Originary Humanicity: Locating Anthropos
Originary Humanicity: Locating Anthropos
Originary Humanicity: Locating Anthropos
Vicki Kirby
Access provided by Goldsmith's College, University Of London (16 Jul 2018 23:50 GMT)
Originary Humanicity
Locating Anthropos
Vicki Kirby
First of all, I didn’t say that there was no center, that we could get
along without the center. I believe that the center is a function, not
a being—a reality, but a function. And this function is absolutely
indispensable. The subject is absolutely indispensable. I don’t
destroy the subject; I situate it. That is to say, I believe that at a
certain level both of experience and of philosophical and scientific
discourse one cannot get along without the notion of subject. It is
a question of knowing where it comes from and how it functions.
—Jacques Derrida Structure, Sign, and Play in the
Discourse of the Human Sciences. Discussion
The need to understand human behavior will all too often make a quick
appeal to individual intention and personal motivation as the explanatory cause
of conduct. However, within certain areas of Western academic thinking,
especially over the last forty years, the assumption that the individual authors
his own life, or that “the agential subject” is, indeed, an autonomous individual
whose decisions are properly her own, is significantly compromised. Close
analysis of the agential subject through psychoanalysis, poststructuralism,
various forms of discourse and media theories, or even classical sociological
methodologies that focus on the problematic relationship between the indi-
vidual and society, discover a subject whose identity is more conceded than
43
At this point it might be salutary to return to the opening citation from Jacques
Derrida, especially the final sentence, where Derrida refuses to reject outright
the notion of a subject or center, and by implication, the assumption that the
subject is centered, or individuated. “It is a question of knowing where it comes
from and how it functions” (1970, 271). Interestingly, both Lacan and Derrida
make explanatory appeal to this notion of “function,” and we could be forgiven
for assuming that their respective differences converge in this word. However,
this is not the case, as Calvin O. Schrag’s clarification of its use in the Derrida
passage makes clear.
The justification for this conclusion usually makes reference to the English
cleric, William Paley, who recounts a hypothetical scene: when out walking on
a heath he discovers a watch on the ground and ponders its origins. 13 Given its
intricate mechanism he argues that we would surely attribute its manufacture to
someone. “There must have existed, at some time, and at some place or other,
an artificer or artificers, who formed [the watch] for the purpose which we find
it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use”
(2009, 3–4). If the complexity of the watch presumes a designer, then Paley
argues that the complexity of nature should lead us to the same conclusion.
“Every indication of contrivance, every manifestation of design, which existed
in the watch, exists in the works of nature; with the difference, on the side
of nature, of being greater and more, and that in a degree which exceeds all
computation” (2009, 19). 14
Two things should be underlined here. The first is that human beings
are defined tautologically; put simply, the Cogito equates intelligence with
self-possession—a subject is one who thinks and to think is to be a subject, a
human subject. As we saw above, the truth of the self, the subject’s existence
as the repository and definition of intelligence, is guaranteed by faith in a
pre-existent, absolute deity—omniscient, omnipresent—who can turn doubt
into certainty. If to be human is to be intelligent by default, to be purposeful
and accountable for one’s actions because God exists, then Paley’s equation
makes a lot of sense, at least, for believers. And yet nonbelievers can be just
as persuaded that the identity of the agential subject is necessarily human,
as if what makes this identity and its capacities identifiably special requires
no further justif ication. We might recall that despite Lacan’s elaborate
explanations about the subject’s necessary denials and disavowals of its own
fragility, his faith that this state of affairs discovers what is uniquely human
is never in doubt.
What I have tried to argue is that a belief in haecceity—“the thisness of
things” as fundamental and given—is essential to both religious and secular
argument. This need for an entity, a process or capacity, to operate as First
Cause is prerequisite to this logic making sense, regardless of an argument’s
content or direction. We see this in Lacan’s appeal to an absolute, a bar of
prohibition that contains and defines human complexity in terms of intellectual
curiosity, a fascination with paradox and willful self-deception. Importantly,
although Lacan will question the manufacture of human identity, the focus of
his interrogation is confined to the internal structuration of the human mind.
Consequently, a belief in the self-evident existence, identifiable autonomy, and
Notes
1. To be fair, the proposition that the subject can only occupy one position or the
other at any one time is further complicated by the necessity for a transcendental
subject who can discern the difference between them such that the notion of
“choice” can retain any purchase. If this isn’t the case, then we have no way to
explain how a subject “decides” to be indecisive, or to put this another way, how a
subject who appears to lack all motivation can change her ways. How is the switch
triggered? Indeed, is there a switch? If the subject is an empirico-transcendental
phenomenon then the source and site of agency and intention is unclear.
2. The Innocence Project’s website, https://www.innocenceproject.org/, provides
ample information about the injustice of such assumptions. For example, juries
are most persuaded by what they perceive as the truth of an eye-witness testimony,
and yet, even when this evidence is provided in good faith it remains profoundly
unreliable. The harsh lesson is that for all of us, memory is a pastiche of retrieved,
reconstructed, and even invented images and experiences. If the subject’s appearing
is one of dynamic fabrication, then the weight of guilt and personal culpability
may be felt by those who did not commit a crime, and not at all by those who did.
3. Although Lacan’s thesis entrenches the nature/culture split, his elaboration of
culture as techne and the sense that the subject is ego-free represent a significant
assault on humanism and its accompanying investments. We could certainly
reroute this argument through “originary technicity,” wherein the machinic, or
cybernetic, would not be a break, or supplement, to what supposedly came before.
For an excellent introduction to such themes in Lacan, see Bradley (2011).
4. There is a problem in describing what comes before the image, or gestalt, of the
“Ideal-I.” Because Lacan assumes that difference is oppositional, a “not this,” he
Works Cited