Putting Disarmament Back in The Frame

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

Review of International Studies (2006), 32, 353–376 Copyright  British International Studies Association

doi:10.1017/S0260210506007066

Putting disarmament back in the frame


NEIL COOPER*

Abstract. This article begins by deconstructing the dominant discourse on arms control and
disarmament, and argues that it works to dismiss disarmament as an idea whilst simul-
taneously coopting really existing disarmament into a perspective that imagines a world long
on dangers and short on peaceful strategies to confront them. In contrast, it is argued, not only
is the traditional distinction between arms control and disarmament problematic but, in
certain respects, the world is experiencing quite a lot of disarmament. Partly however, this is
because both disarmament and broader arms limitation activities are taking place as part of an
asymmetrical arms limitation system underpinned, in particular, by the US in its role as a
‘disarmament Empire’. Nevertheless, there are a number of factors immanent in the
contemporary international system that suggest a more radical form of emancipatory
disarmament might be both realisable and indeed necessary.

Introduction

This article aims to examine both arms control theory and practice from a critical
security studies perspective. It is therefore concerned to deconstruct the mainstream
discourse on arms control in order to illuminate the interests that underpin received
wisdom on the issue; to outline the structures of power established by current
practice; to highlight the emancipatory potential immanent in contemporary
approaches to arms limitation and to consider how these might be extended to build
a system of ‘disarmament from below’.1
First, I will suggest that the supposed distinctions between arms control and
disarmament that lie at the heart of arms control theory represent the mirage-
creation of a dominant disciplinary discourse. I will also argue that Stuart Croft’s
attempt to reinvent arms control for the post-Cold War era has produced a
teleological history that ignores the extent to which the development of arms
limitation has been non-linear and which downplays the role of power in shaping
discourse and practice.
Second, I suggest that – in contrast to the impression created by an increasingly
pessimistic literature on the topic – the world is not only experiencing a lot of arms
limitation, but that it is also experiencing a significant amount of disarmament,

* I am grateful to Malcolm Chalmers, David Mutimer, Mark Lacy, Michael Pugh, Joanna Spear,
Maria Sultan and the anonymous reviewers of the article for their comments and insights.
1
For discussions on critical security studies, see Ken Booth (ed.), Critical Security Studies and World
Politics (Boulder, CO and London: Lynne Rienner, 2005); Richard Wyn Jones, Security, Strategy
and Critical Theory (Boulder, CO and London: Lynne Rienner 1999); Keith Krause and Michael C.
Williams (eds.), Critical Security Studies: Concepts and Cases (London: University College Press,
1997).

353
354 Neil Cooper

particularly when judged against the goals elucidated in the disarmament negotia-
tions of the 1950s and 60s. Furthermore, I will suggest that this point is largely
ignored in the mainstream literature on arms control, which still persists in
‘imagining’ disarmament as a failure. Such a framing acts as a powerful tool of
delegitimisation that means proposals for more far-reaching and emancipatory forms
of disarmament arrive still-born into the zeitgeist of IR academia and global society
more generally. Whilst in some ways depressing, such an analysis nevertheless implies
that disarmament utopias may well be realisable.
However, I will also suggest that the current disarmament and broader arms
limitation system is, to a significant extent, an asymmetric one, designed to preserve the
military hegemony of the US in particular and the West in general. On the one hand
therefore, we can now be said to live in a disarmament system of sorts, but its
configuration is one primarily shaped in the interests of a disarmament empire – the
USA. Ironically therefore, the current disarmament system is one that nevertheless
legitimises significant levels of global – and particularly US – military expenditure and
which serves to further embed both the military supremacy of the USA and the stark
disparities that exist between spending on armaments compared with spending on
human security. Moreover, the very asymmetry in military power that the current arms
limitation system is designed to shore up actually creates an incentive for weaker
nations to pursue non-conventional military technologies or strategies (NBC weapons/
terrorism) as a way of offsetting their marked inferiority in conventional weaponry.
Finally, I will suggest that whilst the influences maintaining this system are certainly
very strong, practices immanent in the contemporary arms limitation system and the
challenges presented to it by emerging military technologies suggest that a more
emancipatory system of ‘disarmament from below’ – one geared less to the preserva-
tion of hegemony and more to the promotion of human security – may be realisable.
This article will begin, then, by first detailing how disarmament is both captured
and dismissed by arms control theory, before moving on to outline a typology of
disarmament. The implications of this typology for the validity of arms control
theory will then be explored, as will the problems associated with disarmament under
conditions of asymmetry. The article will then use a critique of Croft’s Strategies of
Arms Control as a vehicle for highlighting the problems inherent in even the best
examples of mainstream arms control thinking. Following on from this, it will be
suggested that a more useful distinction than that between arms control and
disarmament is one between strategies of forcible disarmament, traditional arms
limitation and new limitation. The article will then delineate the various asymmetries
in the current architecture of arms limitation before concluding with some brief
comments outlining how and why a more emancipatory system of disarmament from
below might be both necessary and achievable.

Capture and dismissal: arms control theory and the marginalisation of disarmament

Arms control, if not quite dead, is widely reported to be in crisis.2 Instead, the arms
control scepticism of offensive realists is deemed to hold sway amongst the
2
Deborah A. Ozga, ‘The Reluctant Giant of Arms Control’, Security Dialogue, 34:1 (2003),
pp. 87–102; See also: Avis Bohlem, ‘The Rise and Fall of Arms Control’, Survival, 45:3 (2003),
pp. 7–34; Sean Howard, ‘A Receding Disarmament Horizon? Lessons from an Era of Retreat and
Putting disarmament back in the frame 355

neo-conservatives who influence policy in the US. For such sceptics, both arms
control and disarmament are deemed to be profoundly problematic given the
condition of anarchy that states exist in, and the difficulties inherent in forging
effective agreements with rogue or revisionist states when neither their motives nor
their word can be trusted (or indeed verified with any reasonable degree of
assurance).3
Traditional arms control thus appears to have been rejected both in rhetoric and
policy – at least by the Bush White House. Despite this, I want to suggest that the
persistence of arms control theory in academic and policymaking circles continues to
perform important functions – not least in the way it serves to delegitimise more
radical proposals for disarmament. Moreover, current concerns over the death of
arms control also mask the strong elements of continuity between past approaches to
arms limitation and those of the present Bush White House – both of which have
been profoundly unequal in their impact on actors and have thus fostered contem-
porary insecurities rather than resolved them. What is the basis for such assertions?
There is an established body of arms control theory that forms the basis of most
textbooks on arms control and security or strategic studies. This is despite the fact
that much of the subsequent discussion of contemporary arms control practice in the
very same books often demonstrates the essential inadequacy of these principles.
There are a number of key points that are normally recited. In particular, the
development of arms control theory is presented as a reaction to the perceived failure
of successive initiatives on general and complete disarmament (GCD).4 Indeed, this
scepticism about the real world relevance of disarmament has been a recurring theme
in the traditional literature on arms control that students of IR and security studies
are still weaned on.5 Typical of such scepticism is Buzan’s conclusion that:
within anarchy, the logic of disarmament is so obviously flawed that except for propaganda
purposes, and for limited reductions in the context of arms control the idea is, as the
historical record indicates, a non-starter.6
Thus, the claim to superiority made by arms control theory has consistently rested on
its real-world relevance and practicability compared to the failed utopianism of

Defeat’, Disarmament Diplomacy, 73 (October/November 2003), pp. 3–14; Mark Bromley, David
Grahame and Christina Kucia, Bunker Busters: Washington’s Drive for New Nuclear Weapons,
BASIC Research Report, 2002.2 (Washington and London: BASIC, July 2002), p. 10.
3
Colin S. Gray, House of Cards: Why Arms Control Must Fail (Ithaca, NY and London, Cornell
University Press, 1992); Colin S. Gray, Modern Strategy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999);
David Frum and Richard Perle, An End to Evil: How to Win the War on Terror (New York:
Random House, 2003), esp. pp. 201–3.
4
Barry Buzan, Introduction to Strategic Studies: Military Technology and International Relations
(London: Macmillan with the ISS, 1987), p. 237; Trevor Taylor, ‘The Arms Control Process: The
International Context’, in Jeffrey A Larsen and Gregory J. Rattray (eds.), Arms Control Toward the
21st Century (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1996), p. 35; Barry Buzan and Eric Herring, The Arms
Dynamic in World Politics (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1998), p. 213; Emanuel Adler, ‘Arms
Control, Disarmament and National Security: A Thirty Year Retrospective and a New Set of
Anticipations’, in Emanuel Adler (ed.), The International Practice of Arms Control (Baltimore, MD
and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992), p. 1–2.
5
For instance, see Hedley Bull, The Control of the Arms Race: Disarmament and Arms Control in the
Missile Age (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson for the IISS, 1961), pp. 135 and 155; Bernard
Brodie, War and Politics ( London: Cassel, 1974), p. 324; Laurence Martin, Arms and Strategy: An
International Survey of Modern Defence (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1973), p. 242; Ken
Booth, ‘Disarmament and Arms Control’, in John Baylis, Ken Booth, John Garnett and Phil
Williams, Contemporary Strategy: Theories and Policies (London: Croom Helm, 1975), p. 91.
6
Buzan, Introduction to Strategic Studies, p. 250.
356 Neil Cooper

disarmament. Moreover, arms control is understood to be philosophically distinct


from disarmament.7 In particular, it is based on different assumptions about the
relationship between arms and the inception of war. For disarmers, all arms are
destabilising and thus likely to increase the risk of war, while for arms controllers
certain arms and arms relationships can be stabilising and can thus serve to mitigate
the insecurity inherent in an anarchic international system. Consequently, as in
the case of SALT 1 and II, arms control may even permit an increase in certain
categories of arms. This difference is often characterised by reference to Bull’s
distinction between disarmament, understood as the reduction or abolition of arms,
and arms control understood as restraint internationally exercised upon armaments
policy – not only in terms of the number of arms but also their character, deployment
or use.8
Thus, arms control and disarmament are deemed to be philosophically distinct. At
the same time though, there is a blurring that occurs in the discourse – between arms
control expressed as an alternative to disarmament understood solely as GCD (which
has been a failure and thus discredited) and arms control as a practice, of which
disarmament initiatives such as the Biological Weapons Convention (BWC) or the
Chemical Weapons Convention (CWC) are represented as a subset. Indeed, there is
often a double blurring at work, because disarmament’s link with GCD is often used
to damn disarmament as utopian in principle and unachievable in practice, whilst
arms control’s association with really existing disarmament treaties is used to
demonstrate its greater realism and (potential) relevance. We can see these processes
at work in the quote from Buzan above, but a more recent example is from Larsen
who notes that:
. . . arms control should be distinguished from general and complete disarmament.
Proponents of disarmament [note the move from GCD to disarmament] see the goal as
simply [so naive, so crude] reducing the size of military forces, budgets, explosives power
and other aggregate measures. . . . Disarmament has a longer legacy than arms
control..[but] 1960s international security specialists believed [disarmament] lacked precision
and smacked of utopianism.9
Despite the above conclusion from Larsen, just a few lines later on, the second kind
of blurring occurs: ‘advocacy of disarmament [can also be] part of a state’s arms
control policy’. As evidence of this, Larsen cites US negotiation of conventions on
biological and chemical weapons, noting (not incorrectly) that ‘The US decided in
both cases that maintaining such weapons would not enhance its security’.10
Thus, for mainstream strategic and security studies, disarmament is simul-
taneously distinct from arms control and a utopian project characterised by failure
whilst also a subset of arms control that has produced concrete results. The effect is

7
Joseph Kruzel, ‘Arms Control, Disarmament and the Stability of the Postwar Era’, in Charles W.
Kegley, The Long Postwar Peace: Contending Explanation and Projection (New York: Harper
Collins, 1991), p. 249.
8
Bull, Control of the Arms Race, p. vii; John Baylis, ‘Arms Control and Disarmament’, in John
Balylis, James Wirtz, Eliot Cohen, and Colin S. Gray, Strategy in the Contemporary World: An
Introduction to Strategic Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press), p. 184.; Jeffrey A. Larsen,
‘Introduction’, in Jeffrey A. Larsen (ed.), Arms Control: Cooperative Security in a Changing
Environment (Boulder, CO and London: Lynne Rienner, 2002), p. 4; Buzan, Introduction to Strategic
Studies, p. 253.
9
Larsen, ‘Introduction’, p. 3.
10
Ibid., p. 3–4.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 357

to neatly condemn ‘disarmament’ as both an activity with a long record of failure and
as a project suitable only for naive idealists.
However, as I intend to demonstrate below, if GCD is understood as merely one
kind of disarmament activity (some of which has a decidedly non-utopian flavour to
it) then it becomes clear that, at least when judged against the kind of criteria set by
the disarmament negotiators of the 1950s and 60s, a great deal of disarmament can
be said to have occurred – much of it quite successful. What are the different kinds of
disarmament activity that can be identified?

Towards a typology of disarmament activity


Pure disarmament
This is the proposal that all arms everywhere should be abolished. It is this idea that
has gained little ground but it is also the case that the majority of disarmament
proposals do not envisage such scenarios.

General and complete disarmament


This is often associated with pure disarmament in the popular imagination, and even
dismissed as such in some of the academic literature on the topic. For instance,
Laurence Martin simultaneously critiques GCD proposals for failing to envisage
complete disarmament because of their provision for internal security forces and also
to depict GCD proposals as ‘defining an equitable level of armaments as zero’.11
However, whilst the negotiations on GCD centred around the abolition of nuclear,
chemical and biological weapons and substantial cuts in conventional forces – the
proposals put forward generally envisaged the retention of significant conventional
forces (see below). This was also the position in the disarmament negotiations of the
interwar years. For instance, Article VIII of The Covenant of the League of
Nations – the basis on which interwar disarmament negotiations took place –
advocated ‘the reduction of armaments to the lowest point consistent with national
safety and the enforcement by common action of international obligations’ (my
italics).12 Similarly, the world disarmament conference of 1932 was labelled a
conference for the reduction and limitation of armaments’ not the total elimination.
Indeed, this view of disarmament was even accepted by prominent advocates of GCD
such as Philip Noel Baker.13

Structural disarmament14
This occurs where autonomous factors – for example, a change in the political logic
of the Cold War or the impact of inflation in defence costs – brings about unilateral

11
Martin, Arms and Strategy, p. 241.
12
Jozef Goldblatt, Arms Control: A Guide to Negotiations and Agreements (London: Sage, 1996),
p. 269.
13
Philip Noel-Baker, The Arms Race: A Programme for World Disarmament (London: Atlantic Books,
1958).
14
This is a different use of the term ‘structural’ than is the case in arms control theory when the term
‘structural arms control’ is often used in contrast to ‘operational arms control’. The former being
358 Neil Cooper

Table 1. Comparison of armed forces with disarmament proposals of 1952.

Country Disarmament proposals 1952 Actual armed forces 1954 Armed forces 2002

USA 1–1.5 m 2.9 m 1.4 m


Russia 1–1.5 m 4.5 m 988,000
China 1–1.5 m — 2.3 m
France 7–800,000 803,000 260,000
UK 7–800,000 950,000 210,000
Total 4.4–6.1 m 5. 16 m

Source: Philip Noel-Baker, The Arms Race: A Programme for World Disarmament (London:
Atlantic Books, 1958), pp. 14 and 48; International Institute for Strategic Studies, The Military
Balance 2003–2004 (Oxford: Oxford University Press for the IISS, 2004), Table 33, pp. 335–40.

arms reductions. In other words this is disarmament by default, as opposed to


disarmament by diplomacy. Perhaps the best example is the reduction in manpower
and equipment numbers brought about by rising unit defence costs, the concen-
tration on technology as a force multiplier and the end of the Cold War. For instance,
with the exception of China, the manpower numbers of the major military powers are
either at, or below, the force levels proposed to the UN Disarmament Commission
in 1952 by the US, Britain and France (see table above). Nor were the numbers
proposed in 1952 unusually high in the context of the disarmament negotiations of
the period.15
Even in the rest of the world the majority of states possess force numbers that lie
within the disarmament proposals of the 1950s and 60s. For instance, in 1957 Russia
proposed manpower limits of 200,000 for all states other than the major powers,
whilst a year earlier the US had proposed a limit of 500,000.16 As of 2002 just 20
states (excluding China, Russia, the US, France and the UK) had forces numbering
more than 200,000 and just six (India, Iran, North Korea, Turkey, South Korea, and
Pakistan) exceeded the 500,000 limit proposed by the US in 1956.17
A similar picture is evident when we examine the massive quantitative reductions
that have occurred in the armaments held by national defence forces, a process that
has been spurred by the quite substantial rise in unit defence equipment costs from
one generation of weapon to the next. Indeed, since 1950, the unit cost of arms has
risen at an annual average rate of 9–11 per cent, such that weapons costs double every
7–8 years.18 This has led Thomas Scheetz to coin the phrase ‘military Malthusianism’
to describe the gap between the exponential growth in the unit costs of major
weapons systems and the (at best) linear growth in fiscal income. As he notes, faced
with this contradiction militaries have either had to purchase obsolescent weapons
systems, emphasise manpower in their defence plans and/or reduce equipment

agreements concerned with the quantity and quality of armaments and the latter with the behaviour
of armed forces (for example, crisis management or confidence building measures).
15
Bull, Control of the Arms Race, p. 117.
16
Ibid., p. 120.
17
International Institute for Strategic Studies, The Military Balance 2003–2004 (Oxford: Oxford
University Press for the IISS, 2004), Table 33, p. 335–40.
18
D Kirkpatrick, ‘The Rising Costs of Defence Equipment – The Reasons and the Results’, Defence
and Peace Economics, 6:4 (1995), pp. 263–88; P. G. Pugh. ‘The Procurement Nexus’, Defence
Economics, 4:2 (1993), pp. 50–61.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 359

numbers.19 In consequence, the fall in equipment numbers has been quite startling.
For instance, in 1950 the UK had 276 frigates and destroyers and 62 submarines,20
today it has just 32 frigates and destroyers and 16 submarines21 with further cuts
scheduled.22
This is not to suggest the world is free from violence and arms. After a post-Cold
War fall, global military expenditure, mainly driven by rises in US defence spending,
has increased by an average of 6 per cent in real terms over the period 2002–04.
Global military expenditure was over $1 trillion in 2004 accounting for 2.6 per cent
of world GDP and amounting to $162 per capita.23 Nor is it to dismiss the fact that
changes in force numbers are, in part, a function of conscious decisions to invest in
technology as a force multiplier. Quantitative disarmament has occurred side-by-side
with very significant qualitative improvements in military technology. Nevertheless,
the fact is that, partly by design and partly by default, certain forms of quite radical
conventional disarmament have occurred.

Limited negotiated disarmament

There have been a whole variety of multilateral and bilateral initiatives that have
produced limited or partial disarmament24 either in the form of agreements that ban
whole categories of weapons – the Biological Weapons Convention (BWC), the
Chemical Weapons Convention (CWC), the Intermediate Range Nuclear Forces
Treaty (INF), the Ottawa Convention banning landmines – or agreements that ban
particular weapons from specific regions. These include the Antarctic Treaty, the
Outer Space Treaty, the Seabed Treaty and a number of regional nuclear-weapons-
free zones (NWFZ) that together have now made most of the Southern hemisphere
a nuclear-free zone.25 As already mentioned, however, what is notable about such
agreements is the way in which they are generally coopted in the literature as an
example of realistic arms control.
There have even been cuts in nuclear weaponry, although the scale of global
nuclear arsenals still remains vast. Global nuclear arsenals reached their peak in 1986
when there were some 70,000 nuclear warheads in the armouries of the five states
defined by the NPT as nuclear weapons states (China, France, Russia, the UK and
the USA).26 Today, SIPRI estimates the total number of nuclear warheads held by

19
Thomas Scheetz, ‘The Argentine Defense Industry: An Evaluation’, in Jurgen Brauer and J. Paul
Dunne, Arms Trade and Economic Development: Theory, Policy and Cases in Arms Trade Offsets
(London: Routledge, 2004), pp. 205–16.
20
Speech by Secretary of State for Defence, John Nott at the IISS (excerpts), Survival, 24:2 (1982),
pp. 89–90.
21
Gavin Berman, Defence Statistics: July 2002, House of Commons Library Research Paper 02/48, 19
July 2002, p. 20, Table 11.
22
BBC News, ‘Forces Chief Backs Defence Cuts’, 22 July 2004; see: 〈http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/
uk_politics/3915747.stm〉.
23
Elisabeth Sköns, Wuyu Omitoogun, Catalina Perdomo and Petter Stålenheim, ‘Military
Expenditure’, in SIPRI, SIPRI Yearbook 2005: Armaments, Disarmament and International Security
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), p. 307.
24
Buzan and Herring, The Arms Dynamic in World Politics, p. 246.
25
Joanna Spear, ‘Arms and Arms Control’, in Issues in World Politics (Basingstoke: Palgrave,
forthcoming).
26
Paul Rogers, Losing Control: Global Security in the Twenty-First Century (London: Pluto Press,
2000), p. 15.
360 Neil Cooper

these countries at 32,300.27 Partly in response to the non-proliferation norm


established by the NPT, states such as Argentina, Brazil, Taiwan, South Korea,
Sweden, Australia, Switzerland and now Libya have all abandoned nuclear weapons
programmes. A number of states (South Africa, Ukraine, Kazakhstan, Belarus) have
even acquired nuclear weapons only to subsequently renounce them. Consequently,
by 2004, ten countries were believed to have nuclear weapons or well-advanced
programmes compared with 21 in the 1960s.28 Moreover, the SORT Treaty (Strategic
Offensive Reductions Treaty) whilst flawed in a number of respects, nevertheless
envisages substantial cuts in deployed US/Soviet warheads, permitting each state to
hold between 1,700–2,200.29
Of course, not all states in the international system have signed up to such partial
disarmament agreements. For instance, as of December 2004, whilst 169 states had
signed the BWC, 16 of these had not yet ratified it and a further 25 non-signatory
states remained totally outside its purview.30 Similarly, although 184 states have
signed the CWC, 15 of these have yet to ratify and a further ten states are listed as
non-signatories.31 Moreover, even where states have made commitments to such
agreements these have not always been implemented. Nevertheless, despite such
problems, when considered together with the radical changes brought about
by structural disarmament, these initiatives have established a form of global
disarmament that is remarkably extensive – particularly given the pessimism about
disarmament in the mainstream literature.

Post-conflict disarmament, demobilisation and reintegration (DDR)


This has emerged as a key element of the international community’s approach to
ending civil wars. As a strategy, the internationally supervised disarmament,
demobilisation and reintegration of former combatants (DDR) has had mixed
success in contributing to peace. In places like Angola for instance, flaws in the DDR
processes have contributed to the resurrection of conflict. In other instances,
Mozambique or El Salvador for example, the process, whilst not perfect, has been
relatively more successful and has contributed to the establishment of viable peace.32

Forcible disarmament
The issue of forcible disarmament will be examined in detail below. At this juncture
therefore, it is sufficient to note that forcible disarmament represents the use of
27
SIPRI Yearbook 2005.
28
George Perkovitch et al., Universal Compliance: A Strategy for Nuclear Security (Washington, DC:
Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, June 2004), p. 11.
29
Shannon N. Kile, ‘Nuclear Arms Control, Non-Proliferation and Ballistic Missile Defence’, in
SIPRI Yearbook 2003, p. 600.
30
See: 〈http://www.opbw.org/〉.
31
See: 〈http://www.opcw.org/index.html〉.
32
Joanna Spear, ‘Disarmament and Demobilisation’, in Stephen John Stedman, Donald Rothchild
and Elisabeth M. Cousens (eds.), Ending Civil Wars: The Implementation of Peace Agreements
(Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2002), pp. 141–82; Mats R. Berdal, Disarmament and Demobilisation
after Civil Wars: Arms Soldiers and the Termination of Armed Conflicts, Adelphi Paper, no. 303
(Oxford: IISS and Oxford University Press, 1996); Stephen Hill, ‘Creating an Analytical Framework
for United Nations Disarmament in Civil Wars’, Civil Wars, 2:4 (Winter 1999), pp. 57–82; Stephen
Hill, United Nations Disarmament in Intra-State Conflict (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2003); UNIDIR,
Managing Arms in Peace Processes: The Issues (New York and Geneva, United Nations, 1996).
Putting disarmament back in the frame 361

military force or other forms of coercion to bring about disarmament or prevent arms
build-ups, and that the most vivid example of its implementation in recent times has
been the invasion of Iraq.

Rescuing disarmament from capture and dismissal

This categorisation of disarmament highlights part of the problem with the way
in which arms control theory frames both arms control and disarmament. First, in
framing disarmament as failed and utopian it downplays the progress made in
realising the disarmament agenda of the 1950s and 60s that structural disarmament
combined with a series of partial disarmament treaties has brought, and thus the
extent to which even utopia might be realistic for future generations. Second,
in enveloping a succession of really existing disarmament initiatives within the
essentially realist/neorealist framework of the arms control perspective it undermines
the claim of disarmament as a practice and set of goals with real-world relevance. In
combination this amounts to a very powerful discursive strategy that works to
maintain the intellectual hegemony of arms control theory in particular and realist
academia and policymaking more generally. To invert Ken Booth, what is at work
here is what might be termed realist utopianism33 – the capture and suborning of
utopian achievements in ways that work to shore up the realist view of a world long
on dangers and short on peaceful strategies to confront them. In contrast, when the
various types of disarmament (some of which have a decidedly non-utopian flavour
to them) are reclaimed under the disarmament rubric, then it becomes clear that the
world has, and is, experiencing a tremendous amount of disarmament – some of it
relatively successful.
This also has profound implications for the supposed distinction between arms
control and disarmament around which arms control theory is based. Once we move
from framing (successful) partial disarmament as merely one variant of arms control,
and instead frame both GCD and partial disarmament as variants of disarmament
practice; once we understand disarmament as an activity that is advocated by both
utopians and hyper-realists alike (albeit in different ways) then both the empirical
and philosophical distinctions between arms control and disarmament fall away. As
will be noted below, this implies that we need to develop an alternative way of
conceptualising the different strategies of arms limitation and the structure of the
contemporary arms limitation system.
However, whilst it is important (if only to counter the pessimistic discourse
surrounding this issue) to recognise the various disarmament outcomes that have
been generated under the current arms limitation system, it is also important to
recognise the context in which these have occurred. In particular, both disarmament
and broader arms limitation initiatives are now taking place as part of an asymmetri-
cal arms limitation system that has replaced the emphasis on balance between the
superpowers that dominated Cold War practice.34

33
Ken Booth, ‘Security in Anarchy: Utopian Realism in Theory and Practice’, International Affairs,
63:3 (July 1991), pp. 527–45.
34
Keith Krause and Andrew Latham, ‘Constructing Non-Proliferation and Arms Control: The Norms
of Western Practice’, Contemporary Security Policy, 19:1 (1998), p. 24–5.
362 Neil Cooper

It is sufficient at this juncture to note that what characterises this system of arms
limitation is the way in which it is structured to consolidate and preserve the military
superiority of the US in particular and the West in general. Moreover, rather than
reinforcing security this profound military imbalance promotes insecurity – both by
creating incentives for other actors to pursue asymmetric technologies (NBC) or
strategies (terrorism) that offset the US’s conventional superiority,35 and by diverting
resources that could be expended on human security to militarism. At best, the
contemporary arms limitation system aims to keep the lid on such contradictions by
setting in place a variety of disciplinary mechanisms that attempt to constrain
asymmetric military responses whilst simultaneously preserving the asymmetrical
advantages of the West. At worst, in attempting to contain pressures that may
ultimately be uncontainable, the contemporary arms limitation system may promote
an illusion of relative security whilst positively fostering a variety of insecurities.
However, a few more comments are in order before we proceed to consider this
system of asymmetrical arms limitation in more detail.

Stuart Croft and arms control as threat construction

The corollary of the preceding critique of arms control theory is of course a require-
ment to develop conceptual frameworks (and framings) that are capable of simul-
taneously challenging the hegemonic discourse within the discipline and of producing
greater explanatory value. To date this attempt has been most convincingly pursued
by critical theorists and postmodernists such as Mutimer,36 and Krause and Latham.37
Even within the mainstream literature on arms limitation however, there has been
some attempt to reconceptualise arms limitation practice. Most notably, Stuart Croft
in Strategies of Arms Control explicitly rejects the distinction between arms control
and disarmament as a basis for framing discussions of arms limitation.38 Instead he
develops a typology based around five different strategies of arms control: arms
control at the conclusion of major conflicts, arms control to strengthen strategic
stability, arms control to create norms of behaviour, arms control to manage the
proliferation of weapons and arms control by international organisation.
This certainly represents an improvement on more traditional discussions of arms
limitation. However, there are also a number of problems with his analysis. First,
Croft locates his typology in a broader analysis that emphasises the idea that arms
control as an activity has been constantly widening (in the sense that there has been
a gradual accretion of strategies deployed to achieve it) and that arms control
agreements have become ever ‘deeper’ (in the sense that agreements have become
35
Paul Dunne, Mariá del Carmen García-Alonso and Paul Levine, ‘Managing Asymmetric Conflict’.
See: 〈http://carecon.org.uk/Armsproduction/Annex0204.htm〉; Dan Plesch, The Beauty Queen’s Guide
to World Peace: Money, Power and Mayhem in the Twenty-First Century (London: Politicos, 2004),
p. 292.
36
David Mutimer, The Weapons State: Proliferation and the Framing of Security (Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner), 2000; David Mutimer, ‘Reimagining Security: The Metaphors of Proliferation’, in Keith
Krause and Michael C. Williams, Critical Security Studies: Concepts and Cases (London: University
College London Press, 1997), pp. 187–221.
37
Krause and Latham, ‘Constructing Non-Proliferation and Arms Control’.
38
Stuart Croft, Strategies of Arms Control: A History and Typology (Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 1996), pp. 11–12.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 363

more detailed, arrangements for verification have become both more common and
more sophisticated, and the likelihood of agreements taking on the qualities of a
regime have increased). Consequently, although Croft states that he is determined to
avoid making judgements on the success or failure of arms control both as theory and
practice, he nevertheless manages to produce a profoundly teleological (and indeed
optimistic) account of the history of arms control/arms limitation.
However, there has not been a straightforward accretion of arms limitation
activity. Partly this is because the relevance of many arms control agreements has
simply declined with the advent of new military technology. But even where this has
not been the case, politics and power have constantly intruded both to kill off arms
limitation initiatives and to influence their depth. Examples include Japanese and
German disarmament after the Second World War, and the US decision to renounce
the ABM Treaty. Similarly, the two page SORT Treaty highlights how the inexorable
increase in depth described by Croft in 1996 was, at best, a function of historically
contingent Cold War practices rather than some evolutionary manifest destiny.39
Second, Croft states that investigation of the motivation for arms limitation is
outside the remit of his book. Despite noting the influence of politics and power on
arms limitation then, what Croft presents is a largely mechanistic and apolitical
analysis of the subject. Indeed, the development of arms limitation practice is
depicted as an essentially autonomous process – as if, to paraphrase Cox, arms
limitation were not always for some purpose and for someone.40 This is not untypical
of the majority of the literature in this field which tends to focus on the technical
minutiae of military strategy, diplomatic texts or policy battles. The problems that
arms limitation deals with are generally taken as given and the purpose of such
activity (just like arms control theory itself) is to engage in producing ‘problem-
solving’ solutions to these issues. What Croft, and mainstream arms controllers in
general ignore, is the role that arms limitation activity plays in both reflecting broader
constructions of threat and in reinforcing them. Moreover, whilst the idea that arms
limitation represents an arena where political power is exercised is taken as
axiomatic, power is generally understood to be expressed in the relations between
states (or internal bureaucracies) negotiating (or sometimes imposing) specific
treaties, and measured in terms of who wins or loses in these negotiations. The
myriad ways in which hegemonic power is expressed through developments in the
dominant modes of arms limitation thinking and practice rarely intrude. For
example, the power expressed as a result of the role played by discourse and action
over arms limitation in affirming hegemonic projects of securitisation; the power
manifested in the specific ways in which the system of arms limitation contributes to
maintaining particular military and social hierarchies whether internally, within the
state, or throughout the global system; and the relationship between the interests of
power and the ways in which arms limitation reflects and reinforces powerful
political, economic and cultural tools of legitimation/delegitimation surrounding
military technology.
In other words (from a critical security studies perspective at least), the key
questions surrounding arms limitation are not so much who wins or loses in

39
‘Letter of Transmittal and Article-by-Article Analysis of the Treaty on Strategic Offensive
Reductions’, Arms Control Today, 32:6 (July/August 2002), pp. 28–30.
40
Croft, Strategies of Arms Control.
364 Neil Cooper

negotiations over a specific treaty or how effective/ineffective that treaty turns


out to be. Rather, the principal concern is with how the dominant discourse
and practice of arms limitation (not always the same thing) contributes to
processes of securitisation and othering as well as military and broader hegemonic
practices.
Good examples of these processes at work are in fact cited by Croft himself, but
their implications are not followed through in his overall analysis. For instance, the
prohibition imposed by the Second Lateran Council in 1139 on using crossbows
against Christians and Catholics reflected powerful processes of othering against
non-christians who remained exempt from a ban against what was otherwise depicted
as ‘that deadly and God-detested art of slingers and archers’.41 At the same time, the
ban itself not only reflected the political power of the church at the time, but its main
purpose was actually to protect the nobility, whose armour could be pierced by the
crossbows wielded by the lower class soldiery.42
The discourse on arms as objects of control is also intrinsically linked to the
shifting and symbiotic relationship between threat construction and the legitimation
of military technology and strategy. This does not simply occur at the macro
level – for example, in the ways that the discourses surrounding the birth and then
death of the ABM Treaty have reflected and reinforced alternative constructions of
threat (or indeed, of the utility of nuclear deterrence when faced with thousands of
Soviet nuclear weapons compared with its utility when faced with nascent nuclear
programmes in North Korea and Iran).43 Even apparently minor disputes over
language reflect shifting areas of contention between hegemonic and counter-
hegemonic discourses. Thus, the use of the appellation ‘WMD’ as a catch-all term to
describe nuclear, biological and chemical weapons (NBC) is often contested. In
particular, commentators have noted how this entails a particular categorisation (and
representation) of NBC weapons as equally (and uniquely) horrifying, a categorisa-
tion that is either deemed too broad or too restrictive depending on the observer.
What is interesting about this debate is not so much who is right and who is wrong
but the way in which the parties in this debate have changed over time and what this
signifies about the link between representations of military technology, the framing of
the arms limitation agenda, and the interests of power. Thus, in the 1950s and early
1960s a number of mainstream institutions and academics were concerned to
challenge the veracity of the term WMD, whereas peace academics/activists were
concerned to preserve it. Consequently, the academic and peace activist Philip
Noel-Baker could bemoan US and NATO attempts to erode the link between
nuclear, chemical and biological weapons and to portray the latter two as ‘normal
and legitimate means of war’.44 In contrast, Hedley Bull could note the attempts of
the US Chemical Corps to make chemical biological and radiological (CBR) warfare
respectable and could argue that when it came to such weapons: ‘it is misleading
to regard them as forming, along with nuclear weapons, a category of ‘‘weapons of
41
Canon 29 of the Second Lateran Council of 1139, reproduced in Richard D. Burns (ed.),
Encyclopaedia of Arms Control and Disarmament (New York: Charles Scribner, 1992), p. 1409, cited
in Croft, Strategies of Arms Control, p. 24.
42
Ibid., p. 24.
43
On the link between changing US conceptions of deterrence and the ABM issue, see Tom Sauer,
‘Back to Arms Control: Limiting US National Missile Defence’, in Contemporary Security Policy,
24:3 (2003), pp. 91–128.
44
Noel-Baker, The Arms Race: A Programme for World Disarmament, pp. 315–19.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 365

mass destruction’’ . . . the depiction of them as all alike peculiarly evil and terrifying
is not unquestionable’.45
Thus, in a period when the major powers retained an interest in chemical and
biological weapons their framing as ‘WMD’, as opposed to weapons with military
utility, was under interrogation from establishment outlets. Similar attempts
were also made to distinguish more usable tactical nuclear weapons from strategic
ones.46 In contrast, in a context where CB weapons have now been formally
renounced by these same powers – in part, at least because of their role as force
equalisers47 or ‘the poor man’s atom bomb’, there has been a reorientation of
positions in this debate. The ‘WMD’ label now lies at the very heart of the dominant
discourse on proliferation to others (horizontal proliferation). Indeed, as early as
1992 Krauthammer could characterise the post-Cold War period as ‘the era of
weapons of mass destruction’.48 In contrast, the discourse on domestic nuclear
armouries is less likely to be burdened with this kind of sobriquet. Indeed, current
arguments for a new generation of mini-nukes directly echo Cold War attempts to
distinguish between different kinds of ‘WMD’, whether it be those between nuclear
and CB weapons or more particularly in this case, between tactical and strategic
nuclear weapons.
In many respects, this does not make for a particularly consistent and coherent
contemporary discourse on ‘WMD’/NBC. Nevertheless, the combined effect of such
linguistic devices is to ensure that ‘our’ WMDs are framed as nuclear whilst ‘their’
nuclear technologies are framed as ‘WMDs’, thus de-linking discussion of ‘our’
technology from the acute moral opprobrium and heightened images of threat and
danger that are currently constructed around the term ‘WMD’ in popular culture and
the mainstream of academia.
In contrast, those concerned to challenge the dominant discourse now highlight
the way in which the depiction of NBC as ‘all alike’ in discussions of horizontal
proliferation is not only questionable but now functions to legitimise the exclusive
possession of nuclear weapons by the NWS states, to obfuscate the inequality in the
NPT and to legitimise other ‘conventional’ technologies (such as fuel-air bombs) or
political strategies (such as sanctions against Iraq) that produce ‘mass destruction’.49
What these examples illustrate is the way in which discourse and action surround-
ing military technology and arms limitation has precisely not proceeded in an
autonomous and evolutionary straight line as suggested by Croft. Rather, it shifts

45
Bull, Control of the Arms Race, p. 123.
46
A. J. Bacevich, The Pentomic Era: The US Army between Korea and Vietnam (Washington, DC:
National Defense University Press, 1986).
47
Daniel Feakes, ‘Global Civil Society and Biological and Chemical Weapons’, in Mary Kaldor,
Helmut Anheier and Marlies Glasius (eds.), Global Civil Society 2003 (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2003), pp. 90 and 96.
48
Charles Krauthammer, ‘The Unipolar Moment’, Foreign Affairs, 70:1 (1991), pp. 32–3. Also see:
Wolfgang K. H. Panofsky, ‘Dismantling the Concept of Weapons of Mass Destruction’, Arms
Control Today, 28:3 (April 1988), available at: 〈http://www.armscontrol.org/〉; Iraq’s Weapons of
Mass Destruction: The Assessment of the British Government (London: HMSO, 2002); Robert
Hutchinson, Weapons of Mass Destruction: The No-Nonsense Guide to Nuclear, Chemical and
Biological Weapons Today (London: Cassell, 2004); National Strategy to Combat Weapons of Mass
Destruction, December 2002. See: 〈http://www.state.gov/t/np/wmd/〉.
49
Mutimer, The Weapons State; Eric Herring, ‘Rogue Rage: Can We Prevent Mass Destruction?’, in
Eric Herring (ed.), Preventing the Use of Weapons of Mass Destruction (London: Frank Cass, 2000),
pp. 189–212; Daniel Feakes, ‘Global Civil Society and Biological and Chemical Weapons’,
pp. 87–117; Geoffrey Wheatcroft, ‘Weapons of Mass Distortion’, The Guardian, May 2003.
366 Neil Cooper

to reflect the competing discourses and interests of hegemonic power and its
challengers.
This brings me neatly to the final problem with Croft’s analysis. Croft’s solution
to the problematic nature of the distinction between arms control and disarmament
is to label all arms limitation as arms control. Whilst Croft’s text is rich and
informative – a contemporary classic indeed – in terms of the dominance of the
disciplinary discourse surrounding arms control and disarmament it is still problem-
atic. In setting out to defend ‘arms control’ from arms control sceptics such as Colin
Gray,50 Croft becomes a participant in the various projects by which the asymmetric
post-Cold War system of arms limitation has been legitimised. Indeed, he manages to
simultaneously dismiss disarmament and reinvent arms control under a new guise,
whilst adopting a historical determinism that effectively obscures the mechanisms of
power and interest at work in contemporary arms limitation.
The question remains then – if the distinction between ‘arms control’ and
disarmament is problematic and if Croft’s typology of ‘arms control’ is equally
flawed, how might the contemporary (albeit historically contingent) system of arms
limitation best be conceptualised? I would like to suggest that a particularly useful
way to conceptualise contemporary arms limitation practice is to characterise it as a
spectrum along which three different approaches can be discerned: forcible disarma-
ment, traditional arms limitation and the new arms limitation agenda and practice.
These are not hard and fast categories. In particular, some arms limitation
agreements share elements of both traditional and new arms limitation. Nevertheless,
this represents a useful analytical device that helps us conceptualise the features and
variety of contemporary arms limitation practice. It also permits analysis of the
asymmetric control agenda that lies at heart of the contemporary discourse and
action on arms limitation. Indeed, the following analysis will not only attempt to
outline the three kinds of arms limitation but will then go on to map the key
asymmetries embodied in each approach.

Forcible disarmament

Forcible disarmament represents the use of military force or other forms of coercion
(sanctions, physical interdiction) either to bring about significant reductions in
military forces or to prevent military build-ups and/or the acquisition of military
technology perceived as particularly threatening. Forcible disarmament is by no
means a new phenomenon – an early example being the Treaty of Zama imposed on
Carthage by the Romans in 202 BC.51
More relevant to the discussion here, however, is the Bush administration’s
adoption of pre-emptive attack as a strategy of forcible disarmament.52 The emphasis
on forcible disarmament is also reflected in the Proliferation Security Initiative (PSI),
a loose multilateral initiative which aims to prevent trafficking in ‘WMD’ and related

50
Gray, House of Cards.
51
Croft, Strategies of Arms Control, p. 42.
52
The National Security Strategy of the United States (Washington DC, September 2002), p. 15.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 367

technology through improved intelligence sharing and enhanced efforts at interdic-


tion.53
This adoption of pre-emption does not represent quite the radical break with past
practice that is sometimes suggested. Charles Kegley has cited the Third Punic War
between Rome and Carthage as an early example of pre-emption (or what he more
accurately terms prevention).54 Other examples include the Israeli raid on Iraq’s
Osiraq reactor nuclear reactor in June 1981, the bombing of the Iranian Bushir
reactor by Iraq in the mid-1980s,55 and the Clinton Administration’s use of cruise
missiles in 1998 to destroy a Sudanese pharmaceutical plant claimed to be producing
a precursor chemical for VX nerve gas. Furthermore, the first moves towards
articulation of a formal US policy on pre-emption came not with the Bush
Administration but with the enunciation of the Clinton Administration’s 1993
Defence Counterproliferation Initiative, generally understood to incorporate what
Virginia Foran has described as ‘active pre-emption or interdiction of proliferation
activities’.56
This emerged at the same time as a growing discourse on the threats from so-called
rogue states and the legitimacy of humanitarian intervention. These various factors
combined together, constantly reflecting and reaffirming each other, producing a
representation of threat and action that provided a powerful rationale both for the
maintenance of US defence expenditure in the midst of a dissipating Soviet menace57
and the legitimation of military action.58 Moreover, it is also the case that the EU has
given serious consideration to such an approach. For instance, although ultimately
dropped from the final version, a draft EU security strategy envisaged the use of force
(albeit with UN authority) for non-proliferation purposes.59
Thus, the adoption of strategies of forcible disarmament by the Bush admin-
istration does not so much represent a sudden break with past practice but rather the
crystallisation of emerging trends in US (and wider) discourse and policy that have
become particularly powerful since the end of the Cold War. Indeed, such strategies
are a corollary of the ensemble of threat discourses and practices that serve to
legitimise relatively high levels of US defence expenditure and the expeditionary
interventions they permit. The US has ineluctably become what Jonathan Schell has

53
Jofi Joseph, ‘The Proliferation Security Initiative: Can Interdiction Stop Proliferation’, Arms Control
Today, 34:5, June 2004. See: 〈http://www.armscontrol.org/act/2004_06/Joseph.asp〉; Wade Boese,
‘The Proliferation Security Initiative: An Interview with John Bolton’, Arms Control Today, 33:10
(December 2003). See: 〈http://www.armscontrol.org/act/2003_12/PSI.asp〉.
54
Charles Kegley, ‘Preventive War and Permissive Normative Order’, International Studies
Perspectives, 4 (2003), p. 388; Robert S. Littwak, ‘Nonproliferation and the Use of Force’, in Janne
E. Nolan, Bernard I. Finel and Brian D. Finlay (eds.), Ultimate Security: Combating Weapons of
Mass Destruction (New York: The Century Foundation Press, 2003), p. 78.
55
Tom Sauer, ‘The ‘‘ Americanization’’ of EU Nuclear Non-Proliferation Policy’, Defense and Security
Analysis, 20:2, p. 120.
56
Virgina I. Foran, ‘Preventing the Spread of Arms: Nuclear Weapons’, in Larsen and Rattray (eds),
Arms Control Toward the 21st Century, p. 191; Robert S. Littwak, ‘Nonproliferation and the Use of
Force’, in Nolan et al. (eds.), Ultimate Security, p. 82; Joanna Spear, ‘Organizing for International
Counterproliferation: NATO and US Nonproliferation Policy’, in Nolan et al. (eds.), Ultimate
Security, pp. 216–17.
57
Michael Klare, Rogue States and Nuclear Outlaws: America’s Search for A New Foreign Policy (New
York: Hill and Wang, 1995); Mutimer, The Weapons State, pp. 92–5 and 135; Krause and Latham,
‘Constructing Non-Proliferation and Arms Control’, pp. 34–9.
58
Naom Chomsky, The New Military Humanism: Lessons From Kosovo (London: Pluto, 1999).
59
Sauer, ‘The ‘‘Americanization’’ of EU Nuclear Non-Proliferation Policy’, p. 127.
368 Neil Cooper

described as a ‘disarmament empire’,60 but this did not simply occur with the election
of Bush and the neo-conservatives (or in the bloody aftermath of 9/11) – and there
are strong (if not insurmountable) pressures for it to remain that way after they are
gone.

Traditional arms limitation and new arms limitation

Traditional arms limitation refers primarily to the arms limitation agreements that
typified Cold War arms limitation practice. This is not to suggest however, that
such agreements and practices have completely disappeared with the end of the
Cold War – they have not. It is however, a useful term with which to distinguish
these kinds of arms limitation practices from the new arms limitation agenda that
has emerged primarily in the post-Cold War era. The two approaches can be
distinguished in the following ways:
1. In traditional arms limitation the agenda, and actual negotiation, is primarily
driven by states and/or the bureaucracies of multilateral institutions. Discussion
and policy is dominated by diplomats, the military and narrow groups of
academic experts all holding a monopoly on both technical knowledge and the
details of negotiations. For example, Feakes could note in 2003 that ‘the most
recent CWC and BWC meetings were attended by, respectively, only six and 16
civil society organisations’.61 In comparison, the International Campaign to Ban
Landmines (ICBL) involved a coalition of more than a thousand nongovernmen-
tal organisations.62 Although civil society groups are not without influence in
traditional arms limitation,63 this influence is constrained by their role as outsider
groups. At worst, such groups may even be viewed as an enemy within which has
to be monitored and discredited (CND in the 1980s) or even attacked (the sinking
of the Greenpeace boat, Rainbow Warrior, by French intelligence). In contrast,
new arms limitation practices are marked by the key role played by NGOs in
setting the agenda, most notably in the case of the Ottawa Convention banning
landmines. Indeed, they may even become party to negotiations, as was the case
in the negotiations over the Kimberley certification scheme for conflict diamonds
or incorporated in official state delegations as occurred in the case of some states
involved in the Ottawa process.64
2. In traditional arms limitation, the problem of arms restraint is framed in terms of
addressing the threats to states and to state security. Moreover, the focus is on
military security, the agenda is primarily set by the developed world and largely
reflects its security concerns. In new arms limitation the problem of military

60
Jonathan Schell, The Unconquerable World: Power, Nonviolence and the Will of the People (London:
Allen Lane, 2003), p. 341.
61
Daniel Feakes, ‘Global Civil Society and Biological and Chemical Weapons’, in Mary Kaldor et al.,
Global Civil Society 2003 (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2003), pp. 99–100.
62
Richard A. Mathew and Kenneth R. Rutherford, ‘The Evolutionary Dynamics of the Movement to
Ban Landmines’, Alternatives, 28 (2003), p. 30.
63
Jeffrey W. Knopf, Domestic Society and International Cooperation: the Impact of Protest on US
Arms Control Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
64
Richard Price, ‘Reversing the Gun Sights: Transnational Civil Society Targets Land Mines’,
International Organization, 52:3 (Summer 1998), pp. 613–44.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 369

technology is framed in terms of human rather than state security and/or in terms
of economic rather than military security – the issue of small arms proliferation
being a case in point. Moreover, the core of the new arms limitation agenda has
been directed towards addressing the problem of arms and civil conflict in the
poorest parts of the developing world – new arms limitation for the new wars if
you like. Consequently, although not arms control in the traditional sense of the
term, indirect initiatives such as commodity sanctions that target the financial
resources of insurgents in order to limit their ability to purchase arms have become
a more central element in contemporary arms limitation practice.65
3. In traditional arms limitation the negotiation of agreements is often a highly
bureaucratic and cumbersome process. For instance, the negotiations on Mutual
and Balanced Force Reduction in Europe during the Cold War era dragged on for
over fifteen years with no agreement.66 In contrast, new arms limitation is
characterised by speed and adaptive flexibility. For instance, the successful
conclusion of the landmines treaty represented a speedy and adaptive reaction to
the failure to adequately revise the Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons
(CCW) to ban landmines and the concern that proposals for a ban would be mired
in endless wrangling in the Conference on Disarmament.67 The issue of conflict
diamonds provides an even more dramatic example. The role of conflict diamonds
in fuelling civil conflicts first came to prominence in 1998 with the publication of
a Global Witness report on the role played by the illicit diamond trade in
sustaining the conflict in Angola.68 Just four years later agreement was reached on
a global scheme aimed at preventing the trade in conflict diamonds.
4. Traditional arms limitation agreements are more likely to give rise to substantial
verification commitments and/or institutions and bureaucracies designed to
implement them, although this is not always the case. For example, START 1 and
its various protocols ran to 250 pages and stipulated details such as the number of
times a year each party could request the other to display the weapons covered in
the agreement.69 Similarly, the NPT and the CWC are underpinned by the work
of the IAEA and the OPCW respectively. The latter, for example, had a budget of
$92 m in 2004 and has conducted 1,800 inspections of military and industrial sites
of the states parties.70 In contrast, no comparable organisation was established
under the Ottawa treaty, a gap that has been filled by Landmines Monitor, a civil
society network that scrutinizes implementation of the Treaty.
Classic examples of traditional arms limitation practice includes treaties such as
START I and the NPT. It also covers the sclerotic, bureaucratic and mostly
tokenistic activities of the Conference on Disarmament. Archetypal examples of new
arms limitation include the Ottawa Treaty on landmines, the Kimberley certification
regime for conflict diamonds and, to a significant extent, the ongoing campaign on

65
Michael A. Levi and Michael E. O’Hanlon, The Future of Arms Control (Washington, DC:
Brookings Institution Press, 2005), pp. 115–17.
66
Renée de Nevers, Regimes and Mechanisms for Global Governance. Project on World Security (New
York: Rockefellers Brothers Fund, 1999), note 20, p. 7.
67
Price, ‘Reversing the Gun Sights’.
68
Global Witness, A Rough Trade: The Role of Companies and Governments in the Angolan Conflict
(1998). See: 〈http://www.globalwitness.org/〉.
69
Croft, Strategies of Arms Control, pp. 73–5.
70
See SIPRI Yearbook 2004, p. 670. Also see: 〈http://www.opcw.org/〉.
370 Neil Cooper

small arms. Other agreements contain elements of both traditional and new arms
limitation. For example, the CWC emerged after a long process of negotiation and
was framed in terms of preserving state security. However, whilst civil society
influence on WMD issues is certainly constrained, the development of the CWC did
at least feature notable input from industry.71 Similarly, the SORT agreement was an
archetypal bilateral Cold War style agreement between states. However, it was also
negotiated quite speedily, has not resulted in additional verification commitments
and has most definitely avoided creating a large bureaucracy to implement it. It thus
encompasses some of the speed and adaptivity characteristic of new arms limitation.
As already noted, this mix of traditional and new arms limitation has produced
some quite significant developments that should not be ignored. However, it is also
the case that the three approaches to arms limitation outlined above make up a
contemporary arms limitation system that is characterised by a number of asym-
metries that ultimately create insecurity rather than reduce it. It is not my intention
to provide a detailed review of them all here but some brief comments on the key
aspects of asymmetries, and why they create insecurity, are necessary.

Asymmetric arms limitation

The first asymmetry

The Bush Administration has fused forcible disarmament with the rogue state
doctrine to produce not a generic policy of pre-emption but one selectively applied.
The purported NBC programmes of ‘rogues’ such as Libya, Iraq, Iran and North
Korea have become the targets of rhetoric, invasion and PSI initiatives. In contrast,
the NBC activities of states such as Pakistan or Israel, states that could equally be
tagged with the rogue label, are essentially treated as legitimate.72 Although there are
problems with the use of the term, one might say that two classes of ‘rogues’ have
been created – the ‘illegitimate rogues’ and the ‘legitimate rogues’.73
As with the move to forcible disarmament, this is not a particularly new
development, but the advent of the Bush administration, and particularly the policies
pursued after 9/11, have made the asymmetry in approach between the ‘legitimate
rogues’ and the ‘illegitimate rogues’ even starker. Moreover, membership of these
two camps is not fixed and permanent. Pakistan, for instance, has managed to move
from illegitimate to ‘legitimate rogue’ as the politics of post 9/11 created new
imperatives in US policy – a process that demonstrates the extent to which the rogue
label has less to do with the particular characteristics of individual states and their
NBC programmes, and more to do with the way in which these are framed. Indeed,
despite emerging as the centre of a clandestine global proliferation network the
country has, in the wake of 9/11, been the recipient of military aid, IFI funds and
political legitimacy.

71
de Nevers, Regimes and Mechanisms for Global Governance, p. 8.
72
See for instance, David Frum and Richard Perle, An End to Evil: How to Win the War on Terror
(New York: Random House, 2003), pp. 257–63.
73
For an example of the distinctions made by the Bush administration, see Wade Boese, ‘The
Proliferation Security Initiative: An Interview with John Bolton’.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 371

Of course, whilst such discrimination between the legitimate and illegitimate


‘rogues’ may undermine the goals of arms limitation this is arguably not the point.
The discourse around ‘illegitimate rogues’ is, ultimately, not one that can simply be
understood in terms of any existential threats posed by North Korean, Iranian or
Pakistani ‘WMD’ programmes. Rather, it can be understood as the product of
the interrelationship between the process of identity construction within the US
and other states, the construction of external interests and the legitimation of
overwhelming military superiority.

The second asymmetry

The second asymmetry is that established in traditional arms limitation agreements


on NBC technology – the asymmetry between the ‘WMD’ haves (those states whose
nuclear weapons are deemed legitimate under the terms of the NPT) and the ‘WMD’
have-nots. This enshrines a profoundly discriminatory system of ‘WMD’ apartheid,
under which a small category of states are permitted to possess a class of ‘WMD’
denied to all others.74 Indeed, even in the case of the CWC which is supposedly
universal, the US Senate made its ratification conditional on a set of provisions that
contravene the letter and spirit of the CWC. For example, inspection of US facilities
may be refused and, if allowed, collected laboratory samples may not be transferred
for analysis to a lab outside the US.75
When combined with the first asymmetry, this essentially creates three classes of
‘WMD’ states – those formally permitted to hold WMD, those informally permitted
to hold ‘WMD’ (the ‘legitimate rogues’) and those demonised for holding or
attempting to develop ‘WMD’. In addition, there is also an asymmetry of approach
towards failure to abide by the commitments implied by the various NBC treaties.
The ‘illegitimate rogues’ face sanctions of various kinds, the ‘legitimate rogues’
experience a discourse of criticism but little concrete action, and the failure of the
formal ‘WMD’ states to abide by their commitment to nuclear disarmament under
the terms of the NPT is merely met with a faint descant from critics off-stage.

The third asymmetry

The third asymmetry is that between the disciplinary mechanisms deployed to


enforce restrictions on NBC technologies and the disciplinary mechanisms surround-
ing conventional military expenditure, arms transfers and the conflict goods covered
by the new arms limitation agenda. In the case of NBC technologies the mechanisms
deployed are severe, ranging through pre-emptive attack, sanctions, loss of trade and
diplomatic isolation.76 At the level of conventional arms exports and expenditure the

74
Jaswat Singh, ‘Against Nuclear Apartheid’, Foreign Affairs, 77:5 (1998), pp. 41–52.
75
Goldblatt, Arms Control: A Guide to Negotiations, p. 152.
76
Joshua Lederberg (ed.), Biological Weapons: Limiting the Threat (Cambridge, MA and London: The
MIT Press, 1999); Malcolm R. Dando, Preventing Biological Warfare: The Failure of American
Leadership (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002); Richard M. Price, The Chemical Weapons Taboo (Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1997); Hans Blix, Disarming Iraq: The Search for Weapons of Mass
Destruction (London: Bloomsbury, 2004).
372 Neil Cooper

disciplinary mechanisms deployed are either non-existent or are weak and tokenistic.
Thus, the notable successes of civil society in successfully pushing for the creation of
novel arms limitation regimes in this arena has been mitigated by the reality of the
limits to either their effectiveness or their scope. For instance, with the notable
exception of IFI/donor initiatives aimed at restricting the military expenditures of
supplicant states,77 direct initiatives to restrict defence spending are notable by their
absence. Similarly, initiatives to curb arms exports are either voluntary and/or focus
on transparency (the UN arms register), weak regulatory mechanisms that have
marginal impact on the volume of arms sales (the UK and EU arms export codes,
current initiatives on small arms)78 or symbolic acts of tokenism that have little
impact on the overall direction of the arms dynamic. Examples of the latter include
the landmines treaty and UN arms embargoes. For example, UN embargoes usefully
express diplomatic disapproval and may also raise the cost of arms acquisition by
forcing states to source from the global networks of the black market. However, the
record of such embargoes in actually preventing arms reaching targeted states is
abysmal and the sanction for states that breach such embargoes rarely amounts to
little more than an exercise in diplomatic finger-wagging.79

The fourth asymmetry

The combined effect of the preceding asymmetries has been to produce a con-
temporary system of arms limitation that acts to preserve the profound military
supremacy of the US in particular and the West in general. Thus, the NBC
disarmament system now in place legitimises and – through the deployment of a
range of disciplinary mechanisms – imposes both a ‘WMD’ supremacy for the US
and its allies and the ‘WMD’ disarmament of other states. This is especially the case,
of course, with respect to that imagined and shifting category of states constructed as
‘rogue’. In contrast, the mechanisms of control developed to cover military expendi-
ture, conventional arms exports or conflict trade are weak or non-existent. It is, of
course, precisely in these areas of conventional military expenditure and trade that
the US and the developed world has a profound advantage. For instance:
• The US now accounts for virtually half (47 per cent) of global military expenditure,
NATO countries for 70 per cent and OECD states 78 per cent.80

77
Nicole Ball, Jordanna D, Friedman and Caleb S. Rossiter, ‘The Role of International Financial
Institutions in Preventing and Resolving Conflict’, in David Cortright (ed.), The Price of Peace:
Incentives and International Cooperation (Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997), pp. 243–64;
Security Sector Reform and the Management of Military Expenditure: High Risk for Donors, High
Returns for Development. Report on an International Symposium Sponsored by the UK Department
for International Development (London: DFID, 2000).
78
Various European Union Non-Governmental Organisations, Taking Control: the Case for a more
Effective European Union Code of Conduct on Arms Exports (London: Saferworld, 2004); Jane
Chanaa, Debbie Hillier, Kiristiana Powell and Ken Epps, Guns or Growth: Assessing the Impact of
Arms Sales on Sustainable Development (June 2004). See 〈www.controlarms.org〉. Neil Cooper,
‘Arms Exports, New Labour and the Pariah Agenda’, Contemporary Security Policy, 21:3
(December 2000), pp. 54–77.
79
SIPRI Yearbook 2003, pp. 448–51; David Cortright and George A. Lopez, Sanctions and the Search
for Security: Challenges to UN Action (Boulder, CO and London: Lynne Rienner, 2002), pp. 153–79.
80
SIPRI Yearbook 2005, Table 8A.1, pp. 346–71.
Putting disarmament back in the frame 373

• Eighty of the top 100 defence companies reside in North America or Europe.81
• The US accounts for 35 per cent of all small arms companies in the world, with
authorised exports of $741.4 million in 2001.82 Europe/CIS and North America/
Central America accounts for 79 per cent of all small arms companies in the world.
• In the period 2000–04 the US accounted for 31 per cent of global supplies of major
conventional weapons and NATO countries for 57 per cent.83
In other words, the current disarmament and broader arms limitation system is
structured to preserve and reinforce both the ‘WMD’ and conventional military
hegemony of the US and its allies. To be sure, this same system also creates a
permissive environment for other actors who may actively support specific aspects.
Russia and China for instance, clearly benefit from the legitimisation of their nuclear
weapons status enshrined in the NPT, although their conventional forces remain
dwarfed by those of NATO. Similarly, rogues, guerrillas and warlords are all
beneficiaries of the far more permissive regulatory frameworks that are applied to
conventional weapons. This means that even the current asymmetric arms limitation
system is not without its contradictions. For example, whilst the US has consistently
opposed any substantive action on the problem of small arms and light weapons
(SALW), its forces in Iraq and Afghanistan are facing insurgents mostly armed with
these same weapons.84 However, for such actors, these kinds of tension in policy
represent the collateral benefit from a legal and normative order that nevertheless
broadly works to sustain and legitimise the kind of overwhelming military-
technological superiority of the US and its allies that was demonstrated in the recent
invasion of Iraq.

The fifth asymmetry

The final asymmetry is that which exists between the level of resources expended on
the military sector, compared with those devoted to development and human
security. The contrast is startling. For instance, in 2001 the 32 richest countries (those
classified as high income countries by the World Bank) allocated ten times more
resources to the military ($555 bn) than to official development assistance. Indeed, in
2001 the combined annual military expenditure of the 32 richest states was roughly
equal to the aggregate debt of all low income countries and US defence expenditure
alone amounted to 60 per cent of the total.85 In a world of postmodern irony this is
perhaps the biggest irony of all – we have, to a large degree, achieved the general and
complete disarmament agenda of the 1950s and 60s, we are living in the disarmament
system of a disarmament empire, but the funds expended on defence remain gross in
absolute terms and both immoral and abhorrent relative to the funds spent on human
security.

81
SIPRI Yearbook 2004, Table 11.1, p. 390.
82
Small Arms Survey 2004 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), Table 4.1, pp. 103–6.
83
SIPRI Yearbook 2005, Table 10A2, pp. 453–4.
84
Spear, ‘Arms and Arms Control’.
85
SIPRI Yearbook, 2004, p. 308–9.
374 Neil Cooper

Conclusion: towards disarmament from below

The preceding analysis has attempted to demonstrate how, contrary to the impres-
sion given in the mainstream literature on arms limitation, there has in fact been a
great deal of disarmament – at least in the terms understood in the disarmament
negotiations of the 1950s and 60s. Yet these very successes have been coopted by
arms controllers in ways that function to delegitimise disarmament as utopian and
appear to confirm realist representations of a world system with limited potential for
transformation. This article has also demonstrated the way in which global civil
society has been able to set an apparently more radical, new arms limitation agenda
for the new wars – one in particular which has emphasised human and economic
security rather than state and military security. These factors then, represent a basis
for optimism about the future prospects for further disarmament.
However, it is also the case that the contemporary disarmament and broader arms
limitation system is a highly asymmetric one geared to preserving the military
hegemony of the US and its allies. Moreover, even the new arms limitation agenda
is characterised by its own asymmetries. In particular, civil society has manifestly
failed to gain the same level of influence over core military security issues – for
example, NBC or the trade in major conventional weapons that keeps Western
defence industries viable. In some respects then, this analysis shares certain commo-
nalities with offensive realist critiques that emphasise the problematic nature of arms
control theory (albeit from a different standpoint) and the supremacy of politics and
power in determining the possibilities for the control of arms.86 One response,
therefore, might be to adopt a similar attitude of resigned cynicism in the face of the
overwhelming influence of power and interest in shaping discourse and practice – and
to conclude that a truly emancipatory, as opposed to asymmetric, disarmament
agenda is unrealisable.
However, there are both material and ideational factors immanent in the
contemporary international system that suggest a politics of radical emancipatory
disarmament can be constituted. First, the success of existing disarmament
initiatives – albeit under asymmetry – highlights the real-world relevance of disarma-
ment proposals still dismissed as failed and utopian. This illustrates the potential for
a more radical disarmament agenda to be realised by simultaneously deconstructing
hegemonic framings of the arms limitation problem and developing alternative
narratives that contain inherently transformatory meanings – a powerful political act
in itself. Second, the influential role of global civil society in new arms limitation
suggests the possibility of a truly progressive practice of arms limitation – a kind of
disarmament from below.87 In particular, campaigns such as those on landmines or
conflict diamonds demonstrate the (as yet unfulfilled) potential for networked and
adaptive rhizomatic movements to envision and realise radical alternative security
futures. This is not to deny the significant power differentials that exist between states
and civil society movements that may themselves have different goals. However, the
flexibility of such movements contrasts sharply with the rigid and sclerotic statist
institutions most immediately geared to dealing with the diplomacy of arms
limitation. Moreover, at their optimal, such swarming resistances to hegemony have

86
Gray, House of Cards; Gray, Modern Strategy, pp. 193–7.
87
Mary Kaldor (ed.), Europe From Below: An East-West Dialogue (London: Verso, 1991).
Putting disarmament back in the frame 375

the potential to exploit the uncontrollable spaces and flows of a networked


information age88 to generate focused policy goals and shared understandings; to
generate political and cultural power by exploiting global media tropes (Princess
Diana as beatified saint opposed to landmines) or creating their own (diamonds as
blood diamonds);89 to challenge both the threat discourses that underpin the arms
dynamic and the counsels of despair in the face of anarchy and a supposed military
technological imperative that lie at the heart of arms control theory; and to thus effect
change by eroding the legitimacy of institutions and actors upholding militarism.90
Moreover, such movements have the potential to resolve the perennial debate
over what has to come first before disarmament is realised – radical reduction of
armaments or radical political change. The inevitable corollary of the emergence
of such rhizomatic social movements is that the very act of campaigning for a
radical disarmament agenda presages radical change in the nature of local-global
politics – the one brings the other into being, and vice versa.
Third, it might also be argued that this is precisely the wrong time to articulate a
new disarmament agenda, particularly given the imperatives of the ‘war on terror’.
However, to the extent that the threat of ‘WMD’ terrorism is rooted in material
conditions, the safest response is to eliminate the very weaponry that might be
utilised – to move, if you like, from a policy that aims to prevent loose nukes to a
policy that aims simply to lose nukes. Furthermore, rather than being an inopportune
moment to pursue a radical disarmament agenda, it is clear that we are now facing
a range of new and old arms limitation challenges that will require a radically
different kind of arms regulation. These include challenges such as the growing
pressure to weaponise space, the military potential of the new biology, the weapon-
isation of nanotechnology and the challenge of controlling the military uses of
cyberspace. A further challenge is that presented by the growing importance of
dual-use technology for the military. This has been compounded by the simultaneous
concentration and globalised integration of the defence industry in a largely
Western-dominated hub and spoke model characterised by the erosion of defence
industrial national identities and increased intra-firm movement of technology and
knowledge.91 Finally, there is the problem presented by the extension and intensifi-
cation of illicit global arms networks that exploit porous borders, corrupt officials,
lax regulation and the mechanisms of globalisation to move arms to conflict zones.92
The corollary of all this is that traditional, supply-side non-proliferation initiatives
based around the ability of hermetic nation-states to supervise the physical move-
ment of military technology will inevitably be subject to declining utility. Such
developments then, are likely to require a qualitative step-shift in the application of
end-use monitoring and the kind of intrusive verification of civil industries dealing

88
Athina Karatzogianni and Andrew Robinson, ‘With or Without You: US Foreign Policy,
Domination, Hegemony and Rhizomes of Resistance’ (Draft), 2004; Price, ‘Reversing the Gun
Sights’.
89
Mathew and Rutherford, ‘The Evolutionary Dynamics of the Movement to Ban Landmines’,
pp. 29–30.
90
David Cortright, ‘Civil Society: The ‘Other Superpower’, Disarmament Diplomacy, 76 (March/April
2004), pp. 40–42.
91
Richard A. Bitzinger, Towards a Brave New Arms Industry, Adelphi Paper no. 356 (London:
International Institute for Strategic Studies and Oxford University Press, 2003).
92
Michael Pugh and Neil Cooper with Jonathan Goodhand, War Economies in a Regional Context:
Challenges of Transformation (Boulder, CO and London: Lynne Rienner, 2004).
376 Neil Cooper

with dual-use technologies presaged in the CWC; the innovative adaptation of


existing arms limitation methodologies adopted by recipients and the peripheries –
such as the extension of nuclear weapons-free zones to incorporate bans on other
military technologies, or the greater use of moratoria/bans on arms imports; and an
enhanced role for local-global civil society as presaged by the role of NGOs in
monitoring implementation of the landmines treaty.
In sum, if the challenge of controlling contemporary military technology is to be
addressed effectively (and it may not be, of course), then the new arms limitation
agenda of the current era is likely to represent merely a half-way house towards a
radically novel practice of arms limitation. This will entail a move away from control
primarily based on physical management of objects (finished weapons, national
militaries) and their accumulation and movement within or across borders. Instead,
current trends will require a shift to a form of oversight and limitation characterised
by swarming.93 Such an approach will focus far more on dual-use technologies and
thus intrude into the very warp and weft of socioeconomic life. It will be marked by
a move from the asymmetry of hegemon/supplier-dominated control and non-
proliferation instruments and imply a far greater role for recipients and the
peripheries. It will require such a qualitative intensification and expansion of the
network of arms limitation practices that this in itself will constitute a radically novel
approach to arms limitation. And it will require the interactive, interpenetrated
agency of multiple institutions and actors from states, multilateral institutions,
NGOs, industry, media, epistemic communities and society generally.

93
Michael Dillon and Julian Reid, ‘Global Liberal Governance: Biopolitics, Security and War’,
Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 30:1, p. 63.

You might also like