1 August 22, 2012: M275 Notes
1 August 22, 2012: M275 Notes
1 August 22, 2012: M275 Notes
Evan Chen
Solution. Let I = [0, 1]. If we remove 0 from I, then I is still connected. On the
other hand, no point in R has this property, so we lose, since homeomorphism preserves
connectedness.
Example. The category G of groups, with ob(G) being “the set of all groups”, except
this leads to a contradiction, so we call it a class instead. In fact, if the objects of a
category are a set, it is called a “small category” or “kitty-gory”.
Given two groups G1 , G2 ∈ ob(G), then mor(G1 , G2 ) is the set of all homomorphisms
from G1 to G2 . For vector spaces V1 , V2 ∈ ob(V), then mor(V1 , V2 ) is the set of all linear
maps from V1 to V2 .
Finally, T op is the category of topological spaces. ob(T op) is the set of topologi-
cal spaces, and M or(T op) is the set of morphisms M or(X, Y ), which are continuous
functions from X to Y .
1
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 1 August 22, 2012
Note that morphism sets M or(X, Y ) can be small or even empty. For example, there
are very few homomorphisms from Z/3Z to Z.
Suppose we have a morphism ϕ : X → Y and a morphism ψ : Y → Z. As one might
expect, we define composition to yield another morphism. Also mor(X, X) must contain
the identity.
We define morphisms ϕ : X → Y and ζ : Y → X such that ϕ ◦ ζ = ζ ◦ ϕ = id, then
we say they are inverses, and both of them are called “isomorphs.”
1.3 Outsourcing
In algebraic topology, we say topology is too hard and start with the category T op and
the category of groups G.
2
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 2 August 27, 2012
The issue is as follows: homology groups are harder to define, but are relatively easy to
compute. Homotopy groups are easy to define and hard to compute.
x2i = 1}
X
S n = {(x0 , · · · , xn ) :
Corresponding geometric idea: crumple a piece of paper, and lay it on a copy of itself.
Then there are two corresponding points which are directly above each other. (We can
use paper (rectangles) instead of discs, since D2 ≈ I × I.)
Other spaces which satisfy Brouwer Fixed Point Theorem are said to find the fixed
point property. This is strong; for example S1 does not satisfy this property (just rotate
it 90◦ ; now no points are fixed. Remember that S1 is a circle, not a disk.)
We will prove later that ∃ϕ : D2 → S 1 such that ϕ |S 1 = idS 1 (that is, no continuous
function from D2 → S 1 which fixes the circumference.)
3
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 2 August 27, 2012
Pictorially, we can draw the image of the path ϕ(I). This does not contain all the
information (e.g. speed).
Since I is compact, ϕ(I) cannot go off to infinity or oscillate around a point, or do
any other silly things.
Definition. A path-connected space is one where any two points are connected by a
path.
A special case we will use a lot is if we have two paths in Y that both start and end
at the same point.
It is not hard to check that these operations are all equivalence relations. We write
them as f ' f 0 , f 'A f 0 and f 'p f 0 . This is left as an exercise, since it’s actually not
hard.
Since apparently this is confusing people:
4
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 3 August 29, 2012
Musing: for any two paths p1 and p2 in X, can we find a larger space Y for which
they are path-homotopic? Probably yes.
This, of course, generalizes. For example, given a loop at the North Pole of S 2 not
passing through the South Pole, we can show that it is homotopic to the constant
function of the North Pole. Consider γ : I → S 2 . Of course we can’t simply use the map
H(s, t) = (1 − t)γ(s) + t · h0, 0, 1i, since this will in general not be on the sphere, but we
can recover this by dividing by the magnitude, forcing it to lie on the sphere; hence, the
1
desired homotopy is simply F (s, t) = H(s, t) · |H(s,t)| .
1 3
0 2 4 1
γ1 γ2 γ3
γ1 γ2 γ3
0 1 1 1
4 2
5
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 3 August 29, 2012
It is not hard to check that this is well-defined. It is easy to verify that γ1 (2s) and
γ2 (2s − 1) are continuous, and they agree at the common point s = 21 , so this implies
that the product is continuous by the pasting lemma.
The operation ∗ is not associative; an easy way to see that (γ1 ∗γ2 )∗γ3 6= γ1 ∗(γ2 ∗γ3 ) by
evaluating at s = 1/4. However, it is associative with respect to homotopy classes. The
easy special case is to show that the above quantities are homotopic. . . by distorting time
linearly, we can establish the homotopy by a rather irritating computation. Explicitly,
the homotopy F : I 2 → X is
4s t+1
γ 1 t+1 0≤s≤ 4
t+1
F (s, t) = γ (4s − t − 1)
2 4 ≤s ≤ t+2
4
γ 4s−t−2
t+2
≤s≤1
3 2−t 4
and this is continuous by the Pasting Lemma and composition. (Since t ∈ I, no denom-
inators are zero.)
6
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 4 September 5, 2012
4 September 5, 2012
4.1 Homeomorphism
Definition. X is homeomorphic to Y , denoted X ≈ Y , if ∃f : X → Y a homeomor-
phism.
Definition. We say X is of the same homotopy type as Y , written X ' Y , if ∃f, g with
g ◦ f ' idX and f ◦ g ' idY .
Answer. Yes. Again, not hard to verify. The constant loop is the identity, and as-
sociativity is evident: more generally, if f, g, h are paths, we showed last time that
f ∗ (g ∗ h) 'p (f ∗ g) ∗ h. The inverse of [f ] is [f¯], where f¯(t) = f (1 − t) for each t.
These groups are, in general, hard to compute. Unlike homology classes, which
are rather easy to compute.
Example. π1 (S 1 , 1) ∼
= Z.
7
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 4 September 5, 2012
Note that these loops are restricted to path components. If X is not path-connected,
then the path components are completely unrelated in terms of their fundamental groups.
So, it really only makes sense to discuss fundamental groups of path-connected spaces.
Now the triumph:
8
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 5 September 10, 2012
Proof. All loops at x0 can be compressed, lol. More formally, since X is contractible,
we know that idX ' cx0 . Now consider a loop γ. Then,
But the left-hand side is γ and the right-hand side is cx0 , implying the loop is itself
nulhomotopic and yielding the conclusion.
Proof. We are given that ∃g : Rn → Y with g|A = H. Let j be the inclusion. Then
g ◦ j = h.
Now we use functorial properties. We have h∗ = g∗ ◦ j∗ . But this is a map
j∗ g∗
π1 (A, a0 ) −→ π1 (Rn , a0 ) −→ π1 (Y, y0 ).
1
That is, f : X → Y and f (x0 ) = y0 . This generalizes to subsets in place of x0 and y0
2
This is a terrible abuse of notation. But “everyone does it”, so whatever.
9
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 5 September 10, 2012
Example. Let [n] denote {1, 2, · · · , n} with the discrete topology. Take P : B ×[n] → B
by (b, k) → b. Then this is a simple example of a covering projection.
10
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 6 September 12, 2012
Definition. The fiber of a point b0 is the inverse image p−1 ({b0 }).
Example. Take (0, 2) → S 1 by θ 7→ e2πiθ . This is a local homeomorphism. But now take
a small neighborhood around 1 in S 1 , say the arc joining e−2πi to e2πi . We get small
intervals (0, ), (1−, 1+) and (2−, 2). But this map is not a homeomorphism between
(0, ) to the arc. So local homeomorphisms are not necessarily covering projections.
11
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 6 September 12, 2012
12
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 7 September 17, 2012
X 0 = X/ ∼
= {[x] : x ∈ X}
= {orbits}
Example. Take X = R2 and G = Z × Z and consider the right action (x, y)(n, m) =
(x + n, y + m). The fundamental domain is [0, 1)2 , which ends up as a box. This is a
torus; we now have a covering projection from R2 to the torus, which can the be viewed
as S 1 × S 1 .
13
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 7 September 17, 2012
It is not necessarily the case that we always get a covering projection. Consider the
action S 1 × S 1 → S 1 by (z, w) 7→ zw. This action is transitive, so S 1 / ∼ is a group with
one element. Its pre-image is the entire S 1 . However, we need to write this as a disjoint
union of homeomorphic “spaces” (which are in this case points). But these points are
not open in S 1 .
Coverings which arise from group actions are called regular. In regular coverings
E → B, the coverings correspond to the normal subgroups of π1 (B, b0 ).
7.3 Liftings
f p
Suppose X −→ B is continuous and E −→ B is a covering projection, then a mapping
f˜
X −→ E is called a lifting if p ◦ f˜ = f .3
Liftings don’t always exist. However, suppose we pick X to be the interval I = [0, 1],
and suppose f (0) = b0 ∈ B. Select a e0 in the fiber p−1 ({b0 }). If B is path-connected,
then there exists a unique lifting f˜ with f˜(0) = e0 .
To prove this, we use the following lemma.
Definition. If (X, d) is a metric space and {Oi } is an open covering for X, then q is a
Lebesgue number for the covering if any set of diameter at most q is contained entirely
in one of the Oi .
Lemma 4 (Lebesgue Number Lemma). A Lebesgue number exists for every covering
whenever X is a compact metric space.
3
The lifting problem, in category theory, is the dual of the inclusion problem.
14
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 8 September 19, 2012
The fact that this function is well defined now follows from γ̃1 'p γ2 ⇒ γ̃1 (1) = γ̃2 (2).
Proof. Suppose e1 ∈ p−1 ({b0 }). Suffices to prove ∃[η] with Φ([η]) = e1 .
We know there is a path η̂ joining e0 to e1 . The function p ◦ η̂ is now a loop in B. We
claim that η = p ◦ η̂ is the desired loop. Indeed, by uniqueness of lifting, η̃ = η̂! (All we
did was project down and lift back up). Now we’re done.
Proof. Suffices to prove that if Φ([γ1 ]) = Φ([γ2 ]), then [γ1 ] = [γ2 ].
Lift to γ̃1 and γ̃2 . In E we get γ̃1 'p γ̃2 since their endpoints coincide. Project down!
If F̃ is a path-homotopy between γ̃1 and γ̃2 , then F = p ◦ F̃ is now a path-homotopy
between γ1 and γ2 .
4
This is actually just a function, since it takes a group. There is no sense of “continuity” here, etc.
15
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 8 September 19, 2012
p
This gives a covering projection S 2 −→ RP 2 (the inverse image of a patch is two
patches diametrically opposite it). But we know that π1 (RP 2 , [1]) is in a one-to-one
correspondence with Z2 . Since there are not that many groups of order two, we find
that π(RP 2 , [1]) ∼
= Z2 . Finally a nontrivial fundamental group!
Let’s try and understand RP 2 . It seems to be the northern hemisphere, with half the
equator included. If we are Santa and look down, we see this is a disk with half the
boundary included. We call it a manifold since locally it looks like Euclidean space.
In this image of a disk, the nontrivial loop is just a path from 1 to −1.
Suppose that Φ([γ1 ]) = n = γ̃1 (1), where we view n ∈ R, and Φ([γ2 ]) = m = γ̃2 (1).
But [γ1 ] · [γ2 ] = [γ1 ∗ γ2 ]. Take a lifting of γ1 ∗ γ2 starting at zero defined by
0 ≤ s ≤ 21
(
γ̃1 (2s)
ζ̃ : I → R by ζ̃(s) = 1
.
n + γ̃2 (2s − 1) 2 ≤s≤1
It is trivial to check that this is well-defined and continuous. But one can check that
this is a lifting. Also, we have easily enough that
Hence, ζ̃(s) is a lifting. Since liftings are unique, we get Φ([γ1 ∗ γ2 ]) = n + m, implying
the conclusion.
16
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 9 September 24, 2012
Claim. The group π1 (B, b0 ) acts on p−1 (b0 ) from the right with p−1 (b0 ) × π1 (B, b0 ) →
p−1 (b0 ) via
(e, [γ]) 7→ γ̂(1)
where γ̂ is the unique lifting of γ into E.
We need only show that (e[γ])[η] = (e[γ][η]). This is left to the diligent student.
9.2 Orbits
What is the orbit? eπ1 (B, b0 ). Any time we have an orbit xG, then this is essentially
(i.e. can be modelled by) as the set of right cosets {Hg : g ∈ G} with G acting on the
right by (Hg)g 0 = H(gg 0 ). Here H = Gx is the isotropy subgroup, or the stabilizer, of
x.
We need to find which elements of π1 (B, b0 ) fix e.
We want to characterize e with e[γ] = e. If γ̂(1) = e, then γ̂ is actually a loop. But γ̂
lifts γ; i.e. [p ◦ γ̂] = [γ]. This is p∗ ([γ̂]).
Hence, the stabilizer of e is precisely p∗ (π1 (E, e)) and the orbits are right cosets of
this set.
However, we saw last time that if E is path-connected, then the action is transi-
tive. That is, eπ1 (B, b0 ) = p−1 (b0 ). So the entire fiber can be modelled as cosets of
p∗ (π1 (E, e)).
(Based on the restrictions of E, it’s connected iff path-connected.)
Now recall:
Theorem 5 (Lagrange’s Theorem). The number of cosets of G divides |G| for finite G.
So if we know that π1 (B, b0 ) is finite, then we know that the fiber p−1 (b0 ) is pretty
limited (given E is path-connected). Remember, we have a transitive action on a finite
group on a finite set.
p p∗
Claim. If E −→ B is a covering, then π1 (E, e) −→ π1 (B, b0 ), p∗ is an injective homo-
morphism.
17
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 9 September 24, 2012
18
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 10 September 26, 2012
10.2 Topology
B 2 does not retract onto its boundary S 1 ; i.e.
@r : B 2 → S 1 : r |S 1 = idS 1
We proved this using the fact that B has a trivial fundamental group, but S 1 does not.
The most well-known consequence of this is
Munkres uses a proof using vector fields. The proof that most people usually see
doesn’t rely on this.
Remark. We say that X has the fixed point property if ∀f : X → X continuous, f has
a fixed point.
(ii) S 1 doesn’t have the fixed point property (consider rotation). R doesn’t either via
translation. Neither does S 1 × S 1 or Rn .
(iii) If X ≈ Y and Y has the fixed point property, then so does X. In other words, the
property is a topological invariant. If we have h : X → Y a homomorphism, then
for any f : X → X we can construct f˜ = h ◦ f ◦ h−1 . We know that f˜(y0 ) = y0 for
some y0 . Then x0 = h−1 (y0 ) is a fixed point of f .
19
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 10 September 26, 2012
For x, we say x is outward-pointing if w(x) = kx for some scalar k > 0. If k < 0 then
instead we say it is inward-pointing. This result implies the Brower fixed point theorem.
Vector fields can be viewed as e.g. a part of the ocean, where the vector corresponds
to the strength and direction of the current, etc.
A tangent-vector field is trickier; the output of v(x) needs to be “tangent” to the point
(the definition of tangent depends on the space). In other words, the domain depends
on f .
Theorem 10 (Hairy Ball Theorem). S 2 does not have a nowhere vanishing tangent
vector field.
Fact. There exists a non-vanishing tangent vector fields on S n if and only if n is odd.
so we can get a tangent vector field by taking (z00 , · · · , zn0 ) where zk0 = −y + xi for
zk = x + yi.
Which S n are parallelizable? Something like {S 1 , S 3 , S 7 }. Prove only in early 1960’s
by Adams.
10.4 Algebra
R1 is a field. R2 can be thought of as C, which form a field.
For R3 we don’t have what we want.
However, R4 has a quaternion structure H. We get a division algebra (almost a field,
except non-commutative multiplication). In R∗ we have the octonians O, but we lose
associativity.
In R16 we have the Cayley numbers, which loses even more. These things are called
algebras. It turns out that we can’t have algebra structures for sufficiently large Rn
which is closely related to the parallelizable spheres above.
Punk hairy ball theorem.
20
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 11 October 1, 2012
11 October 1, 2012
11.1 Something
f
If X −→ Y is a function of sets X, Y , and we have an equivalence relation ∼ which
is preserved under f , then we have an “induced” function fˆ : X/∼ → Y from defined
by fˆ([x]) = f (x). This function is generally continuous when you want it to be (by
composition).
(z, 1) ∼ (z 0 , 1)∀z, z 0 ∈ S 1 .
F̂
This is clearly an equivalence relation. Now define (S 1 × I)/∼ −→ X as above. Since
z ∼ z 0 ⇒ F (z, t) = F (z 0 , t) is evident, we see that F̂ is a continuous function. But we
claim that B 2 ≈ (S 1 × I)/∼. Indeed, it’s like a cone, which can be flattened to a disk.
This proves the claim.
h
Any time we have Z −→ X nulhomotopic, we can try the same trick to get an extension
k
CZ −→ X, a “cone”-like version of Z. The cone on Z is actually contractible, since we
can pull everything towards the tip. As a particular example, CS n−1 = B n ; we have
invoked n = 2.
The converse of this turns out to be true.
11.3 Antipodes
Definition. If h : S n → S m , then we call h antipode-preserving if h(−x) = −h(x).
21
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 11 October 1, 2012
k∗ : [q ◦ γ] 7→ k∗ ([q ◦ γ]) = [k ◦ q ◦ γ] = [q ◦ h ◦ γ]
q∗ ◦ h∗ = k ∗ ◦ q∗
22
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 12 October 3, 2012
12 October 3, 2012
12.1 Something
Want to show the identity i : S n → S n is not nulhomotopic.
If @r : B n+1 → S n a retraction, then f : S n → X is nulhomotopic is equivalent to F
extending to f˜.
f
Sn - X
-
f˜
j
?
n+1
B
If the identity were homotopic, then upon taking f the identity, f˜ ◦ j is the identity,
i.e. a retraction.
12.2 Geography
f
You can’t “map”, i.e. embed S 2 into R2 . That is, there is no S 2 −→ R2 which is
homeomorphic to its image, because the Borsuk-Ulam Theorem implies ∃x0 ∈ S 2 with
f (x0 ) = f (−x0 ); in particular, f cannot be injective.
For all n, if f : S n → Rn , Borsuk-Ulam ∃x0 ∈ S n such that f (−x0 ) = f (x0 ). That is,
Borsuk-Ulam generalizes to arbitrary n instead of just n = 2.
23
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 12 October 3, 2012
12.4 Retracts
We say A ⊆ X is a retract if there exists a retraction; i.e. a function r : X → A such
that r ◦ j = idA , where j : A → X is the inclusion.
In other words, r is a “left-inverse” function for j. If r were a right-inverse for j; i.e.
j ◦ r = idX , then A = X and this is quite stupid. Let’s weaken the condition that r is a
right-inverse, as follows
Definition. If r is a retraction onto A ⊆ X such that j ◦r ' idX we call r a deformation
retraction and say that A is a deformation retract of X.
Munkres actually requires something stronger; not all books agree on a definition here.
Example. A = {~0} ⊆ Rn = X is a deformation retract of X. Let r be a constant map
to zero; we can check that j ◦ r ' idX simply because Rn is contractible.
Example. In Rn , the map r : hx1 , x2 , · · · , xn i = hx1 , 0, 0, · · · , 0i is a defromation re-
traction.
Now for a less trivial example:
Example. The topologist’s comb (also called the harmonic comb) is the set X ⊆ R2
defined by
[ 1
X= { } × I × ({0} × I) ∪ (I × {0})
n≥1
n
If A = {(0, 1)}, then A is a deformation retraction of f . We can deform it continuously
by smashing the teeth onto the base, pushing that to (0, 0) and the brining the whole
thing up to (0, 1).
Example. The topologist’s fan (also called the harmonic fan) is the set X ⊆ R2 defined
by joining the segments (0, 0) to (1, n1 ) for each integer n, as well as (1, 0). Again
A = {(1, 0)} is a deformation retraction
These aren’t terribly useful deformation retractions, so the alternate definition called
by some authors as a strong deformation retraction is given by
Definition. A strong deformation retraction r : X → A is a deformation retraction
such that the homotopy F between j ◦ r to idX fixes A; i.e. the homotopy doesn’t fix A.
Both the examples above fail under this stronger definition; on the other hand, the
earlier two examples (contractible spaces and projecting onto the x-axis) still are okay.
Munkres just calls this a deformation retraction, so we will do so as well.
24
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 13 October 8, 2012
13 October 8, 2012
13.1 Homotopy Equivalence
Last time we had an equivalence relation, the homotopy type.
g ◦ f ' idX
f ◦ g ' idY
Fact. If n 6= m, then Rn 6≈ Rm .
h - m
Rn R
-
h˜
Sm
So there are ways to show spaces X and Y are different even if they are homotopy
equivalent.
13.2 Retraction
Recall that A ⊆ X is a (strong) deformation retract if ∃r : X → A such that r ◦ j is the
identity on A and j ◦ r 'A idX . (See the first lecture).
It turns out that if you take the category of topological spaces, you can make a new
category hTop which are equivalence classes of homotopy classes. In Top, the objects are
topological spaces and the morphisms are continuous functions. In hTop, the objects are
homotopy classes of maps, and the morphisms are equivalence classes of maps. Hence,
the arrows are not actually functions between objects. Hence, the space hTop is not
concrete.
If A is a deformation retract of X, then A is the same homotopy type as X.
Example. The space C \ {−1, 1} is homotopy equivalent to pair of tangent circles; i.e.
the figure eight. These spaces are both deformation retracts of C \ {−1, 1}, but neither
is a deformation retract of the other; however they are of the same homotopy type.
25
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 13 October 8, 2012
f ◦ γ 'p g ◦ γ
Now define K : I × I → Y by
K(s, t) = H(γ(s), t)
α̂
-
π1 (Y, y1 )
Then f∗ and g∗ are most certainly not the same (their domains are different), but if we
consider a loop [ζ] ∈ π1 (Y, y0 ), then we have α̂([ζ]) = [ᾱ ∗ ζ ∗ α]. Remember that α is an
isomorphism.
It turns out that g∗ = α̂ ◦ f∗ . In particular, f∗ is surjective/injective/trivial iff g∗ is
surjective/injective/trivial, etc.
h
In particular, if X −→ Y is nulhomotopic with h(x0 ) = y0 , then h∗ : π1 (X, x0 ) →
π1 (Y, y0 ) is trivial.
Anyways,
26
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 13 October 8, 2012
that is,
(fx0 )-
∗
π1 (X, x0 ) π1 (Y, y0 )
g∗
(fx1 )-
∗
π1 (X, x1 ) π1 (Y, y1 )
g∗ ◦ f∗ = (g ◦ f )∗ = α̂ ◦ (idX )∗ = α̂
So we still have an isomorphism, but g∗ is not the inverse; it goes to the wrong place!
27
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 14 October 10, 2012
H ∗ K := hH, Ki ≤ G
as the smallest subgroup of G containing both H and K, also known as the subgroup of
G generated by H and K. This consists of words of elements of H and K.
This is called the (internal) free product of H and K.
Here is an example of an external free product:
H ∗ K = hwords of a and bi
that is, the elements all look like an1 bm1 · · · ank bmk , where ni , mi ∈ Z.
This is the free group on two generators.
with letters a and b such that neither the pattern aa nor bb appears.
jU
iU
x0 ∈ U ∩ V X
-
iV
jV
-
V
Where i and j are inclusions. We have homomorphisms
28
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 14 October 10, 2012
π1 (X, x0 ) ∼
= (jU )∗ (π1 (U, x0 )) ∗ (jV )∗ ((π1 (V, x0 ))).
and the main idea is basically the same as the specific problem we did.
Example. Consider the figure eight. Consider two copies of S1 called U and V with
X8 = U ∩ V , U ∩ V = {x0 }. Hence the intersection (which is quite small!) is simply
connected. But U and V are not open in the union! So we need a slight modification:
add a little bit of U and V , open, to the set (so U looks like a fish with the vertical
segment erased).
Now, π1 (U, x0 ) = S 1 . With some handwaving we can get (jU )∗ (π1 (U, x0 )) = Z as well.
Therefore, by Von Kampen we obtain that π1 (X, x0 ) is the free group on two genera-
tors.
Exercise. Show that the space X8 is a deformation retraction of the punctured torus.
The fundamental group of the torus is Z×Z, and the space X8 is now the abelianization
of the free group F2 .
29
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 15 October 15, 2012
γ = (γ1 ∗ ᾱ1 ) ∗ (α1 ∗ ᾱ2 ) ∗ (α2 ∗ γ3 ∗ ᾱ3 ) ∗ · · · ∗ (αn−2 ∗ γn−1 ∗ ᾱn−1 ) ∗ (αn−1 ∗ γn ) (1)
jU
iU
-
U ∩V U ∪V
-
iV
jV
-
V
For example, consider a space B 2 a disk of radius 3. Let V denote the disk with radius
2 and U denote the annulus with outer radius 3 and inner radius 1.
If we take a [η] ∈ π1 (U, x0 ) ≈ Z, we get something that’s not trivial if we consider it
in the larger space B 2 = U ∩ V . In other words, (jU )∗ ([η]) ∈ π1 (B 2 , x0 ) is trivial even
though [η] ∈ π1 (U, x0 ) is not. In still other words, (ju )∗ need not be one-to-one.
π1 (U ∪ V, x0 ) ∼
= π1 (U, x0 ) ∗ π1 (V, x0 )
The difference here is that if the intersection is simply connected, then “what you see
what you get” in 1.
For example, if π1 (X8 , x0 ), where X8 is the figure eight, gives the free group F2 = ha, bi.
Generally, let’s look at (jU )∗ ([γ1 ]) ∗ (jV )∗ ([γ2 ]) where [γ1 ] ∈ π1 (U, x0 ) and [γ2 ] ∈
π1 (V, x0 ).
But if [η] ∈ π1 (U ∩ V, x0 ) such that [γ1 ] = (iU )∗ ([η]) and [γ2 ] = (iV )∗ ([η]−1 ), then we
have trouble. It could turn out that we have a ∈ π1 (U, x0 ) and b ∈ π1 (V, x0 ) but ab = 1
in the larger group π1 (X, x0 ).
The full description is
30
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 15 October 15, 2012
where N is the normal closure of (i.e. the smallest normal subgroup which contains)
((iU )∗ [η])−1 · (iV )∗ [η] for every [η] ∈ π1 (U ∩ V, x0 ).
This is called the amalgamated product, written
(Y ∪ (S 1 × I))/ ∼
where ∼ identifies S 1 × {0} to a single point, and (z, 1) with f (z) for each z.
The result is what appears to be a witch’s hat.
We now split this into two pieces: let U be a S 1 × [0, 1006
2011 ]; that is, a little more than
1004
the upper half of the hat. The second piece V is the union of Y and S 1 × [ 2011 , 1]; the
base of the hat plus a little above half the hat.
31
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 16 October 17, 2012
16.2 Torus
Consider the frame of a torus T (the two loops with generate π1 (S 1 × S 1 )). It is not
hard to see that this is a figure-eight.
Denote by U a square patch open in T . Let V be all of T minus some smaller co-centric
square patch contained entirely in U . Then U ∪ V = T , and U ∩ V is isomorphic to S 1 .
Then π1 (T, x0 ) = π1 (U ∪ V, x0 ) ∼
= [π1 (U, x0 ) ∗ π1 (V, x0 )]/N for some N .
Now once again we look at the torus as the orbits of Z2 acting on R2 by addition. We
can take as representatives the square given by [− 21 , 12 )2 .
So, we get π1 (V ) ∼
= ha, bi = F2 . But although it’s not trivial in the figure eight, we
find that aba−1 b−1 becomes trivial in T .
In other words, in the torus, ab = ba.
That is; we find now that π1 (U ∪ V, x0 ) = ha, b | ab = bai ∼
= Z2 .
Actually, consider a torus with a rectangle cut out. We can consider patching it with
a cone pointing outwards; so it looks like a torus with a spike on it. This is a mapping
cone!
Now we can consider a free group hr̃, s̃i and the canonical homomorphism ϕ to D8 .
Denote by K the kernel of ϕ.5
Zorn’s Lemma states that any poset such that every totally ordered subset has an
upper bound, then there is a maximal element in the whole poset (that is, no element
which exceeds it). Once again, this is equivalent to the axiom of choice.
Consider the following subgroup of ha, bi:
5
Completely random sidenote: every vector has a basis if and only if the Axiom of Choice holds.
32
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 16 October 17, 2012
N includes the rest of the elements that makes the group normal). These are called
relators; any relation can be converted to a relator by moving everything to one side.
4 2 −1
We get presentations at this point as well, namely D8 = r, s | r , s , rsr s .
Go back to the figure eight with π1 (X8 ) = hr, si. We will mold this into the dihedral
group D8 as follows:
• Take a disk and map its boundary onto the loop [r] by z 7→ z 4 . This forces r4 = 1.
• Take another disk and map its boundary onto the loop [s] by z 7→ z 2 . This forces
s2 = 1.
• Take a third disk and map it in this super troll way that causes rsr−1 s = 1.
33
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 17 October 22, 2012
p1
p2
-
B
ϕ is a morphism of covering spaces if the diagram commutes; that is, p2 ◦ ϕ = p1 .
In particular, φ must take fibers to fibers.
If ϕ is one-to-one and onto, and ϕ and ϕ−1 are both continuous, then ϕ is an “iso-
morphism”.
17.3 n-Cells
We’ve actually seen this space X before! All we are doing is identifying antipodal points
on the boundary, which is our much earlier space S 2 /A, where antipodal points are
mapped. Now if we look downwards, we get our space (except circular).
This is also equivalent to applying a mapping cone on S 1 , but with the loop we are
applying it to being 2. The whole process is called attaching a 2-cell to Y ; we are
attaching the northern hemisphere of B 2 onto the space Y .
We can generalize this to n-cells by replacing “half of B 2 ” without “half ofB n ”.
In this way, we can build up spaces form the bottom; starting with a bunch of points,
we attach 1-cells. Now ∂B 1 = [−1, 1] and S 0 is {−1, 1}. Hence, adding 1-cells let us add
“loops” and “edges”. Then we go on to n-cells, etc.
34
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 17 October 22, 2012
17.4 Manifolds
A manifold is a space which locally looks like a flat Euclidean sphere; that is, every
point has a neighborhood homeomorphic to Euclidean space. For example, S 2 is a
two-dimensional manifold.
These manifolds are called closed, meaning it is compact and without boundary.
n = 2 is easy, but n ≥ 5 was proven in the 60’s. The n = 4 case is hard and involves
“elegant procrastination”, but the n = 3 case is the hardest.
Gauss-Bonnet Theorem
35
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 18 October 24, 2012
a
4 4
6 6
b b
4 - 4
a
Etymology: flasche and fiasco are related, but fläche means surface.
Once again, we take punch a hole in the middle of the square. Let V be K minus the
hole, and U be a slightly large band-aid. Again, by Seifert van-Kampen, we can get
D E
π1 (K) = π1 U ∗π1 (U ∩V ) πV = 1 ∗Z Z = a, b | bab−1 a .
Note: in general, there is no easy way to prove that we’ve gotten all the relationships,
but in our case our U ∩ V are all generated by one generator, which makes it easy.
The “word problem” basically states that given a presentation of a group, it is not
algorithmically possible to determine whether a word is equal to the identity. It is also
not algorithmically possible to determine whether two groups are isomorphic, given their
presentations.
p
?
B
Given two covering projections (E1 , p1 ) and (E2 , p2 ) onto the same space B, then am
orphism between the two is a map ϕ such that p2 ◦ϕ = p1 (see last week). Geometrically,
ϕ maps p−1 −1
1 (b0 ) to p2 (b0 ).
In other words, the morphisms between covering projections are continuous functions
which preserve fibers. Isomorphisms are those which are invertible.
Suppose a “finite” group G acts freely6 on a space E.
Later we will see that the nicest covering projections are those which can be repre-
sented by this group modding.
6
That is, the stabilizer of each x ∈ E is trivial. In still other words, @g ∈ G \ {1}, x ∈ E with g · x = x.
36
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 18 October 24, 2012
p
?
I - [b0 ] ∈ π1 (b) B
We will see that with “nice” projections, then either the lifts of a loop [γ]inπ1 (B) are
all loops or all non-loops.
f ?
- b0 ∈ B
(Y, y0 )
Let f : Y → B with b0 = f (y0 ). We seek a lifting f˜ of f that takes y0 to e0 ∈ p−1 (b0 ).
We restrict our attention to connected and locally path connected7 spaces Y , E, B. (It
turns out that spaces which are connected and locally path connected are automatically
path-connected).
Theorem 16. Let f : (Y, y0 ) → (B, b0 ) be continuous and consider a covering projection
p : (E, e0 ) → (B, b0 ). Then a lifting f˜ with f˜(y0 ) = e0 if and only if
Proof. For the “only if” part, suppose such a lifting f˜ exists. Then p ◦ f˜ = f . Thus,
f∗ = p∗ ◦ f˜∗ . Hence,
where the last step follows from the obvious f˜∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ⊆ π1 (E, e0 ).
For the other direction, assume f∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ⊆ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )). First, we will show that
if f˜ exists, it is unique! (This turns out to be instructive).
Suppose f˜1 and f˜2 are both liftings of f that start at e0 . We wish to show f˜1 (y1 ) =
˜
f2 (y1 )∀y1 ∈ Y . If y1 = y0 this is obvious. Hence assume y1 6= y0 and consider a path α
from y0 to y1 . In that case, f ◦ α is a path from f (y0 ) = b0 to f (y1 ). Lift f ◦ α to a path
γ starting at e0 ; this path is unique. But p˜◦(f1 ◦ α) = f ◦ α, so f˜1 ◦ α is a lift of f ◦ α
starting at f˜1 (α(0)) = f˜1 (y0 ) = e0 . Hence, the ending points are certainly the same;
7
X is locally path-connected if ∀x ∈ X and U an open neighborhood of x0 , ∃V a path connected open
set with x0 ∈ V ⊆ U . This lets us exclude things like that harmonic fan...
37
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 18 October 24, 2012
that is, γ(1) = f˜1 (α(1)) = f˜1 (y1 ) (that is, their ending points are the same). Similarly
f˜2 (y1 ) = γ(1) as well, so we’re done.
Anyways, to define f˜ we just use the same thing. That is, if α is a path from y0 to
y1 , then let γ be the lifting of f ◦ α and define f˜(y1 ) = γ(1). (In practice, it is very hard
to clean up this definition of f˜ to something reasonable.)
We need to check that this map is both well-defined (since α was chosen arbitrarily)
and that it is continuous. USE THE CONDITION NOW (oops I did not notice that).
You need the first condition to get the well-defined part, and the second part is just sort
of blah.
To be finished next time. . .
The “only if” direction intuitively should be easy: going from topology to algebra
tends to lose information, so it is natural to guess that the existence of a lifting is
strong, while the algebraic condition is weak.
38
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 19 October 29, 2012
e0 ∈ P −1 (b0 ) ⊆ E
f ?
y0 ∈ Y - b0 ∈ B
Want to show f lifts to a unique map f˜ with f˜(y0 ) = e0 if and only if f∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ⊆
p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )).
Idea: connect y0 to y1 via α; then f ◦ α is a path in B with f (α(0)) = f (y0 ) = b0 and
f (α(1)) = f( y1 ) = b1 . Lift this to a path γ starting at e0 and define f˜(y1 ) = γ(1).
We got up to here last time, and now we need to show this is well-defined and contin-
uous. This is probably a good time to use the condition.
Example. To show what goes wrong without said hypothesis, consider the following:
E=R θ
f = id
? ?
1- B = S 1 e2πiθ
Y =S
Here, this hypothesis doesn’t hold since f∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ≈ π1 (Y, y0 ) ≈ Z and π1 (E, e0 ) =
{1} ⇒ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) = {1}. Indeed, this causes the function to not be well-defined: the
two paths α1 , α2 : [0, 1] → S 1 from 1 to −1 given by t 7→ eiπt and t 7→ eiπ3t yield different
values when lifted.
OK, let’s try to prove well-definedness. Consider two paths α and β in Y with the
same endpoints, and consider paths f ◦ α and f ◦ β in B from b0 to b1 . Lift f ◦ α and
f ◦ β̄ to γ and δ, where γ(1) = δ(0). Also, γ ∗ δ lifts (f ◦ α) ∗ (f ◦ β̄), since
p(γ ◦ δ) = (p ◦ γ) ∗ (p ◦ δ) = (f ◦ α) ∗ (f ◦ β̄).
Now
[f ◦ (α ∗ β)] = f∗ ([α ∗ β̄]) ∈ f∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ⊆ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 ))
so that f ◦ (α ∗ β̄) 'p p ◦ (η) where η is some loop at e0 .
Hence, η is a lifting of (f ◦ α) ∗ (f ◦ β̄) = f ◦ (α ∗ β̄) which starts at e0 . Now by
uniqueness of lifting, then, this is a loop. So δ̄ = ¯β = β ends at the same place as γ.
Hence, the function is well-defined.
Continuity can be shown from the fact that f is continuous and we have evenly covered
neighborhoods (i.e. homeomorphisms on a local scale.)
39
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 19 October 29, 2012
p 0
p
p∗ )
0 ∗
- (p
-
B
π1 (B, b0 )
Theorem 17. There’s a unique equivalence h of coverings (E, p) and (E 0 , p0 ) such that
h(e0 ) = e00 if and only if
Proof. Suppose h exists. Then p0 ◦ h = p ⇒ (p0 ◦ h)∗ = p∗ ; i.e. p0∗ ◦ h∗ = p∗ . In that case,
h is a lifting of p; by our previous theorem we have p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) ⊆ p0∗ (π1 (E 0 , e0 )).
E0 E
-
-
1
h−
p0
h
p ? p0 - ?
E - B E0 B
But now by doing the same thing with h−1 , we find p0∗ (π1 (E 0 , e00 )) ⊆ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 ));
this establishes the reverse inclusion and hence the groups in question are equal.
For the reverse direction, we can perform the same trick with double inclusion to find
that p lifts to h : E → E 0 with h(e0 ) = e00 , and p0 lifts to g : E 0 → E with g(e00 ) = e0 .
We want to show that g and h are inverses, but don’t know anything about them yet.
E E
-
-
h
E
◦
p p
id
g
p ? p ?
E - B E - B
40
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 19 October 29, 2012
e0 , e1 ∈ p−1 (b0 ) ⊆E
p
?
b0 ∈ B
Let Hi = p∗ (π1 (E, ei )), for i = 0, 1. If γ is a path from e0 to e1 then α = p ◦ γ is the
loop from b0 to itself.
Now, [α]−1 ∗ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) ∗ [α] = p∗ (π1 (E, e1 )); indeed,
h - e0 ∈ E 0
e0 ∈ E 0
p0
p
b0 ∈ B
these coverings are equivalent if and only if p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) is conjugate to p0∗ (π1 (E 0 , e00 )).
If they are conjugate, then, ∃e01 ∈ E 0 with p0 (e01 ) = b0 for which p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) =
p0∗ (π1 (E 0 , e01 )); actually equal.
Next time: universal covers!
41
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 20 Halloween, 2012
20 Halloween, 2012
Assume all spaces are connected and locally path connected (which implies path-connected
and locally path-connected).
Last time, we saw that a lifting of a map f : Y → b exits if and only if f∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )) ⊆
p∗ (π1 (Y, y0 )). Hence, given two coverings of the same space B, there exists an equivalence
h with h(e0 ) = e00 iff p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) = p0∗ (π1 (E 0 , e00 )).
E0
-
p0
h
?
E - B
p
Then, there exists a equivalence h, period, if and only if p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )) is conjugate to
p0∗ (π1 (E10 , e00 )) in π1 (B, b0 ). Here, e0 ∈ E and e00 ∈ E are both in the fiber of b0 .
E2
-
p2
p1 - ?
E1 B
Hence, R is the universal covering of S 1 since R is contractible (via θ 7→ e2πiθ ). Similarly,
R2 = R × R covers S 1 × S 1 = T by (θ, φ) = (e2πiθ , e2πiφ ), so it is also the universal
covering. This implies, for example, that S 2 cannot cover the torus because S 2 is also
simply connected, but we already have R2 as the universal covering and R2 6≈ S 2 .
Why do we call these universal? First, recall the facts:
q r
Fact. Let r ◦ q = p be continuous maps by E1 −→ E2 −→ B.
E2
-
r
q
?
E1 - B
p
If p, r are coverings then so is q. If p, q are coverings then so is r.
Claim. If (Ẽ, p̃) is a universal covering of B and (E, p) is any covering of B,
8
Strictly, (E, p).
42
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 20 Halloween, 2012
Proof. Notice that p̃∗ π1 (Ẽ, ẽ0 ) = p̃∗ 0 = 0 ⊆ p∗ (π1 (E, e0 )); this inclusion is strict if E is
not a second universal covering (since p∗ is trivial). Hence, we must have a lifting φ; by
the fact above we see that we φ is actually a covering projection!
E
-
φ
p
?
Ẽ - B
p̃
f12
E1 - E2
p1
p2
-
B
Now are categories are starting to look more complicated! Here’s another example:
Example. Fix groups {Gi }. The objects of the category are a group and families of
homomorphisms from some external group H, not fixed. That is, we can view our objects
in the form
ϕi
(H, {H −→ Gi }).
Our morphisms will be homomorphisms Φ12 such that ϕ2i ◦ Φ!2 = ϕ1i for all i.
Φ12
H1 - H2
ϕ1
2i
ϕ
i
Gi
The object
pr
Y nY o
i
Gj , Gj −→ Gi ,
which is the product of all the groups where the homomorphisms are just protections,
are universally attractive. Indeed, just take
43
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 20 Halloween, 2012
All these points are tangent at (0, 0). You can show this is continuous and such. Here,
this is NOT semi-locally simply connected, so there is no universal covering of this space.
You can also look at the higher-dimensional version, where spheres are replaced by
circles, then we get some other interesting stuff.
0 = π1 (Ẽ) Ẽ
q
-
p̃ E
p
?
B
44
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 20 Halloween, 2012
h
E - E
p
-
B
This is a group under composition; the identity is idE , et cetera.
Next time: how does C(E, p, B) act on E?
45
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 21 November 5, 2012
21 November 5, 2012
21.1 Examples of Group Actions
Definition. Let G be a group. It acts freely from the left on X if ∀x ∈ X : Gx = {1}.
That is, the stabilizer of any x ∈ X is the trivial subgroup.
Definition. Let X/G denote the set of the orbits of elements in X, endowed with the
quotient topology.
Our goal is, given a group G and a space X, to get a covering projection p : X → X/G
by x 7→ [x]; that is, we project each element of the space to its image in the group X/G
with the quotient topology.
Why do we need the group to act freely? Consider the following example with X = B 2 ,
where G does not act freely be the stabilizer of 0 is all of G.
Intuitively, this means that G acts in such a way that if 1 6= g ∈ G, then elements of
X are moved “sufficiently far away”. The example X = G = R does not work, but. . .
Note. Some book use freely and properly discontinuously. However, if an action is
properly discontinuous, then it is automatically free (for obvious reasons).
We can start viewing X as topological groups; a group endowed with a topology. For
example,
hζn i = Zn ≤ R ∼
= S1
Other important groups: SO(n), GLn (R). Anyways, on a side note
46
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 21 November 5, 2012
-
h
p
?
E - B
p
h is a lifting of p, where h(e) = e. But by uniqueness of lifting, we immediately obtain
h = idE .
It turns out that this is properly discontinuous as well. Consider some e ∈ E, let
b0 = p(e), take some neighborhood Ub0 of b0 . Now p−1 (Ub0 ) is a collection of disjoint
neighborhoods around p−1 (b0 ), per even covering. Let Ue be the one around V .
Then, p(Ue ) = Ub0 . If h is some homeomorphism which preserves projection, then
h(Ue ) must be Ub0 . Unless h is the identity, then h(Ue ) ∈ p−1 (Ub0 ), and this is a bunch
of disjoint sets.
E
p
π
-
?
E/G B
Let π : E → E/G be a group quotient map, and p : E → B be the standard covering
projection. Can E/G = B?
Let ∼π be the relation that equates elements of E in the same orbit of π. Let ∼p be
the relation that equates elements in the same fiber of p.
Fact. e ∼π e0 ⇒ e ∼p e0 . The converse is not necessarily true.
Proof. Compute
e ∼π e0 ⇒ e0 = ge = g(e)
⇒ pp(e0 ) = p(g(e))
= p(e)
0
⇒ e ∼p e
⇒ e ∼p e0
47
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 22 November 7, 2012
22 November 7, 2012
22.1 Groups
We are given a covering projection p : E → B, with b0 ∈ B having fiber F = p−1 (b0 ).
Let G = π1 (B, b0 ) from now on.
1. G acts from the right on F . The action F × π1 (B, b0 ) → F sends (e, [γ]) to γ̃(1)
where γ̃ is a path starting at e.9
Consider C(E, p, B) as defined in the previous section. Then, define Aut(F ) to be the
set of G-automorphisms of F ; that is
These are both groups under composition. Now we claim these groups are isomorphic!
(This implies that C(E, p, B) is completely determined by what p does to a fiber.)
Claim. C(E, p, B) ∼
= Aut(F ).
But then
p ◦ (ϕ̃ ◦ γ̃) = p ◦ γ̃ = γ.
So ϕ ◦ γ̃ is a lifting of γ starting at ϕ(γ̃(0)) = ϕ(e). So, ϕ(γ̃(1)) = ϕ(e)[γ] by
definition. This establishes the desired equality. Hence, we finally get ϕ|F ∈
Aut(F ).
• Check that ϕ|F is a homomorphism. This is trivial since the operations are
composition in both groups.
9
Since p(γ̃(1)) = γ(1) = b0 , we see that this is well-defined in the sense that γ̃(1) ∈ F .
48
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 22 November 7, 2012
• Check that Φ is injective. We can just check that the kernel is trivial. Suppose
ϕ|F is the identity; i.e. in the kernel. Then ∀e ∈ F : ϕ|F (e) = e ⇒ ϕ(e) = e. Then
ϕ is a lifting of p that takes e to e, so it must be the identity.
So p∗ π1 (E, e) = p∗ π1 (E, e0 ).
E
-
p
ϕ
p ?
E - B
It turns out later that Aut(F ) = NGe (G)/Ge , where NGe (G) is the normalizer of Ge in
G. In the case of covering projections, we know that Ge = p∗ π1 (E, ee ) and G = π1 (B, b0 )
and we can compute stuff. In particular, if π1 (E) = 1 then Aut(F ) = π1 (B, b0 ).
49
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 23 November 14, 2012
Aut(F ) ∼
= NG (Ge0 )/Ge0 .
although it is certainly true for finite groups. Also, recall the facts (i) H ≤ NG (H) ≤ G
for any H ≤ G, (ii) H E G ⇔ NG (H) = G, and (iii) H E NG (H)
Proof. We will do this completely in the context of group theory; let F = Ge \G where
Ge0 is the stabilizer of some e0 ∈ F and suppose G acts transitively on F . Consider some
φ ∈ Aut(F ) = Aut(Ge \G) mapping Hg 7→ φ(Hg) = φ(H)g. Notice that Φ is completely
determined by any H. So, for any automorphism φ, we let gφ denote a representative of
the coset φ(H1G ) = φ(H).
Hence, we are motivated to construct the automorphism Γ : Aut(F ) → NG (Ge0 )/Ge0
by
φ 7→ Hgφ .
Okay, details. . .
φ1 φ2 (H) = φ1 (Hgφ2 ) = φ1 (H)gφ2 = (Hgφ1 )gφ2 = H(gφ1 gφ2 ) = Hgφ1 Hgφ2 = Γ(φ1 )Γ(φ2 ).
• To get that Γ is injective, notice that Γ(φ) = φ(H) = H. Then φ(Hg) = φ(H)g =
Hg for every g, so φ is the identity, and hence ker Γ = {1} and we win.
50
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 23 November 14, 2012
23.2 A Diagram
We have that C(E, p, B) acts properly discontinuously on E.
E
p
π
? -
E/C(E, p, B) ............
- B
E p
p - ?
E B
Hence, we can find a φ if and only if p∗ π1 (E, e) = p∗ π1 (E, e0 ); yet p∗ π1 (E, e0 ) = [γ] ∗
p∗ π1 (E, e)[γ̄] for every [γ] ∈ π1 (B, b).
Yet this is normality.
In conclusion, p : E → B is effectively an orbit projection if and only if it is a regular
covering.
-
?
E/H .........
- B = E/G
51
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 23 November 14, 2012
23.4 Example
Let E = R2 and G = Z×Z, where G acts on E in the usual manner giving E/G = S 1 ×S 1 .
Now π1 (S 1 × S 1 ) = π1 (S 1 ) × ı1 (S 1 ) = Z × Z.
Consider Z × 2Z ≤ π1 (S 1 × S 1 ).
Then E/(Z × 2Z) we get another torus which is “not as tightly wrapped”. Now our
induced map is a covering projection from a torus to a torus.
52
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 24 November 19, 2012
It turns out that the boundary of a manifold with boundary is an n − 1 manifold with
boundary.
If G acts properly discontinuously on E, then the projection E onto its orbit space is
a covering projection.10 The proof was discussed in an earlier section which I am too
lazy to look up; the basic idea is that one takes a small neighborhood around each of
the elements in the fiber, which is possible because the action is properly discontinuous.
Claim. The group of covering transformations of this projection is precisely G; that is,
C(E, p, E/G) = G.
We observe that (m, n) = (m, 0)(0, n) = (1, 0)m (0, 1)n . Now define a = (1, 0) and
b = (0, 1); these generate the group. Now, check that bab−1 = a−1 .
Hence, we may write D E
G = a, b | bab−1 = a−1 .
53
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 24 November 19, 2012
y
3
b2 x
2
bx
1
a−1 x x ax a2 x
0
−1 0 1 2 3
x
−1
6 6
-
Therefore, the fundamental group of a Klein bottle is Z o Z. We’ve seen this earlier
with the van Kampen Theorem, when the condition βαβ −1 α = 1 was added by the
patching.
10
This is also a regular covering projection; it’s equivalent to p∗ π1 (E) E E/G.
54
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 25 November 21, 2012
defined by
(m, n)(k, `) = (m + (−1)n k, n + `).
Our group action gave a map R2 → R2 /G from R2 to its orbit space, which gave a
regular covering projection from R2 to the Klein Bottle K.
Again, as we saw last time, since this is a regular covering we get π1 (K) = G = Z o Z.
Now, suppose H ≤ G. Then H acts on R2 as well, and we can get mod out again:
R2
-
?
R2 /H ........
- R2 /G = K
55
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 25 November 21, 2012
Obviously, two things equivalent under the H action are equivalent under the G action,
but not vice versa. Hence, the equivalence classes of H are “finer” than those of G. In
still other words, there is less collapsing.
Now we get a covering projection of R2 /H onto R2 /G. Note, however, that if H is
nontrivial then this cannot be regular.
25.4 Example
Let
H12 = Z o 2Z = {(n, 2m) | n, m ∈ Z} ≤ G.
What does our action look like?
y
3
(0, 2)x
2
−1
This time, there’s no “twist”: so the result is that R2 /H12 ≈ T , the torus. Now we
can rewrite our diagram earlier:
Torus
-
?
R2 - Klein Bottle
Actually, H12 ∼ = Z × 2Z if we just check that the group multiplication is “normal”.
This is consistent with the fact that the fundamental group of the torus is Z × Z.
Now, consider the covering we have obtained, q : T → K. Then
C(T, q, K) = Nπ1 (K q∗ π1 (T )/q∗ π1 (T )
56
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 25 November 21, 2012
(0, 2)x
2
(0, 1)x
1
x (2, 0)x
0
−1 0 1 2 3
x
−1
Note that the [0, 2] × [0, 1] doesn’t work here, since (2, 0) ∼ (−1, 1) which doesn’t get
mapped to anything on the line y = 1 within that rectangle.
And. . . we get a Klein bottle. Hence the Klein bottle covers itself. In fact, if we use
H33 = 3Z o 3Z we get the Klein bottle once again. Unfortunately, H33 is not normal in
Z o Z.
25.6 GAP
Just something to Google.
57
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 26 November 26, 2012
Solution. This is equivalent to ghg −1 ∈ H∀g ∈ G. It suffices to check that this is true
when g is a generator of G. Compute
(1, 0)(3s, 3t)(1, 0)−1 = (3s + 1 + (−1)3t , 3t) = (3s + 1 + (−1)t , 3t).
Unfortunately, this is false for t odd. Hence it is not the case that H E G.
[G : H] = [G : N ][N : H].
What we care about is the group of covering transformations, which is N/H is the stuff
p̂
above. We also know that the covering R2 /H −→ R2 /G is not regular because it is not
the case that H is normal in G. (Recall that E → B is regular iff p∗ π1 (E) E π1 (B), but
π1 (X/G) = G.)
OK, so let us try to compute NG (H). If (m, n) ∈ N then g(3s, 3t)g −1 . Computing,
(m, n)(3s, 3t)(m, n)−1 = (−1)n · 3s + m(1 − (−1)2n+3t ), 3t .
This lies in 3Z o 3Z if and only if m(1 − (−1)t ) is divisible by 3. Since this must hold
for all t, this is true when m ∈ 3Z.
We then conclude that NG (H) is 3Z o Z, by our index argument.
26.1 Pictures
Let H = 3Z × 3Z.
The fundamental domain is [−1, 2) × [0, 3). This is obvious. Both yield Klein bottles.
Then, a lifting of α3 can be viewed as a path from (−1, 0) to (−1, 3) and also one from
(0, 0) = (1, 3) to (0, 3). The latter is closed but the former is open.
11
i.e. γ̃(0) 6= γ̃(1).
58
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 26 November 26, 2012
Z o `Z E Z o Z
by showing that the covering of G/(Z o `Z) onto the Klein bottle is regular.
How de prove this claim? One direction is straightforward. Suppose p∗ π1 (E) E π1 (B)
so that C(E, p, B) = π1 (B)/p∗ π1 (E).
ϕ
E - E
p
-
B
Take [ϕ] ∈ π1 (B). Lift it to γ̃ starting at e0 . Then every ϕ◦γ̃ is a lift of γ if ϕ ∈ C(E, p, B).
Now every ϕ ◦ γ̃ is also a lift of γ if ϕ ∈ C(E, p, B). This turns out to be all the possible
liftings; some technical details omitted here.
Conversely, consider the case where ∀[γ] all lifts are open or all are closed. We wish
to show
59
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 27 November 28, 2012
G∼
= GL2 (C)/{I2 , −I2 }.
60
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 28 December 3, 2012
28 December 3, 2012
Recall the definition of a semidirect product.
R2
-
?
K = R2 /G R2 /H
Same setup as before, where H ≤ G.
28.1 An Aside
Actually, as a curiosity
D E D E
Z o Z = a, b | bab−1 = a−1 ∼
= α, β | α2 = β 2 .
Ẽ
r
-
p̃ Ẽ/H
ν
?
Ẽ/G = B
We have π1 (B) ∼
= G = C(Ẽ, p̃, B). Now G acts on Ẽ to yield B, et cetera.
r
Let H ≤ G. Then H acts on Ẽ, and Ẽ −→ Ẽ/H is a covering transformation as well.
So, we find a get a map from the subgroups of G to the quotients of Ẽ by
H 7→ (Ẽ, r, Ẽ/H).
At the extremes {1} 7→ E and G 7→ E/G = B. On the other hand, any covering
Y → B can be recovered12 as Ẽ/H for some H.
12
No pun intended.
61
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 28 December 3, 2012
Now we get
r
Ẽ - Y
q
?
B
ϕ ∈ C(Ẽ, r, Y ) ⇒ ϕ : Ẽ → Ẽ has r ◦ ϕ = r.
ϕ ∈ C(Ẽ, r, Y )
Ẽ - Ẽ
r r
-
Y
q
?
B
Hence, with a few more details we obtain
Fact. For “nice” B, the spaces which cover B correspond precisely to the subgroups of
G = C(Ẽ, p̃, B).
How does this correspond to Galois theory? Let k be a subfield of K and suppose
K H = {k ∈ K | σ(x) = x ∀σ ∈ H}.
62
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 28 December 3, 2012
pr−1 (x0 ) = {(x̃0 , e) | pr1 (x̃, e) = x; p(e) = f (x)} = {(x0 , e) | p(e) = f (x0 )} = {x0 }×p−1 (f (x)).
63
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 29 December 5, 2012
29 December 5, 2012
If n < m then any map from S n → S m if n < m since it is not surjective, and then one
can take the missed point and expand it to something else. However, S n → S m is often
not nulhomotopic if n ≥ m > 1.
q
E0 - E
p0
?
B
q is called a bundle map if p ◦ q = p0 ; that is q “preserves” fibers.
If b0 ∈ B then
−1
q p0 (b0 ) ⊆ p−1 (b0 ).
hV hU
(V ∩ U ) × F p−1 (V ∩ U ) - (V ∩ U ) × F
pr (V (U
)
1 ) r 1
-
? p
V ∩U
hU ◦h−1
V
We have hU and hV are homeomorphisms. Then (b, f ) 7→ (b, L(b, f )) for some
arbitrary function L.
64
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 29 December 5, 2012
E = f ! EG - EG
? f - ?
B BG
These are called “classifying spaces”.
13
e.g. F = Rn and G = GLn (R) or F = {a1 , · · · , an } and G = Sn the symmetric group
65
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 30 December 10, 2012
p
pr 1
?
Ub
ϕ-U −1 ϕV
(Ub ∩ Vb ) × F p (Ub ∩ Vb ) (Ub ∩ Vb ) × F
≈ ≈
pr p pr 1
1
- ?
Ub ∩ Vb
Then, we require that there is a “transition” function ΓV U : Ub ∩ Vb → G for which
x 7→ ΓV U x for which
(ϕ−1
V ◦ ϕU )(x, f ) = (x, ΓV U (x)f )
for all f ∈ F .
Finally, if b ∈ Ub ∩ Vb ∩ Wb we require ΓW V ◦ ΓV U = ΓW U .
Finally, we can define morphisms as such:
u
E0 - E
p0 p
? ?
B0 - B
f
A morphism between fiber bundles with the same fiber F and structure group G is a
pair (u, f ) such that p ◦ u = f ◦ p0 .
Thus, we have a category of fiber bundles with fiber F and group G.
66
Evan Chen M275 Fall 2012: Notes 30 December 10, 2012
30.2 Categories
Now, let H be the category of topological spaces and homotopy classes of maps. The
objects consists of category of topological spaces X, and arrows are the homotopy classes
of maps [X, Y ].
Also, Set is the category whose objects are sets and arrows are arbitrary set functions.
Now we consider a map kG : X 7→ kG (X), the set of all fiber bundles with structure
group G and fiber F over X. This is a set, of course. Then kG is a contravariant14
functor. We want to send [f ] ∈ [X, Y ] to some map f ∗ : kG (Y ) → kG (X).
f ! Ey - Ey
? ?
X - Y
f
So, we just use the pullback. The claim is that f ! Ey → X is a fiber bundle with the
same fiber and such.
Now, we say that kG is representable in the sense that there is a unique (up to ho-
motopy) space BG and an element of kG (BG ) (i.e. a fiber bundle EG → BG ) such that
∀X : kG (X) = [X, BG ].
That is, if E → X is a fiber bundle, there is a unique [f ] ∈ [X, BG ] such that this
commutes:
E ≈ f ! EG - EG
? ?
X - BG
f
Hence, for every group G we can get a “master” EG → BG which describes all fiber
bundles with structure group G.
As an example, we have for F = {1, 2} and G = Z2
S1 ⊆ S2 ⊆ S3 ⊆ · · ·
? ? · · · RP 1 ⊆ RP 2 ⊆ RP 3 ⊆ · · ·
?
14
Meaning the direction is flipped.
67