Directions in Sexual Harassment Law
Directions in Sexual Harassment Law
Directions in Sexual Harassment Law
CATHAlUNE A MACKINNON & REVA B. SIEGEL EDS. FORTHCOMING YALE PRESS 2003
Introduction
Some two decades after the federal courts first recognized sexual harass-
ment as a form of sex discrimination, debate still continues about what sexual
harassment is, why it might be sex discrimination, and what law can and
should do about it. Many voices take up these questions in the pages to follow.
In this introduction I will describe the historical foundations of this conversa-
tion, a conversation that continues without sign of diminishing, in the work-
place and the popular press, as well as in such academic fora as the conference
from which this book grew.
What can history bring to our understanding of sexual harassment? Sexual
harassment is a social practice. Social practices have lives, institutional lives
and semiotic lives. And so social practices like sexual harassment have his-
tories. Considering sexual harassment in historical perspective allows us to
ask some fundamental questions about the nature of the practice, the terms
in which it has been contested, and the rules and rhetorics by which law
constrains-or enables-the conduct in question.
My object in these pages i~ tQ invite r.eflection, not only about sexual harass-
ment, but also about the law of sex discrimination itself. It is only quite
recently that sexual harassment acquired the name of "sexual harassment"
and was prohibited as a form of "sex discrimination." By examining the pro-
cess through which a persistent and pervasive practice came to be recognized
r
2 Reva B. Siegel
as discrimination "on the basis of sex," we learn much about what law does
when it recognizes discrimination.
Clearly, this act of recognition was a momentous one. For the first time in
history, women extracted from law the means to fight a practice with which
they had been struggling for centuries. And yet, when we consider this de-
velopment from a historical vantage point, it becomes plain that legal recogni-
tion of sexual harassment as sex discrimination was at one and the same time a
process of misrecognition- involving a sometimes strange account of the
practice in issue. On a moment's reflection, this is not terribly surprising.
When law recognizes the harms inflicted by social practices, it is intervening in
the social world it is describing, both enabling and constraining challenges to
the social order of which the practices are a part.
For this reason, the language of discrimination is a specialized language, one
that describes the social world in selective ways. When we in turn talk about a
practice in the language of discrimination, we are viewing the world through
this conceptual filter. Recourse to history supplies one way in which we can
think about the languages in which we characterize the social world, to con-
sider what work they are doing, and to ask again what work we might have
them do.
It is in that spirit that I offer the following short history of sexual harass-
ment, as a prelude to a much larger conversation, and as a provocation of
sorts: an invitation to meditate, yet again, on what we mean when we say that
a practice discriminates "on the basis of sex." The longer I think about what
that proposition might mean, the more I appreciate how its elusive meaning is
the very source of its power-its maddening capacity to excite and to deaden
curiosity, to challenge and to legitimate the social arrangements that make
men men and women women.
It is with a view to continuing a several-decades-old conversation about
what discrimination "on the basis of sex" might mean that I begin my short
history of sexual harassment at a time well before anyone dreamed of describ-
ing the practice in such terms. I begin my story, quite self-consciously, with a
provisional account of what sexual harassment might be and end by speculat-
ing about some ways that the practice seems to be changing in our own day. In
this way, I hope to survey the terrain of the debate that the essays in this book
join- a debate about what sexual harassment is and what law should do
about it, a debate about the terms in which we describe apd remedy the
wrongs we have only recently come to call "discrimination."
Introduction 3
Here was a population, low-class and mostly foreign, hanging always on the
verge of starvation, and dependent for its opportunities of life upon the whim
of men every bit as brutal and unscrupulous as the old-time slave drivers; under
such circumstances immorality was exactly as inevitable, and as prevalent, as it
4 Reva B. Siegel
was under the system of chattel slavery. Things that were quite unspeakable
went on there in the packing houses all the time, and were taken for granted by
everybody; only they did not show, as in the old slavery times, because there
was no difference in color between the master and slave .10
Tort law was only marginally more effective as a weapon against sexual
coercion at work. Initially, tort law gave women no right to recover damages
for sexual assault. At common law, sexual assault gave rise to an action for
damages insofar as it inflicted an injury on a man's property interest in the
woman who was assaulted; thus, a master might have a claim in trespass 1
against a man who raped his slave, 16 or a father niight bring a seduction action
against an employer who impregnated or otherwise defiled his daughter. 17 ;
When American law eventually began to recognize a woman's right to recover
for sexual· injury in her own right-whether through an action for seduction
or indecent assault- tort law developed a specialized body of law on "sexual"
touchings that incorporated doctrines of consent from the criminal law of
rape. 18 By the early twentieth: century, some jurisdictions moderated the con-
sent requirement in actions for indecent assault, but none seems to have relin-
quished it. 19 The tort action for seduction, by contrast, seems to have been
more plastic, as it evolved from an action designed to recompense a father's
economic injli.ry (when it focused on his daughter's out-of-wedlock preg-
nancy) to an action designed to recompense injuries to a father's honor (when
it focused his daughter's loss of virginity) to an action designed to recompense
women directly for injuries suffered in "sexual connexion." 20 In this newly
configured form, Lea VanderVelde reports, by the late nineteenth century
there were at least some seduction cases in which "the coercive force of words
of economic threat were sufficient to render the sexual predation redress-
ible."21 But this development was by no means uniform across jurisdictions22
and was, moreover, short-lived: by the early twentieth century, many states
began legislatively to repeal the tort of seduction along with other "heart-
balm" actions.23
The law's failure to protect women from sexual predation at work did not, of
course, pass unnoticed; it has been a subject of protest since the days of the
antislavery movement. We might count in this tradition abolitionist Henry
Wright's description of South Carolina as "one great legalized and baptized
brothel,"24 or Harriet Jacobs's Incidents in the Life of a Slave Girl,Z 5 or the
petitions of Henry McNeal Turner and other African-American men in the
aftermath of the Civil War who protested the sexual violation of black women
in domestic service: "All we ask of the white man is to let our ladies alone, and
they need not fear us." 26 As the story of Turner's petition reminds us, the parties
most interested in achieving law reform in such matters were for the most part
disfranchised. Petition thus emerged as a crucial weapon in the campaign. For
example, even before the movement for woman suffrage emerged in the r84os,
women's moral reform societies had begun to wage petition campaigns de-
signed to persuade state legislatures to enact legal penalties for seduction.27The
6 Reva B. Siegel
campaign to reform tort law had both practical and expressive purposes.
Abolitionist Lydia Maria Child described the dignitary affront of a tort regime
that recognized the sexual injury of women as an economic loss to men. She
protested the common law of seduction as it denied to women the legal subjec-
tivity to sustain sexual injury and the legal agency to secure its redress, and
argued that women had internalized their devaluation and objectification by
law: "[A) woman must acknowledge herself the servant of some-body, who
may claim wages for her lost time! ... It is a standing insult to womankind; and
had we not become the slaves we are deemed in law, we should rise en masse ...
and sweep the contemptible insult from the statute-book.''28
With the rise of the woman's rights movement in the decade before the Civil
War, some of its more vocal spokespersons began to discuss the socioeco-
nomic conditions that made women susceptible to sexual coercion. The por-
trait they painted of heterosexual interaction was completely at odds with the
common law's, insofar as it presented coercion as the normal rather than
deviant condition of heterosexual relations. On this account, restrictions on
women's labor market participation ("crowding") and the systematic depres-
sion of their wages left women as a class dependent on men for economic
support, and it was in this condition of "pecuniary dependence" that men
could extract their sexual compliance, in and out of marriage. 29 As Ernestine
Rose explained at an r8 56 woman's rights convention: "What was left for her
but to sell herself for food and clothing either in matrimony or out of it; and it
would require a wise head to determine which was the worse.'' 30
In this critique of marriage as "legalized prostitution" 31 the woman's rights
movement had begun to analyze the political economy of heterosexuality in a
way that took as structurally interconnected the institutions of marriage and
market. This socioeconomic understanding of sexual relations shaped the
movement's response to the trial of domestic servant Hester Vaughn in the
aftermath of the Civil War. Vaughn was fired by her employer when she be-
came pregnant by him; she gave birth alone, ill, and impoverished, and was
found several days later with her dead infant by her side, adjudged guilty of
infanticide, and sentenced to death. 32 As Elizabeth Cady Stanton, Susan B.
Anthony, and other woman's rights advocates publicized the Vaughn case,
they pointed to a variety of gendered injustices that cumulatively sealed
Vaughn's fate-an analysis that started with the gender and class restrictions
that drove Vaughn to domestic service, and the sexual vulnerability her eco-
nomic dependency engendered.33 For the woman's rights movement, the
Vaughn case presented an occasion to protest the economic arrangements and
social understandings that visited the judgment of death on Vaughn for a
Introduction 7
Women in the early feminist and labor movements never managed to orga-
nize a sustained assault on the set of practices we have come to call "sexual
harassment," but they did articulate an indictment of the practices that antici-
pated many of the arguments that women in the modem feminist and labor
movements voiced in the 1970s.
AS SEX DISCRIMINATION .
As we know, the practice of subjecting employees to unwanted sexual
advances at work was made legally actionable under a particular legal regime,
Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.42 During the 1970s, lawyers, advo-
Introduction 9
cates, and theorists had to persuade the American judiciary that sexual harass-
ment is "discrimination on the basis of sex." For this to happen, the injuries
inflicted on women by sexual coercion at work had to be presented to courts in
terms that could be assimilated to a body of law adopted to regulate practices
of racial segregation in the workplace. Catharine MacKinnon's analysis in
Sexual Harassment of Working Women 43 - a stunningly brilliant synthesis of
lawyering and legal theory- played a crucial role in this process.
I want now briefly to revisit the 1970s campaign, with a view to understand-
ing the legal system's "reception" of the sexual harassment claim, its transla-
tion into antidiscrimination discourse. By considering how MacKinnon and
Farley described the injury of sexual harassment, and how judges interpreting
federal employment discrimination law explained the harm of the practice, we
learn much, not only about sexual harassment, but, just as important, about
what law does when it recognizes claims of discrimination.
Writing in the 1970s, MacKinnon and Farley had only sketchy knowledge
of the history we have just surveyed; much of this scholarship was produced as
an outgrowth of the same set of social transformations that gave rise to the
sexual harassment claim in the 1970s. Nevertheless, there are certain striking
parallels between their arguments, and arguments advanced by Child, Rose,
Stanton, Anthony, and Goldman before them. Like these early advocates,
MacKinnon and Farley understood the sexual coercion women encountered
at work as part of the larger political economy of heterosexuality, a social
order that situates sexual relations between men and women in relations of
economic dependency between men and women, an order in which marriage
and market play reinforcing roles in the reproduction of women's social subor-
dination as a class. 44 As MacKinnon wrote in 1979: "Sexual harassment per-
petuates the interlocked structure by which women have been kept sexually in
thrall to men and at the bottom of the labor market. Two forces of American
society converge: men's control over women's sexuality and capital's control
over employees' work lives. Women historically have been required to ex-
change sexual services for material survival, in one form or another. Prostitu-
tion and marriage as well as sexual harassment in different ways institutional-
ize this arrangement."45
Farley and MacKinnon each then proceeded to read the sexual advances
constituting harassment within a semiotics of status inequality. Farley defined
sexual harassment as the "unsolicited nonreciprocal male behavior that as-
serts a woman's sex role over her function as a worker."46 Drawing on sources
as diverse as Adrienne Rich and Erving Goffman, Farley asserted that the
practice of sexual harassment was properly understood within the «micropoli-
tics" of "the patriarchy." She drew upon psychologists and sociologists to
I o Reva B. Siegel
of adverse employment actions against women; what they may not do is treat
women employees differently than they treat, or would treat, male employees.
Note how, on this conception of discrimination, the harm of sexual harass-
ment no longer involves interaction of social structure and social meaning, but
instead reduces to an inquiry into the criteria by which an employersorts
employees. MacKinnon offered a variety of arguments that sexual harassment
was sex discrimination on the differences approach, while at the same time
conducting a detailed diagnosis of how the antidiscrimination tradition was
misrecognizing status harm in the course of recognizing discrimination. 55
Without rehearsing the different iterations of disparate treatment and dispa-
rate impact arguments MacKinnon and others offered in briefing the sexual
harassment claim in more conventional legal terms, I would like, in the inter-
ests of concision, to consider how, as a matter of history, the American legal
system made sense of the proposition that sexual harassment was sex discrimi-
nation within the meaning of Title VII. Much was gained, and lost, in this act
of "recognition."
tion "on the basis of sex." In the words of the district court in Barnes, "The
substance of plaintiff'& complaint is that she was discriminated against, not
because she was a woman, but because she refused to engage in an affair with
her supervisor."67 Even if the plaintiff's sex was a "but-for cause" of the rela-
tionship on the "orientation" account above, her sex was not the sole ground
of distinction; the employer selected among women employees, using some
criterion in addition to and putatively distinct from the plaintiff's "sex." 68
Because the supervisor had targeted some, but not all, class members for
sexual attention, his harassing conduct did not amount to discrimination "on
the basis of sex."
The Supreme Court itself gave stature to such arguments when it ruled in
I974 that statutes regulating employees on the basis of pregnancy were not
sex-based for purposes of Fourteenth Amendment equal-protection analysis, a
rule that the Court then applied to the interpretation of federal employment
discrimination law in I976. 69 In the Court's reasoning, a policy refusing em-
ployment disability benefits to pregnant women discriminated on the basis of
pregnancy, not on the basis of sex: "[t]he program divides potential recipients
into two groups- pregnant women and nonpregnant persons. While the first
group is exclusively female, the second includes members of both sexes." 70 In
other words, it was not enough for the plaintiff to show that the challenged
policy affected members of one group only; the plaintiff would have to show
that the challenged policy affected all members of the targeted group before
the court would characterize the policy as discriminating "on the basis of sex."
During the I970s, the federal judiciary invoked this formalistic conception
of discrimination to explain why some sex-dependent practices were not "sex-
based" and relieve defendants of the obligation to justify them under constitu~
tional or statutory antidiscrimination laws. Employers eagerly seized upon the
defense. Businesses argued that employers were not discriminating on the
basis of sex (so did not have to supply a "bona fide occupational qualifica-
tion"71 defense) when they refused to give employment benefits to women who
were pregnant,72 or to hire women with pre-school age children, 73 or women
who were married, 74 or men with long hair, 75 or women in pants suits,76
or gays and lesbians77 or men with effeminate mannerisms78 - or to retain
women who wouldn't sleep with their supervisors.79 All these policies singled
out members of one sex and imposed conditions on their employment that
preserved traditional gender roles in the workplace. Yet courts applying Title
VII law did not characterize the policies as openly discriminating on the basis
of sex and so require employers to supply business justifications for the poli-
cies that would meet the rigorous "bona fide occupational qualification" ex-
ception to Title Vll's antidiscrimination norm. Instead, courts characterized
I4 Reva B. Siegel
rooted in the experience and animating commitments of this civil rights pi-
oneer. 89 (The Barnes opinion is written with a particularly rich consciousness
of race/gender intersections as, not only the judge, but also the plaintiff and
her alleged harasser, the director of the equal employment opportunity office
for the Environmental Protection Agency, are black.)90 Barnes concludes its
discussion of the sex-plus problem by pointing to cases where employees had
been dismissed for engaging in interracial sexual relations, and notes that in
each of these cases "a cause of action was recognized although it did not
appear that any other individual of the same gender or race had been mis-
treated by the employer."91 At one and the same time, the Barnes opinion
demonstrates that there are formal inconsistencies in the ways that Title Vll
law defines "discrimination on the basis of sex," and insists that questions
about how to characterize practices under the statute should be resolved on
normative rather than formal grounds. Just as prohibitions on interracial sex-
ual relationships play a role in the perpetuation of racial inequality, Barnes
suggests, coerced sexual relations in the workplace play a role in the perpetua-
tion of gender inequality. Thus, in taking the momentous step of recognizing
sexual harassment as sex discrimination, the court reasoned about the practice
as perpetuating group status inequalities and not simply group-based differen-
tiation. Robinson concludes his opinion in Barnes- the first appellate opinion
recognizing the sexual harassment cause ofaction- by quoting from Rogers v.
EEOC, 92 the first appeJlate to recognize a hostile environment claim of racial
harassment under Title Vll: Congress deliberately left the language of Title Vll
open-ended," 'knowing that constant change is the order of our day and that
the seemingly reasonable practices of the present can easily become the in-
justices of the morrow.' "93
While the first cases recognizing the sexual harassment claim as a form of
sex discriminatiop under Title Vll labored mightily with the "sex-plus" prob-
lem,94 the issue simply disappeared thereafter. Federal courts still use sex-plus
doctrine to remove a variety of sex-specific policies from Title VII scrutiny
(employers may refuse to hire women who wear pants, men who wear dresses,
women who date women, men who display "effeminate" mannerisms),95 yet
no one remembers that sexual harassment was once legally grouped with these
practices, disaggregated into a policy based on "sex plus refusal to furnish sex-
ual consideration." Plainly, if we are to account for the different doctrinal
analysis of sexual harassment and sex-specific grooming codes under Title Vll
today, we would have to seek an explanation in the domain of social, not for-
mal, logic. Today, under Title Vll employers may not fire women who refuse
to sleep with them, but they may fire women who sleep with other women.
The gender transformations of the I970S persuaded the federal judiciary that
z6 Reva B. Siegel
some; though surely not all, features of heterosexual social practice were at
odds with the nation's egalitarian commitments.
We can thus read the formal distinctions in the 1970s case law as remnants
of a larger social struggle, doctrinal residue of a wide-ranging debate about
whether and how law would intervene in a fieid of contested gender rela-
tions.96 (We might liken this dispute to arguments about whether separate-
but-equal was discrimination on the basis of race that took place in the thir-
teen years spanning Brown,97 the per curiams/8 and the Court's ruling in
Loving v. Virginia 99 that antimiscegenation laws unconstitutionally discrimi-
nated on the basis of race- a decision the Court did not hand down until
1967, the same year that Guess Who's Coming to Dinner? won the Academy
Awards. In our own day, we can see a similar dynamic at work as social
movement protest pressures federal courts to decide whether the state's use
of race in suspect descriptions amounts to discrimination "on the basis of
race"- a dispute over the meaning of the equal protection clause in which a
version of "race-plus" figures.)1° 0 In short, judgments about whether prac-
tices discriminate "on the basis" of sex or race may depend on evolving so-
cial intuitions about whether a practice unjustly perpetuates a status regime,
rather than formal characteristics of the practice itself, as antidiscrimination
discourse leads us to believe.
But if judgments a bout whether practices discriminate on the basis of race or
sex are social constructions, shaped by social-movement protest and the like,
we do not, of course, generally experience them or discuss them in such terms.
Antidiscrimination doctrine selectively internalized changes in gen.der norms
during the 1970s without acknowledging the project in which it was engaged.
Even as the Barnes opinion recognizes that sexual harassment is discrimination
on the basis of sex, it still clings to the fiction that it is merely analyzing
discrimination as the practice of sorting sexed bodies: sexual harassment in-
volves "a treatment differential allegedly predicated upon an immutable per-
sonal characteristic gender which subjected appellant to a marked disadvan-.
tage in comparison with men employed at the agency. " 101 Sex discrimination
law, like race discrimination law, pretends that it analyzes distinctions on the
basis of physiologically, rather than sociologically, defined aspects of iden-
tity.102 In this way, antidiscrimination law represses the social history, social
structure, and social meaning of the practice of sexual harassment in the very
act of declaring the pJ;actice a legal wrong.
Consider again the way that doctrine reasons its way to the conclusion that
sexual harassment is sex discrintination. At first, courts viewed the conduct
constituting sexual harassment as completely distinct from practices the law
Introduction 17
calls sex discrimination; then cases such as Barnes tie the practice of sexual
harassment to the concept of discrimination by means of a narrative that finds
discrimination in the way that persons of monosexual sexual orientation se·
lect sexual objects (on this account, discrimination is an act of differentiation,
a species of taste or desire, and its objects are particular kinds of sexed bodies).
Antidiscrimination law explains how sexual harassment is sex discrimination
in terms that are fundamentally uninterested in the social circumstances of the
harasser's target (for example, her position in an employment hierarchy, her
other economic alternatives if she does not stay employed at this job). It also
excludes from the formal account of why harassment is discrimination "on the
basis of sex" the particulars of what the harasser does to his targets once he
selects her. 103
Finally, and most important, the law's account of sexual harassment as
discriminating "on the basis of sex" does not address the particular kinds of
harm that sexual harassment inflicts on its targets-the ways that it engenders
them. When the sex discrimination in sexual harassment is conceptualized as a
form of desire (selecting appropriately sexed bodies given the nature of one's
orientation), the act of differentiation that makes sexual harassment sex dis-
crimination would appear to be a normal, natural, and fundamentally benign
feature of social life. On this account, the harm of sexual harassment is some·
how incidental to the practice of sex discrimination; the harm arises from an
act of sexual coercion that just happens to be inflicted on a person with a body
sexed female. (This is exactly the understanding expressed by sex-plus doc-
trine when it conceptualizes sexual harassment as "sex" "plus" the "neutral"
criterion of "unwillingness to furnish sexual consideration.") What is more, as
antidiscrimination law begins to recognize sexual harassment as sex discrimi-
nation, it treats the sexual coercion in sexual harassment as a harm so obvious
as not to need explanation or account. But this very failure to explain "the
obvious" means that antidiscrimination law rather unselfconsciously incorpo-
rates a gender-conventional understanding of why harassment harms women
(it is a form of socially inappropriate conduct, "not a nice way to treat a
lady").
And so, as antidiscrimination law recognizes sexual harassment as sex dis-
crimination, it never acknowledges the power dynamic that women over two
centuries have described: the way that men extracting sex from economically
dependent women reiterate a coercive relationship that organizes heterosex-
ual relations in marriage and the market both. Sexual harassment would be
sex discrimination on this account, not because of how it sorts sexed bodies,
but because of how this form of coercion, iterated across social institutions,
18 Reva B. Siegel
Contemporary Transformations in
the Practice of Sexual Harassment
To this point in our story, we have considered sexual harassment as a
relatively stable social practice that is an integral part of a variety of hetero-
Introduction I 9
sexual relations"; 113 after resisting, she capitulated. According to her com-
plaint, she then had sex with her supervisor some forty or fifty times in the next
several years, and on several occasions was raped by him. 114 The Court's next
harassment case, Harris v. Forklift Systems, 115 handed down in 1993, presents
the "new" sexual harassment scenario involving work roles that do not con-
form to gender conventions. Here the plaintiff worked as a manager of a
company that rented heavy equipment to construction companies. Hardy,
Forklift's president, harassed the plaintiff in terms that differ in important
particulars from the harassment at issue in Vinson. For example, Hardy con-
tinually made the plaintiff the target of comments such as: "You're a woman,
what do you know" and "We need a man as the rental manager," and at least
once, he told her she was "a dumb ass woman." 116 These comments were
interspersed with a variety of sexualized interactions. As the Supreme Court
relates: "In front of others, he suggested that the two of them 'go to the
Holiday Inn to negotiate [Harris' ] raise.' ... Hardy occasionally asked Harris
and other female employees to get coins from his front pants pocket.... He
threw ,objects on the ground in front of Harris and other women, and asked
them to pick the objects up .... He made sexual innuendos about Harris' and
other women's clothing." 117
In both Vinson and Harris employers ask their female employees to go to a
motel, but this "proposition" does not have the same meaning in the two
cases. It does not appear from the facts of the Harris case that the employer is
the slightest bit interested in consummating sexual relations with the plaintiff,
as an expression of "desire" or "power." Rather, the "proposition" he makes
reiterates his claim that "we need a man as the rental manager." Like the other
sexually demeaning performances that Hardy exacts of Harris and the other
women in his ·employ, Hardy's mock proposal is intended to humiliate, send-
ing the message that, by trying to fill a man's job, Harris has made herself
contemptible: a failure, both as a woman and as a man.
Sexual harassment in nontraditional job settings communicates anxiety
about male authority not as visible in harassment in traditional job settings.
The harasser- who may stand to harassee in the role of superior, coworker, or
subordinate- uses harassment as an informal way to exclude women he lacks
formal legal or institutional authority to fire. The woman has violated gen-
dered work spaces or roles, and, as the Harris facts illustrate, sexualized con-
duct aims to restore the gendered order of work by expressing all the ways a
woman invading male work space is out of her proper role and place.
As Vicki Schultz has recently emphasized, harassment in nontraditional job
settings can involve many kinds of conduct, much of it not typically character-
ized as sexual; she demonstrates that judges in some circuits have failed to
.2.2 Reva B. Siegel
recognize the ways that sexual harassment can enforce occupational segre-
gation, so have refused to analyze harassing conduct that is nonsexual in
nature-or have "disaggregated" sexual and nonsexual harassing conduct in
ways that obscure their interactive exclusionary dynamics. 118
But as this discussion should suggest, differences in the harassment dynamic
in traditional and nontraditional job settings can produce confusions about
the sexual elements of harassment as well. As the Harris case illustrates, ha-
rassment in nontraditional job settings is often accomplished by sexualized
conduct. (In fact, one study reports that women in male-dominated work
settings "were generally more likely than other women workers to report a
variety of different kinds of social-sexual behavior in their current jobs."}119
Because of the different dynamics of harassment in traditional and nontradi-
tional job settings, there may be confusion about the kind of injury the "sex"
in sexual harassment inflicts. Is the harm of sexual harassment sexual coer-
cion? Or occupational exclusion?
In the classic harassment scenario-the kind Catharine MacKinnon first
analyzed in the I970s- a woman is forced to participate in sexual relations
she does not want in order to keep her job; in these circumstances, sexual
coercion enforces a traditionally gendered form of subjection that is fraught
with the kinds of dignitary meanings and distributive consequences that
women have protested since the first critique of marriage as legalized prostitu-
tion in the decade before the Civil War.
This classic form of harassment continues to flourish. But, as Harris illus-
trates, alongside it, there are newer forms of harassment, in which econom-
ically leveraged sexual coercion does not play the same central role. In these
kinds of cases, men are· not using economic power to secure sexual access to
women they otherwise would not have; rather, in this new kind of harassment
case that arises as women enter nontraditional jobs, men use sexualized and
nonsexualized conduct to communicate to women their outsider status in the
workplace. In this new scenario, the harm of sexual harassment is not a tradi-
tional kind of sexual coercion but a new cousin of it. Harm occurs- not
through the traditional pathway in which the harassed woman lacks capacity
to refuse an unwanted sexual relationship,- but instead because the harasser
uses sexualized and nonsexualized conduct to construct the harassed woman
as an outsider in the workplace-de-authorized and denigrated, in her own
eyes and in the eyes of others. As Harris illustrates, the harm here involves
forms of gender-role policing,120 often accomplished through sexualized at-
tention of a denigrating or mocking sort, rather than classic forms of sexual
coercion.
Consider the facts of Harris again. When Harris' boss suggested that he
Introduction 23
go with her to the Holiday Inn to discuss a raise, Harris was perfectly able
to say no; but the moment Hardy propositioned Harris (in front of her sub-
ordinates), he inflicted harm as directly as when he uttered the "nonsexual"
remarks he was in the habit of directing her way ("You're a woman, what
do you know?" "We need a man as the rental manager," "[You're] a dumb
ass woman"). The mock "proposition" here communicates to the plaintiff,
"You're a woman, what do you know?" "We need a man as the rental man-
ager," and "[You're] a dumb ass woman- but it interpellates gender by invok-
ing the sexual prerogative performed in Vinson and in countless scenes like it
for centuries prior. By invoking this social memory- in the form of the mock
proposition and the various commands to assume sexually compromising
positions-the president of Forklift seeks to assert ma~culine authority over
his "dumb ass woman" rental manager that she has challenged by her very
presence in a traditionally male occupation.
In Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore Services, 121 a case involving "same sex"
sexual harassment, the Supreme Court acknowledged the existence of dif-
ferent scenarios or paradigms in sexual harassment case law. In Oncale, a
group of men on an oil platform in the Gulf of Mexico harassed a male
coworker, in ways Justice Scalia was too uncomfortable to discuss, but which,
according to the plaintiff, involved different forms of assaultive sexualized
conduct: not only threats to rape the plaintiff, but part- or mock-performances
of the act (holding the plaintiff down while placing their penises up against his
body, grabbing him in the shower and doing the equivalent, or more, with a
piece of soap). 122 The Court held that the plaintiff could sue his employer for
sexual harassment under Title VII so long as the plaintiff could show that the
conduct in question amounted to discrimination on the basis of sex. The
Court's discussion of the different ways that sexual harassment plaintiffs can
demonstrate sex discrimination provides a revealing account of the case law:
Courts and juries have found the inference of discrimination easy to draw in
most male-female sexual harassment situations, because the challenged con-
duct typically involves explicit or implicit proposals of sexual activity; it is
reasonable to assume those proposals would not have been made to someone
of the same sex. The same chain of inference would be available to a plaintiff
alleging same-sex harassment, if there were credible evidence that the ha-
rasser was homosexual. But harassing conduct need not be motivated by
s~xual desire to support an inference of discrimination on the basis of sex. A
trier of fact might reasonably find such discrimination, for example, if a
female victim is harassed in such sex-specific and derogatory terms by another
woman as to make it clear that the harasser is motivated by general hostility
to the presence of women in the workplace . ... Whatever evidentiary route
24 Reva B. Siegel
the plaintiff chooses to follow, he or she must always prove that the conduct at
issue was not merely tinged with offensive sexual connotations, but actually
constituted "discriminat[ion] ... because of sex." 123
same time, there is a danger in underreading the sex here, in ways that sever it
from its genealogical referents. Sex between men and women is part of the
semiotics of status betWeen men and women- surely as expressive as "You're
a woman, what do you know?" and "We need a man as the rental manager." H
sex has been taken up in the defense of gender-traditional work roles, as a
mechanism for enforcing the code that marks some work roles "male" and
others "female"- it would make little sense to ignore it because there was no
real risk of sexual coercion in the traditional-scenario sense.
Which brings us back to the "rape" scene in Oncale. Where, if at all, do we
find sexual harassment on these facts? The Court seems confident that there is
sexual harassment on these "same-sex" facts, if Oncale's harassers are gay.
Then, by the Court's logic, what Oncale's harassers are doing to him reflects
"desire" and, by reason of the harassers' orientation, would count as an act of
discrimination "on the basis of sex." H, however, Oncale's harassers are not
gay, then, by the Court's logic, it is unlikely that what they are doing is "dis-
crimination on the basis of sex" unless it reflects "hostility to women in the
workplace." The Court's aversion to contemplating the facts of this case and
considering how they might enact discrimination on the basis of sex (even as
the Oncale opinion insistently- and somewhat remarkably for a discrimina-
tion case-reminds us that sexual harassment doesn't arise in every act of
gender differentiation but instead requires context-attentive interpretation of
the facts) 124 suggests that the Court doesn't in fact see harassment on these
facts, unless the men harassing Oncale are gay.
But our reading of Harris reveals how sexualized conduct can parodically
"recall" the traditional gender order and mark certain work roles "male."
Suppose the men harassing Oncale are straight. The male-male harassment in
Oncale could well be assimilated to the male-female harassment in Harris.
On this view, Oncale's harassers would be deploying sexualized conduct to
gender-mark work roles, even though no woinen are on the scene-in some
important sense to ensure that no women ever appear on the scene. Oil plat-
forms in the Gulf of Mexico, just like construction-equipment rental com-
panies, are "male" space, and performing certain masculinities in the course of
performing one's work is apparently an important mechanism for keeping
them so.
Suppose, by contrast, the men harassing Oncale are gay. The hypotheti-
cal case the Court seems to thinks an easy case of "sex discrimination" in
Oncale- the case involving "credible evidence that the harasser was homo-
sexual"125 is one that we would have to think about much harder. On these
facts, involving an attempted rape, there would be no doubt whatsoever
in calling the conduct an actionable assault- but do we want to call it sex
26 Reva B. Siegel
Notes
I. Slave women were subject to sexual coercion by masters and overseers. See Eliz-
abeth Fox-Genovese, Within the Plantation Household: Black and White Women of the
Old South 49, 297-99, 325-26 (I988); Jacqueline Jones, Labor of Love, Labor of
Sorrow: Black Women, Work, and the Family from Slavery to the Present 20, 28, 3 7-3 8
(I985); Melton A. McLaurin, Celia, A Slave: A True Story 24-25 (I991). For a discus-
sion of the literature on the sexual exploitation of slave women, see Catherine Clinton,
"Caught in the Web of the Big House: Women and Slavery," in The Web of Southern
Relations 19-35 (Walter Fraser, Jr., et al., eds. I985). For sources discussing the law
governing slave rape, see infra note I I.
2. On the sexual exploitation of African-American women working as domestic
servants in the South in the decades after emancipation, see Paula Giddings, When and
Where I Enter: The Impact of Black Women on Race and Sex in America 86-87 (1984);
Tera W. Hunter, To 1oy My Freedom: Southern Black Women'S Lives and Labors After
the Civil War 34, 106 (1997);jones, supra note I, at I 5o; Bettina Berch, '"The Sphinx in
the Household': A New Look at the History of Household Workers," I6 Review of
Radical Political Economics 105, II5-16 (1984). On the predicament of women in
domestic service generally, see Kerry Segrave, The Sexual Harassment of Women in the
Workplace, I6oo-I993· at 23-39 (1994) (analyzing sexual abuse of women working in
domestic service and comparing practices in United States and various European coun-
tries); see .also Faye E. Dudden, Serving Women: Household Service in Nineteenth-
Century America 213-19 (1983) (discussing prevalence of sexual relations in domestic
service, focusing on seduction and abandonment); Gerda Lerner, The Majority Finds Its
Voice: Placing Women in American History 57 (1979 ), quoted in Giddings, supra, at 48-
49 ("Victorian morality applied to the 'better class' only. It was taken for granted during
the period and well into the twentieth century that working-class women- and especially
Black women- were freely available for sexual use by upper-class males").
3· For an overview of factory working conditions in the United States and several
other nations in the period from .1800 to the mid-I9oos, see Segrave, supra note 2 at 40-
73; see also Mary Bularzik, "Sexual Harassment at the Workplace: Historical Notes," 12
Radical America, 25, 28-38 (1978). On clerical workers, see Ruth Rosen, The Lost
Sisterhood: Prostitution in America, I900-I9I8, at I52-55 (1982) (discussing pros-
titutes who report~d sexual harassment in previous employment as domestic or clerical
workers); Bularzik, supra, at 2 5; see also Alice Kessler-Harris, Out to Work: A History of
Wage Earning Women in the United States 102 (1982) (quoting report of the U.S. Com-
mission on Industrial Relations) ("'A good many girls in department stores have got to
give in to the demands ... of certain ... buyers, managers, and floor walkers ... if they
want to hold their positions'").
4· For sources discussing how sexual exploitation of slave women was rationalized as
an expression of the natural promiscuity of African-American women, see bell hooks,
Ain't I a Woman: Black Women and Feminism 52 (1981) ("Whitewomenand white men
justified the sexual exploitation of enslaved black women by arguing that they were the
initiators of sexual relationships with men"); Deborah Gray White, Ar'n't I a Woman:
Female Slaves in the Plantation South 61 (1985); Regina Austin, "Sapphire Bound!"
1989 Wisconsin Law Review 539, 570 (1989) ("Jezebel was the wanton libidinous black
3o Reva B. Siegel
woman whose easy ways excused white men's abuse of their slaves as sexual 'partners'");
Peter Bardaglio, "Rape and the Law in the Old South: 'Calculated to Excite Indignation
in Every Heart,'" 6o Journal of Southern History 749, 757· On domestic servants, see
Dudden, supra note :z., at 217 ("Some .observers thought that prostitution recruited many
ex-servants because service was filled with 'low' women"); Segrave, supra note :z., at :z.6-
2 7 (discussing reputed promiscuity of servant girls).
5· See McLaurin, supra note I, at 81; accord Kristin Hoganson, "Garrisonian Aboli-
tionists and the Rhetoric of Gender, 185o-I86o,'' 45 American Quarterly 558, 571-73
(I993) ("[T]he many images of slave women as victims of seduction and rape that perme-
ated abolitionist publications contradicted Southern images of the slave woman as Jeze-
bel"); see also Karen Sanchez-Eppler, Touching Liberty: Abolition, Feminism, and the
Politics of the Body 83-I04 (1993) (analyzing account of sexual exploitation in Harriet
Jacobs's Incidents in the Life ofa Slave Girl).
6. See Dudden, supra note 2, at 2I3-I9.
7. Helen Campbell, Prisoners of Poverty: Women Wage- Workers, Their Trades and
Their Lives 234 (I 8 87 ), quoted in Lin Farley, Sexual Shakedown; The Sexual Harassment
of Women on the Job 39 (I978).
8. See, e.g., Campbell, supra note 7, at 22-29, 87, I3 5-56.
9· Upton Sinclair, The Jungle ( I96o) (1905 ).
Io. Id. at I09 (emphasis added}.
II. Masters who raped their female slaves were not held legally accountable. See
McLaurin, supra note I, at 93; Bardaglio, supra note 4, at 756-6o; Margaret A. Burn-
ham, "An Impossible Marriage: Slave Law and Family Law," 5 Law and Inequality
Journal I 87, :z. I9-:Z.:Z. (I 987); A. Leon Higginbotham, Jr., and Anne F. Jacobs, "The 'Law
Only as an Enemy': The Legitimization of Racial Powerlessness Through the Colonial
and Antebellum Criminal Laws of Virginia," 70 North Carolina Law Review 969, I o 55-
58 (I 99 :z.) (describing thelegal impunity with which white men raped black women).
12. 2 Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Criminal Law 607-I 6 (5th ed. I 8 7:Z. ).
13. As one nineteenth-century treatise explained the "utmost resistance" requirement,
"Nature has given her hands and feet with which she can strike and kick, teeth to bite and
a voice to cry out-all these should be put in requisition in defense of her chastity"; the
treatise went on to explain that there should be "some marks of violence upon the person
of the alleged ravished woman, and her statement is greatly strengthened if the marks are
found to have been present and seen by others immediately after the commission of the
offense.'' Ira M. Moore, A Practical Treatise on Criminal Law and Procedure in Criminal
Cases Bef9re Justices ofthe Peace and in Courts of Record in the State of Illinois 299-30I
(1876), quoted in Lea VanderVelde, ''The Legal Ways of Seduction," 48 Stanford Law
Review 817, 8 56 (I996). For additional nineteenth-century commentary on the utmost
resistance requirement, see id. at 8 55-58.
I4. People v. Dohring, I4 N.Y. 374, 384 (I874) (emphasis added).
I 5. For instance, in Christian v. Virginia, 2 3 Grattan 9 54 (Va. I 873 ), a black man was
acquitted for attempted rape of a black woman, even though he had "laid hold of her,
pushing her down on a pile of lumber, choking her, and trying to pull up her cloths." Id. at
9 55. The court reasoned that the burden of proof varies from case to case, depending on
"the character and condition of the parties." I d. at 9 58. Even though such actions would
Introduction 3I
have been a "shocking outrage toward a woman of virtuous sensibilities .•. how far it
affected the sensibilities of the prosecutrix does not appear," since the defendant's actions
might simply have been an attempt to "work upon her passions." Id. at 959· Racial bias
in rape cases persists today. See Elizabeth M. Iglesias, "Rape, Race, and Representation:
The Power of Discourse, Discourses of Power, and the Reconstruction of Heterosex-
uality,"49 Vanderbilt Law Review 869, 88o-86 (r996) (discussing studies in Gary D.
LaFree, Rape and Criminal Justice [r989], showing that conviction rates depend on the
victim's race as well as on the defendant's).
r6. See Bardaglio,supra note 4, at 756-57 (observing that, according to an inRuential
treatise on slave Ia w, "only the master could seek compensation in the courts because 'the
violation of the person of a female slave, carries with it no other punishment than the
damages which the master may recover for the trespass upon his property'") (quoting
Thomas R. R. Cobb, An Inquiry into the Law of Negro Slavery in the United States of
America 99 [r858]).
r7. See VanderVelde, supra note r3, at 837-4r (r996) (quoting Chitty's r832. edition
of Blackstone as stating that "In no case whatever, unless she has had a promise of
marriage, can a woman herself obtain any reparation for the injury she has sustained
from the seducer of her virtue"). Where touching was sexual, the common law incorpo-
rated the assumptions of rape law, including presumptive consent; moreover, the com-
mon law resisted commodifying what it understood as a "moral" rather than "economic"
injury. On the understandings underlying the common law's failure to provide victims of
rape a private action for recovery, see VanderVelde, supra, at 842.-67. On the tort claim
available to fathers alleging loss of their daughters' services by reason of their seduction,
see id. at 867-9r. On the use of the tort to redress sexual injury inRicted on women
employed outside their own ho.usehold, see id. at 8 37 n.90 (noting that of 2.87 nineteenth-
century reported seduction cases studied, forty-six indicate that the seducer was either the
woman's employer or his son).
rS. See id. at 8 54-67 (analyzing tort of seduction as elaborated in nineteenth-century
treatises and case law); see also Lisa Granik, "Running in Hermeneutic Circles: Challeng-
ing/Embedding Social Hierarchies Through Litigation" r98-2.ro (J.S.D thesis, Yale Law
School, I997) (analyzing tort actions for indecent assault filed by women against their
employers from the mid-nineteenth century to the mid-twentieth century).
19. See Granik, supra note r8, at 2.05-2.08.
20. See VanderVelde, supra note 13, at 883-97 (charting the evolving meaning, and
legal elements, of the seduction action over the course of the nineteenth century).
2. r. Id. at 89 5. Even after statutory reforms nominally accorded women in some states
the right to sue for seduction, courts continued to reject their claims on the ground that a
woman's "consent" to intercourse defeated her seduction action. See M. B. W. Sinclair,
"Seduction and the Myth of the Ideal Woman," 5 Law and Inequality 33,51-52. (r987);
see also Thomas M. Cooley, The Elements of Torts 86 n.r (r89 5) (noting that a woman
could not recover if she was "equally guilty with the man"); Right of Seduced Female to
Maintain Action for Seduction, I2I American Law Reports 1487, 1487-92 (r939)
(citing statutory rape cases, where consent was a legal impossibility, as exceptions to a
general policy of disallowing women's seduction suits).
2.2. See VanderVelde, supra note 13, at 896.
32 Reva B. Siegel
23. See Michael Grossberg, Governing the Hearth: Law and the Family in Nineteenth-
Century America 5 I -6 3 (I 9 85); Ariela R. Du bier, "Wifely Behavior: A Legal History of
Acting Married," Ioo Columbia Law Review 9 57, 1002-1003 (2000) (comparing anti-
common law marriage statutes to anti-heartbalm legislation); Jane E. Larson, "'Women
Understand So Little, They Call My Good Nature "Deceit"': A Feminist Rethinking of
Seduction," 93 Columbia Law Reiliew 374, 393-40I (1993); Sinclair, supra note :z.I, at
72-98.
24. Hoganson, supra note 5, at 571.
25. Harriet Jacobs, Incidents in the Life of a Slave Girl, Written By Herself (L. Maria
Childed., I86I).
26. Hunter, supra note. 2, at 34 (protesting sexual assaults on women in domestic
service in year after war ended).
27. See Barbara J. Berg, The Remembered Gate: Origins of American Feminism 2II-
I 2 (I 978) (describing petition drives for statute crirninalizing seduction in New York that
collected nearly 2o,ooo signatures in I 840, and another involving almost as many signa-
tures that same year in Ohio); Larry Whiteaker, Seduction, Prostitution, and Moral
Reform in New York, I830-I86o,at I42 (1997) (reporting that by 1841 Moral Reform
Society had foiWarded "some 40,000 petitions" to the state legislature seeking a law
criminalizing seduction); Larson, supra note 23, at 391.
28. Ameridan Female Moral Reform Society, Advocate of Moral Reform 4I (1844),
quoted· in Berg, supra note 27, at 2IO (1978).
29. See Reva B. Siegel, "Home as Work: The First Woman's Rights Claims Concerning
Wives' Household Labor, 185o-188o," 103 Yale Law Journal 1073, n21-22 (1994)
[hereinafter Siegel, "Home as Work"].
30. "Woman's Rights Convention in New York," Liberator, Dec. 5, 1856, at 196; see
also id. (reporting that Henry Blackwell asserted that "[h]alf the marriages [which] were
now contracted would not be, were women pecuniarily independent").
3 I. For accounts of the legalized prostitution argument; see Rosen, supra note 29, at
55-57; Siegel, "Home as Work," supra note 29, at n21-22 & n. 166; see also Reva B.
Siegel, "Reasoning from the Body: A Historical Perspective on Abortion Regulation and
Questions of Equal Protection," 44 Stanford Law Review 261, 308-14 (1992) (describ-
ing claims about marriage as legalized prostitution in nineteenth-century debates about
abortion); jill Elaine Hasday, "Contest and Consent: A Legal History of Marital Rape,"
88 California Law Review 1373, 1455 (describing claims about marriage as legalized
prostitution in nineteenth-century debates about marital rape}.
32. See Ellen Carol DuBois, Feminism and Suffrage: The Emergence ofan Independent
Women's Movement in America, 1848-I869, at 145-47 (1978}; Segrave, supra note 2,
at29-30.
33.DuBois, supra note 32,at 146.
34· On pardon, see Segrave, supra note 2, at 30. On the location of the Vaughn case in
the postwar movement's advocacy agenda, see Pillsbury, "The Hester Vaughn Meeting at
· Cooper Institute," Revolution, Dec. 10, I 868, aq 61; see also Eliza beth Pleck, "Feminist
Responses to 'Crimes Against Women,' 1868-1896,'' 8 Signs 451 (1983).
3 5.Jane E. Larson," 'Even a Worm Will Turn at Last': Rape Reform in Late Nineteenth-
Century America," 9 Yale Journal of Law and Humanities 1 (1997).
Introduction 33
against its employees in at least two cases in the early 1970s. See Barnes v. Costle, 561
F.2d 983,990 (D.C. Cir. 1977) (ground of discrimination 'not sex, but refusal "to furnish
sexual consideration"); Williams v. Sax be, 413 F. Supp. 654, 6 57 (D.D.C. 1976) ("since
the primary variable in the claimed class is willingness vel non to furnish sexual consid-
eration, rather than gender, the sex discrimination proscriptions of the Act are not
invoked").
69. Geduldig v. Aiello, 417 U.S. 484, 496-97 n.2o (1974); Gilbert v. General Electric
Co., 429 U.S. 125 (1976). Note that Gilbert was statutorily "overruled" by Congress
when it enacted the Pregnancy Discrimination Amendment to Title VIT in 1978. See
Pregnancy Discrimination Act, Pub. L. No. 95-5 55,92 Stat. 2076 (1978) (codified at 42
U.S.C. § 2oooe(k) (1994).
70. Geduldigv. Aiello, 417U.S. 484, 496-97n.2o (1974).See Gilbert, 429 U.S. at 135
(quoting this passage as a basis for holding that, under Title vn, employment policies that
discriminate on the basis of pregnancy do not discriminate on the basis of sex).
71. See 42 U.S.C. § 2oooe-2(e) (2ooo).
72. Gilbert v. General Electric Co., 429 U.S. !25 (1976); Nashville Gas Co. v. Satty,
434 U.S. 136 (1977)
73· Phillips v. Martin Marietta Corp., 400 U.S. 542 (1970) (holding that policy violates
Title VII).
74· Sprogis v. United Air Lines, 444 F.2d 1194 (7th Cir. 1971) (striking down policy
forbidding female, but not male, flight attendants to marry).
75· Willingham v. Macon Telegraph Publ'g. Co., 507 F.2d 1084 {5th Cir. 1975).
76. See, e.g., Lanigan v. Bartlett & Co. Grain, 466 F. Supp. 1388, 1391 (W.D. Mo.
1979) (applying "sex-plus" doctrine to uphold discharge of female employee who vio-
lated dress code by wearing a pantsuit) ("plaintiff's affection for pantsuits is not an
'immutable characteristic'"); cf. Devine v. Lonschein, 62.I F. Supp. 894, 897 (S.D.N.Y.
1985) ("At least until that dreadful day when unisex identity of dress and appearance
arrives, judicial officers ... are entitled to some latitude in differentiating between.male
and female attorneys, within the context of decorous professional behavior and ap-
pearance").
77· See, e.g., DeSantis v. Pacific Tel. & Tel. Co., 6o8 F.2d 327,331 (9th Cir. 1979) ("We
must again reject appellants' efforts to 'bootstrap' Title vn protection for homosexuals .
. . . [W]hether dealing with men or women the employer is using the same criterion: it will
not hire or promote a person who prefers sexual partners of the same sex. Thus this policy
does not involve different decisional criteria for the sexes").
78. Smith v. Liberty Mutual Ins. Co., 569 F.2.d 325 (5th Cir. 1978).
79· See Barnesv. Costle, 561 F.2.d 983,990 (D.C. Cir. 1977) (ground of discrimination
not sex, but refusal "to furnish sexual consideration"); Williams v. Saxbe, 413 F. Supp.
6 54, 657 (D.D.C. 1976) ("[S]ince the primary variable in the claimed class is willingness
vel non to furnish sexual consideration, rather than gender, the sex discrimination pro-
scriptions of the Act are not invoked").
So. See, e.g., Stroud v. Delta Air Lines, Inc., 548 F.2d 356,1977 WL 25929, at ""2 (5th
Cir. 1977) (unpublished opinion) (holding that in an all-female pool, discriminating
against married women does not violate Title VII) ("[C]ertain women- stewardesses who
36 Reva B. Siegel
are unmarried- are favored over certain other women- stewardesses who are married.
As one of the all-female group of flight attendants employed by Delta, plaintiff suffered a
discrimination, but it was based on marriage and not sex"); Knott v. Missouri Pacific Rail-
road Co., 527 F.2d 1249, 1252 (8th Cir. 1975) (upholding different grooming standards
for men and women) ("While no hair length restriction is applicable to females, all em-
ployees must conform to certain standards of dress. Where, as here, such policies are rea-
sonable and are imposed in an evenhanded manner on all employees, slight differences in
the appearance requirements for males and females have only a negligible effect on em-
ployment opportunities"); Willingham v. Macon Tel. Publ'g Co., 507 F.2d 1084, I092
(1975) (upholding different grooming standards for men and women) ("This frame of
analysis removes Willingham's complaint completely from the Sec. 703 (a) 'sex-plus' cate-
gory, because both sexes are being screened with respect to a neutral fact, i.e., grooming in
accordance with generally accepted community standards of dress and appearance").
8I. Cf. Geduldig v. Aiello, 417 U.S. 484,496-97 n.2o (1974) ("The program divides
potential recipients into two groups- pregnant women and nonpregnant persons. While
the first group is exclusively female, the second includes members of both sexes").
82. Willingham v. Macon Tel. Pub/'g Co., 507 E2d 1084, 1090 (5th Cir. 1975) (en
bane).
83.Id.
84. See id. at 1092.
8s.Seeid. at1091-92.
86. See supra note 67 and accompanying text.
87. See, e.g., Williams v. Saxbe, 413 F. Supp. 654,657-61 (D.D.C. 1976) (distinguish-
ing pregnancy cases and "so-called 'hair cases''' and insisting that "[t]he requirement of
willingness to provide sexual consideration in this case is no different from the 'pre-
school age children' and 'no-marriage' rules" in cases where a sex-plus policy was held to
be sex discrimination in vioiation of statute).
88. See Barnes v. Costle, 561 F.2d 983, 993 (D.C. Cir. 1977).
89. Robinson played a key role in litigating Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948), and
was part of the NAACP team that argued Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483
(1954). He also served as dean of Howard University Law School, where he and his
colleagues and students developed many of the central legal theories of the civil rights
movement. See Richard Kluger, Simple Justice: The History of Brown v. Board of Educa-
tion and Black Ameiica's Struggle for Equality_ 253-55,48 5-505, 667-69 (1976).
90. See id. at 984. A number of the early sexual harassment plaintiffs were African-
Am~rican women, some suing white male supervisors. See, e.g., Miller v. Bank of Amer-
ica, 418 F. Supp. 233 (N.D. CaL 1977) (black female clerk suing white male supervisor);
Munford v. James T. Barnes & Co., 441 F. Supp. 459 (E.D. Mich. 1977) (black female
assistant manager suing white male employer). Other early cases, like Barnes, involved
intraracial harassment. For discussions of several of the early cases and their racial dy-
namics, see MacKinnon, Sexual Harassment, supra note 42, at 61-62, 65-68; Elvia R.
Arriola," 'What's the Big Deal?' Women in the New York City Construction Industry and
Sexual Harassm~t Law, 1970-!98 s," 22 Columbia Human Rights Law ReviB;W 2.I., 4I-
42 (1990).
91. Barnes, 56I F.2d at 993-94 (footnotes omitted).
Introduction 37
"unwelcome" is one much-criticized definitional element. See, e.g., Susan Estrich, "Sex at
Work," 43 Stanford Law Review 8r3, 8rs-r6 (1991) (arguing that the law of sexual
harassment imports many of the "rules and prejudices" endemic in traditional rape law,
including a misplaced emphasis on the victim's conduct).
ro4. See Siegel, "Discrimination in the Eyes of the Law," supra note so, at 109-13
(analyzing how dynamic interaction of antidiscrimination rhetoric and status-enforcing
practices gave rise to dispute about whether civil rights law was best understood to
embody an "antidiscrimination" or an "antisubordination" principle).
ros. In a much relied upon study of sex segregation in employment, Andrea Beller
reports that occupational segregation from 1972 to 198r experienced "a rate of decline
almost three times as large as that during the 196os." See Andrea H. Beller, "Trends in
Occupational Segregation by Sex and Race, I960-198r," in Sex Segregation in the
Workplace r2 (Barbara F. Reskin ed., 1984). .
ro6. See Barbara F. Reskin and Patricia A. Roos,]ob Ques, Gender Ques: Explaining
Women's Inroads into Male Occupations 3-90 (1990) (examining socioeconomic fac-
tors that might account for changing sex composition of occupations during 19705 and
r98os).
107. See id. at 64. The EEOC was at first extremely reluctant to enforce Title VII's
prohibition on sex discrimination. See Cynthia Harrison, On Account of Sex: The Poli-
tics of Women's Issues, 1945-I968, at r87:-205 (r988). Under pressure from the Na-
tional Organization for Women (NOW), formed partly in response to the EEOC's foot-
dragging, the commission gradually became more responsive to feminist concerns. See
Hugh Davis Graham, The Civil Rights Era: Origins and Development of National Policy,
I960-1972., at 205-32 (1990). By the early 1970s, enforcement of Title VII's sex dis-
crimination provision had become a more significant priority for the EEOC. See Reskin
and Roos, supra note w6 at 54-55 (describing sex discrimination litigation during the
1970s involving nontraditional job categories such as banking and insurance).
ro8. See Reskin and Roos, supra note ro6, at I7-I9 tbls. r.6, 1.7. While in many jobs,
such as managerial, administrative, and clerical work, there was a significant increase in
sex integration (see id. at 17), other occupations, such as construction and other tradi-
tionally male blue-collar work, remained overwhelmingly male, with women making up
only I or 2 percent of the field- percentages that remained static or dropped during the
period in question. See id. at 19. See also Barbara R. Bergmann, The Economic Emer-
gence of Women 70 (1986) (tables demonstrating that the percentage of women in the
Occupational Group of "Operators, fabricators, and laborers" rose only from 24 percent
in 1972 to 25 percent in 1985, whereas WOIIle.n_rose from 33 to 42 percent of the
"Managerial and professional specialty" workers over this same period).
109. Farley, supra note 7, at 90 (emphasis added).
I ro. Bergmann, supra note 108, at 106.
II r. Barbara E Reskin and Heidi I. Hartmann, eds., Women's Work, Men's Work: Sex
Segregationonthe]ob 53 (1986).
1!2. 477 u.s. 57 (1986).
II3. Id. at 6o.
II4. Id.
rrs. 510 u.s. 17 (1993)-
Introduction 39