Sidney and Aristotle

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 1

Sidney and Aristotle's Definition of Poetry

The definition of poetry, given by Sidney, agrees substantially with what might be designed
Renaissance Aristotelianism. Poetry, says Sidney, “is an art of imitation, for so Aristotle termeth it,
that is to say, a representing, counterfeiting or figuring forth; to speak metaphorically, a speaking
picture, with this end,—to teach and delight." The definition is less notable for its originality - it is
indebted to Aristotle’s Poetics - than for the insights it gives into the critical controversies of the period.
Sidney’s definition set as an agenda for the discussion of poetry. Generally, it raises three issues; the
nature of imitation, the problem of defining nature, and the injunction that poetry serve moral ends.

The principle of imitation reigned unchallenged in literary theory from Plato to the end of the eighteenth
century, but Aristotle gives a significant argument of it. Aristotle suggest that it is human nature to write
poetry. We are, by nature, imitative creatures that learn by imitating, and we naturally enjoy the works
of imitation. As evidence, we are fascinated by representation of dead bodies or disgusting animals
though the things themselves repel us. We can also learn by examining imitations of things and that
learning is one of the greatest pleasures.

At the centre of the controversy over imitation is a debate about nature itself, what constituted the
nature and what the status of representation of “nature” is. Sidney uses the Platonic theory of Forms
to refute Plato’s criticism of poetry. He says that the nature the poet imitates is the ideal, not the
material, world. Aristotle takes the word “imitation” from his master, Plato, but breathes a new life in it.
Plato considers imitation merely a mimicry copy of nature, but Aristotle interprets it as a creative
process. The poet, while imitating reality, transforms it into something new and much higher. He brings
the emotions within the range of imitation. Poetry imitates not only the externals, but also internal
emotions and experience. According to Aristotle, poetry may imitate men as they are, or better and
worse. Poetry is not concerned with what is, but what ought to be. It gives us an idealised version of
reality. Unlike history, which produces knowledge only of specific situation, poetry describes the
actions of characters who might be any humans.

A fundamental aesthetic problem concerns the object and purpose of poetry’s representation. Sidney
argues that “right poets imitate to teach and delight, and to imitate borrow nothing of what is, hath
been, or shall be, but …..what may be and should be.” The purpose of the poet is ultimately to affirm
the rule of justification and order. The ideal that Sidney invokes – what may be or should be – is more
“real” than what is. Meanwhile, Aristotle claims that good poetry has a positive emotional effect on its
audience, which he calls “Catharsis.” The theory of “Catharsis” enables Arristotle to demonstrate the
healthy influence which poetry, in general, and tragedy, in particular, exercises over the emotions. He
defines tragedy as “a representation of an action that is worth serious attention complete in itself and
of some amplitude in a language enriched by a variety of artistic devices appropriate to the several
parts of the play presented in the form of action, not narration by means of pity and fear bringing about
the purgation of such emotions.” Some commentators have interpreted the term in a medical sense,
as a purgative that flushes out the audience’s unwieldy emotion; others see in it in terms of moral
purification. More recently, critics have equated catharsis with ethical and intellectual clarification.

Posted 12th October 2012 by Mohamed Khamis

You might also like