Justificatory Theories For Intellectual Property Viewed Through The Constitutional Prism
Justificatory Theories For Intellectual Property Viewed Through The Constitutional Prism
M Du Bois*
Abstract
Pioneer in peer-reviewed,
open access online law publications In order to determine the extent to which intellectual property
rights should enjoy protection under the constitutional property
Author clause, some of the classical and newer justificatory theories for
property may be employed, including the labour theory, reward
Mikhalien du Bois theory, incentive theory, theory of natural law, spiritual theories,
personality theory, economic theory, and theory of natural
Affiliation monopoly. These theories must be applied in line with the
Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996, keeping in
University of South Africa mind that other fundamental rights must be balanced with the
protection afforded to intellectual property in order to ensure its
Email
[email protected] continued production. It is also important that intellectual
property statutes be developed to promote a thriving intellectual
Date of submission commons.
20 March 2017
Date published
Keywords
16 March 2018
Constitutional property; intellectual property; justificatory
Editor Prof O Fuo
theories; labour theory; reward theory; incentive theory; theory of
natural law; excludability; spiritual theories; personality theory;
How to cite this article economic theory; theory of natural monopoly; intellectual
commons; public domain.
DU BOIS M "Justificatory Theories
for Intellectual Property Viewed
through the Constitutional Prism"
PER / PELJ 2018(21) - DOI ……………………………………………………….
http://dx.doi.org/10.17159/1727-
3781/2018/v21i0a2004
Copyright
DOI
http://dx.doi.org/10.17159/1727-
3781/2018/v21i0a2004
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 2
1 Introduction
Mikhalien du Bois. LLB LLD (Stellenbosch University). Associate Professor:
Department of Mercantile Law, Unisa, South Africa. E-mail: [email protected].
This article was presented at the Association for Law, Property, and Society's 6th
Annual Meeting in May 2015 at the University of Georgia Law School, Athens, USA.
Special thanks to the late Prof AJ van der Walt for enabling my understanding of
property law theories. Thank you to Prof CJ Visser for comments on this article. The
Unisa School of Law Research and Innovation Fund made this visit to the University
of Georgia Law School possible financially.
1 See Du Bois 2012 SA Merc LJ 177-193; Van der Walt and Shay 2014 PELJ 52-85.
2 These rights include but are not limited to patents, copyright, designs and
trademarks. They are protected in terms of property rules under the Patents Act 57
of 1978, Copyright Act 98 of 1978, Designs Act 195 of 1993, and Trade Marks Act
194 of 1993, respectively.
3 These interests may include commercial information, confidential information, trade
secrets, digital copyright, biotechnological products, traditional knowledge,
commercial property, participatory claims and non-proprietary rights.
4 Drahos Philosophy of Intellectual Property 1; Hughes 1988 Geo LJ 288: In
determining whether the law of intellectual property reflects general theories of
property, one should keep in mind what the theory of intellectual property should be,
and determine from that what the law should be.
5 Drahos Philosophy of Intellectual Property 2.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 3
These objects are nonexclusive: they can be at many places at once and are
not consumed by their use. The marginal cost of providing an intellectual
object to an additional user is zero, and though there are communications
costs, modern technologies can easily make an intellectual property object
unlimitedly available at very low cost.10
Sharing intellectual property objects does not prevent or impair the personal
use of their creator, but prevents the creator from exclusive financial
benefit.12 The purpose of a justification of intellectual property is to explain
why one person should have "the exclusive right to possess and use
something which all people could possess and use concurrently". 13
Exclusive use is not required for personal use in the context of intellectual
property as it is with tangible property. This must be kept in mind while
discussing the justifications for intellectual property. The fundamental value
that society places on freedom of expression and thought must also be
considered while justifying intellectual property rights, since private property
improves one person's freedom to the detriment of all other persons'
At this point one must remember the difference between property protection
in private law (through intellectual property statutes and the common law)
and property protection in constitutional law (through the constitutional
property clause),15 and also the different purposes served by private law
protection and constitutional law protection. The purpose of property
protection in private law is to get strong property rule-type protection for
private rights against competing private parties.16 Constitutional property
protection provides bill of rights-type protection for private interests against
the state and competing constitutional rights of other private parties.
The South African constitutional property clause not only protects property,
but provides for expropriation and deprivation by the state, although there
are strict requirements that need to be met for such actions to be
constitutionally justifiable. This is important where intellectual property rights
conflict with other rights such as those to the public domain, human dignity,
education, or freedom of expression, and they need to be weighed up during
constitutional interpretation.17 This article does not present a unified
constitutional property theory for intellectual property rights. However, it
does highlight and explain the justificatory theories for property that may be
applied to intellectual property, while taking cognisance of the limitations of
the theories in view of the purpose of the Constitution, and particularly
section 25 (the property clause). In line with André van der Walt's descriptive
and normative thesis that the legal protection of property rights does and
should play a 'modest systemic role in the law',18 intellectual property rights
have taken a back-seat in constitutional jurisprudence where intellectual
property rights had to be interpreted in line with non-property constitutional
rights. For example, in Laugh It Off v South African Breweries19 there had
been a trade mark right that was clearly protectable in terms of trade mark
law, but despite this, the right was trumped by the constitutional right to
freedom of expression. The justificatory theories for intellectual property
14 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 35-36; Van der Walt and Du Bois 2013 Stell LR 31-54.
15 Section 25 of the Constitution.
16 See Calabresi and Melamed 1972 Harv L Rev 1089-1128.
17 See Du Bois 2012 SA Merc LJ 177-193.
18 Van der Walt 2014 J L Prop & Soc'y 26-27.
19 Laugh it Off Promotions CC v South African Breweries International (Finance) BV t/a
Sabmark International (Freedom of Expression Institute as Amicus Curiae) 2006 1
SA 144 (CC). For a discussion of the implications of this case, see Du Bois 2012 SA
Merc LJ 188-191.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 5
There are arguments that the fixed term of intellectual property rights (with
the possible exclusion of trademark rights which are perpetual in principle)
makes them fit even better under the justificatory property theories than
other forms of property.21 As justificatory theories for intellectual property,
both the labour22 and personality theory have received much criticism. The
personality theory as derived from the works of Kant and Hegel postulates
that "an author's personality, spirit and will cannot be free unless the author
owns his/her work".23 Radin's24 development of the personality theory is
also important. This article discusses these theories and their criticisms, as
well as other alternative and supplementary theories.
One version of the economic theory states that since intellectual property is
made scarce through artificial constraints imposed by a legal framework and
restricts public access to the intellectual work, a justification for intellectual
property rights should be founded on the creation and protection of investor
value.25 Another fairly recent theory is the theory of natural monopoly, 26
which applies criticisms from natural monopoly theory to the intellectual
property system. The intellectual commons is a final consideration in a
discussion of the justifications for intellectual property, but it is not the focus
of this article.27 The purpose of this article is to discuss each theory that may
justify the legal recognition and protection of intellectual property rights as
well as their criticisms. Some preliminary suggestions are also supplied as
to the particular suitability of applying each theory to intellectual property
rights.
/ or personality theories or would constitute theft". Ciro 2005 JILT 2 would add the
economic theory to this list, but maintains that the justifications used for tangible
property cannot apply to intellectual property due to their lack of scarcity (their use
is non-exclusive). Mostert 1987 SALJ 480 views the labour theory as one of the most
important in support of the recognition of intellectual property rights.
22 For example, Ciro 2005 JILT 2 argues that there is no natural right to intellectual
property in the sense that John Locke argued for a labourer's natural property right
to an item that is created with her labour. See also Van der Walt 2014 J L Prop &
Soc'y 34-35, where he highlights the relational rights theory criticism against a
natural rights based justification for property that "it effectively removes contested
questions about the distribution of property and of power from the realm of normative
debate and political contestation".
23 Ciro 2005 JILT 2.
24 Radin 1982 Stan L Rev 957-1015. See Van der Walt 2014 J L Prop & Soc'y 38-39
where he notes that for the personhood theory, property only safeguards
personhood regarding minimum access to property, such as access to medical care
or education. Applied to intellectual property rights, this would imply that existing
patent rights could be limited in the interest of medical care, or existing copyrights in
the interest of education.
25 Ciro 2005 JILT 2.
26 This theory is expounded by Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1128.
27 For an introduction to the issues surrounding the intellectual commons see Van der
Walt and Du Bois 2013 Stell LR 31-54.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 7
2.1 Introduction
The theory of natural law is derived from the principle that one owns that
which one creates by one's own (intellectual) effort and labour.28 At least for
South African law, Roman law may be a starting point in the development
of a natural-law theory for the recognition of intellectual property.
If the background conditions44 exist, then the laborer may use his body to gain
control over something. If, further, there exist the features of the laboring
situation45 and the physical and psychological effects described, 46 then the
laborer is responsible for a product that he does not misuse and over which
his enduring control has no adverse impact on others. If, finally, the evaluative
and normative features are as specified, 47 then recognizing his enduring
control is the most fitting benefit for his labor and does not infringe the rights
of others. Such recognition is the acknowledgement of property rights.
The initial labour theory claims that the labourer would deserve "moral
property rights in the product in virtue of his labor".48
The assumption that property is justified when there are similar things in
sufficient quantity and quality left for other people and that they lose nothing
by the labourer's acquisition (the enough and as good as left presupposition)
could be made more realistic by relying on the principles of utility and
Intellectual property is about creation and does not "use up" resources in
the way that the creation of physical property does. However, information
resources are taken from the intellectual commons in order to create
intellectual products. Once taken from the intellectual commons and
propertised, these resources are no longer available for other persons to
use in future intellectual creations. The revised labour-desert theory holds
that labour may still serve as a prima facie justification for property rights,
but embodied as rights qualified by external restrictions. In terms of South
African law, some of these external restrictions would entail expropriation
and deprivation of property rights based on the need to promote other
human rights.
Locke's philosophy attempts to address the issue that the earth belonged to
"Mankind in common", with individual property posing a problem. Natural
law proclaimed the existence of a commons, but also had to explain private
ownership.54 Locke's solution55 was that "every Man has a 'Property' in his
own 'Person'. Where a person mixes his own labour with something which
had previously been in the commons, the thing becomes his property".
Locke56 placed two provisos on this justification: that "enough and as good
[must be] left in the commons for others" and preventing spoilage. The first
proviso means that as long as another's position is not worsened by one's
appropriation of a resource, ownership based on labour is permitted. 57
Some argue that patent law does not pass muster under this proviso since
inventors who independently invent an already patented creation are not
even allowed to use their own inventions.58 The "enough and as good"
proviso describes the commons but also references the natural ceiling on
how much each person can appropriate through labour owing to the limited
capacities of humans.59
The second proviso mandates preventing spoilage: one must not take more
than one is able to use. It may be argued that intellectual property will never
be able to meet this proviso entirely due to the nonexclusive nature of
intellectual property. The relative benefit of products would determine how
wasteful prohibition of its use by third parties would be.60
However, the intellectual property rights granted by statutes do not have the
purpose of granting exclusive use rights, but rather the right to prohibit third
persons from doing certain exclusive acts with the work. An example may
be the copyright in a book which does not grant the exclusive right to read
the book. Anyone who is willing to pay a fee to read a legal copy is allowed
to read it. Only when third persons wish to copy and distribute the book (in
other words to do one or more of the acts that fall within the copyright
owner's sphere of exclusivity), the rights granted by copyright become
relevant. Copyright grants the holder the mainly negative right of preventing
third persons from taking away the remuneration to which the copyright
holder is entitled. In other words, it is not exclusive personal use and
These property rights (or at the very least, the statutes provide property rule-
type remedies and private law honours this position) may be justified by the
labour theory without contravening the two provisos. This analysis is
applicable to copyright, patents, designs and trademarks. Since the relative
benefit for third parties from use of trade-mark rights may be viewed as very
low (it is a purely commercial right - and has no benefit such as educational
in the case of copyright or medicinal as in the case with some patents) this
may account for the relatively high excludability of trade-mark rights.
The question of why labour should serve as the justification for ownership
and not, for instance, intention or possession61 takes on a utilitarian form in
Locke's answer:62 just reward for labour is appropriate because it has social
benefits. Locke63 implies that the common stock of mankind is increased by
granting property to people who create things through own labour. "Locke's
overall scheme for property can be viewed as an alloy of the labor and tacit
consent theories".64 However, as long as the new wealth remains the
labourer's property, this does not increase the common stock. This must be
balanced with the risk that free appropriation would discourage the creation
of new wealth.65
One solution to this dilemma would rely on donations from the labourer to
the commons,66 but this would render a well-stocked intellectual commons
a privilege instead of a right. Locke's solution67 is the introduction of the
money economy which makes wealth potentially part of the commons.
Locke assumes three things here: that the individual is able to appropriate
more than what can be used, that the individual will have the motivation to
do so, and that (excepting waste) this is not problematic. Locke also
employs tacit consent to justify his money economy. 68 Locke's general
On the statement that idea production requires labour, the "avoidance" view
of labour, the "value-added" labour theory, and the interaction between
labour and the idea / expression dichotomy70 are relevant in testing the
proposition's validity.
The "avoidance" view advocates rewarding labour with property due to its
unpleasantness: property should be given to motivate people to perform
labour. The creation of ideas is not so pleasant an activity that people would
necessarily choose it above recreation, so this motivation provided by
property rights is also relevant to intellectual products.71
Drahos78 identifies two factors that may determine how much weight could
be attributed to labour as a justificatory theory for intellectual property: "a
conception of community; and the relation of that community to the
intellectual commons".
founded on the natural-law principle that a person should reap the rewards
of his own ingenuity and labour.81
[Th]e natural law theory, which is justified on the interest of the individual to
enjoy the fruits of his own labour, is still of particular prominence in the
protection of modern-day intellectual property and especially new forms of
intellectual property.82
A more pressing problem with the labour theory as justification for property
is that it does not indicate whether a labourer would be entitled to the total
value of the resulting product or only to the value that his labour has added
to the resulting product.83 While Locke84 would attribute 99 percent of an
object's value to human labour, Hettinger85 questions this division. This
question is also relevant to intellectual property: what part of the value of
inventions, writings and business information may be attributed to the
intellectual labourer? While such products would not exist without the
labour, it does not necessarily follow that the whole value of the creation
may be attributed to the labourer.
81 Mostert 1987 SALJ 496-497. This would mean that an author's right is not artificially
granted by way of legislation - the legislation is merely supplementary to the natural
law right of the author. Natural-law theory is not the only theory used in South African
modern-day law to justify intellectual property, the reward and incentive theories also
had an influence. See also Rose Authors and Owners in general on the history of
copyright in the England, which is also applicable to South African copyright law,
since South African statutes are based on English statutes.
82 Mostert 1987 SALJ 500.
83 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 37.
84 Locke Second Treatise of Government ch V para 40.
85 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 37.
86 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 38.
87 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 36-37.
88 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 39-40.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 16
Ultimately the risk of non-excludable benefit must rest with the plaintiff, and if
the plaintiff fails, by such physical means as are at his disposal, to prevent
unconsented visual intrusion into his land, the particular resource at stake –
the 'spectacle' – must be deemed non-excludable. No one can claim 'property'
in a resource in relation to which it is physically unrealistic to control,
consistently over prolonged periods, the access of strangers. 97
3.1 Introduction
The reward theory advocates rewarding individuals not only for their own
labour, but for the societal benefit of their effort (creative effort – in the
context of intellectual property).106 The creator receives an exclusive
intellectual property right as reward for the creative endeavours. The
resource is legally excludable because legislation creates the possibility for
the creators of intellectual products to invoke legal protection for these
products, provided that the requirements are met as stipulated for each
category. Legislation mostly provides explicitly for morally non-excludable
resources. For example, the principle of "no copyright in ideas" is based on
the concept that the resource must stay in the intellectual commons for
utilisation by future creators.
Society rewards inventors and writers in the form of a legal right to exclude
other persons from certain forms of use of the work for making the works
publicly available. Where intellectual property encourages disclosure of
works that would otherwise remain secret, intellectual property rights
(particularly patents, works of copyright and registered designs) enhance
free flow of information. By contrast, trade secret requirements promote
secrecy and restrict information dissemination. An important requirement is
105 Intellectual Property Laws Amendment Act 28 of 2013; Harms 2009 THRHR 175-
191 explains some of the difficulties experienced with the process and the
amendments.
106 Mostert 1987 SALJ 500; Hughes 1988 Geo LJ 287-366.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 20
that the information must not be widely known.107 On this interpretation, the
reward theory justifies patents, copyright works and designs, but not trade
secrets.
Where a right's value is not proportionate to the effort and labour spent, the
most fitting reward may not necessarily be a property right. One may not
necessarily be entitled to the full value produced by the labour, since outside
factors such as luck may inflate the value.109 According to Rawls,110 even
one's capability to expend effort is such an outside factor, which makes
value a morally impermissible criterion in determining distribution.
Proportionality is an important consideration in determining the appropriate
reward, since intellectual property rights may earn the owner much more
value or benefits than the initial expenditure of the intellectual product's
creation.111
For trade secrets and confidential information, the requirement is that the
information not be made known - accordingly the reward theory does not
apply. Digital copyright may also be justified by the reward theory even
though it is protected by contract in addition to the copyright protection
afforded. Biotechnological products that are not liable to remain in the public
domain on conceptual grounds may be protected under patent law and as
such these rights may be justified by the reward theory.
4.1 Introduction
Intellectual property law is intertwined with talk about incentives. 122 The
intellectual property grant is variously viewed as a reward for making a
117 Mostert 1987 SALJ 500; Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 47: this utilitarian argument
based on incentives is the strongest and most widely utilised justification for patents,
copyright and trade secrets.
118 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 47; the Constitution of the United States of America
Article I Section 8 Clause 8 (the so-called Intellectual Property Clause) has
specifically taken up the incentive theory in the context of patents and copyright,
providing that intellectual property rights are granted "to promote the progress of
science and the useful arts".
119 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 48.
120 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 48-49; Intellectual Property Rights from Publicly
Financed Research and Development Act 51 of 2008.
121 Hettinger 1989 Phil & Pub Aff 49-50.
122 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1130.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 23
creative work public; a quid pro quo and as such an exclusive right in
exchange for making new works available; and even natural rights theories
base the rights on the encouragement of creative activities. The incentive
theory predicts little about the structure of intellectual property, holding only
that protection should be as strong as possible to create maximum incentive
(bar a few exceptions introduced by way of afterthought).123
123 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1131; Ghosh 2006 SCRIPT-ed 97-98. See fn 102 on the
exceptions to patentability. Ss 12-19 of the Copyright Act 98 of 1978 provide for
exceptions, for example s 12(1) which provides for fair dealing. S 10(1)-(17) of the
Trade Marks Act 194 of 1993 state the kinds of trademarks that are not registrable,
for example s 10(12): "a mark which is inherently deceptive or the use of which would
be likely to deceive or cause confusion, be contrary to law, be contra bonos mores,
or be likely to give offence to any class of persons". S 14(6) is an example from the
Designs Act 195 of 1993 excluding spare parts from functional design protection,
arguably for purposes of protecting free market competition.
124 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1131-1132.
125 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1128.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 24
For traditional knowledge the incentive theory has even less application
than the reward theory, since incentives in the form of intellectual property
were not necessary for the creation of (existing) traditional knowledge. The
concern with traditional knowledge is to keep unauthorised persons from
exploiting the knowledge.126 A suggestion as to how cultural rights of an
indigenous group may be protected includes
… a claim right to its TK; a power to create rules that bind others in regard to
the copying or reverse-engineering of its TK; a claim-right to receive just
compensation for granting access to its TK; a power to seek and a claim-right
to have a wide range of remedies for others' failure to pay compensation or
obtain informed consent; and lastly powers to modify otherwise applicable
laws of patent and copyright.127
5 Spiritual theories
The personality theory as derived from the writings of Kant128 and Hegel,129
holds that a property right in a creation must be granted before a creator
can be fully in control of their spirit and personality. 130 Hegel's131 writings
aim to "reveal the role that community plays in the evolution of individual
freedom".132 On Drahos'133 interpretation of Hegel's writings on property,
intellectual property may have negative effects on community.
126 Munzer and Raustiala 2009 Cardozo Arts & Ent LJ 73.
127 Munzer and Raustiala 2009 Cardozo Arts & Ent LJ 73.
128 Kant Critique of Practical Reason.
129 Hegel Philosophy of Right para 41-71.
130 See Ciro 2005 JILT 4. See also Maniatis 2002 IPQ 153-166 on the application of the
spiritual theories to trademarks.
131 Hegel Philosophy of Right para 10.
132 Drahos Philosophy of Intellectual Property 73.
133 Drahos Philosophy of Intellectual Property 74.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 25
Property rights and personality may be linked in the case of copyright (which
provides property rule-type protection to literary, artistic and dramatic
works). The link between personality and ownership of the creative work
looks strong in these instances.134 Justifying intellectual property rights that
involve the personality creatively via Hegel's personality theory may be ill-
advised. Contrasting the property theories of Locke and Hegel by reference
to labour and personality may not be the best approach, since Locke's
theory135 approaches property as serving the personality, while Hegel's
theory sees property as the "embodiment of personality".136 Also, Hegel's
theory views individual property ownership as contradictory.137
Basically, some forms of property are more worthy of protection than others,
and should enjoy more stringent legal protection. The theory uses a
continuum, with property closer to the fungible side being more regulatable
than property on the personal side (which has a stronger entitlement to
protection).143 Radin's example of personal property takes the form of a
home because it is closely connected to liberty, privacy and freedom of
association.144 The area of takings law (comparable to expropriation law in
South Africa) is an area where this theory can be applied with some
success. Courts should be more likely to award compensation for the taking
of personal property than for property that constitutes mere monetary
loss.145
6 Economic theory
Intellectual property rights are very closely related to markets, since these
rights create markets in information. Economic theory is important to justify
intellectual property, but has a very wide scope and diverse approaches.
For intellectual property, the basic economic theory holds that a market
failure arises due to high initial creation costs and marginal distribution costs
of intellectual products, so an economic incentive to create must be
provided to overcome market failure.147
A criticism of this theory is that there is no proof that only property rights can
provide this incentive to create. The creators are often not the owners of the
property rights, and even if an incentive is provided there is uncertainty as
to how much compensation would ensure an adequate incentive.148
147 Drahos Philosophy of Intellectual Property 6; Ciro 2005 JILT 6: "Intellectual property
laws produce an artificial restriction that creates the scarcity problem and are then
used to allocate scarce resources through a complex web of private property rights
controlled by intellectual property owners."
148 Ciro 2005 JILT 4.
149 Ciro 2005 JILT 5-7.
150 Ciro 2005 JILT 5. Compare Boyle 2000 Vand L Rev 2007-2039.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 28
The basic economic theory does not answer the question of how much the
reward should be or what form it should take. A property right is not
necessarily the only way to provide compensation or incentive. However, all
forms of intellectual property are created through financial investment,
which renders this theory applicable. They have high initial costs, but
afterwards production and distribution can take place at very low cost.
Without some form of protection, some intellectual property products may
not be created, since creators and investors may not be willing to expend
money and effort.
In the area of inventing, high fixed costs and low distribution costs are often
cited to justify intellectual property exclusivity. This justification is similar to
the one for a natural monopoly: the combination of high fixed costs and low
distribution costs would drive the market down to zero, therefore artificial
scarcity through exclusivity is necessary in order to avoid competition that
would destroy the market.156
154 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1128, 1138-1139: "A natural monopoly arises when the
average costs of producing a product or service declines as more of the product or
service is supplied to the market. Because of declining average costs, it is more
efficient from the perspective of lowering the average cost of production to have one
firm service the market rather than duplicate expenditures. Average costs are falling
either because there are huge fixed costs to production or because the costs of
producing an additional unit of the product or service are negligible". See Berg and
Tschirhart Natural Monopoly Regulation 12-24; Spulber Regulation and Markets
513-514.
155 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1154. Also see Ghosh 2006 SCRIPT-ed 101.
156 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1157-1158, 1159: "Natural monopoly-like justifications for
intellectual property are most prevalent in the controversial areas of database
protection, computer software, and biotechnology".
157 Ghosh 2008 U Ill L Rev 1160-1166.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 30
8 Conclusion
This article asks why and under which circumstances intellectual property
rights and other intangible property interests should and could be
recognised and protected under the constitutional property clause.
The natural-law theory principle that a person should have property in that
which he has created by his own intellectual effort and exertion has played
a large role in the recognition of intellectual property rights, but should not
be the sole justification. While the labour theory is still a strong theory for
the justification of the protection of intellectual property rights (particularly
patents, copyright, registered designs and trademarks), it becomes clear
that it does not justify unlimited rights, but rights subject to private and public
interests. Intellectual property rights are physically non-excludable, but
legally excludable where statutes afford protection and such protection is
invoked by the holder of a particular resource. There are also certain morally
non-excludable resources that need to stay in the public domain – and
intellectual property statutes provide some exceptions for these.
Biotechnological products, particularly DNA-related inventions, may
sometimes provide an example of a resource that may by morally non-
excludable and as such would not receive any property rule-type protection
in either private law or constitutional law.
158 In American law, trade secrets are regarded as a category of intellectual property.
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 31
The incentive theory holds that if creative works are protected by law and
creators are awarded some form of benefit, then this would motivate other
creative individuals to create new intellectual works, and this will benefit
society. A balance must be found between providing an incentive to create
and the public's access to these creations and inventions.
The reward and incentive theories are based on the idea that the disclosure
of useful information should be rewarded by a property right. Where
information is not disclosed (see for example trade secrets and confidential
information) these theories are not useful. Patents, copyright and registered
designs may be justified by the incentive and reward theories, but
trademarks do not appear to confer any particular benefit on society except
for prohibiting the confusion of the products or services sold under the
trademark with other similar products or services, which is possibly not the
kind of benefit envisioned by the reward theory. Traditional knowledge finds
no benefit from either the reward or incentive theory.
The spiritual theories state that an author's personality, spirit and will cannot
be free unless the author is also the owner of the work created. A person
must have dominion over certain objects in order to achieve individual
autonomy. In the context of intellectual property rights, a creator's right to
use his invention must be distinguished from the right to prevent others from
using the invention. This theory has been developed into the personality
theory, which states that a person has to have control over certain resources
in the external environment in order to be a person and such control needs
to be fulfilled by property rights. The question whether an intellectual
property interest may be justified by the personality theory or not depends
on how central an interest is to the fulfilment of one's personhood. The
spiritual theories may serve to justify the protection of intellectual property
only to the extent that they serve to secure a sphere of personal liberty, and
as far as they do not fall into the category of moral non-excludability. The
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 32
would not be able to exclude certain persons from the use of a work. The
public domain is an important interest which should be developed as a right
rather than a privilege, since it is important to keep raw creative materials
out of the property regime so that it can be used freely in future creative
works.
Bibliography
Literature
Blignaut "Copyright"
Blignaut H "Copyright" in Dean OH and Dyer A (eds) Introduction to
Intellectual Property Law (Oxford University Press Cape Town 2014) 1-76
Epstein 1979 Ga LJ
Epstein R "Possession as the Root of Title" 1979 Ga LJ 1221-1243
Grant "Patents"
Grant T "Patents" in Dean OH and Dyer A (eds) Introduction to Intellectual
Property Law (Oxford University Press Cape Town 2014) 237-282
Petersen 2008 LT
Petersen J "Lockean Property and Literary Works" 2008 LT 257-280
Pistorius "Introduction"
Pistorius "Introduction" in Klopper HB et al (eds) Law of Intellectual Property
in South Africa (LexisNexis Durban 2011) 143-154
M DU BOIS PER / PELJ 2018 (21) 36
Case law
Australia
England
South Africa
Biotech Laboratories (Pty) Ltd v Beecham Group Plc 2002 3 All SA 652
(SCA)
Legislation
South Africa
Draft Intellectual Property Policy of the Republic of South Africa (Phase 1),
2017
List of Abbreviations