a nearly sixty-year career. F. R. Ankersmit designates his long-time
interlocutor an “aestheticist” with a neo-Kantian slant. In Ankersmit’s inter-
pretation, White’s tropology resembles Kant’s categories of the understanding,
as Hans Kellner had previously argued,3 by virtue of its success “in reconciling
the claims of empiricism with those of transcendental historical reason.”4
Ankersmit nevertheless regrets that White’s “transcendentalist narrativism”
90 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
White’s “transcendentalism”
the first Critique to draw our attention to the a priori status of White’s tropo-
logical “blueprints” that underwrite historical apprehension and reasoning.
To shed light on the transcendental and political lineaments of prefiguration,
I would like to revisit the question of White’s neo-Kantianism by reviewing
Kant’s distinction between the transcendental and the transcendent in this
section, before turning to his opposition between determinative and reflective
judgment in the next. Very briefly, the term transcendental in The Critique of
Pure Reason identifies the mode of cognition “that is occupied not so much with
objects but rather with our a priori concepts of objects in general.”11 Conversely,
the term transcendence holds out the prospect of thinking beyond experience,
which is conditioned by a priori principles. In effect, Kant’s definition of
transcendental in the first Critique translates into a theoretical focus on the a
priori conditions of possible modes of cognition, or, to update his terms, on the
preconscious forms and parameters involved in the configuration of knowledge.
Kant’s transcendental focus propels him to emphasize the necessity of
distinguishing immanent “principles whose application stays wholly and
completely within the limits of possible experience” from transcendent principles
“that fly beyond these boundaries.”12 By insisting that the “transcendental and
transcendent are not the same,” Kant does not merely draw the “boundaries of
the territory in which alone the pure understanding is allowed its play”; he also
emphasizes the extraordinary power of transcendent principles “that actually
incite us to tear down all those boundary posts [Grenzphähle] and to lay claim to
[anzumaßen] a wholly new territory [einen ganz neuen Boden] that recognizes
no demarcations anywhere.”13
In confining the work of pure understanding to an empirical application, Kant
simultaneously upholds the agency of transcendent principles that “take away”
this limit and thus transcend experience. The need to preserve this opposition
spurs Kant’s worry that judgment might fail to heed the difference between
“immanent” and “transcendent” principles, so defined, and thereby succumb
to the humiliating naivety (or arrogance) of the “transcendental illusion.”
Under the sway of this illusion, judgment defies “all the warnings of criticism”
in transporting “us away beyond the empirical use of the categories” and then
seducing us with the “semblance” of an extension of pure understanding.14 The
problem Kant anticipates here is that “pure understanding” might perpetuate
the transcendental illusion rather than dispel it. An inescapable lesson from
the first Critique is that embarrassing uncertainties result when the faculty of
understanding oversteps its own boundaries. A vigilant and humble recognition
of these boundaries is the departure point for any endeavor to move between
92 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
what we understand and what we desire to know (a desire directed from the
present into the future). Most importantly, perhaps, respect for the empirical
limits of the understanding serves to protect the freedom of those arenas
wherein transcendent principles may suitably come into play.15
In light of Kant’s resolute attention to the forms, boundaries, and pitfalls
of the understanding, it is easy to see why critics (such as Kellner) have been
tempted to compare White’s introduction to tropology in Metahistory with the
Prussian philosopher’s topography of the conditions and limits of cognition and
judgment. Drawing principally from Giambattista Vico’s The New Science and
Northrop Frye’s Anatomy of Criticism, White identifies the “representational,”
“reductionist,” “integrative,” and “negational” operations of metaphor,
metonymy, synecdoche, and irony respectively, along with their corresponding
romantic, tragic, comic, and satirical emplotments, as fundamental schemata
that determine possible “styles” of relating various elements in historical
discourse. In short, Metahistory translates the four tropes into “categories for
analyzing different modes of thought, representation, and explanation,” while
also presenting them as “a basis for classifying the deep structural forms of the
historical imagination in a given period of its evolution.”16
White’s reference to the precritical “structural forms of the historical
imagination” resonates with the ideality of the a priori principles that, in
Kant’s transcendental idealist framework, fundamentally condition experience
and cognition. In keeping with the “transcendental level, which is the level of
philosophical reflection upon experience,” as Allison elucidates it, the term
ideality “is used to characterize the universal, necessary, and, therefore, a priori
conditions of human knowledge.” When Kant in the Transcendental Aesthetic
“affirms the transcendental ideality of space and time on the grounds that they
function as a priori conditions of human sensibility,” he is asserting their status
as “subjective conditions in terms of which alone the human mind is capable
of receiving the data for thought or experience.”17 J. M. Bernstein agrees with
Allison that Kant’s “transcendental idealism is not equivalent to any form of
phenomenalism,” or, for that matter, to a recapitulation of Berkeley’s idealism,
as standard condemnations of Kant’s project presume. As Bernstein notes,
“[o]bjects of experience are not synthetic productions constructed out of
sense data. Rather, categories are best conceived of as characterizing ‘the way
we connect perceptions in thought… if we are to experience through them’
objectively obtaining states of affairs.”18
From a rhetorical standpoint, Kant’s faculties, categories, and concepts
function poetically as modes of transfer between empirical and non-empirical
Hayden White’s Hope, or the Politics of Prefiguration 93
principles and domains. His breakdown in the first Critique of intuition and
concepts as the requisite components of cognition suggests that any attempt
to perform knowledge about historical events will correlate these elements,
and, should one or the other be lacking, then it will have to be discovered or
invented. Robert Doran identifies a parallel between Kant’s claim that intuition
and concepts constitute the foundation of knowledge and White’s contention
that the “tropes are the building blocks of all formed thought (discursivity).”
For this reason, Doran stipulates, they “cannot correspond to reality the
way that literal language is thought to refer to the world—that is, in a direct
unmediated way.” Instead, the “[t]ropes produce or ‘make’ historical reality
because they prefigure (condition) the semantic field in which they are inevi-
tably fulfilled (made manifest).”19 According to Doran, then, “White’s procedure
[in Metahistory] is analogous to that of Kant’s in The Critique of Pure Reason”
in “[sketching] out the conditions of possibility of historical writing, which,
[White] contends, are tropological in nature, in order to assess the unity of what
we call ‘historical knowledge.’”20
Yet while the Kantian categories of the understanding are necessary for
knowledge, Ankersmit notes that “the tropes, and the modes of emplotment,
argument, and ideological implication ‘consonant’ with them are all optional,” or
at least they appear to be.21 According to Ankersmit, “the Whitean counterpart
to Kant’s transcendental aesthetics and transcendental analytics is to be found
in his theory of the ‘prefiguration’ of the historical field, preceding all that the
historian might wish to say about the past.”22 White’s tropological theory of
prefiguration tells us how “a historian determines […] what kind of events
make up the past and what is the nature of the relationship between them.”23
In declaring White a transcendental narrativist, Ankersmit spotlights White’s
assumption that “prefiguration is no longer optional: it can truly be said to be the
transcendental condition of the possibility of historical knowing.”24
Ankersmit acknowledges the limits of grafting tropology onto Kant’s
transcendental categories, preferring instead to dwell on White’s theory of
prefiguration. This theory metahistoricizes Erich Auerbach’s analysis of a
tendency in biblical exegesis to construct the Old Testament as a “type” that
only achieves its full meaning in its “antitype,” the New Testament.25 In effect,
this tendency positions the Old Testament as a prefiguration of events that are
inevitably “fulfilled” in the New Testament, a logic of “figural causation” that
entrenches the privilege of a (progressive) Christian present (and future) with
respect to its (outmoded) Jewish past. As Doran explains, “[t]he theological
understanding of figuralism held the relation between type and antitype to
94 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
be intrinsic and causal; that is, willed by God, providential.”26 White gener-
alizes Auerbach’s figuralism into a tropology that permits us to decode logics
of progressive fulfillment (or unfulfillment) in historical writing. Hence, even
though history is “literally chronological,” it is, in Doran’s rephrasing of White,
“figurally anachronistic,” since it is inspired by “the will to see a later event as
if it were intrinsically related to an earlier event, in the absence of any efficient-
causal connection.” Prefiguration, in this function, is nothing more nor less than
an inventive process with metaleptic and proleptic effects; by elevating a past
to the status of an origin or a model, individuals and groups bestow “meaning
retrospectively” and thereby “choose a present.”27
As Ankersmit describes it, White’s prefiguratively empowered tropological grid
“transforms the chaos—‘the manifold,’ as Kant would put it—of the past into a
reality that can be mapped, investigated, and discussed.” The salient point is that
even though prefiguration conditions the writing of history, it “does not determine
what the historian will actually say about the past…”28 Echoing Kellner, Ankersmit
represents White’s conception of historical writing as oscillating back and forth
“between the tropological constitution of historical reality and what is explicitly
said about the past in the historian’s text. In both the ‘surface’ of the historical text
and its prefigurative ‘depth,’ the nature of historical reality is at stake.”29
Ankersmit’s double reference to “historical reality” in the space of two
sentences divides this concept into different registers that merit a close reading.
In an initial register, a tropologically formed “historical reality” is grammatically
distinct from “what is said about the past in the historian’s text.” This passive
construction implies that a historian’s statements take place in an anonymous
zone without belonging to or emanating from a particular speaker, as if the
author of a historical narrative is merely the vehicle of an intersubjective repre-
sentation without any special agency to bring to bear on it. In another register,
the historiographical text, which is comprised of a historian’s statements, itself
splits into a textual-manifest surface and a prefigurative-latent depth. This split
codes prefiguration as the “repressed” content of both historical consciousness
and its textual configuration. In contending that “the nature of historical reality
is at stake” in this manifest-latent split, Ankersmit ambivalently confirms
White’s radical premise that there is no “reality” with a “nature” for the historian
(or anyone) that somehow exists “out there,” anterior to its formalization in a
discourse; however, a tension nevertheless emerges between the position of the
historian-as-vehicle and a subjectivity empowered to construct history itself.
White consistently argues that the historian’s research and writing do not
recreate a preexisting reality; he or she uses empirical or textual research as a
Hayden White’s Hope, or the Politics of Prefiguration 95
her upbringing and institutional training) and that he or she reinscribes while
assembling the results of a comparative analysis of different sources.
Roland Barthes’s analysis of realist discourse illustrates how it summons
the force of a referential illusion—a feeling of genuine intimacy between
“reality” and its symbolization.32 What I am calling a mimetic fantasy involves
a similar aesthetics of misrecognition, because the historian caught in its
web does not register the precritical confluence of the various behavioral and
aesthetic protocols that elicit the feeling of disciplined thought when fulfilled.33
This fantasy also elides a historian’s identification with past and present
mentors—as well as favored paradigms—as he or she seeks to “do justice” to
an intersubjectively constructed image of an event. In addition, if the faculty
of understanding requires unity according to Kant (and a certain Hegel), the
synthetic interest motivating the recourse to a narrative to bridge disparate
pieces of evidence subliminally establishes the conjunctive possibilities for an
imaginative staging of an historical situation. White’s account of prefiguration
thus blurs the opposition between imagination and understanding in historical
writing by revealing the subterranean poetics historians employ in seeking to
bring about a sense of verisimilitude and coherence.
Yet if White is a “transcendental narrativist,” in Ankersmit’s assessment,
he is not, by any stretch, a transcendental idealist. Rather, he extends the
lessons of the Critical Philosophy to historians who seem reluctant to admit
that a presentation of evidence in writing does not transparently reflect an
unmediated perceptual manifold—a “raw” field of data. White’s rhetorical
approach highlights the malleability of a historical referent that coalesces in the
interplay between passively intuited details and a historian’s training-guided
contact with them.
To identify what is involved in this interplay, it is useful to note that the
translation of Anschauung as intuition does not convey its complexity for Kant.
Allen Wood explains that “[t]he German word Anschauung simply means
‘looking at,’ and the Latin word intuitus (which Kant regarded as its equivalent)
was the traditional term used in scholastic epistemology for any immediate
cognitive contact with individual objects.”34 Kant’s usage of the term intuition is
ambiguous, according to Wood, since “it can refer to the state of being in such
contact, or to the thing with which we are in contact regarded simply as an
object of intuition, or to the mental state (or representation) afforded us when
we intuit an object.”35 Both instances associate intuition with the “receptivity
of the mind that enables an individual object to be given to cognition,” or
sensibility, so defined. When viewed as the material of the senses, or the
Hayden White’s Hope, or the Politics of Prefiguration 97
contends, “[i]n the case of Kant’s analysis of the beautiful, this aim will never
[be] realized, because in the Kantian reflective judgment there is no pre-given
concept in terms of which the realization of the aim could be established.”47
Ankersmit’s move to align White with the aesthetic ideology of the beautiful
is puzzling, when we take into account White’s explicit endeavors to distance
himself from its dangers. Indeed, as Ankersmit knows very well, in “The
Politics of Historical Interpretation: Discipline and De-Sublimation” (originally
published in Critical Inquiry in 1982), White traces the history of a preference
for the beautiful over the sublime beginning in eighteenth-century aesthetics
as the symptom of a conservative expropriation of utopian politics. History
follows suit insofar as its emergence as an autonomous discipline depends on
its demonstration that it could serve the law-preserving interests of the State. To
restore a taste for visionary politics, White famously aligns his view of history
with the aesthetics of the sublime.
To grasp the historicity and connotations of White’s intervention here, it
will be useful to situate it at a particular turning point in intellectual history,
when the anti-foundationalist theories generated by the linguistic turn in
France were reaching the apex of their influence in literary studies. The Hayden
White who published “The Politics of Historical Interpretation” in 1982, two
years before Jean-François Lyotard’s The Postmodern Condition appeared in
English, seemingly anticipated the North American appreciation of Lyotard’s
anti-instrumentalist politics of the sublime. More explicitly than any other of
the so-called “postmodernists” heavily influenced by Nietzsche’s rejection of
false continuities and circular moralities, Lyotard would take to heart Kant’s
rendering of aesthetic judgment as a mode of non-nomological and non-teleo-
logical reflection, as contrasted with Hegelian logic and its alleged unification
of particulars, the totalitarian ideologies of the twentieth century, and the
extensive impact of capitalist rationalization. The Postmodern Condition revises
Martin Heidegger’s and Theodor Adorno’s respective critiques (after Georg
Lukács) of the compartmentalization of knowledge in an alienating modernity.
In “The Age of the World Picture,” Heidegger expresses anxiety that the increas-
ingly hegemonic status of the mathematically based sciences will deform the
temporally open inquiry pursued in the humanities. Lyotard’s promotion of the
sublime responds to Heidegger’s concern about the modern subject’s failure to
consider the dangers of its own “unthought” as the shadow cast by a solipsistic
world picture.48 The French philosopher’s turn toward the sublime also furthers
the Frankfurt School’s repudiation of an instrumental reason that holds thinking
hostage to the capitalist criteria of efficiency, productivity, and calculability.
Hayden White’s Hope, or the Politics of Prefiguration 101
assent. Judgments of the beautiful take place as if they were universally commu-
nicable, and they are aesthetic to the extent that they transpire as if we were
judging in accordance with a (lost) common sense. Bernstein speculates that
this “as-if ” memorializes the feeling that a common sense once existed or could,
in the future, emerge. This feeling is bound up with an indefatigable longing,
at once nostalgic and aspirational, for a community wherein the universal
communicability of aesthetic judgments closes the gap between beauty, on
the one side, and morality and truth, on the other. The forlorn pleasure of the
beautiful both seduces and defers this longing for communion.
Bernstein’s memorial thesis pinpoints the melancholic tone of a judgment
of the beautiful in the third Critique that suffers from a longing for universal
validity it cannot fulfill, even if we recognize taste as the subjectively universal
vehicle of this longing itself. With respect to this want, judgments take place as if
the common sense—Kant’s sensus communis—that preconditions their univer-
sality might have been or could be possible. The key to this particular mode of
judgment in White’s terms is, then, a prefigurative desire for a community in
which everyone shares the same sensibility.
According to Dirk Moses, “White’s aim is to cultivate a utopian subjectivity in
his readers rather than a ‘realistic’ anti-utopian one,” by exposing “the irreducible
ideological or metahistorical component in every historical account.”71
Bernstein’s memorial thesis suggests that this aim could be oriented by the
aesthetic of the beautiful. As a political idea, the as-if community that heartens
judgments of the beautiful refracts a utopian yearning for social integration and
perhaps also for unconditional solidarity. From White’s perspective, however,
the historian who wrests coherence from chaos reverts to a nineteenth-century
script that stages a sensible attunement between understanding and the moral
imagination as an analogue for a harmonious world.72 Moreover, as White is
acutely aware, historical events have shown us how a desire for harmony can
propel a dangerous drive to construct and liquidate difference in the name of
cultural unity and unilateral state sovereignty.
It is intriguing to consider White’s wariness about beauty as the centrifuge
of a deadly aesthetic ideology in light of Hannah Arendt’s recourse to Kant’s
analysis of taste as a supplement to her repudiation of cultural philistinism
and the idea of “mass culture.” In “The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and Political
Significance,” Arendt observes that the third Critique posits “a different way
of thinking, for which it would not be enough to be in agreement with
one’s own self, but which consisted of being able to ‘think in the place of
everybody else’ and which he therefore called an ‘enlarged mentality’ (eine
106 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
empirical field disavows the coextensive relationship between the forms and
conventions precritically directing the historian’s symbolization of a historical
phenomenon and its rhetorical presentation as an object of understanding.
Understanding becomes “deceptive” in Kant’s sense, as historians seek to endow
their choice of form with the authoritative force of empirical necessity by
insinuating that any rational subject would intuit evidence in the same way. To
orchestrate this effect, historians emulate the disinterested subject of aesthetic
judgment who proclaims the beautiful as if everyone could or should agree with
him or her. It is in this respect that Bernstein and Arendt inversely clarify why
White rebuffs the historian’s professional pretension of writing as if he or she
serves as the vehicle of a universal judgment. In exhorting writers of history to
assume the irreducible risks of their statements by struggling over their implica-
tions for transformative action in the present, he also invites historians to take
pleasure in the dissensus that both goads and inspires all rhetorical endeavors—
to divest the prefigurational lull of sensus communis that nurtures a puritanically
realist discipline heaven-bent on instilling quietism.
5
of the overall relative maturity, and we all benefited from the ease with which
we were able to meet with our mentors to discuss intellectual matters. There
was nothing like that for me when I enrolled in graduate school at Columbia,
where I found my professors for the most part pretty gelid and intellectually
indifferent, though they were learned enough. I had applied to the philosophy
departments of NYU and Columbia—I wanted to be in New York because I was
in pursuit of an artistic career—and was turned down by NYU because I had
taken no philosophy courses at Wayne. I never asked Hayden if he had taken
any philosophy there. I had not because one had to first pass a course by a man
suitably named Trapp in order to go on to the course in aesthetics that everyone
talked about, taught by Raymond Hoekstra. So far as I know, Hayden and I
never really met at Wayne, though we got to know one another later, when we
were both teaching in New York. He went on to do graduate work in history,
and though he certainly had a philosophical bent, I surmise that the philosophy
he learned was through his omnivorous reading.
My main influence at Columbia was Ernest Nagel, a distinguished philos-
opher of science; though it was in my first job, teaching at the University of
Colorado, that I encountered the kind of analytical philosophy to which I was
to devote myself. Two of my peers were deep in the British tradition known
as Ordinary Language Philosophy. One was a student of Norman Malcolm,
at Cornell, a disciple of Wittgenstein, the other was a student of Gilbert Ryle
at Oxford, whose The Concept of Mind was the cutting-edge work at the time.
Ryle and Wittgenstein both had the view that philosophy was more or less
the product of linguistic disorders. Through Malcolm’s disciple, John Nelson,
we were able to read monographic editions of The Blue and Brown Books, as
well as of the Math Notes, all of which the three of us discussed endlessly (the
Investigations were not as yet translated.) It was at Colorado that I learned what
was expected of one’s writing if one was going to be taken seriously by other
philosophers in the movement. When I returned to Columbia, I had a mission,
which was to proclaim that all philosophy was philosophy of language. Except
for Nagel, Columbia stood to the philosophy scene like a kind of Tibet. It was
just an awful scene dominated by the fuddy-duddies of early twentieth-century
thought.
What is striking about the two of us is that we both made narrative a central
concept in our thought and writing. In both our cases, though certainly in
mine, I attribute this to Bossenbrook. Hayden’s masterpiece, Metahistory,
published in 1973, more or less took narrative as given, the question being what
the historian was to do with his or her narrative. In effect, he was interested in
Hayden White and Me: Two Systems of Philosophy of History 111
what one might call the rhetoric of narration. Hayden was in some degree a
follower of Kenneth Burke in this. I was a reader of Burke myself, and I suppose
one could call my first book—Analytical Philosophy of History—a study in the
logic of narration. But in truth, the difference between our approaches was
greater than the difference between logic and rhetoric. How different could
be derived from Hayden’s hospitality to the ideas of poststructuralist writing,
which had no appeal for me. My approach, then and now, was an amalgam of
ordinary language analysis and philosophy of science in the Logical Positivist
vein. Metahistory is, in the end, a remarkable work of history: its subtitle is “The
Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe.” The title of my book,
Analytical Philosophy of History, was meant to imply a rejection of speculative
philosophies of history, exemplified by Hegel and Marx, so I suppose it could
be called in a subtitle “Historical Speculation in Nineteenth-Century Thought,”
though a more piquant title might be: “Why We Can’t Write the History of the
Future.” In any case, White’s book is about a set of actual narratives written
by nineteenth-century historians. Mine was not concerned primarily with
specific narratives, but with narratives as explanatory schemata, in contrast
with scientific explanations as logical schemata. I was from the outset taking a
stand against the philosophy of history as conceived of by the Encyclopedia of
Unified Science, which expressed the way Logical Positivism construed history
as a retarded form of science.
The canonical text in the analytical philosophy of history was a famous
essay by C. G. Hempel, published in 1942: “The Function of General Laws in
History,” perceived at the time as a fundamental contribution to the Unity of
Science agenda of the Logical Positivist movement. The idea of Unified Science
was opposed to an alleged irreducible division drawn in German philosophy,
between nature and what Hegel called Spirit, or Geist, and hence between two
kinds of science—natural science, or Naturwissenschaft, and the sciences of
“spirit” (for which we have no exact English term) called Geisteswissenschaft.
These were thought to have contrary modes of cognitive address—explanation
(Erklären) and understanding (Verstehen). A natural phenomenon is explained
with reference to a general law, but a spiritual phenomenon has a kind of
uniqueness that rules out explanation, so understood. It has to be grasped
through a special operation of understanding. History accordingly can be
understood, but not explained, since there are no historical laws. Each unhappy
family is unhappy in its own way, but each happy family is happy in its own way
as well. We understand families, happy or unhappy, by grasping what is unique
in each. And what is true of families is true of nations, and indeed of forms
112 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
they did upon events that could not be predicted because there were no laws,
and that could not be intended, since they typically involve consequences that
cannot be foreseen. In Analytical Philosophy of History—reissued under the
title Narration and Knowledge1—I used as a paradigm Yeats’s great poem, Leda
and the Swan, in which he writes “A shudder in the loins/engendered there/the
burning wall, the broken tower/and Agamemnon dead.” All that was engen-
dered in the rape of Leda was something to which anyone who saw a woman
being molested by a swan had to have been blind. Zeus’s other rapes—Europa,
Danae, and the many like—have no history similar to the one that would bring
into the same plot Agammenon, Clytemnestra, Orestes, Elektra, Cassandra, and
of course Iphegenia, and to make the climax of Zeus’s act seem retrospectively
a destiny. At the moment it took place it would merely have been one of Zeus’s
picturesque erotic interventions, no more important in his eyes than any of the
others. It turned out to be important because Helen—but only under narrative
redescription, Helen of Troy—was conceived on that occasion, and she was to
become causally implicated in the great event of antiquity, the Trojan War. There
would or could be no law of nature connecting up the shudder in the loins,
the successful investiture of Troy (“the broken wall, the burning tower”), and
the murder of Agamemnon. None of this could have been predicted but only,
perhaps, prophesied, to use the profound distinction Karl Popper introduced
in The Poverty of Historicism (1957). Prophecy is not a scientific achievement,
and it only seems like a cognitive possibility because we are able to construct
a narrative that leads back from the death of Agamemnon, through the fall of
Troy, to that fateful moment when Zeus inseminated his squirming victim.
What makes that event important is the later interest of those whose lives were
affected by the momentous conflict on the plains of Troy. It is this overlay of
interest onto happening that singles out events as having historical significance.
Helen’s twin brothers, Castor and Pollux, were great athletes who led busy and
eventful lives before they became stars in the ancients’ firmament. Her sister and
future sister-in-law, Clytemnestra, are coincidentally related to one another in
the Fall of Troy, since the latter’s daughter and the former’s niece, Iphigenia, had
to be sacrificed because a prophet believed that that would enable the battle to
proceed. Her son, Orestes, does not enter the narrative at all.
Witnesses to the monstrous event of Leda ravished by Zeus in his swan
metamorphosis would naturally be blind to the narrative that the poet, from
a later position in the temporal order, is able to spell out for his auditors. The
narrative sentence refers to two time-separated events, and though the first
event can have been observed, it cannot be observed under the description
Hayden White and Me: Two Systems of Philosophy of History 115
the later event makes available, turning the first event into history. Thinkers
used to say that it is a defect of history that the events it speaks of cannot be
observed—but it would do us no good to observe them, as far as history is
concerned. It is not a metaphysical defect in history, but what makes history
possible. But it is human interest—what the Positivists used to refer to as
the pragmatist dimension of meaning—that relates the two events. What we
cannot do is break the narrative down into explanatory episodes under laws of
a number of social or social-psychological or economic sciences, for we lose the
meaning the conditions in the explanandum acquire under the perspective of
narration, which in turn derive from our interests in the like of great beauties,
acts of treachery and betrayal, codes of honor, terrible sacrifices—the past seen
as a tapestry of dramatic occurrences. It is human interest that guarantees the
autonomy of history and the inescapability of narrative redescription that hold
us spellbound as storytellers take us from the ravishing of Leda to the death of
Agamemmnon and beyond—the story arbitrarily ending when the Furies are
transformed into the good guys, and the age of justice begins. Tell me about it.
Jürgen Habermas told me that my book brought analytical philosophy to
the threshold of hermeneutics. It breached the gap between analytical and
continental philosophy, and, I was told, it had considerable impact on higher
education in Germany. Administrators were seriously concerned with the place
of history in the curriculum and proposed to replace history with one or another
social science. But here was a book, which came out of the scientifically oriented
movement of High Positivism, that argued for the autonomy of history. History
teaches us about ourselves, for the interests that lead us to the past are those that
relate us to one another, which is what it means to say that narration is internally
related to what it means to exist historically, as a mode of being human.
Let us now consider the second sense of living in history, which was insuf-
ficiently emphasized in my book. This other mode of historical being is not quite
so readily indexed to matters of tense, reference, and observation, but it is of no
less human importance than viewing life as narratively structured. It concerns
the fact that we are always living in a historical period. A period—or a culture—
is the weave of everything in what Hegel called “objective spirit,” which consists
of all the institutions of human life at a given time: language, art, clothing, laws,
etc. In any period, there are certain temporal concepts indispensable to the
conduct of life: earlier and later; before, after, and at the same time; now and
then. But these would not enable those who belong to a period to experience
time, as most of us do, historically—seeing things as belonging to other periods.
Hence they could not experience their period as a period.
116 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
fountain, one might say. The truth is that we owe little to one another, despite
our veneration for the same teacher as undergraduates at Wayne State. My
hunch is that his branch of the philosophy tree has a lot more leaves than mine.
That is because philosophers who are interested in the philosophy of history are
pretty scarce. Maybe that is true of historians as well—but there are a lot more
of them than there are philosophers.
Robert Doran, a far closer student of Hayden’s writing than I, has suggested
a way in which our two bodies of thought have a greater community than that.
He has pointed out Hayden’s engaging discussion of figurational mimesis,2
brilliantly used by Erich Auerbach in his great work on literary history, Mimesis:
The Representation of Reality in Western Literature. The notion of figuration is
really the notion of prefiguration, where hermeneuticists seek ways in which
New Testament events are foretold by Old Testament events. “Foretelling” is
of course prophesy. An Old Testament episode, if it foretells a New Testament
episode, does not enable one to predict but to foresee, which is not scientifically
credible. The one certainly does not cause the other, whereas with narrative
sentences, the first steps in a causal narrative are laid down.
But figurational mimesis is another matter. Later figures copy earlier ones in
certain ways. The great mime of history as he reads it is Don Quixote, and his
book is comedic because it is too late. My own politics encourage me to believe
that the Tea Party is quixotic in this respect, making clowns out of those who
regard themselves as heroes. But when later characters get it right, as in making
the Renaissance, as Hayden tracks it, then something like history happens twice.
This is a great example. It consists in using the past as a model for the present
or the immediately future. It is mimesis, if you can bring it off. History becomes
a guide to the perplexed. Like Columbia University in 1969 mimes Columbia
University 1968, taken as a scenario. The scenario got more and more diluted as
the years advanced. It need not happen as a farce the second time, but it often
does. White’s idea is very rich indeed, a produce of Wayne at its ripest.
6
thinker Ibn Khaldun), which brought space and time together in the forms
of history and social structure, White instantiated both this privileging of the
present as the scene for rejecting a historical practice dedicated to valorizing
“the historically given world as a value in itself,” and the incidence of historical
speculation carried on within the broader arena of world cultures.3 Here, it
seems to me, White’s appraisal of Ibn Khaldun’s monumental achievement,
occurring outside of the zone of European historical consciousness and
conceived well before the formation of modern society, explicitly bespeaks how
forms of thought are still culturally derived expressions mediated by time and
space, and, despite showing a commonality across borders, are thus remote
from reflecting a universally shared cognitive disposition. More often than
not, they are markedly different from what might ordinarily look familiar to
us and what we think they resemble. In the case of Ibn Khaldun, there is the
genuine absence of human agency in the making of history, which, according
to White, distinguishes it from the “great philosophies of the history” of the
Western tradition centered on “man as a social creature burdened with ultimate
responsibility for his own fate.” Instead, what we have in the Muqaddimah is the
action of an abstract mechanism personified by the figure of a social structure
that writes its own history.4
In any case, White’s observation implies that the present resembled a
reservoir filled with the multiplicity of forms and their different temporalities,
whereby the spectacle of their coexisting occupancy made it both the scene of
the historical itself—what writers like Paul Ricoeur and Peter Osborne have
called the “historical present”—and the place of production of its critique.
What philosophy of history had managed to preserve, in White’s reckoning,
is precisely the identity of a “multiplicity of life forms” in the present, with
their trailing train of temporalities marking their moment, always capable of
inducing the “fatigue” or “ennui” that will lead to attempts to overcome them.5
Yet it was the vocation of national history to undermine the creative force of
a present filled with multiple, coexisting forms denoting different pasts, to
prevent their unscheduled, untimely appearances from interfering with the
temporal dominant of rectilinearity in a nation’s narrative. More than any other
factor, this bonding of nation and its history resulted in altering the relationship
between space and time and literally severed history from the force of time by
spatializing the nation form as a static, completed figure that subsumed time.
The specter of untimeliness was always associated with the “scandal” of under-
development and backwardness attributed to societies outside of Euro-America,
outside of the frame of the nation-form and its temporally sophisticated
122 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
All history is contemporary history; not in the ordinary sense of the word,
where contemporary history means the history of the comparatively recent past,
but in the strict sense: the consciousness of one’s own activity as one actually
performs it. History is the self-knowledge of the living mind.6
Here, White discerned that the lasting purpose of philosophy of history was to
criticize a current situation exhausted by a crowding of cultural forms, which
invariably would lead to exhaustive “fatigue” and the necessity of constructing a
critique aimed at its overcoming.
It is interesting to note, in this connection, that Japanese philosophers of
the Kyoto school in the late 1930s, armed with Ernst Troeltsch’s powerful
critical articulation of what he called the contemporary “crisis of historicism,”
similarly sought to provide a philosophic critique for the effort to “overcome”
the “contemporary” (gendai) filled with plural cultural forms.7 For the Kyoto
philosophers, as for White, this required relating philosophy to history, for
without this linkage there would be no possibility for understanding the
“actuality” of the present situation and of constructing an appropriate critique
of it. White’s own criticism of historical practice in his present was, I believe,
prompted by a Cold War obsession to “end ideology” in the name of value-free
scientific objectivity, which had already driven historical practice further from
the perspective of philosophic critique and closer to the safety of an empirically
grounded (social) science.
In what follows, I would like to explore further some of the possibilities offered
by this effort to reunite historical practice and philosophic reflection. Instead
of returning to the more familiar terrain of White’s theorization of narrative
discourse, which others are better qualified to address, I will be especially
concerned with his observation, derived from his reading of the philosophy of
history, regarding in particular how the present constitutes a vast historical inter-
section of different temporalities containing “multiple life forms” and how these
forms come to embody the critical force of temporal agency in constructing
and containing a historical field, rather than merely providing the occasion for
exhaustion. In this respect, my attention will focus on trying to provide a critical
philosophy of history with a slightly revised vocation that seeks specifically to
expand and enlarge upon the primacy of the present as the site of the historical,
ascertaining its promise for a prospective strategy of historical comparability
consisting of temporal forms acting as agents. It is my contention that any
historical account founded on the linearity of time will inhibit and foreclose the
prospect of comparability, as against representations based on the presumption
of non-linear coexistence of heterogeneous temporalities, which leave open the
possibility of constructing perspectives for comparative research.
It has often been observed that different pasts and their temporalities
continue living on into the present, pressing upon it, thereby making visible the
124 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
diverse experiences that produced them. Yet this observation suggests that the
coexistence of different pasts and their trailing train of temporalities marking
their moment are only products of the present, some attaining dominance,
others fading into forgetfulness and taking up residence as retired memories,
often invisible but never entirely disappearing from sight and always ready
for recall and reanimation. What seems striking about this observation is the
role played by the immediate phenomenal present in structuring historical
pasts and the practice devoted to extracting its knowledge of them. Moreover,
the “scandal” attributed to untimely occurrences, especially their capacity for
interruptions and caesura, invariably comes in the form of confrontations
challenging the present’s version of history’s narrative, an exigency of the rarely
questioned vocation of historical practice to focus on the dominant unit of
national history, thereby further risking calling into question the relationship
between the two tenses of past and present. The unscheduled appearance of
revenants in the present, reminding its inhabitants of the untimely past now in
their midst, refer less to some debt the present must pay to the past than to the
transformative energy such ghostly arrivals are capable of unleashing.
Before World War II, French sociologist Maurice Halbwachs had already
rejected this presumption of acculturation to externality, in what he dismissed as
“historical memory,” which, he warned, invariably leads to a gradual bleaching
of the strange and unfamiliar from history and thus to the disappearance of
its uncanniness.8 Halbwachs had already absorbed the Bergsonian discourse
on time and especially its stunning proposition of mixed temporalities, which
pointed to the possibility of rescuing what the national narrative had elimi-
nated as strange. At the same moment Halbwachs was discounting history’s
involvement in the nation, the Japanese literary critic Kobayashi Hideo (another
closeted Bergsonian) was similarly proclaiming that all historical narratives,
Marxian and bourgeois alike, inevitably miss the real content of historical
experience, which only the vocation of literature is able to conserve. For
Kobayashi, the content of true history was the common and the ordinary—the
everyday—which never changes.9 In my reading, the recognition of multiple
and overlapping pasts in the present, which we might designate as the “historical
present,” exemplifies the defect of the national narrative form, because it seeks
to eliminate the equivalence claimed by the insinuation of coextensive pasts. In
this understanding, the uncanny refers to the spectacle of coexisting, uneven
temporalities. What is troubling about national narratives is the presumption
of a completed past and a national experience that all are asked to commonly
share, which enables the virtual eviction of the force of time itself, apart from the
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 125
time from capitalist time, which resulted in subordinating the former to the
latter through the process of inversion enabled by the commodity form. Thus,
Benjamin famously warned that the representation of time he characterized as
homogenous and empty became the avenue through which ideology filtered
into the precincts of historical materialism. Marxian historical practice, in
close imitation of the bourgeois historiography it has eschewed, differs only in
content rather than form (as it should have) and has maintained agreement over
the presumed correspondence between the trajectory of time and meaning, as
if the former dutifully reflected the latter and the latter provided the authori-
tative ground of the former. The relation between writing and history “cannot
be reduced to narratives that are supposed to impose order on the chaos
of facts.” There is a “disjunction,” “discrepancy,” “discordance,” an inevitable
“uneven relation” and development between “material production and artistic
production,” and a social formation is always “irreducible to the homogeneity
of the dominant production relation.”17
Perhaps this is what Michel Foucault meant when he proclaimed that he
could see no difference between Marxism and bourgeois historical practices.
Here, it is worth noting that the national narrative worked hand in glove with
capital to remove the very incidence of mixed and uneven temporalities and
to contain capitalism’s own temporal contradictions, by transmuting them into
the smooth, untroubled succession demanded by both the nation-state and
capital to operate properly. Chronology, an abstract and quantitative measure
of time, came to replace the movement and action of time by routinizing and
standardizing time in such a way as to establish an agreed-upon normal social
time regulating the rhythms of state and society that would allow no alternative
forms of temporal accountancy to interrupt it. This was precisely the function of
world standard time, which would regulate the temporal conduct of states and
economies. Georg Simmel once remarked that if all the clocks and watches in
Berlin stopped for a few minutes the whole social, political, and economic life
of the city (and probably the nation) would cease. The relationship thus meant
that the nation-form would act as a placeholder for the contradictory temporal
operations of capital, that is to say, the linearity demanded by production, the
cyclical and negative time driving circulation, and the organic time of repro-
duction. In fact, the nation-form shared with capital Marx’s reformulation
of time into the organization of social time, a radical desacralization, which
reconfigured historical representation into what Antonio Gramsci described
as “immanent history.” But rather than lead to history as an immanent work in
process occurring in the present, always in a state of incompletion, as Marx had
128 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
envisaged in his own histories, its fixed spatial form turned to a finished past
as the location of historical time. In this regard, the nation form and its history
increasingly functioned to contain the surplus of capital’s ceaseless movement,
its cycles, rhythms, crises—in short, the excess of an untotalizeable history
of development and any present filled with the contradictory uncertainties
announced by untimely residues and new quests.
If, in any case, historians have manifested a studied indifference to recog-
nizing the temporal imperative demanded by their own conceptions of history,
literary critics, writers and philosophers early on expressed their unease with
strategies employed to measure and quantify the external and objective world.
Georg Lukács’s powerful attack on philosophy’s own dedication to quanti-
fication and objectification (enacted by both modern science and capital)
reinforced a growing dissatisfaction with the disappearance of qualitative and
internal time, and his turn to the present, what he described (glossing Ernst
Bloch) as the “unbridgeable and persisting ‘chasm of the present,’” announced
a new perspective on historical time he shared with others, like M. M. Bakhtin,
in their respective explorations of literary genre. What is significant about this
turn to the present was the recognition of how time acquired the force of form
to affect and alter the historical scene. Hence, Lukács’s meditations on the
historical novel worked to fill the past with the present, by pointing to those
writers who were able to grasp the social processes “arising” in their present and
thereby understand the nature of social reality lived in past presents. Lukács was
obviously calling attention to the writer’s capacity to totalize a social situation,
discerning in it the interplay of its contradictions, as a condition of grasping the
social configuration marking prior presents.
By the same measure, Bakhtin sought to fill the present with prior pasts
in the effort to explain the character of the modern novel enabled by the
category—or, as he called them, “forms”—of the chronotope: the modalities
of space/time relationships embodied in literary forms that ceaselessly change
over and through time in a continuous process of reappropriation. While in
this connection White turned to the chronotope as a containing strategy in
an essay he wrote years after Metahistory, titled “The ‘Nineteenth Century’
as Chronotope”18 (which sought to revisit the question of historical time and
reconfigure the basis of periodization, to which I will return below), it should
be said here that in its original formulation Bakhtin wanted to demonstrate
how elements of prior chronotopic figuration were reappropriated to acquire
new leases on literary life in later periods. In the process, the deposited residues
continued to signify the moment of their production as they now coexisted
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 129
with a different time/place relationship. But what both Lukács and Bakhtin were
pointing to was how things change through time’s action itself, through forms
embodying it, rather than in it, where their place or moment is only marked and
dated.
In this regard, Paul Ricoeur has observed that despite the kinship shared
by narrative and temporality and especially their reciprocal structures,
their concurrence has usually been overlooked. The reason for this is that
epistemologies and methodologies of history and criticism of fictional narratives
take for granted that every narrative must occur within a temporal framework.
Because this presupposition is assumed to be unproblematic, it is seen as
unworthy of serious attention within a temporal matrix that corresponds to
the ordinary representation of time as a linear succession of instants. Ricoeur
condemns philosophers too for having ignored the contribution of narrative to
a critique of time, by appealing either to cosmology and physics or by simply
falling back on an inner experience of time and duration without considering
a relationship to a narrative activity.19 It should be pointed out, as well, that
the Japanese philosopher Tosaka Jun had already made this observation in the
1930s, when he demonstrated how the practice of history has been uncriti-
cally based on what he described as “borrowed time,” rather than on its own
time, which he identified as the now of the everyday present. What troubled
him most was how considerations relating to the representation of historical
time resulted in re-presenting a representation of time that derived from the
“temporal representation of things.” This maneuver linked time to the problem
of consciousness, making it foremost an aspect of its domain. For this reason,
he continued, historical time was nothing more than an accessory to a sense of
time belonging to consciousness, which he named “phenomenological time,”
an interior, psychological temporal state that history must “borrow” from
the representation of “phenomena that are outside of history.” As a result, the
temporal principle of phenomenology, despite its unhistorical derivation and
application, is smuggled into history to replace true historical time with a
temporality derived from phenomena that are not, as such, historical.20 What
Tosaka identified as “phenomena outside history” was the state of interior
consciousness and psychological time of the individual subject, as against an
everyday present constituted by the calculation of labor time, which he located
within history. But even more importantly, Tosaka saw in narrative construction
the dangers of large-scale developmental plots that risked resembling the
story lines of national history (he remained silent on the great contemporary
debate among Marxists on the development of capitalism in Japan) and how it
130 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
predictably departed from history’s true content and its proper temporal calling,
which corresponded to what he called the “character of politics” of any specific
era. By the time of World War II, Kyoto philosophers such as Miki Kiyoshi,
Kosaka Masaaki, and Tanabe Hajime had gone even further in discounting
the utility of historical narrative and its association with Japan’s “modernity,”
in favor of seeing in it the historical index of a stage Japan had surpassed and
which had contributed to preparing it for the momentous engagement with the
present and an evolving world historical perspective that promised to exceed
the unit of the nation-state and the vocation of historical practice dedicated to
it.
In this connection, both Ricoeur and White come close to identifying
narrative—the form of emplotment—as a cognitive endowment. Yet in doing
so, they risked subordinating the force and form of historical time to narrative
space and an irreducible linearity that marked the unfolding of a story-line,
resulting in a closing off of any real possibility for historical comparisons other
than the recounting of a blank and homogenous seriality of successive moments
denoting a before and an after.
With Ricoeur, there is a sensitivity to how history should be answerable to
both literary production and philosophy and vice versa, which dramatizes the
imperative to reunite narrative function and the experience of time. White
is right to remind us that one of the consequences of Ricoeur’s theorization
of history and narrative is to show that, despite the differences between
“history” and “literature,” they ultimately share a common referent: “the human
experience of time or the ‘structure of temporality.’”21 But we already know
that such a structure of temporality belongs to phenomenology and to interior,
psychological time inscribed in consciousness. While White appears to have
differed from Ricoeur by evading a dependency on a Heideggerian conception
of time and historical temporality, he still manages to integrate this “structure
of temporality” into the formal rhetorical properties of the form of historical
narrative itself, to become narrative’s time. Ricoeur, following a Heideggerian
trajectory, is constrained to distinguish a state of “within-time-ness” that already
differs from conventional linear time. In Ricoeur’s reckoning, “historicality”
constitutes time at an even deeper level of temporality and permits the recovery
of the extension between birth and death in the “work of ‘repetition,’”22 which
he proposed as the true content of time’s form. In this Heideggerian scheme, it
is already possible to see the positing of a temporal totalization comprised of a
palimpsestic figure of multiple layers of time marked by the coexistence of past,
present, and future. But despite this conception of time, it remains subordinated
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 131
to the form of narrative and thus becomes human (as against cosmic) insofar as
it is addressing human existence.23 Hence, Ricoeur is directed to reducing the
philosophic (and historical) problem of time to a “poetics of time,” by placing
it within the “space of historical and fictional narrative,” where the “aporetics of
temporality” find their “deepest imaginative exploration.”24 This gesture further
runs the risk of removing the dialectical tension between the analytic rescue of a
historical mise en scène and its capture in narrative space by closing the distance
between them, a distance that resulted from a reduction of a distinct historical
time to an “imaginative exploration.” Ultimately, Ricoeur is primarily interested
in historical consciousness rather than the force of temporal circumstances (like
Tosaka’s now [ima] of the everyday acting as a chronotopic intersection of time
and space) that constitute history’s true principle and the source of its distinct
temporality.
This effort to restore the lost family resemblance between history’s time and
narrative, while avoiding the implied hint of a fetishizing of the latter at the
expense of the former, was more recently reactivated by Jacques Rancière in
a penetrating article that aimed to contest what the historian Lucien Febvre
proclaimed as the historical “sin of sins,” which, of course, is anachronism.25
Rancière seized upon the dangers of this notorious temporal disorder and its
misrecognition by arguing that what, at bottom, is a philosophic question—the
constitution of historical time—cannot be resolved as if it were reducible to the
methodology or epistemology of history. In fact, the knotted problem posed
by history’s time concerns not a fidelity to the idea of the past as it really was,
running in a straight sequential series of nows, but rather a question between
the present of historical enunciation and the pasts it seeks to rescue. With this
observation, Rancière was able to shift the trajectory of history’s time from a
horizontal to a vertical direction, since he was convinced that to determine what
was and is sayable depends more on the relationship between time, speaking,
and truth, rather than the presumption that there is a time proper to what can
or cannot be said. For Rancière, like for White, the resolution of this problem
takes place not within the historian’s discourse, as such, but rather through the
operation of poetic procedures. Anachronism thus becomes a poetic concept,
often approximating the behavior of allegory itself, which works to resolve
the difference between asynchronic moments. But the resemblance historians
presume to exist between what was sayable and its time is achieved only in
the eternal present, in a time without chronology. Therefore, in the scenario
depicted by Rancière, the chronological time of succession that authorizes
the identity of anachronism—being outside of time, the untimeliness of time
132 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
with time”) devoted to finding the domain of qualitative time. For our purpose,
the Marxian observation of the conquest of the working day and the recon-
figuration and secularization of everydayness allowed the identification of
those efforts committed to regaining what many believed to be an authentic
historical time, not through a linear experience involving a Hegelian negation
of negation, but by praxis—concrete activity—directed toward an approximate
recovery of the original historical nature of humans. In this sense, Marx’s
decision to separate historical time from capitalism meant that history could not
be associated with a socially normative time as simply empty and homogenous,
or even with a “continuous and infinite succession of precise moments,” since it
showed that capitalist modernity—the regime devoted to the “restless striving of
the new”—had not yet been able to conceive an experience of time adequate to
its notion of history.27 History occurs when capitalist crises explode; according
to the rhythmatics of capital,28 this is when homogenous time is interrupted and
politics become primary. Marx had clearly proposed the idea that humanity
never strives to remain as something it has become, but rather aims to exceed
itself in “the absolute movement of becoming,” which is the “absolute working
out of creative potentialities.”29 In this respect, Giorgio Agamben reminds us of
the split between “being-in-time” as an elusive flow of instants and the “being-
in-history” that refers to an original human historical nature, inflecting the
threefold claim: 1) that a distinctive social being has existed since the first act
of cooperation; 2) that it possesses an accompanying and distinctively human
temporality that has become historical; and 3) that history itself has come to
be associated with philosophy, notably through its capacious totalization of the
time of the human.30
What this temporal architecture suggests is the silhouette of a strategy for
comparison that might allow us to identify the appearance of those instants
when coexisting temporalities are sharply drawn and accentuated by observers
or writers, who are made aware of them by living through the competition of
multiple claims or by being made sensitive to the presence of a disjuncture
between normal time and the lived time of a particular everyday they have
entered. Frequently exemplified by a not always self-reflexive ethnographic
experience, this perception of temporal dissonance is found in those who might
actually expect to see such a spectacle, or in writers like both Sato Haruo, who
unexpectedly confronted an isolated native group living in its own time, such
as the aborigines of colonial Taiwan in the 1920s, and Carlo Levi, when he was
forcibly exiled by the fascist government to southern Italy to literally live and
experience the “southern question.” These and other similar cases reveal the
134 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
to actively intervene in and shape the everyday.34 Finally, I might offer the idea
of world conjuncture itself as a temporal site momentarily empowered to draw
together a number of disparate forces and societies into a unified yet compar-
ative experience, as exemplified best by the 1930s.
The examples chosen for illustration, which will be briefly described, consist of
three attempts by workers in different locales and times to wrest their disposable
time from the regime of abstract labor by expending it in artistic and cultural
activity. These three episodes were initially discounted or disregarded in their
respective national histories, but were recently narrativized in Jacques Rancière’s
La Nuit des prolétaires (Proletarian Nights, 1981),35 concerning French workers
in the mid-nineteenth century, Peter Weiss, Die Aesthetik des Widerstands (The
Aesthetics of Resistance, 1975),36 a historical novel focused on young German
workers in the 1930s, putting into question the crucial relationship between
fiction and history, and the “worker’s circles” of Japan in the decade of the
1950s, whose narrative first appeared in the journal Gendai shiso (2007).37
Furthermore, each attempt, it should be recognized, was implicated in seizing
time from the everyday or from that portion of it that did not belong to either
capital or to the nation. This seizure supplied a temporally unified basis for the
activities taking place in three different moments and places.
To grasp the mode of appearance of these three narratives, we must first
recall our previous discussion of Hayden White’s early turn to the present and
its capacity to house coexisting, multiple cultural forms. White had observed
that the present constituted a vast arena filled with diverse, residual forms
derived from previous pasts, bringing with them their different temporal tenses,
and thereby making it, the present, the site of the historical itself, the “historical
present” and the place of producing its critique. The coextensive presence of
White’s “multiple cultural forms” and the spectacle of competing temporalities
announced a capability, if not an aptitude, for inducing the “fatigue” and
“ennui” or demanding a resolution that might finally consign these forms of
exhaustion and the residues that had produced them to their proper pasts, or
deliver them to an indefinite future. In this respect, these cultural forms would
lead to the present’s attempt to confront the challenges they posed and the
search for ways to overcome their charged occurrence. We know that history’s
principal vocation has been to prevent the unscheduled, untimely spillover
of these residual cultural forms from intervening in the temporal dominant
of the present, to displace them or simply quarantine their possible appetite
for disruption. The narrativization of these three events, one in a “history” of
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 137
later “fulfillment” of the earlier “figure.” In this process, White envisaged the
realized state of fulfillment as having been produced from a kind of “reverse
causation,” whereby the past that is brought into the present is made new or
different.43 Moreover, the “fatigue” and “ennui” transmitted from the past to
the present, especially if it appears overdetermined, now requires some kind of
determined confrontation in order for the present to move beyond its past(s).
(As will be shown below, this theme is amplified when White addresses the
figure of the chronotope.) It is, in any event, worth noting that White’s inter-
pretation of the “prefiguration-fulfillment” model supplies a way of accounting
both for how forms produced by historical cultures are renewed and recreated,
and for the identity of repetition as its corresponding mode of temporal agency,
or, as he named it, “a retrospective expropriation” of the past that strives to
either resolve or make new a prior experience.44
Returning now to our examples, what we thus have is a combining of three
different episodes from different times and places that bear out a common
struggle to actively fuse culture and politics and finally reunite mental and
manual labor through the decision of workers to seize time to produce art and
literature in a capitalist society that excluded their entry into such domains.
The “fulfillment” of events, initially signaling the moment of seizure and
entry, was embodied in narrative repetitions, which are more recreations and
reawakenings than “reconstructions” of past episodes, whose overdetermined
appearance in our present would dramatize the challenge posed by its demand
for resolution.
These are all stories that had already been lived, experienced, and told, and
their example suggests that their importance for today is not simply in their
telling and retelling (the closure fixed by narrative), but in their capacity to be
remembered, lived, and experienced again in the present. They are thus less
about telling than doing, which, unlike narrative, is never completed, since the
images they call up are charged with a productive and transformative energy.
This is particularly true of the illustration they portray of workers in different
times who refused to remain confined in the category of labor and, by extension,
in any rigid system of classification. Their singularity in our present provides
the occasion for their further renarrativizing in relation to one another, by
bringing them together, out of their times in our present, which constitutes
for us the threshold of common convergence. This renarrativization of three
different events from differing pasts and places into an expression of common
resonance allows us to think beyond both their singularity and their specificity,
without abandoning either, to open up the perspective of a making-worldly of
140 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
their history. If they are now linked in a relationship each has not known and
could not have possibly known and that has nothing to do with the immediate
contexts in which each was generated, they collectively signify yet another
event, forms of time still capable in combination to provide agency in a time
other than their own.
The question raised by the three cases and the resonating commonness
that brings them momentarily together was the effort of workers (and thereby
anyone) to lay claim to addressing and engaging the aporetic relationship between
politics and culture in the production of art. In committing themselves to cultural
activity, workers were already exceeding the limits defined by class and occupa-
tional grouping and striking at the heart of the informing principle of modern
bourgeois society, which abstracted and separated manual from mental labor.
Why this seems so important is that cultural activity, based on this division, had
been monopolized by the bourgeoisie, defining its difference from all other classes
and insisting upon the necessary separation of an autonomous domain of art
and culture from the sphere of politics as a condition of value formation. The
workers who laid claim to making art saw this act of appropriation as a vital
component in their own formation; they no longer wished (as Rancière demon-
strates) to be identified with the merely social classification of labor, as such, but
were free to choose other identities and pleasures once exclusively reserved by
and for the middle classes. What this move pointed to was entry into a world of
artistic production no longer proscribed to workers, one which, by removing
the class privilege regulating admittance, would lead to a transformation of art
and presumably politics. The radical effect of the act would be to undermine the
categorization of culture, especially into high and low, elite and mass registers, and
conceivably lead to a re-evaluation of value itself. The action called into question
the ways the bourgeois social order had used art and culture to differentiate those
who were in a position to know from those who were not. To those who know,
like the bourgeois, is “granted the science of the conjuncture,” that is to say, “the
privilege of reconstituting a hierarchy that is principally a domain of time and
value that others are presumed not to share,” which permits them to decide when
it is proper to act in certain ways and what is good and bad.45 But it is precisely this
relationship between knowledge and the masses—and thereby between different
temporalities—that was announced the moment workers began to invade the
domain of art and culture. If, then, there is the time of intervention manifest in
the workers’ appropriation of culture and art, there is also the time of its recovery,
pointing to what in the various movements demands its subsequent “rescue”
in our present. The importance of these two temporalities, according to Kristin
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 141
Ross,46 derives from time’s capacity to give form and force to multiple relationships
of power and its aptitude for “denaturalizing” and “destabilizing” those relations.
In the cases I have cited, the form is expressed as an event, whereby those who
have remained silent and unseen acquire speech, that is, powers of expressibility,
and thus are positioned to realize the potentiality of the subjective moment.
The appropriation of an entire language (verbal and visual), claiming what has
not been allowed, given a fixed identity, resembles the performance of an act of
dis-identification, what art historian Adrian Rifkin has called the écart, the fissure
in whatever had previously secured identity but that is driven by the decision to
now “tear time,” rupture and arrest the temporal structure from which previous
identities, inclusions, and exclusions derived their fixed place in society.47 Here,
I believe, is the relevance and utility of Narita Ryuichi’s characterization of the
worker’s circles as an expression of subjectivization (rather than a fixed theory
of the subject) that exceeds its immediate Japanese historical habitus and speaks
directly to the larger and transnational perspective and context.48
All three events are concerned with enunciation and enactment by workers,
with their decision to seize time to become subjects capable of experiencing
a qualitative lived time and its pleasures. More importantly, each has targeted
the classic bourgeois problematic of politics and art. Rancière, in his La nuit
des prolétaires, recovers from the archive the instant when French workers in
mid-nineteenth-century Paris are launched in the act of stealing time. What
Rancière wishes to show is the operative force of Marx’s powerful observa-
tions concerning the capitalist organization of the “working day.” While some
have proposed that Rancière was actually trying to demonstrate how strongly
Marx had sided with capitalism and the production of surplus value by drama-
tizing the capture of night for cultural work—composing poetry, writing
stories, essays—I think that the setting aside of the night for this activity is
consistent with Marx’s own response to how the worker was obliged to elude the
constraints imposed by the working day—particularly the effects of commodifi-
cation.49 Marx had recognized in the remainder of the everyday not devoted to
surplus value its importance for the worker and his/her well-being as an outside
to the working day. “The worker needs time,” he wrote, “in which to satisfy
his intellectual and social requirements.”50 But we are, I believe, indebted to
Rancière for having relocated the worker in another kind of time and for having
recorded for us the way he/she was able to move from the working day to its
everyday remainder and the possibilities it offered, without hierarchicizing the
two temporal domains. This is a movement of non-synchronicity—a fracture
through which the worker acquires subjectivity and is momentarily free from
142 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
the standard working time and the regime of producing surplus labor for the
pursuit and production of art and culture.51
With Weiss’s account of young German workers in the 1930s, the narrative is
cast in the form of a historical novel that charts the activities of the workers in
their quest for self-formation (bildung) during the Hitler era. Although formally
a fictional narrative, The Aesthetics of Resistance shares a kinship with the
classic form of the historical novel, inasmuch as only the anonymous narrator
(obviously a young worker) and his friends are imagined, while the majority
of figures peopling it have historic and empirical authenticity. While Weiss’s
narrative “commemorates political failure and defeat,” as Fredric Jameson writes
in his introduction to the novel, it is neither a testimony nor bears witness to the
depredations of fascist violence in 1930s Germany.52 Rather, it was concerned
with the “immediacy of the body and the anguished mind,”53 the movement to
fuse manual and mental labor. Weiss’s German workers are in reality subalterns
confronting the violence of a system of abstraction founded on the separation
of mental and manual labor. Their history of failed resistance is inextricably
woven into their effort to fuse the domain of labor with the realm of art and
culture, body and mind, as it were. In this sense, their subalternity had less to do
with representing and becoming the custodians of a fixed and timeless culture
than with the practice of actively making culture while they remained laborers,
thereby signaling the merger of doing and thinking, and self-formation. While
Weiss’s workers share with Rancière’s French and the Japanese workers a
subalternity immersed in the process of an aesthetic education, a difficult and
different labor, the choice of the form of a historical fiction over a narrative
historical account enriches our understanding of the psychology of self-
formation and the labor expended in the signal act of dis-identification leading
to the reunion of mental and manual work. But it is still the shared condition of
subalternity, according to Jameson, that marks this invasion into the bourgeois
world with genuine difference.54
Through Weiss’s novel we are made to see the self-formation of young
German workers, who learned about resistance through history and myth as
embodied in the statuary of the Pergamum Altar in Berlin. “Historic events,”
Weiss writes, “appeared in mythological disguise,” yet not entirely under-
standable to the populace who, on solemn days, scarcely looked up to the “effigy
of its own history.” In the archaic scene that produced this frieze, only the priests,
philosophers, poets, and artists were informed with a knowledge that permitted
them to talk about the altar. “The work gave pleasure to the privileged; the
others sensed a segregation under a draconian law of hierarchy.” What these
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 143
young workers grasped was that art gave to the privileged rank and authority
“the appearance of the supernatural.” If they learned about resistance through
history, they also grasped it through the appropriation of “a whole aesthetic
culture.”55 This appropriation of an aesthetic culture was meant to augment
their political education and develop the powers of their enunciative voice in
completing the process to subjecthood, which, in many ways, would become the
precondition of learning the more practical and contingent lessons of politics.
The first step in this praxis-oriented bildungsroman was a visit to the Pergamum
Altar by three school friends (one soon to depart for Spain), who gaze upon a
representation of the Giants defeated by the Olympians. This inaugural political
lesson is thus “a mythological, aesthetic and imaginary one.”56 “We looked back
at a prehistoric past,” the narrator remarks, “and for an instant the prospect
of the future likewise filled up with a massacre impenetrable to thoughts of
liberation.”57
Despite its longer but recessive history, the recent resurfacing of the “worker’s
circles” under the auspices of an issue of the journal Gendai shiso (Contemporary
Thought) devoted to “The Postwar People’s Spiritual History” heralds the retrieval
of one of postwar Japan’s most promising, if not forgotten, social movements.
By the early 1960s, it had all but disappeared from the scene, eclipsed by the
shadow cast by economic success and the politics of single-party “democracy.”
With the publication of this special issue, along with earlier essays by scholars
such as Narita Ryuichi and the collective work sponsored by the editorial
committee of the Shiso no kagaku kenkyukai, we are offered the ongoing labor
of scholars dedicated to collecting an archive of worker’s circles magazines,
journals, poetry, and wood block illustrations. Its moment in the 1950s,
according to Michiba Chikanobu, reminds us of a context marked by a rich
tableau of aspirations of the masses in the immediate postwar period and before
the spectacle of a consensus society and the “impact” of “Politics” proposed by
the communists.58 What this context resembles is a thick present filled with
mixed temporalities reflected in the diversity of aspirations and desires. Michiba
claims that this mixture of diverse contexts was so discernable that it eluded
narrativization as a “pure bildungsroman.” And he is correct, I believe, to argue
that studies of the time failed to position the cultural movement as a component
of political history and as a necessary complement to political pedagogy. Here,
Narita’s understanding of the historical importance of the worker’s circles is
particularly useful, as I have already suggested, and points to how their moment
brought together a movement of “mass socialization” connected to the social
problem:
144 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
I should add to this that they were, at the same time, subjects who worked. Yet
it was also an immense effort, according to another historian, that aimed to
expand the “range toward a (greater) adherence between everyday life and the
position of labor,” inasmuch as the cultural work of workers echoes precisely
Marx’s earlier injunctions concerning how disposable time should be spent:
Under the capitalist mode of production this necessary labor can form only a
part of the working day; the working day can never be reduced to this minimum.
On the other hand, the working day does have a maximum limit. It cannot be
prolonged beyond a certain point. This maximum limit is conditioned by two
things: first, by the physical limits of labour-power; within the twenty-four
hours of the natural day, a man can only expend a certain quantity of his vital
force. Similarly, a horse can work regularly for only eight hours a day. During
part of the day the vital force must rest and sleep; during another part the man
has to satisfy his physical needs to feed, wash, and clothe himself. Besides these
purely physical limitations, extensions of the working day encounter moral
obstacles. The worker needs time in which to satisfy his intellectual and social
requirements, and the extent and number of these requirements is conditioned
by the general level of civilization.60
For a moment, the possibility for a genuinely social democratic order in Japan
appeared within reach.
We must read these poetic texts of the South Tokyo group and the literary
productions of circle groups elsewhere not for what they tell us of workers’ lives,
but rather for their unscheduled “interruptions” and “suspensions” of working
life when workers try to appropriate for themselves the power claimed by and
reserved for their “other”: the intellectual and the bourgeois. What is important
is the act of bringing the workday and the everyday into closer congruence for
a mass audience that could see themselves in it; by addressing specific problems
of the times, they had also wrested time itself from the working day to address
the immediate question of politics and art and challenge their received limits.
Moreover, the decision to compose poetry or illustrate a theme announced a
break with the rhythms of the workplace and the sociability of everyday life. This
practice, which acquired the status of an event, was neither merely political nor
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 145
cultural, as such, but rather both simultaneously, inasmuch as the theft of time
constituted a necessary step in the political education of workers to acquire a
subjective voice through the active production of culture, thereby momentarily
shifting and shaking the old myth about who has the right to speak. But it was
also an attempt to dramatize precisely the division between mental and manual
labor, which had constituted the privileged representation of the bourgeois
conception of the social order and the class delegated as the custodian of its
preservation. In this sense, the worker’s circles constituted a form of bildung—
self-formation—and closely resemble the historical figures portrayed by both
Rancière and Weiss. It is important to recognize that these diverse, marginal
subalterns arrived in their time like “time travelers,” as if by “accident, neither as
spokespersons nor as representatives of sociological categories, but as worker-
poets, writers and artists, committed to struggle and mobilized to engage in
and provide a diagnostic for the contemporary situation.”61 And because of that
“they are beyond our reach,” “untimely remnants, revenants,” not demanding
debt repayment but rather refugees who came onto its scene quickly to take hold
of it and make it for themselves, in order to fully enter a modernity into which
they have only been allowed partial entry. But they have never disappeared
from the present, where they have remained, still waiting to be summoned to
exact their promise at any moment, for they are “released from time, not at the
millennium, but now.”62
dialectical tension between historical time and narrative by closing the distance
between them. In diminishing the agency of time’s forms, White also managed
to displace the differing and multiple times of temporality that always intersect
with each other in any present to announce the moment of politics and the
“radical immanence” of history.
But in the above-mentioned essay “The ‘Nineteenth Century’ as Chronotope”
(written in 1987, but rarely read by historians, even today), White revisited the
question of historical time and the forms embodying it and invested with the
force of determination and agency, to literally reverse his prior commitment
to narrative’s privilege and its cognitive claims. This essay resembles a classic
instance of inversion, which turns the relationship between narrative and time
inside out. In this turnabout, faintly recalling Marx’s observation of how space
dissolves into time, quantity into quality, narrative time is folded into the time
governing narrative and cognition into consciousness. White’s embracing of
the containment strategy offered by M. M. Bakhtin’s conceptualization of the
chronotope required abandoning the linearity driving the storyline, if not the
genres disposing them, for embodiments of specific space-time relationships
capable of comprising generic environments, criss-crossed by different times
and places. This does not mean abandoning narrative, but rather turning to
other cultural forms, like the everyday, a primary temporal category that comes
to us as sedimented strata of “repetitive practices” and past temporal residues,
yet remains incomplete and open to chance, the unexpected, “the surprising
event,” what Bakhtin identified as “novelization.”63 In Bakhtin’s reckoning, the
novel embodied the sense of modern everyday life, as had earlier narrative
forms denoting previous modes of production and that, in time, would be
supplanted by successive forms of communication. Despite subsequent forms
of familiarization induced by montage cinema and the logic of the image,
replacing more formal plot lines authorizing a certain kind of story, as well as
the further reinforcement of the structure of different temporalities making the
present the center of orientation and experience, the result was not some form
of “postmodern” injunction calling for dehistoricization and the disappearance
of narrative connection, but the reverse. Rather these changes demanded paying
greater attention to both the different ways experience in the larger, epochal-
totalizing structure has been unified by narrative and to the opportunities
offered by “new cultural forms” for newer “historicizations and temporaliza-
tions of history.”64
Here, White pointed to how conventional chronologically defined periods
like “the nineteenth century” might be reinvented and refigured into distinct
Uneven Temporalities/Untimely Pasts 147
sea, Benjamin’s arcades, etc.), than the “period” or any such macrocosmic unit
of analysis. Owing to this dimension of scale, it contains and excludes, but also
functions as a form of repression of older, forgotten residual content beneath
the surface, laying in readiness to be recalled and rescued in the present. At
the same time, it offers to stand as a mediate point that affords us the prospect
of seeing the complex interrelationships between large-scale, world-historical
events, epochal spatial durations, and the world of high culture, as well as the
social experiences, practices, and demands of everyday life.72
But while acknowledging the necessity of contemporary historical practice
to distance itself from earlier forms in order to allow us to finally release them
to a finished past, to find our own way in the present, so to speak, White
reminds us that the chronotopic figure of coexisting past times in the present,
what have been “systematically and generally forgotten, repressed… excluded
or marginalized”—a society’s unconscious—not only regularly stalk every
present, including our own, but also come to us as enactments of “general social
condition(s)” that still involve us as much as those who preceded us.73 For
White, like Marx, recognizes that pasts persist in the presents, are “alive” and
are immediately contemporary “in the form of residues” that will act as “causes”
and “impediments” to the “resolution” of problems unique to our moment,74
heralding the immanence of untimeliness and its spectacle of non-contempo-
raneous contemporaneity. Where such intersections of temporal discordance
appear is the point of politics and is history’s true vocation.
7
To study the career of Hayden White is to study a series of concepts. His work
is not primarily a sequence of monographs about one period, or one thinker, or
one problem. It is, rather, driven by the force of the conceptual proposals he has
offered. The first major proposal was that we consider the formal and ideological
structures of historical texts from a standpoint that was based, at bottom, on
the organizational force of rhetorical tropes in the construction of a coherent
account of the past. Certainly, White’s desire to see things from a higher point of
view, his tactic of moving up to a higher level of abstraction to grasp and better
characterize a complex field of phenomena, found its first major expression
in the tropes. Operating at a higher level than the field of historical discourse
they were meant to clarify, the tropes could serve other discursive forms as
well, and White was not reluctant to extend his ideas to narrative in general,
by focusing on the level of narrative discourse where the tropological strategies
came into play. And so, in time, the language of the tropes virtually disappeared
from White’s work, to be replaced by a discussion of emplotment. No longer
simply a way of categorizing plot-forms, such as the forms he had found in the
work of Northrop Frye, emplotment became an ideological device of narrative,
always forcing coherence (even by giving form to incoherence) on the events it
presents. In this sense, emplotment, with its suppression of any sense of sublime
chaos in history, is far from being a neutral medium for the representation
of human events; it is rather, as White recognized, the ideological content of
narrative form and the fulfillment of the promise provided by the tropes as
narrative structures.
From the study of emplotment, White moved on to the mechanism by
which emplotment, and narrative discourse in general, produced meaning and
152 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
White begins as a young medievalist who quickly allied himself with older
colleagues in publishing projects—appealing in the publishing world of the
1960s, when history was an important academic major—that took him into
much wider areas than the medieval Church, his academic beginning.1 In 1966,
with the encouragement of friends—Louis Mink and Richard Vann—White
expressed the professional discontents of some of his generation in “The Burden
of History,” and then proceeded to locate the source of the problem in the
nineteenth century.2 Metahistory was one result of this. On the one hand, it is a
historical sketch (and no more) of how a Golden Age of romantic freedom and
individualism gave way to the professional and ideological world of discipline;
but, intertwined with this story-sketch is another Metahistory, a sprawling,
ambitious, rather messy book, fascinating and questionable in all its parts. The
method presented was cobbled together from available sources and made to
look systematic; but the most apparently rigorous part, identified as the “deep
structure,” became the flashpoint, the offensive member for those who felt that
they were under attack—in Greek, no less—by the “theory” of tropes.
It was the tropes that turned White’s story away from disciplinary history,
slowly, by presenting a tool so general (or deep, if you prefer) that it could
be used as a historiographic index (as in Metahistory), or a kind of intel-
lectual history (as in White’s essays on Darwin, Croce, and Foucault, among
others),3 or as an account of almost anything else that has a discursive form
(including the description of a fountain in Proust).4 Derrida’s famous “il n’y
a pas de hors-texte” (there is no outside to the text) is another way of saying
“il n’y a pas de hors-trope.” It need not have been the case that Metahistory
and tropes became synonymous; this was a case of the reception creating, to
some extent, the book. Or rather, books, since Metahistory contains a number
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 153
That the mere matter of a poem [history], for instance—its subject, its given
incidents or situation; that the mere matter of a picture [history]—the actual
circumstances of an event, the actual topography of a landscape—should be
nothing without the form, the spirit, of the handling; that this form, this mode
of handling, should become an end in itself, should penetrate every part of
the matter: this is what all art constantly strives after, and achieves in different
degrees.11
linguistics never had a place in the system. For White, the “deep structures”
were never so deep as to be more than “conventions.” Jakobson had provided
a general sense of how figures of speech (metaphor and metonymy) could be
inflated into cognitive models (similarity and contiguity), but White always
adapted what he needed, which was usually a broadly linguistic vocabulary,
particularly a description of the levels of language.
But, since there would be no way of arbitrating among the different modes of
Insofar as there was a problem here, it lies in the consequences. White remarked,
citing the “aged Kant” at the end of Metahistory, that histories should be judged
on “moral and aesthetic” grounds, but the balance between them is hard to find.
In his lectures on Kant’s third Critique, Jean-François Lyotard writes: “the Idea
of freedom leads not to moral action but to aesthetic feeling.”13 And aesthetic
feeling is always a little scandalous, particularly among historians and in a time
that has turned away from formal poetics.
White has had little use for psychology in his work; he seems to share the
disdain for psychoanalysis displayed by Sartre and Foucault. His treatment of
Freud is as a tropologist and follows Émile Benveniste in its general direction.
And so we read in Metahistory White’s explanation of why a set of four person-
ality types are missing. In the first place, he says, “present-day” psychology
is as anarchic as history was in the nineteenth century, and therefore liable
to show the same interpretive forms that Metahistory found in historical
discourse. The second point is more important. Psychoanalysis is meant for
neurotics and psychotics, those who are by definition unable “to sublimate
successfully” their dominant obsessions. The geniuses discussed in Metahistory,
however, have demonstrated by their very accomplishments their “sublimative
capability.”14 This suggests that these people are to be defined not by who they
156 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
The lexical and semantic levels seem to be the avatars of poetry, its prefigura-
tions. Prose, on the other hand, is the fulfillment of grammar and syntax, the
middle levels of language, where the basic terms and ultimate meanings are
deployed, but rarely questioned. And the later nineteenth century, in giving
birth to the social sciences, renounced the dreams of the Golden Age and its
creative, sometimes Utopian, visions of humanity in time, replacing this with
narratives that aspired to re-presenting the past as it was, while marginalizing
versions of the past—those that might lead to a new direction or choice of
ancestry—as “philosophy of history,” a very different thing indeed. This is what
White told us in Metahistory.
Irony is the enemy throughout Metahistory. It was found in the debilitating
skepticism that the Enlightenment bequeathed to the Romantics, who had the
task of overcoming it, in White’s view, but again and again “fall” back into it.
The professionalization of history as a value-free sort of activity with truth as its
158 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
goal was the return of the repressed irony. In the eighteenth century, the man of
letters could look upon the past from a detached philosophical viewpoint, as did
David Hume or Edward Gibbon. A century later, the historian would try to be
equally detached, but the detachment came from a methodological stance based
on the exclusion of fundamental aspects that were either too basic or too grand.
But the way out of irony is through irony itself. If we can envision human
experience as a semantic field in which irony is only one of the possible plausible
(that is, “epistemologically responsible”) ways of figuring the story, then we
have a dialectical view that liberates us from indenture to any one vision. By
way of this higher ironic attitude, we leave irony behind as bondage, and enter
a new world of ironic freedom. We have only to will this to prove that “the
aged Kant was right, in short; we are free to conceive ‘history’ as we please,
just as we are free to make of it what we will.”21 Thus, we have an escape from
eighteenth-century irony, via Hegel and the dialectic, followed by a fall into
nineteenth-century irony, defined as the historicist straitjacket that rendered
illegitimate any fundamentally critical view of the past. And this was followed
by a new freedom made possible by a crisis:
The “crisis of historicism” into which historical thinking entered during the last
decades of the nineteenth century was, then, little more than the perception
of the impossibility of choosing, on adequate theoretical grounds, among the
different ways of viewing history which these alternative interpretive strategies
sanctioned.22
Another, related, strike against the nineteenth century was its neutering (White
speaks of feminization) of art as a significant cognitive authority, by suppressing
rhetoric in the interests of a masculinized discourse. Aestheticism and utilitari-
anism marginalize both art and rhetoric, which might otherwise have offered
genuine insights into the nature of power relations in society and shown the
other elements of the trivium, grammar and logic, to be tropic alternatives
within a fully articulated human community.23 Rhetoric claims to know the
secret to both the poetic and the practical; namely, that they are essentially one,
a figural product through and through.24 Rhetoric is the mediator, as dialectic
had been earlier.
But there is yet another suppression to be blamed on the nineteenth century,
namely, the suppression of the historical sublime, presented as the apprehension
of the meaninglessness of history. For “Ranke and his epigones,” whatever
problems might be encountered in historical reflection are to be attributed to
“surface phenomen[a],” gaps in the evidence, errors in archival maintenance,
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 159
What happened between the third and eighth centuries was that men ceased
to regard themselves as descendants of their Roman forbears and began to treat
themselves as descendents of their Judeo-Christian predecessors.31
been the case,” the future anterior. Because White’s notion of narrative is based
on emplotment, rather than on voice or topic; the plot creates the tale, and it
does this backwards. Only at the end of the tale do we know whether we have a
comedy, tragedy, or whatever. Figuralism in its original form as a mechanism for
narrative imagines a very narrow cosmos, with only two dimensions—forward
and backward, prolepsis and analepsis; it is all the product of the arrow of time,
at least on a given level of discourse. Only with the fulfillment do we know the
figure’s truth. But the figure lends itself to foreshadowing for those who claim to
be armed with special insight, as the fulfillment does to backshadowing.
Backshadowing turns the past into a tightly emplotted drama, and insists
that the actors (like stage actors) pretend not to know what the ending will be,
but actually do know, or ought to. Signs of the denouement are being signaled
throughout the drama. As Chekhov said, if a gun hangs over the mantle in the
first act, it must go off by the end of the third. It is the outcome that determines
what events occur in the drama—everything is focused backwards. And we
judge the actors by the outcome, because we have the feeling that they should
have known.33
Was the Holocaust the inevitable result of cultural and political events, or
the free choice of individuals who could have been stopped? The preference
for the former attitude, I think, is an attempt to match the magnitude of the
event with a large and powerful explanatory mechanism. To say that it was all
the fault of a handful, or even a nation, of individuals, is to diminish the event.
It was, however, an unimaginable event. The paradoxes of backshadowing are
described by Michael André Bernstein:
armory. Lyotard comes close to describing the open figure, without a fulfillment
in view, in his evocation of the sublime. “It takes place, on the contrary, when
the imagination fails to present an object which might, if only in principle, come
to match a concept.”35
White has used the example of a promise to illustrate the relation of figure
and fulfillment. To make a promise is to put in place a figure, which may or may
not be fulfilled—or “kept,” as we say of promises. If kept, the figure-fulfillment
logic is maintained, according to this example. Certainly, Christian doctrine
(but not Jewish) would see the commandments given to Moses on Mount
Zion as a figural promise, waiting to be “kept” or fulfilled by the Beatitudes
of the Sermon on the Mount in the New Testament. Presumably, without the
New Testament fulfillment that forms the model for Dante’s, and Auerbach’s,
and White’s figuralism, the Old Testament would be waiting for an infusion of
spiritual meaning that could be provided only by a Messiah. And, to be sure, this
describes the attitude of hopefulness in the Hebrew messianic tradition. This is
not to say that there is any explicit theological foundation in any of the modern
discourses of figuralism and narrative, although in Walter Benjamin we find a
historical theorist who might disagree. The post-theological role of the figure,
however, remains.
What I am suggesting here is that the notion of figuralism that is the basis of
narrative understanding and of historical reasoning, as White describes it, has
a Messianic anticipation at its heart. Like the Jewish wish at Passover—“Next
year in Jerusalem”—there is a hopefulness, a speech-act that reaches out for a
fulfillment that may or may not come. This is a “hopeful monster,” an unfulfilled
figure. (I borrow the phrase “hopeful monsters” from genetics, where it once
described a mutant that survives and may lead to a new species.) What has
interested me about figuralism is the idea of the unfulfilled figure. Any event
may become a figure, but that cannot happen until it is fulfilled, somehow, for
some reason. Then we may view it as a foreshadowing of the later happening;
the usual rhetoric of prolepsis and analepsis is pertinent. Until the fulfillment
has occurred, which is to say nothing other than that we have chosen the former
(or lower level) happening as our figure, the candidate for figurehood is an
orphan, unclaimed like a pound puppy. At that point—and that point may well
last forever—it has no meaning historically, but it may potentially become many
things.
The unfulfilled figures that I have called “hopeful monsters” resemble both
Lyotard’s happenings for which we do not yet have concepts, and Giorgio
Agamben’s “whatevers.”
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 163
history, find no meaning there and consequently derive no lesson from their
contemplation. And it is not hard to come to this conclusion on the basis of
one of White’s major works, the essay “The Politics of Historical Interpretation,”
where he talks about the suppression of the historical sublime. At crucial points,
his syntax becomes quite tortured. For example, two sentences:
What is ruled out by conceiving the historical object in such a way that not
to conceive it in that way would constitute prima facie evidence of want of
“discipline”?41
And:
In my view, the theorists of the sublime had correctly divined that whatever
dignity and freedom human beings could lay claim to could come only by way
of what Freud called a “reaction-formation” to an apperception of history’s
meaninglessness.42
The triple negation of the first sentence, a rhetorical question that seems to
require the answer, historical meaninglessness, and a clear acknowledgment of
history’s meaninglessness in the second, are misleading. They imply only that
“history” has no meaning apart from the interpretive activity of the humans
who make it. What White has asserted is not that history has no meaning, but
rather that it possesses many meanings, as many as the protocols of our age and
situation, and the force of our need and will, afford us. At the level of historical
reflection, there will always be a meaning—or contesting meanings—offered,
because there will always be a situation in which people must suffer and hope.
At the level of metahistorical reflection, however, these meanings are figures
of our capacity to create meanings, a capacity White has been describing since
Metahistory. This is why the metahistorical level views the level of practice
ironically.
It is important to keep in mind when considering the systematic Hayden
White that there are usually two levels at which the same thing has different
consequences. The model for this may be said to be Kant’s Analytic of the
Sublime, where at one level, we feel pain, anxiety, and even terror (as Edmund
Burke had noted) when confronted with something that escapes our conceptual
abilities. At another level, however, this produces pleasure, the pleasure of
the sublime, because we are able to observe ourselves considering aesthetic
ideas that surpass mere nature. So it is with irony, which is dispiriting when
it dominates the field of experience, as was the case in the late eighteenth
century, but liberating when it considers the field of experience as open to many
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 165
conceptions, of which the former sort of irony is only one. So it is with narrative,
which is oppressive when it reveals to us the fulfillment for all possible figures in
the form of a masterplot; this is the Grand Narrative (grand récit) that Lyotard
associated with totality. However, the only escape from this turns out to be a
multitude of little narratives (petits récits) that reveal to us, not the many sides of
reality, but our many powers of rendering and fulfilling the figures that we have
chosen. Finally, meaning, as Barthes or Tolstoy feared, can saturate the world
and present us with the banal, useless maps that we encounter everywhere. Yet
an explosion of meanings in a truly creative world (of modern art, for example)
has the opposite effect. More irony, more narratives, more meanings, and, of
course, more histories, are the only antidotes to the problem. And they must
be taken at a different level, an aesthetic level, which will concern itself with,
as Pater said, the forms of things. This reverses the normal hierarchy, in which
the more general transcends the multiplicity, and demonstrates its true content.
And this reversal is the scandal of the aesthetic.
Tolstoy believes in “creation by potential,” in which every moment of time
has a vast number of potentials, all the things that might (or might not) follow
from the moment. Things that might, in other words, figure forth many possible
fulfillments. “Each present moment is to have its own irreducible integrity, and
to demand details that are potentially, but perhaps not actually, significant.”43
What I am saying is that reality, the lives we lead, consist of unfulfilled figures,
which we persistently mistake for, on the one hand, proper completions of past
foreshadowings, and, on the other, as reliable prognostications of the future
dreams we project. The idea that, at any moment, our plans may go anywhere
at all is disheartening, because it suggests that our wills cannot prevail and that
our history may be, well… meaningless. Tolstoy’s novel may be read as a satire
on the human propensity for planning; or put another way, it challenges our
relentless optimism that our actions are figures that will lead to great fulfill-
ments. Again, Morson:
Novels, like histories, are themselves ‘plans’—or models—of how we plan. They,
too, select a few causal lines from among the indefinitely large number that
govern real events, are written and read according to tricks of art and memory,
and cannot escape from their implicit participation—and implication—in the
historical process.44
And at the very end of the novel, in the epilogue that shows us the Bezukhov
and Rostov families in 1820, Karataev is invoked as a test for Pierre’s desire to
166 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
return to the world of society and take part in a political movement. Natasha
asks Pierre whether Karataev would have approved of him and his plans to enter
the political fight. “No, he would not have approved,” said Pierre after reflection.
“What he would have approved of is our family life. He was always so anxious
to find seemliness, happiness, and peace in everything, and I should have been
proud to let him see us.” This is the last scene in the novel. It is not an ending,
but we have no idea what the future holds for Pierre and Natasha.45
Here, surprisingly, White calls out for meaning, for narrative fulfillment, some
hint that a thousand-odd pages of life will pay off for the survivors, whom he
calls “vapid representatives of [Tolstoy’s] growing archaism.”46 Perhaps. But it is
also possible to see them as living in sideshadows, like us, with “no idea what
the future holds.” Although Pierre is always energetically searching for whatever,
Natasha knows herself to be a “whatever,” that is, in Giorgio Agamben’s terms,
she is a singularity that is determined by the “totality of its possibilities.”47 This
knowledge disrupts the present as history (and goodness knows, they have
experienced a lot of history—Pierre had Napoleon in his gunsight!). It frustrates
narrative. Instead of archaism, one might find modernism here, a rejection of
what was bad—in White’s own terms—about the nineteenth century. White
says that Tolstoy gives us a feel for the territory, not a map; the nineteenth
century was full of maps. They turned any present into its history, rather than
its possibilities.
White is ambivalent about everyday life and its pathos. If the “hopeful
monsters” that we all are are not fulfilled, so that a backshadowing choice of
direction can mark our taking charge of ourselves in an existential gesture, we
lack narrative interest. And, as Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht writes, White is not
alone in this:
In Auerbach’s eyes fate as concrete everyday life was always depressing. But he
also experienced everyday life as always elevating and exhilarating because it
implied the obligation to impose the forms of composure and authentic individ-
uality to the suffering which it caused. This may have been why Auerbach,
instead of trying to escape his contemporary world, eagerly exposed himself to
the fate of its challenges and trials.48
Dante’s idea of life as figural, to be fulfilled in another life, as the Old Testament
is fulfilled in another dispensation, inspires Auerbach to emphasize Dante’s
originality in asserting the essential historical reality of this life, thus rejecting
any notion that it is merely allegorical or symbolic or in any other sense less
than fully real. It is in this sense that Dante’s Comedy is a landmark in the
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 167
Western idea of realistic representation that Auerbach took as his subject. And
yet, there is also the sense in Dante that the figure—the unenlightened human
life of Francesca or Brunetto Latini—is preordained, in the mind of God at least.
Neither Auerbach nor White present figuralism as an explicit theology, but there
is a hint of this in the idea that the figure is like a promise. In this presentation,
as White puts it forth, the figure is always linked to a potential fulfillment from
the moment of its emergence in the flow of events. Often, this is the case: decla-
rations of war imply conclusions, victory or defeat; coronations imply reigns, as
birth implies life and death. There are, however, many happenings that imply
nothing, or rather that imply anything at all. These happenings generally have
no (intrinsic) meaning or importance, but sometimes they become crucial to
human events. Insofar as they have no importance, they are not exactly figures,
because no fulfillment attaches itself to them at the moment of their appearance.
And it is unlikely that these events will ever be fulfilled in any way. They promise
nothing. It is tempting to say that from a historical perspective it is these events
that cause “the reality effect” that Roland Barthes has described as a part of
realist literature. The reality effect is characteristic of description, as opposed
to narrative, and it is scandalous for narrative, which Barthes believes to be as
figurally organized as White does, although he never uses the term.
We argue, by contrast, that action, life, and historical existence are themselves
structured narratively, independently of their presentation in literary form, and
that this structure is practical before it is aesthetic or cognitive. This is not to
say that the literary embodiment of narrative is incidental to the life from which
it springs, or that it has no effect on that life. We have said of historical writing
that it is an extension of historical existence, its continuation by other means;
Hopeful Monsters or, The Unfulfilled Figure 169
Carr believes that the traffic-control center that Barthes found in narrative
and its figural entailment is an aspect of human life, which is frighten-
ingly dominated by the relationship of figure and fulfillment that produces
narrative meaning. He writes of stories: “They are told in being lived and lived
in being told. The actions and sufferings of life can be viewed as a process
of telling ourselves stories, listening to these stories, and acting them out or
living them through.”53 The scripted quality of life in this rendering is similar
to the scripted artificiality of narrative. It is just that we have the script in
our heads, collectively.
My contention is simply that there is a contradiction between the closed
text of figuralism, in which everything is taken to be a promise in the mind
of some great promise-keeper, and the open world of the untellable sublime,
where we can speak of things only in terms of a language drawn from another
universe—of “hopeful monsters” and “reality effects” and “unfulfilled figures.”
This latter world, I suggest, is the one we live in, and try to overcome by fitting
our lives into the narratives—that is, by becoming the figures—that David Carr
describes. Redeeming the everyday would seem to be the point of this, but
Tolstoy reminds us that in everyday life, with no promises and no need for hope
of anything better, let alone a hope for “the historical,” we find all the meaning
there is, and all that we need.
By transforming the horizontal figuralism of the Church Fathers (Old
Testament figures and New Testament fulfillments) and the vertical figuralism
of Dante (earthly figures and fulfillments in eternity) into a narrative figuralism
that is both horizontal and vertical, White has inflated the figural process in a
way analogous to his inflation of the rhetorical tropes into narrative devices in
Metahistory.54 The inflated figuralism that White puts forth is horizontal in its
relation to emplotment—what happens in a discourse will be shown to have
meaning at the later moment when the plot has emerged. In this sense, every-
thing is to be made meaningful in a narrative precisely because narrative is
figural in its essence. At the same time, White notes, any portion of a discourse
may figure forth another discursive layer by serving as a microcosmic generator
of the broader view; for a text may be a figure to be fulfilled in its interpretive
170 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
It goes without saying that one hardly needs to stress the critical importance
of Hayden White’s work to the development of historical thought over the
last thirty-five years. Yet the precise ways it which that body of work was
understood, and the complex response that the historical profession had and
continues to have to Professor White’s formulations concerning the nature
of history and historiography is not equally evident. On the one hand, there
is abundant evidence of resistance to his theories, to the point of active (if at
times stealthy) rejection. On the other, there is also widespread recognition
that Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe
represented a significant intervention into questions of historical thought and
writing, ignored only at one’s peril. Having said this, however, it remains the
case that the mixed response to White, initially to Metahistory, and then to the
subsequent volumes of essays, was complicated by what I think were ambigu-
ities in his theory of rhetoric and in the rhetorical ways in which he elaborated
it, ambiguities that engendered correspondingly divergent tendencies and
ambiguities in its reception.
In my view, these ambiguities were of a double nature, that is to say, they
were both contextual and textual and involved not only these two domains in
themselves, but the ways in which they interacted in his writings. Contextual,
in the sense that it was not always easy to locate White’s evolving propositions
about the linguistic character of all historical narration within the larger field
of theory, both structuralist and poststructuralist, that was, during the seventies
and eighties, being deployed to large effect in all the humanistic disciplines.
Textual, in the sense that White himself entertained ambiguous positions on
172 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
speech. It does not suggest that everything is language, speech, discourse or text,
only that linguistic referentiality and representation are much more complicated
matters than the older literalist notions of language and discourse made out.”31
But such defensive rhetoric in 1999, while wholly compatible with White’s
early and perduring insistence on human freedom—including the freedom to
choose one’s own past, as he says at one point—probably came too late for most
historians, who had focused on the prefiguring function of tropes. In that sense,
the rhetorical verve of the earlier articulations of his narrative and discursive
theories worked against a clear understanding of his theory of rhetoric. From
this perspective, White’s efforts to retain the integrity of the literal and extra-
discursive begins to look like an attempt to save the phenomenological along
with the phenomena.
The consequences of White’s notion of tropes as deep structures (if such it
was), understood in a more or less structuralist sense for the status of facts,
“data,” the “historical record,” and so on, are too obvious to describe here. Not
surprisingly, therefore, the ambiguities in White’s articulation of his position
and of its reception came to a head in the 1992 conference organized by Saul
Friedlander at the University of California, Los Angeles on “Probing the Limits
of Representation,” with the central question being how to write the Holocaust.
Here, the relativism inevitably stemming from White’s insistence on the inevita-
bility of formalist choices in the representation of the past came up against the
quasi-sacred character of the Holocaust and the perceived need to preserve it
from willful misrepresentation and, at the limit, revisionism, or what the French
more aptly term négationisme. The Holocaust was, as White himself had earlier
acknowledged, “the bottom line of the politics of interpretation, which informs
not only historical studies but the human and social sciences in general.”32
To understand the rather tortuous path that White sought to tread through
the question of representing the Holocaust, it helps, I think, to recall that 1992
was a moment when revisionism in France and elsewhere was at its height, as
was the corresponding effort to preserve the memory of the Holocaust and its
testamentary transmission, at a time when the generation that experienced it,
and hence served as the keepers of its memory, was approaching its demise.
It was also a moment when concern with the Holocaust was at its peak, after
decades of silence broken first only in the mid-sixties.33 There was, therefore,
a sense of urgency about preserving a literal record of the catastrophe, lest it
slip into oblivion or be delivered into the hands of the revisionists. At bottom,
the question turned on whether or not the representation of the Holocaust
should be allowed to be “normalized,” hence subject to the routine sorts of
Rhetorical Theory/Theoretical Rhetoric 179
reinterpretation that historical work always entails. It was as much against the
“normalization” of the Holocaust as against its denial that scholars like Berel
Lang struggled, although in my view unrealistically, to establish and preserve a
wholly literal, non-aestheticized account of the event.
White’s response to the charge of relativism was, I think, entirely forthright
and appropriate, in his continued insistence that “there is a certain inexpug-
nable relativity in every representation of historical phenomena. The relativity
of the representation is a function of the language used to describe and thereby
constitute past events as possible objects of explanation and understanding.”34
Thus, as White had already asserted in 1975, “there can be no such thing as
a non-relativistic representation of reality, inasmuch as every account of the
past is mediated by the language mode in which the historian casts his original
description of the historical field.”35 Relativism, in any case, had ceased to be a
genuine problem for historians as long ago as Carl Becker’s well-known presi-
dential address, “Everyman His Own Historian,” to the American Historical
Association in 1931,36 and it had been clearly laid to rest in the presidential
address of 1969 by C. Vann Woodward, who proclaimed with lapidary clarity
that “if physicists could live with relativity, historians could live with relativism.”37
Equally consistent was White’s fidelity to the notion that the Holocaust
could be represented and that, in the end, there were no grounds for necessarily
preferring one mode of troping and emplotting its representation over another,
other than a certain sense of appropriateness (decorum) or “elective affinity.”
But, in order to mitigate the seemingly unabashed, if “responsible relativism”
(in Ewa Domanska’s felicitous phrasing)38 of his position, White, in an attempt
to meet the rather stringent demands from participants in the conference
for a non- or minimally narrativized account of the Holocaust, had recourse
to the idea of the “middle voice” and recommended a modernist version of
“intransitive writing” to avoid the problem of unseemly aestheticization. To
those familiar with his work, this appeared to be a retreat from the most basic
positions that he had earlier set forth about the nature of historical represen-
tation as necessarily figural, in that it held out the conceptual possibility of a
sort of denarrativized (literalist) historical account along the lines Berel Lang
advocated (and Lang certainly understood it as such in his response to Hans
Kellner, Wulf Kansteiner, and Robert Braun in the Forum, “Representing the
Holocaust”).39 But also, I think, it did not work even on its own terms.
Leaving aside the fact that in Greek there are five grammatical forms of
the “middle voice”40 and that English has none, the notion that events could
“speak for themselves” seemed particularly unconvincing, coming, as it did,
180 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
from someone who had repeatedly indicated that history, past events, and
the facts “do not speak for themselves” and that “stories are not lived, they are
told,” are invented, not found. And, of course, if tropes are structural and not
merely conventional, then the notion of unmediated access to a past, which
in turn presents itself in literal form in the historian’s account, is a conceptual
impossibility. Notably, White himself insisted at the end of the essay that he
did not think that the Holocaust “is any more unrepresentable than any other
event in human history,”41 only that it required a new, modernist style for its
representation.
However, all the examples that White adduced of the kind of modernist
narrative that he had in mind were those of modernist—or, in the case of
Derrida, postmodernist—authors, the point being that, whatever their specific
character, they were produced by writers. But in the absence of an author, and
assuming a narrative other than that of the transcript of a survivor’s memories,
who, or what, writes the Holocaust? To suggest, in this context, that the events
might write themselves was, in effect, to endow them with Logos, and thus to
sacralize them in a way that might not disturb Lang, but surely runs counter to
everything White believes as a historian.
In this, whether intentionally or not, White’s position was aligned with that
of scholars like Shoshana Felman, Dori Laub, and Cathy Caruth who at the
time were working on Holocaust “traumatic” memory, but with the crucial
difference that he was talking about historians and their narratives and not
survivors and their testimony.42 His effort thus participated in what, at that
moment, I believed was a strenuous effort to recuperate “presence” after the
“linguistic turn,” although White himself has always denied access to presence
when dealing with the past, a position he reiterated as recently as February
2009 in a published conversation with Erlend Rogne.43 In this connection, it is
perhaps apposite to recall that Claude Lanzmann (often invoked in this context
as offering an exemplar of the kind of “distanced realism” that Friedlander,
among others, thought desirable for the representation of the Holocaust),44
explicitly maintained that “the purpose of the [film] Shoah is not to transmit
knowledge,”45 and characterized the film as an “incarnation, a resurrection.”
And to underscore this return of presence via resurrection and reincarnation, it
is noteworthy that, in a passage far less often cited, Lanzmann asserted that the
film is no more memory than history: “The film was not made with memories,
I knew it immediately. Memory horrifies me; memory is weak. The film is the
destruction of all distance between past and present.”46 Such a destruction of the
distance between past and present would, in fact, achieve in historical writing
Rhetorical Theory/Theoretical Rhetoric 181
the effect of Barthes’s notion of intransitive writing as that which “denies the
distances among the writer, text, what is written about, and finally the reader,”47
but it presupposes the ability to resurrect the past and make it live in the present,
a characteristic of Jewish liturgical and commemorative practices, but hardly
tenable in relation to modern, or even modernist, historiography. To the extent
that the “middle voice,” as the grammatical instrument of “intransitive writing,”
participates in this complex of reasoning, one is tempted to say with Nietzsche:
“I am afraid we have not got rid of God because we still have faith in grammar.”48
One could easily identify other domains where similar sorts of ambiguity
reign in White’s work, the most important of which would be the changing
meaning of “prefiguration,” which initially referred to the action of language
and troping in casting the shape of the historian’s perceptions and modes of
narration, but came, in White’s later work, to be synonymous with the kind
of typological relationships established, initially in Biblical exegesis, to link
together Old and New Testament figures and events. In Figural Realism White
deploys typology—or figuralism—to establish retrospective forms of filiation
between earlier and later events, much as medieval exegetes proclaimed Old
Testament figures to be types, and in some special sense determinants, of their
later New Testament fulfillments. In typological, or figural, exegesis, an earlier
event, analogous to the later, becomes a foreshadowing of it, a ‘‘type” of the
later.49 Thus just as Jonah in the belly of the whale prefigures the three days of
Christ’s entombment before the resurrection, so do David, Constantine, and
other exemplary heroes of the past “prefigure” and shape the meaning of a
Charlemagne, who is a “new David,” a “new Constantine,” or the realization of
some other figural complex. By means of typological interpretation in medieval
historical writing, the significance of the past is reaffirmed for the present; the
old becomes a prophecy of the new and its predeterminant, in the sense that
its very existence determines the shape and interpretation of what comes later.
In this way, the past becomes an explanatory principle, a way of ordering and
making intelligible a relationship between events separated by vast distances of
time.
This is precisely the way that White has described the structure of
“emplotment” in historical writing:
It is the fulfilled figure that casts its light back—retrospectively and, in the
narrative account retroactively—on the earlier figurations of the character
or process being related. It is the figure-fulfillment model of narrativity that
lends credence to the commonplace that the historian is a prophet, but one
who prophesies “backward.” It is what justified the notion that the historian,
182 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
But as Erich Auerbach makes clear in his important essay “Figura,” in Scenes
from the Drama of European Literature,51 the “truth” established by identifying
such relationships between earlier and later figures and events is guaranteed
by God, who stands outside of time and crafts its structure, movement, and
meaning. For medieval exegetes, the essential relationship between past and
present is not strictly linear, but interpretive and figural, passing through God
to find its final realization and achievement. To be sure, White is clear that he
intends “fulfillment” to be understood “on the analogy of a specifically aesthetic
rather than a theological model of figuralism.”52 Yet it remains the case that
when White adopts figural reasoning to explain the prefiguring force of relations
between past and later eras as that of “fulfillment,” he is secularizing typological
notions of the relationship between figures and events separated by centuries in
a way that, I suspect, few contemporary historians would understand or accept.
For the notion of “fulfillment” suggests that an earlier event/person/type in
some (perhaps only “figural”) sense causes its much later, distanced realization,
hence bypassing immediate local contexts as principles of explanation. To adopt
White’s notion of figural fulfillment, then, would entail abandoning the most
basic modes of contemporary historical reasoning about causation.53 At the
very least, seen from the perspective of White’s own body of work, it certainly
displaces “prefiguration” from a mode of linguistic and literary activity on the
part of the historian to one inherent in the course of history itself.
So where does all this ambiguity leave us in identifying where White belongs
as a theorist of historiographical narratives and history? In light of his lifelong
embrace of the historical sublime and deeply moral concerns for human
freedom, I think I would be tempted to locate him among, or at least alongside,
those “eschatological structuralists”—Lévi-Strauss, Barthes, Foucault—who, as
he wrote, “concentrate on the ways in which structures of consciousness actually
conceal the reality of the world.”54 Like them, he, too, I suspect, is prone to take
seriously Mallarmé’s conviction that things “exist in order to live in books” and
sees historical narrative as that place where the “Flesh is made word.”
9
Hayden White has generally, though not always, refrained from obtruding his
tastes in historiography into his analyses of it, and thus has seldom directly
told us what they are. He professes a relativism that precludes the usual objec-
tions that historians make to works they do not like and is so far from having
produced any handbook of historiographical method, or even advice, that he
tells readers that if they do not find his books useful, they should just put them
aside.1 He has, however, called loudly from time to time for different, perhaps
enhanced or even transmuted, styles of historical writing. “Very few historians,”
he noted as early as 1966, “have tried to utilize modern artistic techniques in
any significant way.” He offers as one example (of very few, not specified) of
how this might be done: Norman O. Brown’s Life Against Death (1959). Brown,
he says, “begins by assuming nothing about the validity of history” and “uses
historical materials… in precisely the same way that one might use contem-
porary history.” Once all the “data of consciousness” have been reduced to the
“same ontological level,” Brown can then, “by a series of brilliant and shocking
juxtapositions, involutions, reductions, and distortions,” force the reader “to see
with new clarity materials to which he has become oblivious through sustained
association, or which he has repressed in response to social imperatives.”2
Historians are certainly more adventurous than they were in 1966. They
have explored the history of odors, soap, anger, potatoes, sleep, lunacy, and the
limitless world of counterfactual history; and they have broken sufficiently from
the model of the nineteenth-century realistic novel to produce histories without
characters or plots. However, as White argues in his pivotal 1996 article “The
Modernist Event,”3 they have not come to terms in their own writing with the
practices of modernistic writing, and art generally, which proclaim the “disso-
lution of the event as a basic unit of temporal occurrence and building block of
history.” This dissolution, he claims, “undermines the very concept of factuality
184 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
and threatens therewith the distinction between realistic and merely imaginary
discourse.” This means that “the taboo against mixing fact with fiction except in
manifestly imaginative discourse is abolished.” In fact, the conception of fiction
seems to have suffered the same fate as that of factuality, since literature is now
conceived “as a mode of writing which abandons both the referential and poetic
functions of language use.”4
Historians who receive the intelligence that the oldest and most familiar
of their few conceptual friends have now gone missing will probably want
to know more about the circumstances in which they vanished and the
prospects, if any, of their reappearance. However, things are not quite as
desperate as they seem at first blush; what White calls “singular existential
events” (e.g. John F. Kennedy was assassinated in Dallas on November 22,
1963) have not been dissolved, but have been displaced in historical discourse
because, White says, it is no longer possible to know their significance. These
“singular events,” White used to say, can be recounted in chronicles and are
necessary but not sufficient conditions of significant historical narratives;
more recently, he has associated narrative with the exercise of state power
and has explored the possibilities offered not only by chronicles but also
what he calls “anti-narratives.”5 Nevertheless, if truth claims are made about
events at this micro-level, and they are true, no matter how unsuitable for a
“respectably scientific knowledge,” they do shore up the supposedly under-
mined notion of factuality. 6
The “modernist events” that interest White, however, are of vastly greater
scope and duration. His examples are events, he claims, “that not only could not
possibly have occurred before the twentieth century but whose nature, scope,
and implications no prior age could even have imagined.” Among these are
the two world wars, a growth in world population hitherto unimaginable, poverty
and hunger on a scale never before experienced, pollution of the ecosphere by
nuclear explosions and the indiscriminate disposal of contaminants, programs
of genocide undertaken by societies utilizing scientific technology and ration-
alized procedures of governance and warfare (of which the German genocide of
six million European Jews is paradigmatic.)7
the same therapeutic work; for it is their therapeutic effect that determines
their adequacy, and this therapy is incompatible with narrative form. The
modernist—or traumatic—events must not be turned into a narrative, because
“telling a story, however truthful, about such traumatic events might very well
provide a kind of intellectual mastery of the anxiety that memory of their occur-
rence may incite in an individual or a community. But precisely insofar as the
story is identifiable as a story, it can provide no lasting psychic mastery of such
events.”10
In a recent lecture, White introduced yet another term—“non-non-history.”
I do not think he is trying to recognize, much less create, a new genre and
find an acceptable name for it. There are already many loosely applied labels;
besides his “parahistorical representations,” White cites docudrama, faction,
infotainment, the fiction of fact, and historical metafiction.11 He has displayed
interest in, but also skepticism toward, the whole concept of genre, detecting
in it a manifestation of power.12 He is known for his fertility in the coinage of
neologisms, some of which have found their way into general usage, but can be
no less creative with existing words. “Non-non,” if not exactly one of the glories
of our language, offers him and us possibilities not allowed by other languages
where double negatives are mere intensifiers. It might, since it resembles the first
two terms of a rather stripped-down dialectical triad, invite us to think about a
possible, synthetic, third term. Less ambitiously, it could help us find our way
amidst the remarkable flowering in the last ten years of books by historians and
others that “deal with historical phenomena and… appear to fictionalize, to a
greater or lesser degree, the historical events and characters that serve as their
referents in history.”13
What does it mean to “fictionalize”? As White (correctly) says, “it seems
as difficult to conceive of a treatment of historical reality that would not use
fictional techniques in the representation of events as it is to conceive of a
serious fiction that did not in some way or at some level make claims about the
nature and meaning of history.”14 But if “fictional techniques” are present in all
histories, there must be something else that allows us to distinguish “parahis-
torical representations” from ordinary academic histories. Ann Rigney makes a
useful distinction among the various senses in which the word “fiction” and its
attendant adjectives and verbs are employed. The original meaning, and primary
sense, of fiction, is “that which is constructed.” (It comes from fictum, the past
participle of the Latin verb fingo, to form or imagine.) Made rather than found,
in other words—but not excluding the possibility of something made from what
one has found. The appropriate adjective for fiction, in this sense, is fictive. The
Hayden White and Non-Non-Histories 187
word fictitious, a second meaning of “fiction,” distinguishes things that are real
from those that are imaginary. “Fiction” can also be used to characterize an
attitude towards information that sees invention or make-believe as legitimate;
this is the realm of the fictional, which parahistories are attempting to colonize.
Finally, fiction can be a portmanteau word for short stories and novels, to which
library cataloguers and blurb writers resort. These might be called novelistic.15
Histories must be fictive in having plots and also, White says, in being
influenced at the deeper tropological level. Historians seldom discuss these,
and almost all who do fail to distinguish between the fictive elements in
all histories and fictitious or fictional ones, which can lead them to make
the untrue charge that White makes no distinction between histories and
fictions. Of course, when historians do find the fictitious, the fictional, or the
novelistic—invented speeches, made-up characters or events, for example—in
works purporting to be histories, they are unlikely to regard them as such.
Accepted professional standards require that every truth claim be supported
or at least supportable from documents (artefacts as well as written texts) and
that the reader be given adequate information to inspect these documents
for themselves. The author must not be a character in the narrative—using
the pronoun “I” is frowned upon—but should be what literary critics call an
omniscient narrator, not necessarily claiming to know everything, but striving
for a universal viewpoint comparable to the Olympian position of the authors
of the well-made Victorian novels that still serve as models for most long
historical prose works. Speculations are allowable if clearly identified as such,
but the ideal is that nothing be altogether unexplained, and where human
agency is at least part of the explanation, historians must try to reconstruct
the motives of the actor.
Note that this sketch of “histories” is formal. The poorly annotated, the
psychologically inept, or the injudiciously speculative are all histories—they
are just bad ones. If the sketch is at all adequate, it should make it easy to
identify histories, which can usually be done just from inspecting the paratext
(the footnotes, bibliography, foreword, and so forth); there is little need to read
further and none to inquire closely into the adequacy of the arguments. Really
good histories, it is widely believed, offer not only a distinctive way, but the only
one by which to convey the truth about the human past. However, whatever one
might think of White’s assertions about modernist events, or question whether
the examples he gave in 1996 of works that “deal with historical phenomena
and… appear to fictionalize, to a greater or lesser degree, the historical events
and characters that serve as their referents in history” really are “postmodern
188 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Keneally thus appears to believe that Schindler’s life had formed itself into
an exciting story—by chance, a true one—with a hero and a comic peripeteia
its end. The view that stories are lived before they are subsequently told by
historians has its defenders, but it is incompatible with any version of postmod-
ernism. No wonder, though, that Keneally found it hard to decide whether his
book was fiction or non-fiction. His publishers, however, were committed to
claiming that Schindler’s Ark was fiction in order to make it eligible for the very
lucrative Booker Prize, which it won five days after it was published, much to
the annoyance of a number of novelists who complained—bizarrely—that there
are insufficient prizes for novels as compared to histories.
I am content to leave this fiction versus non-fiction issue to publishers
flogging their books, librarians cataloguing them, and bookstores arranging
them on their shelves; but even if we want to deny that the books I have
discussed so far are “really” histories, they are much too much like them to
warrant calling them “non-non-histories.” I would not even call them parahis-
tories. They were all written by novelists, and that is probably why they regarded
them as novelistic, despite the feebleness of their arguments for this position.
Writers like Capote and Mailer say they were seeking to achieve the same
goals as conventional historiography, but in a different way, rather than calling
anything about it into fundamental question. When they contrast fictional
writing with historical research, they smuggle in an association of novels with
form and history books with content. If Hayden White has taught us anything,
it is that this is a false dichotomy.
Furthermore, some historians have already adopted many so-called novelistic
practices. Here is a list taken from literary critics and the “non-fiction novelists”
themselves: shaping the facts reported; manipulating the readers’ response to
the characters and situations described; use of extensive dialogue, foreshad-
owing, flashbacks, and scene-by-scene presentation rather than “historical
narration.”22 To this one must add invention of imaginary characters—not to
affect the course of the action, but to comment on it. Except for this, few devices
claimed to be distinctive to novels would violate acceptable historical practice.
“Shaping the facts” is intrinsic to the fictive character of historical narratives
(even though some historians may assume or persuade themselves that the
facts have arranged themselves into one and only one shape). “Manipulation”
of the readers’ response seems to describe the effort at persuasion that charac-
terizes historians, no less than novelists. Foreshadowing has been regularly
used by historians since Herodotus—some skillfully, some all too clumsily and
obviously. Indeed, since historians know most outcomes of historical actions, as
Hayden White and Non-Non-Histories 191
I am willing to call it by any name that is better: the point of greatest relevance
being the truth and effectiveness of the illusion aimed at—to the extent… to
which it enables the reader to enter into such states of mind and feeling. The
truth of such history (or whatever the critic wishes to call it) cannot of course
be determined by a mere verification of references.
Becker concludes his introduction to the work by thanking a colleague who read
the manuscript, but whom he would name “only if it could be supposed that an
192 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Though the books I have been discussing do not really show the sort of daring
innovation in fictionalizing historical events they claimed for themselves,
this does not discredit White’s arguments in “The Modernist Event.” Instead,
as so often, he seems to have been prescient, because since the publication
of that essay, several books by both historians and novelists have gone in the
direction of experimental history writing. Some have followed in the footsteps
of Capote, Keneally, and Becker; others have undertaken much more radical
experiments with form and produced works that can best be characterized as
“non-non-histories.”
“Non-non-histories” can tentatively be described as, at the very least, fictional,
as having an attitude towards information that sees invention or make-believe as
more legitimate than Rigney does, but also as conveying so much insight into the
Hayden White and Non-Non-Histories 193
past as to leave the boundary between the fictionalized and the historical insub-
stantial. Many of the techniques employed depart radically from some basic
tenets of orthodox academic historiographical practice, such as the necessity,
or at least the appearance, of objectivity, verifiability of all truth claims through
references, clear chronology, a reliable and unobtrusive (preferably invisible)
narrator, and the creation of a well-made and reader-friendly narrative. Yet
they present a perspective on the real—not a counterfactual or wholly imagined
past—that is so thoroughly informed by acquaintance with that past that it is
not appropriate to dismiss them simply as unhistorical.
Historians have moved gingerly in this direction. John Hatcher, an eminently
respectable medieval social historian, has recently produced a “personal history”
or “literary docudrama” about the Black Death in an East Anglian parish. He
has invented the characters of a saintly parish priest (loosely based on Chaucer’s
idealized one) and another priest to serve as the narrator within the text. Many
parishioners are named (the manorial records are unusually full), but they
would have been merely names until Hatcher endowed them with experiences
and words. His recourse to fictions, he says, “evolved from a search to find a
new way of adding to our knowledge and understanding” of the Black Death,
and is intended to provide a framework for the facts.30 His formulation leaves
the relationship between facts and fictions unclear (are these frameworks that
constrain or support?), but the claim that fictions can “add to our knowledge”
and not just our “understanding” is noteworthy.
Fictions are justifiable, Hatcher argues, “because there is scarcely any truly
personal information on a vast majority of men and women who lived at the
time.” The documentary sources were created by clerks and administrators with
very different interests; histories that rest entirely on them leave the ordinary
people in a “deep, impenetrable shadow.”31
The literary problems that usually attend writing that attempts to blend
fictions with adherence to fact are incompletely resolved in Hatcher’s tale. He
chose conventional styles of historical writing both for the story of the afflicted
parish and for the unproblematized factual sections inserted in italicized
sections before each chapter. Hatcher, the narrator of the text, affects invis-
ibility. He tells us that the narrator within the story “has a similar voice and
character” to that of Master John, the parish priest; but in fact his voice is similar
to Hatcher’s. Nobody would mistake his “historical” account for a medieval
chronicle, and Master John hardly has a voice at all, since the majority of his
utterances are sermons, liturgies, or pastoral addresses. Finally, in a laudable
effort to avoid the “pish! tush!” vocabulary sometime used by Sir Walter Scott
194 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
and his innumerable imitators, Hatcher has made his characters use today’s
standard English. His characters did not know how rats and fleas affected them
and attributed their misfortunes to the wrath of God, but they speak too much
like our contemporaries.
Whether fictional elements can actually add to our knowledge of the past
is an intriguing problem best left to epistemologists; but if they can, historians
would have to suppress their instinct simply to add them to what is orthodox
historiography in every other respect. When this instinct is given free rein, the
result may be something like what Keith Hopkins, a distinguished social and
demographic historian of ancient Rome, has produced in A World Full of Gods:
The Strange Triumph of Christianity (1999).
It is always a bad sign—and perhaps an indication of fictionalized histories
in search of a generic label under which they can take shelter—when historians
introduce their work with apologies or evasive descriptions of what they are
up to. Hopkins characterizes himself as “far too inhibited an academic to make
things up” and denies having produced a novel—even if his book “has a few
novel-like characteristics.”32 Nevertheless, the first two chapters feature two time
travellers who report on paganism (in Pompeii in 77 ce and Roman Egypt) and
a television interview with a survivor of the Qumran community (imagined to
have been excommunicated before the rest of the community committed mass
suicide at Masada). He does scrupulously reproduce visual images and amass
textual support for the reports of the time travellers and the participants in
the television show. Furthermore, after the inventions of the first two chapters,
he seems to settle definitively into ordinary discursive historical prose for a
couple of hundred pages, until the reader suddenly comes upon a section called
“Augustine’s Nightmare.” It purports to be another “confession,” which Saint
Augustine wrote in 430 ce, “in secret, so as not to distress his closest admirers”
and buried “beneath the floor of his library, which miraculously escaped being
burned when the Vandals captured Hippo a few months later.”33
In it Augustine questions many of the major decisions of his life: leaving
his mistress, his encouragement of harsh measures against the Donatists, his
polemics against Pelagius. This is sensational stuff, and it comes as a let-down,
almost ninety pages later, in endnote 82, to learn that Hopkins wrote it—what
he calls “my invented reconstruction of what Augustine should have thought
if he wondered that he was wrong, and took the accusations of his opponents
more seriously than the defensive stance in his polemical writings.”34 Nothing
seems to follow from this counterfactual exercise. Hopkins in this book has
clearly managed to transcend his inhibitions about making things up, but to
Hayden White and Non-Non-Histories 195
little effect; the fictional elements in the book as a whole do not rise above the
level of arbitrary intrusions.
Despite these reservations, I welcome any effort to vivify historical imagi-
nation. I only regret that historians active today have not yet used—or, more
likely, trusted—their imaginations enough to create an aesthetically successful
hybrid between fictional and factual elements. Hatcher, Hopkins, and Schama
have fictionalized one or more elements of orthodox academic history, but only
ones like invented dialogue or positing modal persons that have been on the
borderline of professional acceptability. They have also carefully distinguished
what they have made up (obviously fictional) from what can be supported by
documentary evidence. But if you infringe the canons of orthodox historiog-
raphy, why not sin boldly and go further than these exercises in the insertion
of some fictions into history? Besides enhancing “the short and simple annals
of the poor,”35 thoroughly fictionalized historiography can also complicate the
notion of historical knowledge that is presupposed by uncritical acceptance of
the fiction/non-fiction binary. It can intimate to readers all the uncertainties
and ambiguities confronting historians as they try to make out the lineaments
of the past through the opaqueness of “the sources”—the impenetrable silence
where no documents ever existed, the vagaries of memory, the deliberate obfus-
cations and unacknowledged prejudices of witnesses, or the sheer sublimity of
“modernist events.”
Peter Carey’s True History of the Kelly Gang (2000) accomplishes both goals.36
It reworks what is in some ways a familiar story, at least to Australians, since
Ned Kelly is the preeminent Robin Hood/Jesse James figure of Australian lore.
In Carey’s treatment, Kelly is the narrator and his infant daughter the (eventual)
narratee of thirteen “parcels” of “stained and dog-eared papers” that constitute
a history, his autobiography, and an apologia for his career as an outlaw. In
Carey’s book they are prefaced by a two-page “undated, unsigned, handwritten
account” of his last shoot-out with the police. This preface, despite its (to say the
least, uncertain) provenance seems to have been roughly contemporary with the
event, and Carey, by printing it in italics, appears to signal that it is authentic, but
of unknown or undisclosed authorship. It has a shelf mark from the Melbourne
Public Library and presumably can be consulted there. At the very end of the
book, also in italics, is a “12–page pamphlet in the collection of the Mitchell
Library, Sydney,” printed in 1955, which gives a much fuller account of the
confrontation between the Kellys and the police more than seventy years earlier.
Sandwiched between these are the thirteen manuscript “parcels.” Carey has
taken pains to impart verisimilitude to them, especially by describing their
196 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Then for almost twenty years they lose touch, during which time both moved
to England (Austerlitz became a professor at what sounds like the Warburg
Institute).
By chance they encounter one another again. By this time, Austerlitz had
decided to take early retirement, partly “because of the inexorable spread of
ignorance, even to the universities” and partly out of his hope to “set out on
paper my investigations into the history of architecture and civilization.” His
retirement, however, provoked a deep mental crisis, so that he could no longer
write or even read, talk, or listen to others talk. The voluminous manuscripts he
had written on architecture and civilization had become unintelligible to him,
and he eventually buries them in his garden. His life as a historian seems to have
come to a dead end; but actually it is only starting, for now he begins to become
a historian of his own life.41
The process begins in the disused Ladies’ Waiting Room in Liverpool Street
Station with his first memory: that “it must have been to this same waiting-
room I had come on my arrival in England half a century ago.” The “sense of
desolation through all those past years” begins slowly, and incompletely, to lift
as he realizes “how little practice I had in using my memory, and conversely how
hard I must always have tried to recollect as little as possible, avoiding every-
thing which related in any way to my unknown past.”42
We now see why the ruin of his project as an academic historian was a
necessary precondition of this breakthrough. Austerlitz says that while growing
up he did not know “anything about the conquest of Europe by the Germans
and the slave state they set up, and nothing about the persecution I had
escaped.” For him, “the world ended in the late nineteenth century. I dared
go no further than that, although in fact the whole history of the architecture
and civilization of the bourgeois age, the subject of my research, pointed in the
direction of the catastrophic events already casting their shadows before them
at the time.” He had repeated his foster parents’ avoidance of newspapers, and
he listened to the radio only at certain hours; now he recognized that his pursuit
and accumulation of historical knowledge was an attempt to create a “substitute
or compensation memory” to protect himself “from anything that could be
connected in any way, however distant, with my own early history.”43
His protective amnesia crumbles further when he overhears a radio program
in a bookshop where two women were discussing the “children transports”
that took German Jewish children to England. One happened to mention her
crossing the North Sea on the ferry Prague. “I knew beyond any doubt that these
fragments of memory were part of my life as well,” says Austerlitz; furthermore,
198 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
“although I did not know whether I had come to England on the Prague or
some other ferry, the mere mention of the city’s name in the present context was
enough to convince me that I would have to go there.”44
Fortunately, he still has his research skills, and some luck as well, for in
Prague he finds in the register of households for 1939 the name and address of
his mother Agáta. He goes there and meets Vera Ryšanov, who was his nursery
maid as a boy and could tell him what happened to his mother before she was
deported to Theresienstadt (now Terezin).45 The photographs she shows him
really unlock his memories (Austerlitz was much given to sorting his many
photos, and small reproductions of them are found all over the text). Now that
he knows what Agáta looked like, he is consumed by a desire to see a picture of
her in Theresienstadt and, from some frames of a Nazi propaganda film played
at one-quarter speed, believes he might have glimpsed her.
Austerlitz expresses his disgust with academic historiography when it proves
useless in his search for his father. He rails at the Bibliothèque Mitterand (now
known as the Bibliothèque National de France), built, as he notes, on the site
where the Nazis stored their loot: “an immensely complex and constantly
evolving creature which had to be fed with myriads of words, in order to bring
forth myriads of words in its own turn.” As this suggests, the book is no comedy
of therapeutic knowledge. Austerlitz is still plagued by anxiety attacks (“It was
obviously of little use that I had discovered the sources of my distress”) and
later falls prey to several fainting fits, causing temporary but complete loss of
memory.46 In the rest of the book, Austerlitz relates, with a mixture of poignancy
and horror, what life was like in Theresienstadt, with its characteristic brutality
administered with bureaucratic rationality. All his evidence comes from Sebald’s
historical research, a good deal of it (including the contents of the twelve-page
sentence), from H. G. Adler’s Theresienstadt 1941–1945. Das Antlitz einer
Zwangsgemeinschaft. Geschichte, Soziologie, Psychologie.47
In picking out only a single narrative thread from Sebald’s vast and intricate
tapestry, I have made it sound like an epic parable based on Nietzsche’s The Use
and Disadvantage of History for Life. This would be a gross simplification, since
its form, with its involutions, disgressions, and aporias, exemplifies a modernist
anti-narrative. Its content is in its form, not in any précis—including this one.
Austerlitz is thus like an imaginary toad in a real garden.
Austerlitz contains a polemic against academic history pronounced by a
professional historian who, throughout the book, is thinking about concepts
salient in historiography today—“modern events,” memory, time, trauma.
Another theme is the dead coming back to life, which is what historians in
Hayden White and Non-Non-Histories 199
their way try to achieve.48 And it seems almost to have been foretold by Hayden
White.
Even if “non-non-histories” remain a class with very few members, which,
given the extraordinary skill required to create one, seems likely, they nevertheless
challenge conventional ways to represent the past and open up possibilities for
the future, possibilities that White’s oeuvre has effectively prefigured.
10
Could we, without any irreverence, or better still, with full consciousness and
respect, apply the famous phrase of Dietrich Bonhoeffer “Einen Gott, den es
gibt, gibt es nicht” (A God that exists does not exist)1 to the problem of Evil: “Ein
Boeses, das es gibt, gibt es nicht” (An Evil that exists does not exist)? This would
not only be a way to sum up much of the traditional speculation on the problem
of Evil—beginning with Saint Augustine—but it would also be a thesis that is
perfectly in line with that of the “destructuring of ontology”2 begun by Martin
Heidegger, which constitutes one of the most important and most intimately
religious achievements of twentieth-century philosophy.
One could even demonstrate that Heidegger’s destructuring of ontology—or
rather, his thesis according to which Being is not to be identified with beings, that
Being has nothing “objective” about it except perhaps the light in which every
objectivity is able to appear—is a direct consequence of the traditional reflection
on the problem of the “reality” of Evil. It is precisely in the case of Evil, as moreover
in the case of God, that the insufficiency of the notion of Being that Heidegger
called “metaphysics” is revealed, a notion he identifies with a form of objective
existence, “given” as definitive, necessary, and therefore graspable by reason. Yet
when we specify that God is, or exists, we do not really understand very well what
this could mean: certainly it cannot mean that God “exists” in the sense that God
“is there” [si dà], es gibt (is there/is given),3 like a being that can be encountered in
space-time, an object of which we can have ordinary experience. Philosophical
atheism of all historical periods has always reveled in demonstrating the absurdity
of the “existence of God,” understood in these terms. However, this God is the
God of the philosophers which, as Pascal said, has nothing to do with the God of
Abraham, of Isaac, and of Jacob, or with the incarnation of God as Jesus Christ.
202 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
Just as in the case of the “existence of God,” it is above all Jesus who renders
superfluous both the metaphysical notion of divinity and, for that very reason,
the thesis of atheism (since demonstrating that the God of the philosophers
does not exist does not in any way undercut the truth of the Gospels). Thus,
the arguments about the reality or non-reality of Evil can be transcended only
by the Christian message of the Resurrection. The thesis I proposed earlier, that
is, “an Evil that exists does not exist,” simply translates Saint Paul’s question:
“Death, where is thy victory?”4
Let me clarify: 1) the metaphysical arguments about the reality or non-reality
of Evil have never been able to resolve the problem they set out to resolve.
Nothing that exists can be called Evil, either because, from a religious stand-
point, it was created by God, or because, even without reference to God, it
appears impossible not to identify the Good with Being itself. This impossibility
of conceptualizing Evil reveals the insufficiency of the ontological categories
given to us by metaphysics. After all, Heidegger began his critique of the
metaphysical conception of Being by reflecting on the problem of freedom and
predestination: if true Being, that is, divine Being, were really pure act or the
necessary Being of metaphysics, that is, the God of the philosophers, we would
not be able to conceive of our existence as Being—since we are history, freedom,
hope, everything except stable and necessary reality.
2) Within the framework of the metaphysical conception of Being—in
which Being is really only what “exists/is there/is given” [si dà] in a stable
form, rationally necessary, demonstrable, and “scientifically” verifiable—one
cannot think either God or Jesus, or the historicity of our existence, or even
Evil. All of these “realities,” of which we do nevertheless have experience,
which appear to us as undeniable, do not “exist” in this metaphysical sense.
But if Being is not objective existence, is not what “gives itself ” (darsi) objec-
tively, what can it be? A phrase of Georges Bernanos (the last one in his
Journal d’un curé de campagne, I think)5 comes to mind: “All is grace.” In
philosophical terms we would say with Heidegger that Being, if it is anything,
is event, Ereignis.6 Certainly, es gibt Sein (there is Being/Being exists); but only
in the sense that es, das Sein, gibt (it, Being, gives). Being gives/Being exists/
there is Being—that is its only conceivable “essence.” I am not proposing
that we simply skip over philosophical language to arrive at that of Christian
revelation. What I mean to say is that philosophy itself—at least in the form
that seems to me most capable of corresponding to our epoch and to our
specific historical vocation—must turn to the Christian message to resolve the
contradictions and aporias of metaphysics.
From the Problem of Evil to Hermeneutic Philosophy of History 203
3) From the perspective of Being as gift or event, Evil does not exist. But this
does not mean that the discussion is over; in fact, it has barely begun. How do
we explain the undeniable experience of Evil? That is to say, social injustice,
mass exterminations, and our own individual awareness of being in some sense
“guilty” (or, according to an emblematic page of the Gospels, the problem of the
Man Born Blind).7
4) For philosophy (mine, ours) today—and therefore not according to a
doctrine that makes a claim to be definitive and metaphysically necessary—
Evil is principally and precisely metaphysics itself, the identification of Being
with existence or “giving itself ” [darsi] as stable object; the confusion of the
God of Jesus with the God of the philosophers. The unbridled domination of
measurable objectivity is Evil, as is the anxiety over the possible loss of this
domination, in all of the multiple ways in which we experience it, from the
pressure not to lose the physical attractiveness that allows us to seduce, to enjoy,
to triumph over others, to the will to power of the great figures of history, to the
multiple forms in which the principle of performance is manifested at all levels
of our existence.
5) But why the reference to Saint Paul and to the question “Death, where is thy
victory?” The metaphysical confusion of Being with the stable and immutable
givenness (Gegebenheit) of the object makes it impossible to conceive of death,
to accept it as “natural.” The greatest crime we know of is to take someone’s life,
homicide. And yet, whoever is born is also always faced with dying a “natural”
death. The traditional problem of theodicy, itself also metaphysical, arises from
this consideration. If one dies, and most often one does so “naturally,” it seems to
be the fault of God, a fault that we have to justify. Biblical Revelation, however,
does not offer any support for a metaphysically satisfying theodicy. Neither the
story of Job nor the Gospel episode of the Man Born Blind offers an explanation
of Evil. In both these cases, it seems in fact that the error, and the Evil itself,
consist in the desire to seek an explanation that does not exist. Human reason, it
appears, would consider itself satisfied if it were able to grasp some objective law
by which the misfortunes of Job or the blindness of the innocent would appear
to have been deserved. But instead, what the Scriptures ask of us in these two
cases is to accept these events as “grace”—as what has pleased God.
If we alter the terms of Bonhoeffer’s phrase thus, “God does (not) exist,”
and we translate it to read, “Evil does not exist,” and this in turn becomes the
keystone of an ontology of the event, by means of which even “a being that exists
does not exist,” but happens, then Bernanos’s sentence that I quoted above,
“everything is grace”—that is, gift, that is, geben (everything is given, is “giving
204 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
itself ” [darsi]: Wittgenstein’s idea that the world is everything “that is the case”
[was der Fall ist]) becomes simply “everything is history.” The revolution against
metaphysics inaugurated by Heidegger is the beginning of a post-Nietzschean
thought, which, realistically, is not only the product of philosophical excogi-
tation, but which also plays a role in the way that Being happens in the epoch of
realized nihilism, the epoch in which es mit dem Sein selbst nichts mehr ist (there
is nothing to Being as such).8
The breakdown of Eurocentrism, the dissolution of the idea that history
provides the only possible development of events whose center has always
been thought of as the civilization of European humanity, is not the invention
of anyone in particular, not even of Hayden White—who nevertheless has
powerfully contributed to making this rupture an explicit part of our cultural
consciousness; it is about precisely the event of (our) Being, or simply the event
of Being that returns us to our existence and to our historical situation. We
know that Michel Foucault used the term “ontology of the present,” though with
much less ontological emphasis than it ought to have been given. For him, the
expression indicated only a thinking that reflects back on the specific historical
existence about which he philosophized; so that it might be more appropriate,
in his case, to use instead the expression “anthropology of the present.” Foucault
was perhaps already beyond structuralism, but his intent remained nonetheless
primarily descriptive. It is only by means of a radical reading of Heidegger—what
I am allowing myself to call a reading “to the left” of Heideggerianism—that the
ontology of the present becomes the only thinkable ontology. And to the extent
that it is not descriptive, is not contemplative or aesthetic (cf. Heidegger’s review
of Karl Jaspers’ Psychologie der Weltanschauungen [Psychology of Worldviews,
1919]), the ontology of the present is involved substantially in the event itself,
which endeavors “to gather together.”9
In short, we are facing a radical historicism, according to which Being is only
that which happens, and the happening is the result of the response that human
beings give to the messages they receive from their Geschick (destiny),10 from
the totality of all that gets sent to them and which, in turn, is nothing but the
result of other such happenings of the same kind. The problem of understanding
the call of Being and Time to “choose one’s own death” can be resolved only if
one interprets it as a call to the radical historicity of human existence; each one
of us is only a mortal who inherits and transforms the traces of other human
beings—and Being is only the crystallization of this inheriting-interpreting-
transforming. Even Benedetto Croce’s view, according to which history is (only)
the (hi)story of liberty,11 must be understood as going beyond the metaphysical
From the Problem of Evil to Hermeneutic Philosophy of History 205
Hegelian residues that seem to weigh it down even now (is Spirit “something”
that has history? or is it nothing but history?);12 and it assumes its full meaning
only if we conceive of it within the framework of the Heideggerian ontology of
Being as event. Thus, as in the famous Eleventh Thesis on Feuerbach, in which
Marx asserts that philosophers should seek to change the world and not just
to interpret it, Croce’s idea assumes a meaning that is no longer metaphysico-
positivistic—that is, if one understands it in the light of the Heideggerian notion
of the event, which is always necessarily interpretation and transformation at
the same time, that is, authentic praxis.
Rethinking the work of Hayden White today in the light of these considera-
tions opens onto a meaning that is not merely commemorative or celebratory. It
has a clearly polemical importance in relation to the call for a return to realism
that characterizes a certain strain of contemporary philosophy, which hopes to
overcome the “linguistic turn”—putting aside for the moment Jacques Derrida
and Richard Rorty, and also, if I may, the hermeneutics of il pensiero debole
(weak thought)13—in the name of an ontology that returns to the early Husserl,
to the regional ontologies that were overcome once and for all by even Husserl
himself, and then by Heidegger, with the shift to fundamental ontology. This
new realism, born from a type of mésalliance between the residues of phenom-
enology and those of analytical philosophy, offers an absolutely innocuous
philosophical thought, whose function nevertheless is to maintain imperial
order. One picks up a dictionary to understand the meaning of words in an
ordinary sense (the legacy of analytical philosophy), then one attributes to these
meanings the status of phenomenological essences, and one extracts from this
a type of metaphysics of the existent, from which one also deduces an ethics,
to serve the existing structures of domination. “In reality you are what the
dictionary says you are, and you must correspond to this ‘essence.’” If one objects
that even the dictionary is just a crystallization of historical meanings, and thus
also of relationships of power, one is immediately accused of relativism—which
is, not for nothing, one of the favorite arguments of the authoritarian teaching
of the Catholic Church of Benedict XVI.
As one will remember, Antonio Gramsci, in his prison writings, called Marxism
the “philosophy of praxis.”14 Thus, facing the always new tendencies of philosophy
to make of itself a description of essences, and, for this very reason, an apology
for the existing order, a hermeneutic ontology of the Heideggerian sort is today
the authentic philosophy of praxis, and perhaps also, for this very reason, the
most radical form of Marxism.15 One cannot change the world, as Marx wanted
to do, by applying a descriptive positivistic schema, as if it were simply a matter
206 Philosophy of History After Hayden White
projectural capacity of the one who receives it and who actively interprets it.
What is “real” is not in any way objective Being, but only that which has been
produced by other beings existing before us, themselves active interpreters,
involved in a process that might have developed differently. Factum infectum
fieri nequit (a thing done cannot be undone) is an old juridical adage that
certainly serves to reinforce the value of contracts and, when necessary, to nail
the guilty to their responsibilities. But the fact that it may carry value in the
world of the law shows perhaps the connection between every pretense of objec-
tivity and structures of power. To whose advantage is it that what has been done,
or simply “that which is,” should appear immutable, and impose itself with all of
the dignity of Being?
In Heidegger’s refusal to identity Being with beings we find that this clearly
political aspect of his thought is not explicit; but to read it in these terms, that
is, to bring his ontology closer to a Marxist type of philosophy of praxis, is
completely legitimate. After all, even the original polemic, already fully present
in Being and Time, against the notion of truth as adaequatio intellectus et rei
(correspondence of mind and reality), is already clearly an anti-metaphysical
(ethical) polemic, and not at all inspired by theoretical motivations (and we
should note that this comes just a few years after Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, when
the conception of the proposition as the depiction of the state of things [the
picture theory of language] was still dominant!). That is to say, one should not
think that Heidegger rejects the idea of truth as “correspondence” in the name
of another description of truth that would be more “adequate.” The inspiration
behind his anti-metaphysical polemic, beginning with the rejection of the idea
of truth as correspondence, can be read only as a politico-ethical revolution
against the objectivism that inspires the scientistic conception of positivism,
which Heidegger, like the entire intellectual avant-garde of the early twentieth
century, considered to be responsible, or at least partly responsible, for the rise,
between the end of the nineteenth century and World War I, of the “totalitarian
society,” as it was called by the Frankfurt School.
It may be that Hayden White, with his “Anglo-Saxon” seriousness, even
if abundantly nourished by the Latin heritage of Giambattista Vico, is not
disposed to consider his own work of reflecting on history as an event of the
“history of Being;”18 or perhaps he considers his work as only potentially a
revolutionary act. But the meaning of an oeuvre, especially if it is an oeuvre of
crucial importance, always goes far beyond the intentions of its author.
Comment
Hayden White
and their rates of growth, but no one would confuse a calendrical system with a
causal factor in the life and death of institutions.
There is much discussion these days on the possibilities of utilizing a
Darwinian model (properly revised in the light of modern genetics) for concep-
tualizing a “deep history” or a species-mutation model of historical phenomena.
I think that it is important to keep in mind that historical systems do not
possess an equivalent of the genetic code by which to map the relations among
generations of the same species, in the way and with the precision that biolo-
gists can do. This is why, it seems to me, that one can insist on the distinction
between genetic affiliation amongst organic systems and the kind of genealogical
affiliations that prevail among historical systems. It is not that the ideas of norm
and mutation are not useful for describing the kinds of changes that occur in
historical systems. But human generations, organized and acting as members
of distinct social groups, effectively choose their ancestors, elect the ideal
ancestors from which they would wish to have descended, as against the geneti-
cally identifiable ancestors from which they actually descended, and constitute
thereby the equivalent of what Freud called cultural “Ego ideals” by which to
constitute a historical identity quite distinct from that of groups that may share
their gene pool, but have made different choices about their ideal identities by
their thought and action in specific “concrete” situations. And it is this element
of choice in the constitution of a cultural or ideal identity that bears upon “the
practical past” and about which students of “the historical past” may have much
to say but hardly the last word.
One last word of my own about the past-present relationship. In his contri-
bution to this volume, my friend (and teacher in matters philosophical) Arthur
Danto remarks that, although it is perfectly acceptable to say of Petrarch that
“he opened the Renaissance,” we should not think that Petrarch acted forward
in history; for Petrarch did not because he could not possibly have “intend[ed]
to open the Renaissance. His famous act of climbing Mount Ventoux opened
the Renaissance only with reference to relations with events that took place
long afterward.”1 This is a salutary reminder of the dangers of the doctrine of
“influences” in history and of the dangers of thinking that one might provide a
scenario for the future in the way that we can quite obviously provide scenarios
of past processes and transformations. In her essay for this volume as well as in
her book Quoting Caravaggio: Contemporary Art, Preposterous History,2 Mieke
Bal has considered whether it makes any sense at all to ask if or how the present
might change the past, and she concludes—if I understand her aright—that in
the domain of culture and specifically of art, the present can change the past,
Comment 213
because by “the past” one must mean that “historical past” which, according
to Oakeshott, is accessible only in history books. Whether the real past, the
past made up of events that are over and done with, events that cannot even be
replicated, much less revised, whether this past can be changed in any way is
a moot point, because the only access we have to this past is that past distilled
into works of history. But the past that we know only as it has been worked
up as a “historical past” in history books, this past can be revised, because it
is itself a complex web of nothing but revisions. Every history is a counter-
history, written against as much as with the archive, and even the first historian,
Herodotus, presupposes a version of “the past” against which his discourse
presents itself as a contending, alternative version.3
But about Petrarch: although he certainly did not “intend to open the
Renaissance,” it is undeniable that he envisioned a renaissance or rebirth of
his notion of classical culture, which he had put forth as a possible program
for his own time or for some future time. This possibility, in the specific form
in which Petrarch presented it, lay, as it were, dormant until it was picked up
by later scholars and intellectuals as a possibility for themselves in a way that
it was not for Petrarch. In building their program on Petrarch’s they effectively
constituted Petrarch as one of the architects of what, through their actions,
became the Renaissance (though even this “Renaissance” was not constituted as
a “historical” reality until the writings of Jules Michelet and Jacob Burckhardt
in the nineteenth century).
It is considerations such as these that lead me to view (Western) historiology
or historiosophy as a complex dialectical relationship between people still
alive and those who are dead or dying, rather than a process in which some
abstraction called “the past” influences, sets limits on, or determines another
abstraction called “the present.” To be sure, it is a process in which what appears
to be still alive or at least not yet dead of the past can be violated, disrespected,
transformed, and destroyed by the living. Why such violation, disrespect, trans-
formation, or destruction should horrify us or why, although it should horrify
us, it might not do so, is the problem that motivates ethical reflection on history,
historical consciousness, and the value that history has for us.
Notes
Introduction
the Historical Understanding (New York: Schocken Books, 1964); Alan Donagan,
Philosophy of History (New York: Macmillan, 1965).
23 Reprinted as Chapter 1 in White, The Fiction of Narrative.
24 Ibid., 21.
25 See Richard Rorty’s Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1979/2009, Thirtieth Anniversary Edition), 322ff. Regarding
Kuhn’s impact in Analytic philosophy, Danto writes: “I have always found it ironical
that Kuhn’s book was a volume in the projected Encyclopedia of Unified Science,
a thirty-volume monument to Neo-Positivist thought. His theory of scientific
revolution subverted the enterprise that sponsored it, and opened the way to
discussing science as a human and historical matter instead of a logical Aufbau of
some immaculate formal language” (Knowledge and Narration, xi–xii).
26 Arthur Danto, “The Decline and Fall of the Analytic Philosophy of History,” in
A New Philosophy of History, 72–3. Danto further notes that “as editor of the
Journal of Philosophy, I see a fair sample each year of what philosophers offer as
their most advanced work: my estimate is that a contribution on any aspect of the
philosophy of history occurs at a rate of one per thousand submissions” (ibid, 72).
However, there are periodic reconsiderations of philosophy of history, such as the
recent “Forum” marking the fiftieth anniversary of Kuhn’s magnum opus: “Kuhn’s
Structure at Fifty,” Modern Intellectual History 9, no. 1 (2012), with contributions by
several prominent philosophers.
27 For example, the article on “Philosophy of History” in the online Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy does not even mention Kuhn’s name.
28 I employ the terms “grand narrative” and “metanarrative” here as loose equivalents.
However, for a more differentiated and precise discussion, see Allan Megill, “‘Grand
Narrative’ and the Discipline of History” (in A New Philosophy of History, 151–73), where
he makes a fourfold distinction between narrative, master narrative, grand narrative, and
metanarrative. He defines “grand narrative” as “the claim to offer an authoritative account
of history generally” (152), which is basically what I have been calling philosophy of
history in this introduction. Like White, Megill also observes a rapprochement between
grand narrative/philosophy of history and academic historiography (such as Ranke’s),
but his typological presentation points up fine distinctions not explored by White.
29 In an interview, White notes that “Like [Fredric] Jameson, my formation was in
existentialism. As a young man I was completely swept into the Jean Paul Sartre
world and Nietzsche” (Angelica Koufou and Miliori Margarita, “The Ironic Poetics
of Late Modernity. An Interview with Hayden White,” Historein 2 [2000] <http://
www.historein.gr/vol2_interview.htm>, accessed January 28, 2013).
30 Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology,
trans. Hazel Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956), 621.
31 See Robert Doran, Editor’s Introduction to White, The Fiction of Narrative, xxv–xxxii.
218 Notes
purposes. What matters is to have seen one or more alternatives to the purposes
that most people take for granted, and to have chosen among these alternatives—
thereby, in some measure, creating yourself ” (original emphasis).
49 See Gianni Vattimo and Santiago Zabala, Hermeneutic Communism: From
Heidegger to Marx (New York: Columbia University Press, 2011).
50 Hayden White, “The Practical Past,” Historein 10 (2010): 10–19.
51 This passage appears only in the manuscript version of “The Practical Past.”
52 White, “The Practical Past,” 16.
53 Ibid., 18.
54 I could also mention in this context White’s recent essay “The Historical Event,”
differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 19, no. 2 (2008): 9–34.
55 The Uses of History: Essays in Intellectual and Social History. Presented to William J.
Bossenbrook, ed. Hayden V. White (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1968), 11.
56 I should note that Bossenbrook introduced White and also Harry Harootunian to
Christopher Dawson. Commenting on White’s Preface to The Fiction of Narrative,
Harootunian writes: “Hayden’s short preface referring to the inclusion of an essay
on Christopher Dawson brought back vivid memories. I was in the class when we
were assigned to read Dawson’s book and listen to Bossenbrook’s amazing lecture
on it” (personal email of May 27, 2010).
57 The decline of “theory” can be traced to 1987, when it was revealed that one of
the foremost avatars of the movement, Paul de Man, in his youth, had published
in a magazine with Nazi sympathies and had authored at least one specifically
anti-Semitic article. The late 1980s also saw the rise of postcolonial theory and
gender studies, which generally eschewed the ideology of “textualism” that
undergirded poststructuralist thought. In these new critical approaches, the figure
of the author is considered crucial to an understanding of his/her text.
58 By 1980, a special issue of History and Theory had been organized to address it, with
the polemical title “Metahistory: Six Critiques.”
59 One could also note, in this context, the influence of American philosopher
Louis O. Mink. Herman Paul observes that “arguably, White’s interest in issues of
narrative was greatly stimulated by a ground-breaking article Mink wrote in 1970
for the journal New Literary History” (Hayden White, 85–6). Mink’s article was
entitled “History and Fiction.”
60 I am referring to the famous 1959 essay by C. P. Snow, first given as a lecture,
entitled “The Two Cultures and the Scientific Revolution.” This concept or slogan
became emblematic of the divide between the humanities and the sciences, a divide
that explains in part why the traditionally humanistic disciplines such as history
and philosophy have sought to align themselves as much as possible with the
sciences.
61 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953), §109.
220 Notes
62 A similar statement from White can be found in the famous footnote to the
Introduction of Metahistory, where White observes that concepts or categories of
thought (such as those used in Foucault’s Les mots et les choses) are “little more than
formalizations of the tropes” (Metahistory, 3).
63 White, “The Ironic Poetics of Late Modernity.”
64 In 1982, White published an anthology of essays, co-edited by Margaret Brose,
entitled Representing Kenneth Burke (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press).
65 In the lengthy footnote to the Introduction of Metahistory, mentioned above, White
writes: “I have also profited from a reading of the French Structuralist critics:
Lucien Goldmann, Roland Barthes, Michel Foucault, and Jacques Derrida. I should
like to stress, however, that I regard the latter [the “former” being Northrop Frye
and Kenneth Burke] as being, in general, captives of tropological strategies of
interpretation in the same way that their nineteenth-century counterparts were” (3).
66 White, Metahistory, 281.
67 It should be said that there is nothing uniquely tropological about historical
discourse; tropology is a theory of discourse tout court.
68 White, Metahistory, xi.
69 Or in David Carr’s felicitous phrase, “metaphilosophy of history”: “this project, it
seems to me, deserves to be called something other than ‘metahistory,’ which many
people now use as a generic term for the analysis of works of history; I suggest
metaphilosophy of history, or the philosophy of the philosophy of history” (Carr,
“Metaphilosophy of History,” in Re-figuring Hayden White, 17).
70 Karyn Ball, in her essay for this volume, explores the Kantian-transcendental aspect
of White’s thought.
71 White, Metahistory, xi.
72 Ibid., 427–8.
73 Ibid., xii, original emphasis.
74 Our knowledge of Sartre’s ethical thought largely derives from his posthumously
published Notebooks for an Ethics, which appeared well after White’s
groundbreaking work of the 1970s.
75 Nancy Partner makes the point that “formal fiction” should be distinguished from
“fictional invention”: “only the formal fictions—for example, significant event, plot,
narrative structure, closure, all the artifacts of intelligibility created by language and
imposed on the formless seriatim of experience—fill the category of ‘the fictions
of history’ in modern lit. crit. discourse, the area Hayden White brought forward
so strongly in Metahistory” (Partner, “Historicity in an Age of Reality-Fictions,” in
A New Philosophy of History, 24, original emphasis).
76 What Vattimo, Sartre, and Heidegger (as well as Nietzsche and Kierkegaard before
them) are aiming at in their discussion of historicity should be understood in light
of the modern project to separate itself definitively from traditional culture, i.e.
Notes 221
from practices and modes of thought based on continuity and the appeal to origins.
Being “modern” means breaking with the past. This perspective yielded the idea
of an objectified past, the past of Rankean historicism. What the existentialists
attempted to do in their critique of modernity was to put into question this
objectification of the past, the absolute discontinuity between past and present,
without however, falling into the traditionalist or “primitive” conception of a living
past (myth). Their individualist conception therefore puts the past at the service of
a self that seeks to affirm its freedom vis-à-vis the past as a function of its “project,”
that is, of a nexus of possibilities.
77 The full title is Figural Realism: Studies in the Mimesis Effect.
78 For a discussion of the question of Auerbach’s methodology in Mimesis, see Robert
Doran, “Literary History and the Sublime in Erich Auerbach’s Mimesis,” New
Literary History 38, no. 2 (2007): 353–69, and Robert Doran, “Erich Auerbach’s
Humanism and the Criticism of the Future,” Moderna, semestrale di teoria e critica
della letteratura 11, no. 1/2 (2009): 99–108.
79 White quotes Northrop Frye in this context: “What typology really is as a mode
of thought, what it both assumes and leads to, is a theory of history, or more
accurately of the historical process: an assumption that there is some meaning and
point to history, and that sooner or later some event or events will occur which
will indicate what that meaning or point is, and so become an antitype of what has
happened previously” (quoted in White, The Fiction of Narrative, 270).
80 Søren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling/Repetition, trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna
H. Hong (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1983), 149.
81 White, The Fiction of Narrative, 270–1.
82 White, Tropics of Discourse, 23.
83 See also Hayden White’s “Comment” at the end of this volume, where he discusses
the “histories of concepts” (Begriffsgeschichten).
84 That is, according to White, the basic tropes are the very glue by which otherwise
isolated elements (congeries of facts and artifacts) are integrated into a coherent
whole known as the historical work.
85 Arthur Danto, “Narrative Sentences,” History and Theory 2, no. 2 (1962): 146–79.
86 Danto, Narration and Knowledge, 143.
87 White, “The Practical Past,” manuscript version (this passage does not appear in the
published version).
88 It should be noted that despite the fact that White associates himself more with
Continental thought, and Danto with Analytic philosophy, Danto and White share
an interest in Sartre (Danto published an introduction to Sartre’s thought in 1975),
which could explain some of the commonalities.
89 Georg Iggers notes that a concept of temporal plurality has figured in many of
the major historical works of the twentieth century: “even within a set social
222 Notes
Chapter 2
1 Richard T. Vann, “The Reception of Hayden White,” History and Theory 37 (1998): 147.
2 Ibid., 149.
3 Ibid., 143.
4 Max Black, “Metaphor,” in Models and Metaphors: Studies in Language and
Philosophy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1962), 25–48.
5 Hayden White, Metahistory. The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century
Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), 250.
6 Hayden White, “The Politics of Historical Interpretation: Discipline and
De-sublimation,” in The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical
Representation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987), 72.
7 Not least am I thinking here of this notion of mirroring, where the historical text
is like a lamp illuminating certain aspects of the past, so that these aspects can be
said to “mirror” (or to reflect) what is said about the past in the historical text. The
Notes 223
idea was nicely put in a comment by Coleridge on Wordsworth’s The Prelude: “of
moments awful,/Now in thy inner life, and now abroad,/When power streamed
from thee. And thy soul received/The light reflected, as a light bestowed.” See F. R.
Ankersmit, Meaning, Truth and Reference in Historical Representation (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 2012), 112, 113.
8 Frans van Mieris, Histori der Nederlandsche Vorsten. Tweede Deel (Graavenhaage:
P. De Hondt, 1733), 210.
9 This fact might invite us to add an extra dimension to Saul Kripke’s theory of the
so-called “rigid designators.”
10 White, Metahistory, 35.
11 The agreement of historicism (as defined by Ranke and Humboldt) with the
circumscription of the nature of historical writing as described here was one of the
main claims of my Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language
(The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983).
Chapter 3
11 Re-figuring Hayden White, ed. Frank Ankersmit, Hans Kellner, and Ewa Dománska
(Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009).
12 Hans Kellner, Language and Historical Representation: Getting the Story Crooked
(Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989), 24.
13 F. R. Ankersmit, De navel van de geschiedenis: Over interpretatie, representatie en
historische realiteit (Groningen: Historische Uitgeverij, 1990), 31.
14 F. R. Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience (Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press, 2005). I am not judging the validity of aesthetic views of history or the
category of “historical experience.” I only wish to point out that both scholars
assume a position that rejects “truth” in favor of something else. This is the choice
White skillfully bypasses.
15 Hayden White, “The Forms of Wildness: Archaeology of an Idea,” in The Wild Man
Within: An Image in Western Thought from the Renaissance to Romanticism, ed.
Edward Dudley and Maximillian E. Novak (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh
Press, 1972), 7. This essay was reprinted in Tropics of Discourse: Essays in Cultural
Criticism (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978): 150–82.
16 White, Metahistory, 2, 4.
17 Ibid., 5.
18 White, “The Forms of Wildness,” 7.
19 Ibid.
20 This device is close to the notion of “the barbarian.” See Maria Boletsi’s brilliant
study on that topic: “Barbarism, Otherwise: Studies in Art, Literature, and Theory,”
Ph.D. diss. (University of Leiden, 2010).
21 See “Historical Emplotment and the Problem of Truth,” in Probing the Limits of
Representation: Nazism and the “Final Solution,” ed. Saul Friedlander (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), 37–53. This essay was reprinted in Figural
Realism: Studies in the Mimesis Effect (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1999), 27–42.
22 As White also notes, the middle voice was used by Jacques Derrida in an
extremely effective passage to explain the point of his term différance (ibid., 39; see
Jacques Derrida, Speech and Phenomena and Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of
Signs, trans. David B. Allison [Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973],
130).
23 As I will later discuss, lying is the foundation of the possibility of signification; a
sign is everything that can be used to lie. See Umberto Eco, A Theory of Semiotics
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1976).
24 Essay collected in White, Figural Realism, 87–100.
25 “Northrop Frye’s Place in Contemporary Cultural Studies,” in Hayden White, The
Fiction of Narrative, 263–72.
26 Michael Ann Holly, Past Looking (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996).
Notes 225
cinema books that both of these texts also reference is D. N. Rodowick’s Gilles
Deleuze’s Time Machine (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1997).
37 See Moira Gatens and Genevieve Lloyd, Collective Imaginings: Spinoza, Past and
Present (London: Routledge, 1999).
38 James Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
39 Eco, A Theory of Semiotics, 10.
40 Mieke Bal, Travelling Concepts in the Humanities: A Rough Guide (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 2002), esp. 253–85.
41 Kaja Silverman, Flesh of My Flesh (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press,
2009).
42 I cannot do justice to Silverman’s rich and dense argument. What she seeks to do
in this ambitious book is to displace the myth of Oedipus, with its emphasis on
rivalry and difference, from its central place in Western thought, in favor of the
myth of Orpheus, which, full as it is of ambivalences, includes thought on analogy.
Silverman is currently writing a book on the relationship between analogy and
photography.
43 Yve-Alain Bois et al, “A Conversation with Hubert Damisch,” October 85 (Summer
1998): 8.
44 Damisch’s concept of the theoretical object sometimes seems to suggest that these
are objects around which theories have been produced. At other times, as in the
interview quoted here, he attributes to the artwork the capacity to motivate, entice,
and even compel thought. I use the term in this second sense.
45 See Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi (London: Athlone Press, 1987).
46 White, Metahistory, 6; emphasis in text.
47 Omar Calabrese, Neo-Baroque: A Sign of the Times, trans. Charles Lambert
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), 21.
48 Calabrese, Neo-Baroque, 132; emphasis added.
49 See Bal, Quoting Caravaggio.
50 This tendency to consider recurrence as equivalent to the transhistorical is fairly
common, although not often theoretically posited. See Jean-Marie Benoist, Figures
du baroque (Paris: P.U.F., 1983); or Christine Buci-Glucksmann, La folie du voir: de
l’esthétique baroque (Paris: Galilée, 1986).
51 See Ernst Van Alphen, “Symptoms of Discursivity: Experience, Memory, and
Trauma,” in Acts of Memory: Cultural Recall in the Present, ed. Mieke Bal, Jonathan
Crewe, and Leo Spitzer (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1999):
24–38.
52 See Ankersmit, Sublime Historical Experience.
Notes 227
Chapter 4
39 This is to stress, with Hans Kellner, White’s “[assertion] that the vision of a given
historian derives not from the evidence, since the vision decides in advance what
shall constitute evidence, but rather from conscious and unconscious choices made
among possibilities offered by the categories of his historical poetics” (“Hayden
White and the Kantian Discourse,” 246–7).
40 “Thus conceived,” Kellner writes, “the purpose of the writing of history is to sound
out the ability of a culture to encode real events with the meanings offered to it by
its inherited and developing literary forms” (ibid., 261).
41 If it can be argued that White accords prefiguration the quasi-transcendental
status of a condition for the linguistic mediation of experience, he does not repeat
Paul Ricoeur’s emplotment of the cycle of threefold mimesis as an Aufhebung of
the hermeneutic circle, whereby readers “transfigure” the prefigurative collective
codes communicated secondarily by narrative as a necessary means of configuring
temporally distended experience. Ricoeur’s prefiguration-configuration-transfiguration
cycle seemingly collapses the distinction between “lived stories” that define
experience at a prefigurative level and the configuration that excavates them. In “The
Metaphysics of Narrativity: Time and Symbol in Ricoeur’s Philosophy of History,”
White gestures at this collapse without explicitly naming it when he characterizes
Ricoeur’s standpoint as follows: “Historical events can be distinguished from natural
events by virtue of the fact that they are products of the actions of human agents
seeking, more or less self-consciously, to endow the world in which they live with
symbolic meaning. Historical events can therefore be represented realistically in
symbolic discourse, because such events are themselves symbolic in nature. So it
is with the historian’s composition of a narrative account of historical events: the
narrativization of historical events effects a symbolic representation of the processes
by which human life is endowed with symbolic meaning” (The Content of the
Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation [Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press: 1983], 178). As Robert Doran observes, White criticizes Ricoeur’s
conception of “lived narratives” (a concept he shares with David Carr), which
identifies historical narrative as “the product of a process of verbal figuration that
insofar as the story told conforms to the outline of the story lived in real life, is to be
taken as literally true” (quoted in Doran, “The Work of Hayden White I,” 109 [White,
Figural Realism, 9, italics in the original]). White objects to “this collapse of the
figurative into the literal,” which “merely puts us back into the position of historical
objectivism.” For if historical narratives are seen as literal in this sense, White writes,
“the task of the historian would be what it has always been thought to be, namely, to
discover the ‘real’ story or stories that lie embedded within the welter of ‘facts’ and to
retell them as truthfully and completely as the documentary record permits” (ibid.).
42 In “Getting Out of History: Jameson’s Redemption of Narrative,” White defends
modernist experimentation against Fredric Jameson’s charge that it represses
232 Notes
politics (The Content of the Form, 167). While White honors the utopian
impulses informing Jameson’s framework in The Political Unconscious for
arriving at the historicity of the poetic forms and imagery that allegorically
sublimates writers’ reactions to the constraints of their sociopolitical situations,
he also disclaims Marx’s assumption that the challenge lies in transforming
a pseudo-historical mindset into a genuinely historical existence as the
springboard and telos of revolution. Over and against Jameson’s Marxist
commitment to historical consciousness as a cause in its own right, White
celebrates modernist experimentation as a repudiation of an “outdated” politics
that leans on a redemptive plot. This repudiation sloughs off the burden of
history in Nietzsche’s sense by relinquishing the “no longer” while beckoning at a
“not yet” (ibid., 168).
43 In Doran’s words, as “a tropological account of historical practice,” White’s
Metahistory “reveal[s] the essential contingency of historical writing and historical
consciousness. This revelation of contingency is not a capitulation to nihilism, but
rather an affirmation of freedom, a freedom born of the necessity of tropes. That
is to say, once the fundamentally rhetorical nature of historical writing is made
manifest, it can have the effect of liberating the historian, not necessarily to satisfy a
will to power (though this cannot be excluded), but to realize his or her creative role
in the self-understanding of his or her community” (“Editor’s Introduction,” xxi,
italics in the original).
44 Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, A11/B24.
45 Kant, The Critique of Judgment, 66–7. Rather than adopting Paul Guyer’s and
Eric Matthews’s translation of bestimmend and reflektierend as determining and
reflecting, I am abiding with Werner S. Pluhar’s use of the terms determinative and
reflective (Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar [Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
Publishing Company, 1987], 18–19). Sidestepping the Prussian philosopher’s
ambiguous use of merely (the German bloß) to delimit reflective judgment,
third Critique readers should be cautious about opposing it in any absolute
sense to determinative judgment. As J. M. Bernstein suggests, “the work of the
understanding presupposes reflective judgment,” which informs the identification
of principles and categories that will act subsumptively. For this reason, it is more
precise “to conceive of the difference between reflective and determinate judgment
as a difference of degree (and use) rather than an absolute difference in kind, since
the former is submerged but present in the activity of the latter” (The Fate of Art,
57). For an analysis of the implications of Kant’s employment of bloß, see Rodolphe
Gasché, “Chapter 1: One Principle More” in Gasché, The Idea of Form: Rethinking
Kant’s Aesthetics (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003), 13–41. Gasché
notes that while bloß typically serves to stigmatize “a modality of nondiscursive,
nonrigorous, or even sloppy thinking” (ibid., 20), Kant’s use of this qualifier
Notes 233
Edition (New York: Penguin Books, 1977), 220–1, citing Kant, The Critique of
Judgment, §40 and Introduction VII).
74 Arendt, “The Crisis in Culture,” 222.
75 Ibid., citing Kant, The Critique of Judgment, §19.
76 Arendt, “The Crisis in Culture,” 222–3.
77 Ibid., 223.
78 Ibid.
Chapter 5
1 Arthur Danto, Narration and Knowledge (New York: Columbia University Press,
2007).
2 Hayden White, “Auerbach’s Literary History: Figural Causation and Modernist
Historicism,” in White, Figural Realism: Studies in the Mimesis Effect (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999), 87–100.
Chapter 6
1 Jacob Burckhardt, Force and Freedom, ed. James Hastings Nichols (New York:
Pantheon, 1943), 72 (translation altered).
2 Ibid.
3 Hayden White, “Ibn Khaldun in World Philosophy of History,” Comparative Studies
and History 2, no. 1 (1959): 111.
4 Ibid.
5 Ibid.
6 For Croce, see R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History (Oxford: Clarendon, 1952),
201–3. White does not deal with this aspect of Croce’s historical thought, which
Collingwood mentions only in passing. But it is important to White’s own effort to
reunite history and philosophy. It is interesting to note that Georg Lukács earlier
proposed that historical materialism was capital’s self-knowledge.
7 See Harry Harootunian, “Philosophy and Answerability: Miki Kiyoshi and The
Epiphanic Moment of World History,” in Overcoming the Modern and Kyoto
Philosophy, ed. Isomae Jun and Sakai Naoki (Tokyo: 2010, in Japanese).
8 Maurice Halbwachs, La Mémoire collective, ed. Gerard Namier (Paris: Albin Michel,
1997), 97–192.
9 For Kobayashi’s thinking on history, see Harry Harootunian, Overcome by
Modernity: History, Culture, and Community in Interwar Japan (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2000), 65–94.
236 Notes
10 Ernst Bloch, The Heritage of Our Time, trans. Neville Plaice and Stephen Plaice
(Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1990), 90.
11 Apart from Reinhart Koselleck’s classic Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical
Time (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990), there have been recent attempts to rectify this
problem in French historical writing. See: Jean Leduc, Les Historiens et le temps
(Paris: Seuil, 1999); Krzysztof Pomian, L’Ordre du Temps (Paris: Gallimard, 1984);
François Hartog, Régimes d’histoiricité (Paris: Seuil, 2003).
12 Giorgio Agamben, Infancy and History, trans. Liz Heron (London and New York:
Verso, 1993), 91.
13 Andrew MacGettigan, “As Flowers Turn Towards the Sun: Walter Benjamin’s
Bergsonian Image of the Past,” Radical Philosophy 158 (November/December 2009):
26.
14 Agamben, Infancy and History, 91.
15 Ibid.
16 Daniel Bensaid, Marx For Our Times, trans. Gregory Eliott (London and New York:
Verso, 2009), 71, 74.
17 Ibid., 21.
18 Essay collected in Hayden White, The Fiction of Narrative: Essays on History,
Literature, and Theory, 1957–2007, ed. Robert Doran (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 2010), 237–46.
19 Paul Ricoeur, “Narrative Time,” Critical Inquiry 7, no. 1 (1980), 169–76.
20 Tosaka Jun Zenshu (Tokyo: Keiso shobo, 1966, vol. 3): 95–6. See also, Robert
Stolz’s translation of Tosaka’s essay “The Principle of Everydayness and Historical
Time” [1934] (Nichijosei no genri to rekishiteki jikan), in From Japan’s Modernity:
A Reader, Select Papers, vol. 11 (The Center for East Asian Studies, University of
Chicago, 2002).
21 Hayden White, The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical
Representation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987), 175.
22 Ricoeur, 171.
23 See Peter Osborne, The Politics of Time (London and New York: Verso, 1995), 47.
24 Ibid., 45.
25 Jacques Rancière, “Le concept de l’anachronisme et la vérité de l’historien,” Inactuel
6 (1996), 53–69.
26 Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism (London and New York: Verso, 2000),
101–10.
27 Agamben, Infancy and History, 99–100.
28 Bensaid, Marx For Our Times, 35; see also Henri Lefebvre, Rhythmanalysis, Space,
Time and Everyday Life, trans. Stuart Elden and Gerald Moore (London, New
York: Continuum, 2004), for the first real attempt to chart the temporal rhythms in
capitalist life, a veritable “rhythmology.”
Notes 237
44 Ibid., 271.
45 Kristin Ross, “Historicizing Untimeliness,” in History, Politics, Aesthetics: Jacques
Rancière ed. Gabriel Rockhill and Philip West (Durham, NC: Duke University
Press, 2009), 24.
46 Ibid.
47 Quoted in ibid., 23.
48 Narita Ryuichi, “Sakuru undo no jidai e no danpen” (Fragment on the Circle
Movement of the 1950s), in Bungaku (Literature) 5, no. 6 (2004): 115. See also
Michiba, in Gendai shiso, 38.
49 See Ross, “Historicizing Untimeliness,” 23.
50 Karl Marx, Capital, A Critique of Political Economy, trans. Ben Fowkes (London:
Penguin, 1975), I, 341.
51 Ross, “Historicizing Untimeliness,” 23–4.
52 Fredric Jameson, Foreword to Weiss, The Aesthetics of Resistance, x.
53 Ibid.
54 Ibid., ix-xix.
55 Ibid., x.
56 Ibid.
57 Weiss, The Aesthetics of Resistance, 9.
58 Gendai shiso, 38.
59 Ibid.
60 Marx, Capital, I, 341.
61 Ross, “Historicizing Untimeliness,” 25.
62 Agamben, Infancy and History, 105.
63 Osborne, The Politics of Time, 197.
64 Ibid.
65 White, The Fiction of Narrative, 243.
66 Bensaid, Marx for Our Time, 32. I am also indebted to Bensaid’s La Discordance des
temps (Paris: Les Editions de la Passion, 1995) for my own understanding of uneven
and untimely temporalities, for what he names contretemps as the French equivalent
to Marx’s formulations on the coexistent heterogeneity of times.
67 Ibid.
68 Quoted in White, The Fiction of Narrative, 240.
69 Ibid., 242.
70 Ibid.
71 Ibid., 243.
72 Ibid., 242.
73 Ibid., 244.
74 Ibid., 246.
Notes 239
Chapter 7
1 White’s doctoral dissertation dealt with medieval Church history and was entitled
“The Conflict of Papal Leadership Ideals from Gregory VII to St. Bernard de
Clarivaux with Special Reference to the Papal Schism of 1130” (University of
Michigan, 1955).
2 See Hayden White, Tropics of Discourse: Essays in Cultural Criticism (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978).
3 See the following essays, collected in White’s Tropics of Discourse: “Foucault Decoded:
Notes from Underground”; “What Is Living and What Is Dead in Croce’s Criticism
of Vico”; “Fictions of Factual Representation” (which contains a section on Darwin).
4 See White’s essay “Narrative, Description, and Tropology in Proust” in Figural
Realism: Studies in the Mimesis Effect (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1999), 126–46.
5 See Hans Kellner, “Twenty Years After: A Note on Metahistories and Their
Horizons,” Storia della storiografia 24 (1993): 109–17.
6 See James Mellard, Doing Tropology: Analysis of Narrative Discourse (Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 1987).
7 See Peter Brooks, “Aesthetics and Ideology: What Happened to Poetics?” Critical
Inquiry 20, no. 3 (1994): 509–23.
8 See Hayden White, “Foucault Decoded: Notes from Underground,” in White,
Tropics of Discourse, 230–60.
9 See Hayden White, “New Historicism: A Comment,” in The New Historicism:
Political Commitment and the Postmodern Critic, ed. H. Aram Veeser (New York:
Routledge, 1989). This essay was republished in White’s Figural Realism as part of
chapter 3: “Formalist and Contextualist Strategies in Historical Explanation.”
10 See “Figura” in Erich Auerbach, Scenes from the Drama of European Literature
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 11–78.
11 Walter Pater, The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry (New York: New American
Library, 1959), 95.
12 Hayden White, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century
Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), 275–6.
13 Jean-François Lyotard, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime, trans. Elizabeth
Rottenberg (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994), 139.
14 White, Metahistory, 430.
15 Ibid., 281–330.
16 White, Figural Mimesis, 99.
17 Lionel Gossman, “History and Literature: Reproduction or Signification,” in The
Writing of History: Literary Form and Historical Understanding, ed. R. Canary and
H. Kosicki (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1978): 23–4.
240 Notes
18 Ibid.
19 White, Metahistory, 433
20 Hans Kellner, “Twenty Years After,” 116.
21 White, Metahistory, 433.
22 Ibid., 432.
23 See White, “The Suppression of Rhetoric in the Nineteenth C entury,” in The Fiction
of Narrative: Essays on History, Literature, and Theory, 1957–2007, ed. Robert Doran
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010), 302–3.
24 Ibid., 300–1.
25 Hayden White, The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical
Representation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987), 71.
26 See Roland Barthes, The Rustle of Language (New York: Hill and Wang, 1986).
27 White, Figural Realism, 39–40, original emphasis.
28 Roland Barthes, The Semiotic Challenge (New York: Hill and Wang, 1988), 95.
29 Roland Barthes, Roland Barthes (New York: Hill and Wang, 1977), 87.
30 Re-Figuring Hayden White, ed. F. R. Ankersmit, Ewa Domanska, and Hans Kellner
(Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2009). The essay in question “What is
a Historical System?” has been republished in White, The Fiction of Narrative,
chapter 8.
31 White, The Fiction of Narrative, 132, original emphasis.
32 Ibid., original emphasis.
33 Gary Saul Morson, Hidden in Plain View: Narrative and Creative Potentials in ‘War
and Peace’ (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1987), 236–7.
34 Michael André Bernstein, “Against Foreshadowing,” in The Holocaust: Theoretical
Readings, ed. N. Levi and M. Rothberg (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University
Press, 2003), 348.
35 Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans.
Geoffrey Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1988), 78.
36 Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, 78.
37 Hans Kellner, “Naive and Sentimental Realism: From Advent to Event,” Storia della
storiografia 22 (1992): 117–23.
38 Hayden White, “Against Historical Realism: A Reading of War and Peace,” New Left
Review 46 (2007): 110.
39 Ibid., 97.
40 Morson, Hidden in Plain View, 293.
41 White, The Content of the Form, 64.
42 Ibid., 72.
43 Morson, Hidden in Plain View, 185.
44 Ibid., 129.
Notes 241
Chapter 8
“it is not necessary that these analyses be homologous, that is, that each of the objects
in question be seen as doing the same thing, having the same structure or emitting
the same message. What is crucial is that, by being able to use the same language
about each of these quite distinct objects or levels of an object, we can restore at least
methodologically the lost unity of social life and demonstrate that widely distant
elements of the social totality are ultimately part of the same global process” (226).
11 Quoted in Lee Patterson, Negotiating the Past: The Historical Understanding of
Medieval Literature (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987), xi. See also
Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1978), 98–9; and Raymond Williams, Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and
Society (New York: Oxford University Press, rev. edn, 1985), 204–6. Mediation in its
“classical” sense here corresponds to Williams’s definition (ii), while Adorno’s falls
within his category (iii).
12 Peter Haidu, “The Dialectics of Unspeakability: Language, Silence and the
Narratives of Desubjectification,” in Probing the Limits of Representation: Nazism
and the ‘Final Solution,’ ed. Saul Friedlander (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1992), 294.
13 Richard T. Vann, “The Reception of Hayden White,” History and Theory 37 (1998):
149.
14 “Historicism, History and the Figurative Imagination,” History and Theory 14, no. 4,
Beiheft 14: Essays on Historicism (1975): 58.
15 For a comparable view of tropes functioning as “deep structures” in White’s
Metahistory, although approached from a rather different perspective, see the
interesting essay by Herman Paul, “Metahistorical Prefigurations: Towards a
Re-Interpretation of Tropology in Hayden White,” Journal of Interdisciplinary
Studies in History and Archaeology 1 (2004): 1–19. Paul makes a compelling case
that, despite White’s insistence on tropes as linguistically cast modes of historical
consciousness and the constitutive role of language in comprehending reality, in
Metahistory tropes refer, in effect, not to the actual linguistic or literary properties
of the historical texts analyzed, but rather to metahistorical concepts, that is to
say, to the moral, aesthetic, and ontological presuppositions underlying historical
writing and thought.
16 Hayden White, “The Fictions of Factual Representation,” in White, Tropics of
Discourse, 121.
17 See, for example, Hayden White, “Historical Emplotment and the Problem of Truth
in Historical Representation,” in White, Figural Realism, 28.
18 White, The Fiction of Narrative, 160.
19 Cited in Richard T. Vann, “The Reception of Hayden White,” 153.
20 A definition proffered in “The Politics of Historical Interpretation: Discipline and
De-Sublimation,” Critical Inquiry 9 (1982): 123.
Notes 243
Chapter 9
16 Quoted in John Hollowell, Fact and Fiction: The New Journalism and the
Non-Fiction Novel (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1977), 79.
17 Quoted in ibid., 64.
18 Norman Mailer, The Executioner’s Song (Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1979),
1051–2.
19 This argument is made most fully by Mailer in his Armies of the Night: History as a
Novel, the Novel as History (New York: Signet, 1968), 384.
20 I am no expert on what White calls “historiophoty,” but when I read the book after
seeing the movie, I was surprised by how faithful the adaptation seemed. I do not
think it was any more “parahistorical” than the book.
21 Thomas Keneally, Schindler’s Ark, Text Plus Edition with introduction by Keneally
and notes by Terry Downie (London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1989), iv-vi.
22 John Hollowell, Fact and Fiction, 85, 91, 70.
23 This is a sentence that refers to an event in terms that incorporates information
about posterior events, such as: “The Thirty Years War began in 1618.” See Arthur
Danto, “Narrative Sentences,” History and Theory 2 (1962): 146, 155.
24 And of course other figural readers who appear in Auerbach’s Mimesis and White’s
Figural Realism.
25 On this, see White, Figural Realism, 76–9.
26 See, for example: Garrett Mattingly, The Armada (New York: Houghton Mifflin
Company, 1959), 39, 49, 228–9, 240, 243, 379, 384, and 388; and Garrett Mattingly,
Catherine of Aragon (Boston: Little, Brown, 1941), 74–5, 77, 101–3, 106–7, 119,
280, 286, 290. Mattingly’s annotations are skimpy at best, and in 1960 he issued an
edition of Catherine of Aragon without any footnotes. Hans Kellner in Language
and Historical Representation: Getting the Story Crooked (Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1989), 45–7, spotted one bit of clearly invented speech and gives
the best short discussion of invented speeches that I have encountered.
27 Carl Becker, The Eve of the Revolution: A Chronicle of the Breach with England (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1919), vii-viii.
28 In Dead Certainties (Unwarrented Speculations) (New York: Vintage, 1991), Part
One, “The Many Deaths of General Wolfe,” Simon Schama imagines what a soldier
fighting with General Wolfe before and in the battle for the Heights of Abraham
might have said about his situation. At least he does not speak like an Ivy League
professor.
29 See the reviews in the American Historical Review 24 (1919), 734–5; and American
Historical Review 47 (1941–2), 579–80.
30 John Hatcher, The Black Death: A Personal History (Philadelphia: Da Capo Press,
2008), ix.
31 Ibid., x-xi. The same claim is made, and artfully vindicated, in Melanie McGrath’s
Hopping: The Hidden Lives of an East End Hop Picking Family (London: Fourth
Notes 247
Chapter 10
Chapter 11
1 Arthur Danto, “Hayden White and Me: Two Systems of Philosophy of History,”
Chapter 5 of this volume.
2 Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999.
3 Recall that Herodotus is specifically writing against the legends, lies, and stories
handed down by what he calls the logographoi or storytellers more interested in
repeating the anecdotes from the past than in discovering what can be said about
the Greek past on the basis of “inquiry” (historia).
Index
figuralism 23–6, 28–33, 93–4, 97–8, 152, Hansen, Mark 80–1, 225
160–2, 167–70, 181–2 Harlan, David 71, 160
figurative language (versus literal language) Harootunian, Harry 2, 15, 19, 29, 215, 219,
11, 18, 90, 175, 231, 243 235, 237
Flaubert, Gustave 168 Hartman, Geoffrey 244
formalism 26, 40, 68–72, 82, 174 Haruo, Sato 133
Foucault, Michel 16, 18, 39, 70, 127, 152–3, Hatcher, John: The Black Death: A Personal
155–6, 173, 177, 182, 204 History 32, 193–5, 246
The Order of Things (Les mots et les Hegel, G. W. F. 3–6, 43, 55, 96, 100, 103–4,
choses) 9, 36, 220, 243 111–12, 115, 120, 126, 133, 158, 205,
Francis I, Emperor of Austria 57–8 209–10, 233, 234, 248
Frankfurt School 100, 207 Heidegger, Martin 17, 32, 100, 130, 132,
free indirect discourse 188 159, 201–2, 204–7, 218, 220, 233, 249
Frege, Gottlob 58–60 Being and Time 8, 13–15, 134, 218, 222,
French Revolution 10, 126 248
Freud, Sigmund 56, 98, 103, 155–6, 164, Hempel, Carl xxiii, 8, 28
177, 212, 243 Covering Law 7, 112, 216
Friedlander, Saul 178, 180, 224, 242, 243, 244 “The Function of General Laws in
Frye, Northrop 18, 21, 13, 48, 76, 92, 138, History” 6–7, 111–13
151, 153–4, 172, 175, 220, 221, 224, Herder, J. G. von 3
230 hermeneutics 2, 33, 115, 205
Anatomy of Criticism 18, 92 Herodotus 190, 213, 250
fulfillment (and prefiguration) 22–5, 30, Hesse, Mary 53
33, 41–2, 76, 94, 97, 138–9, 151, Hideo, Kobayashi 124
154, 156–7, 160–2, 165–70, 181–2, Hilbert, David 60
218, 245 Hillgruber, Andreas 42, 44, 218, 222
historical
Gadamer, Hans-Georg 39 change 86, 138
Gallie, W. H. 8, 216 consciousness 3, 9, 18, 94, 120–1, 131,
Gardiner, Patrick 7, 216 145, 177, 213, 232, 242
Geertz, Clifford 172 knowledge 4, 32, 51, 54, 61, 63, 93, 195,
Geisteswissenschaft (sciences of spirit) 6–7, 197, 211
111 meaning 5, 10, 22–4, 26, 50–1, 161,
genealogy 159–60 164, 205
Gentile, Giovanni 6 reality 4, 16, 19–23, 26–7, 32, 72, 93–4,
Gibbon, Edward 3, 158 166, 186, 213, 233
Goldmann, Lucien 220 system (sociocultural system) 12–13,
Gorgias 154 160, 212
Gospels 13, 202–3 understanding 28, 57, 64, 244
Gossman, Lionel 156, 239 histories of concepts (Begriffsgeschichten)
grammar (grammarians) 18, 106, 112, 209–10, 221
157–9, 181 Historikerstreit (historian’s debate) 30, 43
Gramsci, Antonio 127, 205, 249 Holocaust 30–1, 44, 72, 88, 89, 159, 161,
Guattari, Félix 226 178–80, 185, 243, 243, 245
Hopkins, Keith: A World Full of Gods: The
Habermas, Jürgen 39, 71, 115, 223 Strange Triumph of Christianity 32,
Haidu, Peter 174, 242 194–5, 247
Hajime, Tanabe 130 human sciences (sciences of man) 6–7, 25,
Halbwachs, Maurice 124, 234 36, 38, 40, 43 see also social science
254 Index
myth 11, 22, 37–8, 40–1, 71, 73, 75, 79, poetics 89, 96, 101–2, 131, 153, 155, 231,
142–3, 221, 226 239
Pomian, Krzysztof 39, 236
Nagel, Ernest 110 Popper, Karl 54
Napoleon I 10, 58, 166 The Poverty of Historicism 6, 114, 216
Napoleon III (Louis Bonaparte) 43 positivism 28, 36, 45
narrative 2, 4, 17, 20–5, 30, 37–45, 70–1, logical positivism 111, 115, 207
94–8, 101, 110–11, 119–21, 123–5, postmodernism 188, 190
127, 129–1, 134–9, 142, 145–7, poststructuralism 30, 172–4
151–3, 155–7, 159, 161–2, 166–70, praxis 14, 16, 133, 143, 205–7
174, 178, 180–2, 184–7, 193, 198, prefiguration (and fulfillment) 22–3, 25,
219, 220, 227, 230, 231, 233–4 31, 76, 89–107, 117, 139, 181–2,
grand narrative (grand récit) 9, 165, 217 191
metanarrative 9, 29, 217 linguistic 19, 22–3, 27, 31, 89–107, 120,
narrative sentences 28, 113–15, 117, 122, 157, 181–2, 231
191, 221, 246 prehistory 210
Naturwissenschaft (science of nature) 6–7, Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph 43
17, 111 Proust, Marcel 152, 239
Nazism (National Socialism) 6, 11, 224, 242 psychoanalysis 25, 43, 155
New Historicism 153, 239
New Testament 76, 93, 117, 162, 169, 181, 191 radicalism 6, 20, 32, 56, 204
Nietzsche, Friedrich 4, 9, 15, 30, 89, 99–100, Rancière, Jacques 131–2, 236, 238
160, 181, 198, 204, 206, 217 La Nuit des prolétaires (Proletarian
nihilism 204, 232 Nights) 29, 136–7, 140–2, 145, 237
Nolte, Ernst 42, 218 Ranke, Leopold von 4–6, 14, 19, 29, 43,
62–3, 95, 158, 216, 217, 221, 223
Oakeshott, Michael 14, 210, 213 Reed, Ishmael 185
objectivism 4, 32, 156, 207, 231 referentiality 26, 51–2, 60, 96, 167, 172,
objectivity 4, 11, 14, 21, 25, 83, 89, 102, 106, 174, 178, 184, 230
119, 123, 172, 193, 201, 203, 207 relativism 10, 40, 71, 172, 175, 177–9, 183,
Old Testament 93, 117, 162, 166, 169, 181 205
Osborne, Peter 121, 236, 237, 238 Renaissance 28, 42, 109, 113, 117, 212–13
Burckhardt’s view of 55
Partner, Nancy 71, 218, 220, 229 repetition, retrieve
Pascal 201 Heidegger’s notion of 13–14, 130, 249
Pater, Walter 154, 165, 236 Kierkegaard’s notion of 13, 23, 76,
Paul, Herman 215, 219, 230, 242 138–9, 221
Paul, Saint 13, 202–3 revisionism (negationism) 10–11, 72, 178
Peirce, Charles Sanders 69–70, 223 rhetoric 2–3, 17–18, 28, 30, 43, 71, 89,
Pepper, Stephen C. 154 95–6, 101–2, 107, 111, 130, 145,
performative 18, 85, 95, 102, 104, 225 154, 158, 171–82, 232
periodization, period 23, 29, 86, 115–16, and tropology 151, 145, 169
125, 128, 146–8, 201 Ricoeur, Paul 39, 121, 129–31, 231, 236
Petrarch, Francesco 28, 113, 212–13 Rifkin, Adrian 141
phenomenology 8, 18, 129, 130, 205 Rigney, Ann 186, 192, 246
Piaget, Jean 177 romance (as plot-type) 21, 41, 152, 155
plot 20, 23, 25, 41–2, 48, 95, 97, 114, 129, Romans (Roman empire) 12–13, 35, 160,
146, 151–2, 159, 161, 163, 165, 167, 211
169, 183, 187, 220, 232 Rorty, Richard 8, 17, 205, 217, 218
256 Index