0% found this document useful (0 votes)
42 views

The Einstein

1. In 1935, Albert Einstein co-authored a paper with Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen called "Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?" (EPR). 2. The EPR paper argued that quantum mechanics provides an incomplete description of physical reality based on a scenario where measuring properties of one particle instantly determines properties of another entangled particle even when separated in space. 3. The EPR paper sparked ongoing debates about the interpretation of quantum theory and its implications for concepts like locality and realism. It became highly influential in the development of quantum information theory and remains an important contribution to foundational questions in physics.

Uploaded by

prapya pokharel
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
42 views

The Einstein

1. In 1935, Albert Einstein co-authored a paper with Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen called "Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?" (EPR). 2. The EPR paper argued that quantum mechanics provides an incomplete description of physical reality based on a scenario where measuring properties of one particle instantly determines properties of another entangled particle even when separated in space. 3. The EPR paper sparked ongoing debates about the interpretation of quantum theory and its implications for concepts like locality and realism. It became highly influential in the development of quantum information theory and remains an important contribution to foundational questions in physics.

Uploaded by

prapya pokharel
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 25

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen

Argument in Quantum Theory


First published Mon May 10, 2004; substantive revision Tue Oct 31, 2017
In the May 15, 1935 issue of Physical Review Albert Einstein co-authored a paper with his
two postdoctoral research associates at the Institute for Advanced Study, Boris Podolsky and
Nathan Rosen. The article was entitled “Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical
Reality Be Considered Complete?” (Einstein et al. 1935). Generally referred to as “EPR”,
this paper quickly became a centerpiece in debates over the interpretation of quantum theory,
debates that continue today. Ranked by impact, EPR is among the top ten of all papers ever
published in Physical Reviewjournals. Due to its role in the development of quantum
information theory, it is also near the top in their list of currently “hot“ papers. The paper
features a striking case where two quantum systems interact in such a way as to link both
their spatial coordinates in a certain direction and also their linear momenta (in the same
direction), even when the systems are widely separated in space. As a result of this
“entanglement”, determining either position or momentum for one system would fix
(respectively) the position or the momentum of the other. EPR prove a general lemma
connecting such strict correlations between spatially separated systems to the possession of
definite values. On that basis they argue that one cannot maintain both an intuitive condition
of local action and the completeness of the quantum description by means of the wave
function. This entry describes the lemma and argument of that 1935 paper, considers several
different versions and reactions, and explores the ongoing significance of the issues raised.

 1. Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered


Complete?
o 1.1 Setting and prehistory
o 1.2 The argument in the text
o 1.3 Einstein’s versions of the argument
 2. A popular form of the argument: Bohr’s response
 3. Development of EPR
o 3.1 Spin and The Bohm version
o 3.2 Bell and beyond
 Bibliography
 Academic Tools
 Other Internet Resources
 Related Entries
1. Can Quantum Mechanical Description of
Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?
1.1 Setting and prehistory
By 1935 conceptual understanding of the quantum theory was dominated by Niels Bohr’s
ideas concerning complementarity. Those ideas centered on observation and measurement in
the quantum domain. According to Bohr’s views at that time, observing a quantum object
involves an uncontrollable physical interaction with a measuring device that affects both
systems. The picture here is of a tiny object banging into a big apparatus. The effect this
produces on the measuring instrument is what issues in the measurement “result” which,
because it is uncontrollable, can only be predicted statistically. The effect experienced by the
quantum object limits what other quantities can be co-measured with precision. According to
complementarity when we observe the position of an object, we affect its momentum
uncontrollably. Thus we cannot determine both position and momentum precisely. A similar
situation arises for the simultaneous determination of energy and time. Thus
complementarity involves a doctrine of uncontrollable physical interaction that, according to
Bohr, underwrites the Heisenberg uncertainty relations and is also the source of the statistical
character of the quantum theory. (See the entries on the Copenhagen Interpretation and
the Uncertainty Principle.)
Initially Einstein was enthusiastic about the quantum theory. By 1935, however, while
recognizing the theory’s significant achievements, his enthusiasm had given way to
disappointment. His reservations were twofold. Firstly, he felt the theory had abdicated the
historical task of natural science to provide knowledge of significant aspects of nature that
are independent of observers or their observations. Instead the fundamental understanding of
the quantum wave function (alternatively, the “state function”, “state vector”, or “psi-
function”) was that it only treated the outcomes of measurements (via probabilities given by
the Born Rule). The theory was simply silent about what, if anything, was likely to be true in
the absence of observation. That there could be laws, even probabilistic laws, for finding
things if one looks, but no laws of any sort for how things are independently of whether one
looks, marked quantum theory as irrealist. Secondly, the quantum theory was essentially
statistical. The probabilities built into the state function were fundamental and, unlike the
situation in classical statistical mechanics, they were not understood as arising from
ignorance of fine details. In this sense the theory was indeterministic. Thus Einstein began to
probe how strongly the quantum theory was tied to irrealism and indeterminism.
He wondered whether it was possible, at least in principle, to ascribe certain properties to a
quantum system in the absence of measurement. Can we suppose, for instance, that the decay
of an atom occurs at a definite moment in time even though such a definite decay time is not
implied by the quantum state function? That is, Einstein began to ask whether the formalism
provides a description of quantum systems that is complete. Can all physically relevant truths
about systems be derived from quantum states? One can raise a similar question about a
logical formalism: are all logical truths (or semantically valid formulas) derivable from the
axioms. Completeness, in this sense, was a central focus for the Göttingen school of
mathematical logic associated with David Hilbert. (See entry on Hilbert’s Program.) Werner
Heisenberg, who had attended Hilbert’s lectures, picked up those concerns with questions
about the completeness of his own, matrix approach to quantum mechanics. In response,
Bohr (and others sympathetic to complementarity) made bold claims not just for the
descriptive adequacy of the quantum theory but also for its “finality”, claims that enshrined
the features of irrealism and indeterminism that worried Einstein. (See Beller 1999, Chapters
4 and 9, on the rhetoric of finality and Ryckman 2017, Chapter 4, for the connection to
Hilbert.) Thus complementarity became Einstein’s target for investigation. In particular,
Einstein had reservations about the uncontrollable physical effects invoked by Bohr in the
context of measurement interactions, and about their role in fixing the interpretation of the
wave function. EPR’s focus on completeness was intended to support those reservations in a
particularly dramatic way.
Max Jammer (1974, pp. 166–181) locates the development of the EPR paper in Einstein’s
reflections on a thought experiment he proposed during discussions at the 1930 Solvay
conference. (For more on EPR and Solvay 1930 see Howard, 1990 and Ryckman, 2017, pp.
118–135.) The experiment imagines a box that contains a clock set to time precisely the
release (in the box) of a photon with determinate energy. If this were feasible, it would
appear to challenge the unrestricted validity of the Heisenberg uncertainty relation that sets a
lower bound on the simultaneous uncertainty of energy and time. (See the entry on
the Uncertainty Principle and also Bohr 1949, who describes the discussions at the 1930
conference.) The uncertainty relations, understood not just as a prohibition on what is co-
measurable, but on what is simultaneously real, were a central component in the irrealist
interpretation of the wave function. Jammer (1974, p. 173) describes how Einstein’s thinking
about this experiment, and Bohr’s objections to it, evolved into a different photon-in-a-box
experiment, one that allows an observer to determine either the momentum or the position of
the photon indirectly, while remaining outside, sitting on the box. Jammer associates this
with the distant determination of either momentum or position that, we shall see, is at the
heart of the EPR paper. Carsten Held (1998) cites a related correspondence with Paul
Ehrenfest from 1932 in which Einstein described an arrangement for the indirect
measurement of a particle of mass m using correlations with a photon established through
Compton scattering. Einstein’s reflections here foreshadow the argument of EPR, along with
noting some of its difficulties.
Thus without an experiment on m it is possible to predict freely, at will, either the
momentum or the position of m with, in principle, arbitrary precision. This is the reason why
I feel compelled to ascribe objective reality to both. I grant, however, that it is not logically
necessary. (Held 1998, p. 90)
Whatever their precursors, the ideas that found their way into EPR were discussed in a series
of meetings between Einstein and his two assistants, Podolsky and Rosen. Podolsky was
commissioned to compose the paper and he submitted it to Physical Review in March of
1935, where it was sent for publication the day after it arrived. Apparently Einstein never
checked Podolsky’s draft before submission. He was not pleased with the result. Upon seeing
the published version, Einstein complained that it obscured his central concerns.
For reasons of language this [paper] was written by Podolsky after several discussions. Still,
it did not come out as well as I had originally wanted; rather, the essential thing was, so to
speak, smothered by formalism [Gelehrsamkeit]. (Letter from Einstein to Erwin Schrödinger,
June 19, 1935. In Fine 1996, p. 35.)
Unfortunately, without attending to Einstein’s reservations, EPR is often cited to evoke the
authority of Einstein. Here we will distinguish the argument Podolsky laid out in the text
from lines of argument that Einstein himself published in articles from 1935 on. We will also
consider the argument presented in Bohr’s reply to EPR, which is possibly the best known
version, although it differs from the others in important ways.

1.2 The argument in the text


The EPR text is concerned, in the first instance, with the logical connections between two
assertions. One asserts that quantum mechanics is incomplete. The other asserts that
incompatible quantities (those whose operators do not commute, like the x-coordinate of
position and linear momentum in direction x) cannot have simultaneous “reality” (i.e.,
simultaneously real values). The authors assert the disjunction of these as a first premise
(later to be justified): one or another of these must hold. It follows that if quantum mechanics
were complete (so that the first assertion failed) then the second one would hold; i.e.,
incompatible quantities cannot have real values simultaneously. They take as a second
premise (also to be justified) that if quantum mechanics were complete, then incompatible
quantities (in particular coordinates of position and momentum) could indeed have
simultaneous, real values. They conclude that quantum mechanics is incomplete. The
conclusion certainly follows since otherwise (if the theory were complete) one would have a
contradiction over simultaneous values. Nevertheless the argument is highly abstract and
formulaic and even at this point in its development one can readily appreciate Einstein’s
disappointment.
EPR now proceed to establish the two premises, beginning with a discussion of the idea of a
complete theory. Here they offer only a necessary condition; namely, that for a complete
theory “every element of the physical reality must have a counterpart in the physical theory.”
The term “element“ may remind one of Mach, for whom this was a central, technical term
connected to sensations. (See the entry on Ernst Mach.) The use in EPR of elements of
reality is also technical but different. Although they do not define an “element of physical
reality” explicitly (and, one might note, the language of elements is not part of Einstein’s
usage elsewhere), that expression is used when referring to the values of physical quantities
(positions, momenta, and so on) that are determined by an underlying “real physical state”.
The picture is that quantum systems have real states that assign values to certain quantities.
Sometimes EPR describe this by saying the quantities in question have “definite values”,
sometimes “there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to the quantity”.
Suppose we adapt the simpler terminology and call a quantity on a system definite if that
quantity has a definite value; i.e., if the real state of the system assigns a value (an “element
of reality”) to the quantity. The relation that associates real states with assignments of values
to quantities is functional so that without a change in the real state there is no change among
values assigned to quantities. In order to get at the issue of completeness, a primary question
for EPR is to determine when a quantity has a definite value. For that purpose they offer a
minimal sufficient condition (p. 777):
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with
probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of
reality corresponding to that quantity.
This sufficient condition for an “element of reality” is often referred to as the EPR Criterion
of Reality. By way of illustration EPR point to those quantities for which the quantum state
of the system is an eigenstate. It follows from the Criterion that at least these quantities have
a definite value; namely, the associated eigenvalue, since in an eigenstate the corresponding
eigenvalue has probability one, which we can determine (predict with certainty) without
disturbing the system. In fact, moving from eigenstate to eigenvalue to fix a definite value is
the only use of the Criterion in EPR.
With these terms in place it is easy to show that if, say, the values of position and momentum
for a quantum system were definite (were elements of reality) then the description provided
by the wave function of the system would be incomplete, since no wave function contains
counterparts for both elements. Technically, no state function—even an improper one, like a
delta function—is a simultaneous eigenstate for both position and momentum; indeed, joint
probabilities for position and momentum are not well-defined in any quantum state. Thus
they establish the first premise: either quantum theory is incomplete or there can be no
simultaneously real (“definite”) values for incompatible quantities. They now need to show
that if quantum mechanics were complete, then incompatible quantities could have
simultaneous real values, which is the second premise. This, however, is not easily
established. Indeed what EPR proceed to do is odd. Instead of assuming completeness and on
that basis deriving that incompatible quantities can have real values simultaneously, they
simply set out to derive the latter assertion without any completeness assumption at all. This
“derivation” turns out to be the heart of the paper and its most controversial part. It attempts
to show that in certain circumstances a quantum system can have simultaneous values for
incompatible quantities (once again, for position and momentum), where these are definite
values; that is, they are assigned by the real state of the system, hence are “elements of
reality”.
They proceed by sketching an iconic thought experiment whose variations continue to be
important and widely discussed. The experiment concerns two quantum systems that are
spatially distant from one another, perhaps quite far apart, but such that the total wave
function for the pair links both the positions of the systems as well as their linear momenta.
In the EPR example the total linear momentum is zero along the x-axis. Thus if the linear
momentum of one of the systems (we can call it Albert’s) along the x-axis were found to
be p, the x-momentum of the other system (call it Niels’) would be found to be −p. At the
same time their positions along x are also strictly correlated so that determining the position
of one system on the x-axis allows us to infer the position of the other system along x. The
paper constructs an explicit wave function for the combined (Albert+Niels) system that
embodies these links even when the systems are widely separated in space. Although
commentators later raised questions about the legitimacy of this wave function, it does
appear to guarantee the required correlations for spatially separated systems, at least for a
moment (Jammer 1974, pp. 225–38; see also Halvorson 2000). In any case, one can model
the same conceptual situation in other cases that are clearly well defined quantum
mechanically (see Section 3.1).
At this point of the argument (p. 779) EPR make two critical assumptions, although they do
not call special attention to them. (For the significance of these assumptions in Einstein’s
thinking see Howard 1985 and also section 5 of the entry on Einstein.) The first assumption
(separability) is that at the time when the systems are separated, maybe quite far apart, each
has its own reality. In effect, they assume that each system maintains a separate identity
characterized by a real physical state, even though each system is also strictly correlated with
the other in respect both to momentum and position. They need this assumption to make
sense of another. The second assumption is that of locality. Given that the systems are far
apart, locality supposes that “no real change can take place” in one system as a direct
consequence of a measurement made on the other system. They gloss this by saying “at the
time of measurement the two systems no longer interact.” Note that locality does not require
that nothing at all about one system can be disturbed directly by a distant measurement on
the other system. Locality only rules out that a distant measurement may directly disturb or
change what is counted as “real“ with respect to a system, a reality that separability
guarantees. On the basis of these two assumptions they conclude that each system can have
definite values (“elements of reality”) for both position and momentum simultaneously.
There is no straightforward argument for this in the text. Instead they use these two
assumptions to show how one could be led to assign position and momentum eigenstates to
one system by making measurements on the other system, from which the simultaneous
attribution of elements of reality is supposed to follow. Since this is the central and most
controversial part of the paper, it pays to go slowly here in trying to reconstruct an argument
on their behalf.
Here is one attempt. (Dickson 2004 analyzes some of the modal principles involved and
suggests one line of argument, which he criticizes. Hooker 1972 is a comprehensive
discussion that identifies several generically different ways to make the case.) Locality
affirms that the real state of a system is not affected by distant measurements. Since the real
state determines which quantities are definite (i.e., have assigned values), the set of definite
quantities is also not affected by distant measurements. So if by measuring a distant partner
we can determine that a certain quantity is definite, then that quantity must have been
definite all along. As we have seen, the Criterion of Reality implies that a quantity is definite
if the state of the system is an eigenstate for that quantity. In the case of the strict correlations
of EPR, measuring one system triggers a reduction of the joint state that results in an
eigenstate for the distant partner. Hence any quantity with that eigenstate is definite. For
example, since measuring the momentum of Albert’s system results in a momentum
eigenstate for Niels’, the momentum of Niels’ system is definite. Likewise for the position of
Niels’ system. Given separability, the combination of locality and the Criterion establish a
quite general lemma; namely, when quantities on separated systems have strictly correlated
values, those quantities are definite. Thus the strict correlations between Niels’ system and
Albert’s in the EPR situation guarantee that both position and momentum are definite; i. e.,
that each system has definite position and momentum simultaneously.
EPR point out that position and momentum cannot be measured simultaneously. So even if
each can be shown to be definite in distinct contexts of measurement, can both be definite at
the same time? The lemma answers “yes”. What drives the argument is locality, which
functions logically to decontextualize the reality of Niels’ system from goings on at Albert’s.
Accordingly, measurements made on Albert’s system are probative for features
corresponding to the real state of Niels’ system but not determinative of them. Thus even
without measuring Albert’s system, features corresponding to the real state of Niels’ system
remain in place. Among those features are a definite position and a definite momentum for
Niels’ system along some particular coordinate direction.
In the penultimate paragraph of EPR (p. 780) they address the problem of getting real values
for incompatible quantities simultaneously.
Indeed one would not arrive at our conclusion if one insisted that two or more physical
quantities can be regarded as simultaneous elements of reality only when they can be
simultaneously measured or predicted. … This makes the reality [on the second system]
depend upon the process of measurement carried out on the first system, which does not in
any way disturb the second system. No reasonable definition of reality could be expected to
permit this.
The unreasonableness to which EPR allude in making “the reality [on the second system]
depend upon the process of measurement carried out on the first system, which does not in
any way disturb the second system” is just the unreasonableness that would be involved in
renouncing locality understood as above. For it is locality that enables one to overcome the
incompatibility of position and momentum measurements of Albert’s system by requiring
their joint consequences for Niels’ system to be incorporated in a single, stable reality there.
If we recall Einstein’s acknowledgment to Ehrenfest that getting simultaneous position and
momentum was “not logically necessary”, we can see how EPR respond by making
it become necessary once locality is assumed.
Here, then, are the key features of EPR.

 EPR is about the interpretation of state vectors (“wave functions”) and employs the
standard state vector reduction formalism (von Neumann’s “projection postulate”).
 The Criterion of Reality affirms that the eigenvalue corresponding to the eigenstate of
a system is a value determined by the real physical state of that system. (This is the
Criterion’s only use.)
 (Separability) Spatially separated systems have real physical states.
 (Locality) If systems are spatially separate, the measurement (or absence of
measurement) of one system does not directly affect the reality that pertains to the
others.
 (EPR Lemma) If quantities on separated systems have strictly correlated values, those
quantities are definite (i.e., have definite values). This follows from separability,
locality and the Criterion. No actual measurements are required.
 (Completeness) If the description of systems by state vectors were complete, then
definite values of quantities (values determined by the real state of a system) could be
inferred from a state vector for the system itself or from a state vector for a composite
of which the system is a part.
 In summary, separated systems as described by EPR have definite position and
momentum values simultaneously. Since this cannot be inferred from any state
vector, the quantum mechanical description of systems by means state vectors is
incomplete.
The EPR experiment with interacting systems accomplishes a form of indirect measurement.
The direct measurement of Albert’s system yields information about Niels’ system; it tells us
what we would find if we were to measure there directly. But it does this at-a-distance,
without any physical interaction taking place between the two systems. Thus the thought
experiment at the heart of EPR undercuts the picture of measurement as necessarily
involving a tiny object banging into a large measuring instrument. If we look back at
Einstein’s reservations about complementarity, we can appreciate that by focusing on an
indirect, non-disturbing kind of measurement the EPR argument targets Bohr’s program for
explaining central conceptual features of the quantum theory. For that program relied on
uncontrollable interaction with a measuring device as a necessary feature of any
measurement in the quantum domain. Nevertheless the cumbersome machinery employed in
the EPR paper makes it difficult to see what is central. It distracts from rather than focuses on
the issues. That was Einstein’s complaint about Podolsky’s text in his June 19, 1935 letter to
Schrödinger. Schrödinger responded on July 13 reporting reactions to EPR that vindicate
Einstein’s concerns. With reference to EPR he wrote:
I am now having fun and taking your note to its source to provoke the most diverse, clever
people: London, Teller, Born, Pauli, Szilard, Weyl. The best response so far is from Pauli
who at least admits that the use of the word “state” [“Zustand”] for the psi-function is quite
disreputable. What I have so far seen by way of published reactions is less witty. … It is as if
one person said, “It is bitter cold in Chicago”; and another answered, “That is a fallacy, it is
very hot in Florida.” (Fine 1996, p. 74)

1.3 Einstein’s versions of the argument


If the argument developed in EPR has its roots in the 1930 Solvay conference, Einstein’s
own approach to issues at the heart of EPR has a history that goes back to the 1927 Solvay
conference. (Bacciagaluppi and Valentini 2009, pp. 198–202, would even trace it back to
1909 and the localization of light quanta.) At that 1927 conference Einstein made a short
presentation during the general discussion session where he focused on problems of
interpretation associated with the collapse of the wave function. He imagines a situation
where electrons pass through a small hole and are dispersed uniformly in the direction of a
screen of photographic film shaped into a large hemisphere that surrounds the hole. On the
supposition that quantum theory offers a complete account of individual processes then, in
the case of localization, why does the whole wave front collapse to just one single flash
point? It is as though at the moment of collapse an instantaneous signal were sent out from
the point of collapse to all other possible collapse positions telling them not to flash. Thus
Einstein maintains (Bacciagaluppi and Valentini 2009, p. 488),
the interpretation, according to which |ψ|² expresses the probability that this particle is found
at a given point, assumes an entirely peculiar mechanism of action at a distance, which
prevents the wave continuously distributed in space from producing an action in two places
on the screen.
One could see this as a tension between local action and the description afforded by the wave
function, since the wave function alone does not specify a unique position on the screen for
detecting the particle. Einstein continues,
In my opinion, one can remove this objection only in the following way, that one does not
describe the process solely by the Schrödinger wave, but that at the same time one localizes
the particle during propagation.
In fact Einstein himself had tried this very route in May of 1927 where he proposed a way of
“localizing the particle” by associating spatial trajectories and velocities with particle
solutions to the Schrödinger equation. (See Belousek 1996 and Holland 2005; also Ryckman
2017.) Einstein abandoned the project and withdrew the draft from publication, however,
after finding that certain intuitive independence conditions were in conflict with the product
wave function used by quantum mechanics to treat the composition of independent systems.
The problem here anticipates the more general issues raised by EPR over separability and
composite systems. This proposal was Einstein’s one and only flirtation with the introduction
of hidden variables into the quantum theory. In the following years he never embraced any
proposal of that sort, although he hoped for progress in physics to yield a more complete
theory, and one where the observer did not play a fundamental role. “We believe however
that such a theory [“a complete description of the physical reality”] is possible” (p. 780).
Commentators have often mistaken that remark as indicating Einstein’s predilection for
hidden variables. To the contrary, after 1927 Einstein regarded the hidden variables project
— the project of developing a more complete theory by starting with the existing quantum
theory and adding things, like trajectories or real states — an improbable route to that goal.
(See, for example, Einstein 1953a.) To improve on the quantum theory, he thought, would
require starting afresh with quite different fundamental concepts. At Solvay he acknowledges
Louis de Broglie’s pilot wave investigations as a possible direction to pursue for a more
complete account of individual processes. But then he quickly turns to an alternative way of
thinking, one that he continued to recommend as a better framework for progress, which is
not to regard the quantum theory as describing individuals and their processes at all and,
instead, to regard the theory as describing only ensembles of individuals. Einstein goes on to
suggest difficulties for any scheme, like de Broglie’s and like quantum theory itself, that
requires representations in multi-dimensional configuration space. These are difficulties that
might move one further toward regarding quantum theory as not aspiring to a description of
individual systems but as more amenable to an ensemble (or collective) point of view, and
hence not a good starting point for building a better, more complete theory. His subsequent
elaborations of EPR-like arguments are perhaps best regarded as no-go arguments, showing
that the existing quantum theory does not lend itself to a sensible realist interpretation via
hidden variables. If real states, taken as hidden variables, are added into the existing theory,
which is then tailored to explain individual events, the result is either an incomplete theory or
else a theory that does not respect locality. Hence, new concepts are needed. With respect to
EPR, perhaps the most important feature of Einstein’s reflections at Solvay 1927 is his
insight that a clash between completeness and locality already arises in considering a single
variable (there, position) and does not require an incompatible pair, as in EPR.
Following the publication of EPR Einstein set about almost immediately to provide clear and
focused versions of the argument. He began that process within few weeks of EPR, in the
June 19 letter to Schrödinger, and continued it in an article published the following year
(Einstein 1936). He returned to this particular form of an incompleteness argument in two
later publications (Einstein 1948 and Schilpp 1949). Although these expositions differ in
details they all employ composite systems as a way of implementing indirect measurements-
at-a-distance. None of Einstein’s accounts contains the Criterion of Reality nor the tortured
EPR argument over when values of a quantity can be regarded as “elements of reality”. The
Criterion and these “elements” simply drop out. Nor does Einstein engage in calculations,
like those of Podolsky, to fix the total wave function for the composite system explicitly.
Unlike EPR, none of Einstein’s arguments makes use of simultaneous values for
complementary quantities like position and momentum. He does not challenge the
uncertainty relations. Indeed with respect to assigning eigenstates for a complementary pair
he tells Schrödinger “ist mir wurst”—literally, it’s sausage to me; i.e., he couldn’t care less.
(Fine 1996, p. 38). These writings probe an incompatibility between affirming locality and
separability, on the one hand, and completeness in the description of individual systems by
means of state functions, on the other. His argument is that we can have at most one of these
but never both. He frequently refers to this dilemma as a “paradox”.
In the letter to Schrödinger of June 19, Einstein points to a simple argument for the dilemma
which, like the argument from the 1927 Solvay Conference, involves only the measurement
of a single variable. Consider an interaction between the Albert and Niels systems that
establishes a strict correlation between their positions. (We need not worry about momentum,
or any other quantity.) Consider the evolved wave function for the total (Albert+Niels)
system when the two systems are far apart. Now assume a principle of locality-separability
(Einstein calls it a Trennungsprinzip—separation principle): Whether a determinate physical
situation holds for Niels’ system (e.g., that a quantity has a particular value) does not depend
on what measurements (if any) are made locally on Albert’s system. If we measure the
position of Albert’s system, the strict correlation of positions implies that Niels’ system has a
certain position. By locality-separability it follows that Niels’ system must already have had
that position just before the measurement on Albert’s system. At that time, however, Niels’
system alone does not have a state function. There is only a state function for the combined
system and that total state function does not single out an existing position for Niels’ system
(i.e., it is not a product one of whose factors is an eigenstate for the position of Niels’
system). Thus the description of Niels’ system afforded by the quantum state function is
incomplete. A complete description would say (definitely yes) if a quantity of Niels’ system
had a certain value. (Notice that this argument does not even depend on the reduction of the
total state function for the combined system.) In this formulation of the argument it is clear
that locality-separability conflicts with the eigenvalue-eigenstate link, which holds that a
quantity of a system has a value if and only if the state of the system is an eigenstate (or a
proper mixture of eigenstates) of that quantity with that value as eigenvalue. The “only if”
part of the link would need to be weakened in order to interpret quantum state functions as
complete descriptions. (See the entry onModal Interpretations and see Gilton 2016 for a
history of the eigenvalue-eigenstate link.)
This argument rests on the ordinary and intuitive notion of completeness as not omitting
relevant truths. Thus, in the argument, the description given by the state function of a system
is judged incomplete when it fails to attribute a position to the system in circumstances
where the system indeed has a position. Although this simple argument concentrates on what
Einstein saw as the essentials, stripping away most technical details and distractions, he
frequently used another argument involving more than one quantity. (It is actually buried in
the EPR paper, p. 779, and a version also occurs in the June 19, 1935 letter to Schrödinger.
Harrigan and Spekkens, 2010 suggest reasons for preferring a many-variables argument.)
This second argument focuses clearly on the interpretation of quantum state functions in
terms of “real states” of a system, and not on any issues about simultaneous values (real or
not) for complementary quantities. It goes like this.
Suppose, as in EPR, that the interaction between the two systems links position and also
linear momentum, and that the systems are far apart. As before, we can measure either the
position or the momentum of Albert’s system and, in either case, we can infer (respectively)
a position or a momentum for Niels’ system. It follows from the reduction of the total state
function that, depending on whether we measure the position or the momentum of Albert’s
system, Niels’ system will be left (respectively) either in a position eigenstate or in a
momentum eigenstate. Suppose too that separability holds, so that Niels’ system has some
real physical state of affairs. If locality holds as well, then the measurement of Albert’s
system does not disturb the assumed “reality” for Niels’ system. However, that reality
appears to be represented by quite different state functions, depending on which
measurement of Albert’s system one chooses to carry out. If we understand a “complete
description” to rule out that one and the same physical state can be described by state
functions with distinct physical implications, then we can conclude that the quantum
mechanical description is incomplete. Here again we confront a dilemma between
separability-locality and completeness. Many years later Einstein put it this way (Schilpp
1949, p. 682);
[T]he paradox forces us to relinquish one of the following two assertions:
(1) the description by means of the psi-function is complete
(2) the real states of spatially separate objects are independent of each other.
It appears that the central point of EPR was to argue that any interpretation of quantum state
functions that attributes real physical states to systems faces these alternatives. It also appears
that Einstein’s different arguments make use of different notions of completeness. In the first
argument completeness is an ordinary notion that amounts to not leaving out any relevant
details. In the second, completeness is a technical notion which has been dubbed “bijective
completeness“ (Fine 1996 ): no more than one quantum state should correspond to a real
state. These notions are connected. If completeness fails in the bijective sense, and more than
one quantum state corresponds to some real state, we can argue that the ordinary notion of
completeness also fails. For distinct quantum states will differ in the values they assign to
certain quantities. (For example, the observable corresponding to the projector on a state
takes value 1 in one case but not in the other.) Hence each will omit something that the other
affirms, so completeness in the ordinary sense will fail. Put differently, ordinary
completeness implies bijective completeness. (The converse is not true. Even if the
correspondence of quantum states to real states were one-to-one, the description afforded by
a quantum state might still leave out some physically relevant fact about its corresponding
real state.) Thus a dilemma between locality and “completeness“ in Einstein’s versions of the
argument still implicates ordinary completeness. For if locality holds, then his two-variable
argument shows that bijective completeness fails, and then completeness in the ordinary
sense fails as well.
As we have seen, in framing his own EPR-like arguments for the incompleteness of quantum
theory, Einstein makes use of separability and locality, which are also tacitly assumed in the
EPR paper. Using the language of “independent existence“ he presents these ideas clearly in
an article that he sent to Max Born (Einstein 1948).
It is … characteristic of … physical objects that they are thought of as arranged in a space-
time continuum. An essential aspect of this arrangement … is that they lay claim, at a certain
time, to an existence independent of one another, provided these objects “are situated in
different parts of space”. … The following idea characterizes the relative independence of
objects (A and B) far apart in space: external influence on A has no direct influence on B.
(Born, 1971, pp. 170–71)
In the course of his correspondence with Schrödinger, however, Einstein realized that
assumptions about separability and locality were not necessary in order to get the
incompleteness conclusion that he was after; i.e., to show that state functions may not
provide a complete description of the real state of affairs with respect to a system.
Separability supposes that there is a real state of affairs and locality supposes that one cannot
influence it immediately by acting at a distance. What Einstein realized was that separability
was already part of the ordinary conception of a macroscopic object. This suggested to him
that if one looks at the local interaction of a macro-system with a micro-system one could
avoid having to assume either separability or locality in order to conclude that the quantum
description of the whole was incomplete with respect to its macroscopic part.
This line of thought evolves and dominates over problems with composite systems and
locality in his last published reflections on incompleteness. Instead he focuses on problems
with the stability of macro-descriptions in the transition to a classical level from the
quantum.
the objective describability of individual macro-systems (description of the “real-state”) can
not be renounced without the physical picture of the world, so to speak, decomposing into a
fog. (Einstein 1953b, p. 40. See also Einstein 1953a.)
In the August 8, 1935 letter to Schrödinger Einstein says that he will illustrate the problem
by means of a “crude macroscopic example”.
The system is a substance in chemically unstable equilibrium, perhaps a charge of
gunpowder that, by means of intrinsic forces, can spontaneously combust, and where the
average life span of the whole setup is a year. In principle this can quite easily be represented
quantum-mechanically. In the beginning the psi-function characterizes a reasonably well-
defined macroscopic state. But, according to your equation [i.e., the Schrödinger equation],
after the course of a year this is no longer the case. Rather, the psi-function then describes a
sort of blend of not-yet and already-exploded systems. Through no art of interpretation can
this psi-function be turned into an adequate description of a real state of affairs; in reality
there is no intermediary between exploded and not-exploded. (Fine 1996, p. 78)
The point is that after a year either the gunpowder will have exploded, or not. (This is the
“real state” which in the EPR situation requires one to assume separability.) The state
function, however, will have evolved into a complex superposition over these two
alternatives. Provided we maintain the eigenvalue-eigenstate link, the quantum description
by means of that state function will yield neither conclusion, and hence the quantum
description is incomplete. For a contemporary response to this line of argument, one might
look to the program of decoherence. (See Decoherence.) That program points to interactions
with the environment which may quickly reduce the likelihood of any interference between
the “exploded” and the “not-exploded” branches of the evolved psi-function. Then, breaking
the eigenvalue-eigenstate link, decoherence adopts a perspective according to which the
(almost) non-interfering branches of the psi-function allow that the gunpowder is indeed
either exploded or not. Even so, decoherence fails to identify which alternative is actually
realized, leaving the quantum description still incomplete. Such decoherence-based
interpretations of the psi-function are certainly “artful”, and their adequacy is still under
debate (see Schlosshauer 2007, especially Chapter 8).
The reader may recognize the similarity between Einstein’s exploding gunpowder
example and Schrödinger’s cat (Schrödinger 1935a, p. 812). In the case of the cat an unstable
atom is hooked up to a lethal device that, after an hour, is as likely to poison (and kill) the cat
as not, depending on whether the atom decays. After an hour the cat is either alive or dead,
but the quantum state of the whole atom-poison-cat system at this time is a superposition
involving the two possibilities and, just as in the case of the gunpowder, is not a complete
description of the situation (life or death) of the cat. The similarity between the gunpowder
and the cat is hardly accidental since Schrödinger first produced the cat example in his reply
of September 19, 1935 to Einstein’s August 8 gunpowder letter. There Schrödinger says that
he has himself constructed “an example very similar to your exploding powder keg”, and
proceeds to outline the cat (Fine 1996, pp. 82–83). Although the “cat paradox” is usually
cited in connection with the problem of quantum measurement (see the relevant section of
the entry on Philosophical Issues in Quantum Theory) and treated as a paradox separate from
EPR, its origin is here as an argument for incompleteness that avoids the twin assumptions of
separability and locality. Schrödinger’s development of “entanglement”, the term he
introduced for the correlations that result when quantum systems interact, also began in this
correspondence over EPR — along with a treatment of what he called quantum “steering”
(Schrödinger 1935a, 1935b; see Quantum Entanglement and Information).

2. A popular form of the argument: Bohr’s


response
The literature surrounding EPR contains yet another version of the argument, a popular
version that—unlike any of Einstein’s—features the Criterion of Reality. Assume again an
interaction between our two systems linking their positions and their linear momenta and
suppose that the systems are far apart. If we measure the position of Albert’s system, we can
infer that Niels’ system has a corresponding position. We can also predict it with certainty,
given the result of the position measurement of Albert’s system. Hence, in this version, the
Criterion of Reality is taken to imply that the position of Niels’ system constitutes an element
of reality. Similarly, if we measure the momentum of Albert’s system, we can conclude that
the momentum of Niels’ system is an element of reality. The argument now concludes that
since we can choose freely to measure either position or momentum, it “follows” that both
must be elements of reality simultaneously.
Of course no such conclusion follows from our freedom of choice. It is not sufficient to be
able to choose at will which quantity to measure; for the conclusion to follow from the
Criterion alone one would need to be able to measure both quantities at once. This is
precisely the point that Einstein recognized in his 1932 letter to Ehrenfest and that EPR
addresses by assuming locality and separability. What is striking about this version is that
these principles, central to the original EPR argument and to the dilemma at the heart of
Einstein’s versions, are obscured here. Instead this version features the Criterion and those
“elements of reality”. Perhaps the difficulties presented by Podolsky’s text contribute to this
reading. In any case, in the physics literature this version is commonly taken to represent
EPR and usually attributed to Einstein. This reading certainly has a prominent source in
terms of which one can understand its popularity among physicists; it is Niels Bohr himself.
By the time of the EPR paper many of the early interpretive battles over the quantum theory
had been settled, at least to the satisfaction of working physicists. Bohr had emerged as the
“philosopher” of the new theory and the community of quantum theorists, busy with the
development and extension of the theory, were content to follow Bohr’s leadership when it
came to explaining and defending its conceptual underpinnings (Beller 1999, Chapter 13).
Thus in 1935 the burden fell to Bohr to explain what was wrong with the EPR “paradox”.
The major article that he wrote in discharging this burden (Bohr 1935a) became the canon
for how to respond to EPR. Unfortunately, Bohr’s summary of EPR in that article, which is
the version just above, also became the canon for what EPR contained by way of argument.
Bohr’s response to EPR begins, as do many of his treatments of the conceptual issues raised
by the quantum theory, with a discussion of limitations on the simultaneous determination of
position and momentum. As usual, these are drawn from an analysis of the possibilities of
measurement if one uses an apparatus consisting of a diaphragm connected to a rigid frame.
Bohr emphasizes that the question is to what extent can we trace the interaction between the
particle being measured and the measuring instrument. (See Beller 1999, Chapter 7 for a
detailed analysis and discussion of the “two voices” contained in Bohr’s account. See too
Bacciagaluppi 2015.) Following the summary of EPR, Bohr (1935a, p. 700) then focuses on
the Criterion of Reality which, he says, “contains an ambiguity as regards the meaning of the
expression ‘without in any way disturbing a system’.” Bohr agrees that in the indirect
measurement of Niels’ system achieved when one makes a measurement of Albert’s system
“there is no question of a mechanical disturbance” of Niels’ system. Still, Bohr claims that a
measurement on Albert’s system does involve “an influence on the very conditions which
define the possible types of predictions regarding the future behavior of [Niels’] system.”
The meaning of this claim is not at all clear. Indeed, in revisiting EPR fifteen years later,
Bohr would comment,
Rereading these passages, I am deeply aware of the inefficiency of expression which must
have made it very difficult to appreciate the trend of the argumentation (Bohr 1949, p. 234).
Unfortunately, Bohr takes no notice there of Einstein’s later versions of the argument and
merely repeats his earlier response to EPR. In that response, however inefficiently, Bohr
appears to be directing attention to the fact that when we measure, for example, the position
of Albert’s system conditions are in place for predicting the position of Niels’ system but not
its momentum. The opposite would be true in measuring the momentum of Albert’s system.
Thus his “possible types of predictions” concerning Niels’ system appear to correspond to
which variable we measure on Albert’s system. Bohr proposes then to block the EPR
Criterion by counting, say, the position measurement of Albert’s system as an “influence” on
the distant system of Niels. If we assume it is an influence that disturbs Niels’ system, then
the Criterion could not be used, as in Bohr’s version of the argument, in producing an
element of reality for Niels’ system that challenges completeness.
There are two important things to notice about this response. The first is this. In conceding
that Einstein’s indirect method for determining, say, the position of Niels’ system does not
mechanically disturb that system, Bohr departs from his original program of
complementarity, which was to base the uncertainty relations and the statistical character of
quantum theory on uncontrollable physical interactions, interactions that were supposed to
arise inevitably between a measuring instrument and the system being measured. Instead
Bohr now distinguishes between a genuine physical interaction (his “mechanical
disturbance”) and some other sort of “influence” on the conditions for specifying (or
“defining”) sorts of predictions for the future behavior of a system. In emphasizing that there
is no question of a robust interaction in the EPR situation, Bohr retreats from his earlier,
physically grounded conception of complementarity.
The second important thing to notice is how Bohr’s response needs to be implemented in
order to block the argument of EPR and Einstein’s later arguments that pose a dilemma
between principles of locality and completeness. In these arguments the locality principle
makes explicit reference to the reality of the unmeasured system: the reality pertaining to
Niels’ system does not depend on what measurements (if any) are made locally on Albert’s
system. Hence Bohr’s suggestion that those measurements influence conditions for
specifying types of predictions would not affect the argument unless one includes those
conditions as part of the reality of Niels’ system. This is exactly what Bohr goes on to say,
“these conditions constitute an inherent element of the description of any phenomena to
which the term ‘physical reality’ can be properly attached” (Bohr 1935a, p. 700). So Bohr’s
picture is that these “influences”, operating directly across any spatial distances, result in
different physically real states of Niels’ system depending on the type of measurement made
on Albert’s. (Recall EPR warning against just this move.)
The quantum formalism for interacting systems describes how a measurement on Albert’s
system reduces the composite state and distributes quantum states and associated
probabilities to the component systems. Here Bohr redescribes that formal reduction using
EPR’s language of influences and reality. He turns ordinary local measurements into
“influences” that automatically change physical reality elsewhere, and at any distance
whatsoever. This grounds the quantum formalism in a rather magical ontological framework,
a move quite out of character for the usually pragmatic Bohr. In his correspondence over
EPR, Schrödinger compared ideas like that to ritual magic.
This assumption arises from the standpoint of the savage, who believes that he can harm his
enemy by piercing the enemy’s image with a needle. (Letter to Edward Teller, June 14, 1935,
quoted in Bacciagaluppi 2015)
It is as though EPR’s talk of “reality” and its elements provoked Bohr to adopt the position
of Moliere’s doctor who, pressed to explain why opium is a sedative, invents an inherent
dormative virtue, “which causes the senses to become drowsy.” Usually Bohr sharply
deflates any attempt like this to get behind the formalism, insisting that “the appropriate
physical interpretation of the symbolic quantum-mechanical formalism amounts only to
predictions, of determinate or statistical character” (Bohr 1949, p. 238).
Could this portrait of nonlocal influences automatically shaping a distant reality be a by-
product of Bohr’s “inefficiency of expression”? Despite Bohr’s seeming tolerance for a
breakdown of locality in his response here to EPR, in other places Bohr rejects nonlocality in
the strongest terms. For example in discussing an electron double slit experiment, which is
Bohr’s favorite model for illustrating the novel conceptual features of quantum theory, and
writing only weeks before the publication of EPR, Bohr argues as follows.
If we only imagine the possibility that without disturbing the phenomena we determine
through which hole the electron passes, we would truly find ourselves in irrational territory,
for this would put us in a situation in which an electron, which might be said to pass through
this hole, would be affected by the circumstance of whether this [other] hole was open or
closed; but … it is completely incomprehensible that in its later course [the electron] should
let itself be influenced by this hole down there being open or shut. (Bohr 1935b)
It is uncanny how closely Bohr’s language mirrors that of EPR. But here Bohr defends
locality and regards the very contemplation of nonlocality as “irrational” and “completely
incomprehensible”. Since “the circumstance of whether this [other] hole was open or closed”
does affect the possible types of predictions regarding the electron’s future behavior, if we
expand the concept of the electron’s “reality”, as he appears to suggest for EPR, by including
such information, we do “disturb” the electron around one hole by opening or closing the
other hole. That is, if we give to “disturb” and to “reality” the very same sense that Bohr
appears to give them when responding to EPR, then we are led to an “incomprehensible”
nonlocality, and into the territory of the irrational (like Schrödinger’s savage).
There is another way of trying to understand Bohr’s position. According to one common
reading (see Copenhagen Interpretation), after EPR Bohr embraced a relational (or
contextual) account of property attribution. On this account to speak of the position, say, of a
system presupposes that one already has put in place an appropriate interaction involving an
apparatus for measuring position (or at least an appropriate frame of reference for the
measurement; Dickson 2004). Thus “the position” of the system refers to a relation between
the system and the measuring device (or measurement frame). (See Relational Quantum
Mechanics, where a similar idea is developed independently of measurements.) In the EPR
context this would seem to imply that before one is set up to measure the position of Albert’s
system, talk of the position of Niels’ system is out of place; whereas after one measures the
position of Albert’s system, talk of the position of Niels’ system is appropriate and, indeed,
we can then say truly that Niels’ system “has” a position. Similar considerations govern
momentum measurements. It follows, then, that local manipulations carried out on Albert’s
system, in a place we may assume to be far removed from Niels’ system, can directly affect
what is meaningful to say about, as well as factually true of, Niels’ system. Similarly, in the
double slit arrangement, it would follow that what can be said meaningfully and said truly
about the position of the electron around the top hole would depend on the context of
whether the bottom hole is open or shut. One might suggest that such relational actions-at-a-
distance are harmless ones, perhaps merely “semantic”; like becoming the “best” at a task
when your only competitor—who might be miles away—fails. Note, however, that in the
case of ordinary relational predicates it is not inappropriate (or “meaningless”) to talk about
the situation in the absence of complete information about the relata. So you might be the
best at a task even if your competitor has not yet tried it, and you are definitely not an aunt
(or uncle) until one of your siblings gives birth. But should we say that an electron is
nowhere at all until we are set up to measure its position, or would it be inappropriate
(meaningless?) even to ask?
If quantum predicates are relational, they are different from many ordinary relations in that
the conditions for the relata are taken as criterial for the application of the term. In this regard
one might contrast the relativity of simultaneity with the proposed relativity of position. In
relativistic physics specifying a world-line fixes a frame of reference for attributions of
simultaneity to events regardless of whether any temporal measurements are being made or
contemplated. But in the quantum case, on this proposal, specifying a frame of reference for
position (say, the laboratory frame) does not entitle one to attribute position to a system,
unless that frame is associated with actually preparing or completing a measurement of
position for that system. To be sure, analyzing predicates in terms of occurrent measurement
or observation is familiar from neopositivist approaches to the language of science; for
example, in Percy Bridgman’s operational analysis of physical terms, where the actual
applications of test-response pairs constitute criteria for any meaningful use of a term
(see Theory and Observation in Science ). Rudolph Carnap’s later introduction of reduction
sentences (see the entry on the Vienna Circle) has a similar character. Still, this positivist
reading entails just the sort of nonlocality that Bohr seemed to abhor.
In the light of all this it is difficult to know whether a coherent response can be attributed to
Bohr reliably that would derail EPR. (In different ways, Dickson 2004 and Halvorson and
Clifton 2004 make an attempt on Bohr’s behalf. These are examined in Whitaker 2004 and
Fine 2007. See also the essays in Faye and Folse 2017.) Bohr may well have been aware of
the difficulty in framing the appropriate concepts clearly when, a few years after EPR, he
wrote,
The unaccustomed features of the situation with which we are confronted in quantum theory
necessitate the greatest caution as regard all questions of terminology. Speaking, as it is often
done of disturbing a phenomenon by observation, or even of creating physical attributes to
objects by measuring processes is liable to be confusing, since all such sentences imply a
departure from conventions of basic language which even though it can be practical for the
sake of brevity, can never be unambiguous. (Bohr 1939, p. 320. Quoted in Section 3.2 of the
entry on the Uncertainty Principle.)

3. Development of EPR
3.1 Spin and The Bohm version
For about fifteen years following its publication, the EPR paradox was discussed at the level
of a thought experiment whenever the conceptual difficulties of quantum theory became an
issue. In 1951 David Bohm, a protégé of Robert Oppenheimer and then an untenured
Assistant Professor at Princeton University, published a textbook on the quantum theory in
which he took a close look at EPR in order to develop a response in the spirit of Bohr. Bohm
showed how one could mirror the conceptual situation in the EPR thought experiment by
looking at the dissociation of a diatomic molecule whose total spin angular momentum is
(and remains) zero; for instance, the dissociation of an excited hydrogen molecule into a pair
of hydrogen atoms by means of a process that does not change an initially zero total angular
momentum (Bohm 1951, Sections 22.15–22.18). In the Bohm experiment the atomic
fragments separate after interaction, flying off in different directions freely to separate
experimental wings. Subsequently, in each wing, measurements are made of spin
components (which here take the place of position and momentum), whose measured values
would be anti-correlated after dissociation. In the so-called singlet state of the atomic pair,
the state after dissociation, if one atom’s spin is found to be positive with respect to the
orientation of an axis perpendicular to its flight path, the other atom would be found to have
a negative spin with respect to a perpendicular axis with the same orientation. Like the
operators for position and momentum, spin operators for different non-orthogonal
orientations do not commute. Moreover, in the experiment outlined by Bohm, the atomic
fragments can move to wings far apart from one another and so become appropriate objects
for assumptions that restrict the effects of purely local actions. Thus Bohm’s experiment
mirrors the entangled correlations in EPR for spatially separated systems, allowing for
similar arguments and conclusions involving locality, separability, and completeness. Indeed,
a late note of Einstein’s, that may have been prompted by Bohm’s treatment, contains a very
sketchy spin version of the EPR argument – once again pitting completeness against locality
(“A coupling of distant things is excluded.” Sauer 2007, p. 882). Following Bohm (1951) a
paper by Bohm and Aharonov (1957) went on to outline the machinery for a plausible
experiment in which entangled spin correlations could be tested. It has become customary to
refer to experimental arrangements involving determinations of spin components for spatially
separated systems, and to a variety of similar set-ups (especially ones for measuring photon
polarization), as “EPRB” experiments—“B” for Bohm. Because of technical difficulties in
creating and monitoring the atomic fragments, however, there seem to have been no
immediate attempts to perform a Bohm version of EPR.

3.2 Bell and beyond


That was to remain the situation for almost another fifteen years, until John Bell utilized the
EPRB set-up to construct a stunning argument, at least as challenging as EPR, but to a
different conclusion (Bell 1964). Bell considers correlations between measurement outcomes
for systems in separate wings where the measurement axes of the systems differ by angles set
locally. In his original paper, essentially using the lemma from EPR governing strict
correlations, Bell shows that correlations measured in different runs of an EPRB experiment
satisfy a system of constraints, known as the Bell inequalities. Later demonstrations by Bell
and others, using related assumptions, extend this class of inequalities. In certain of these
EPRB experiments, however, quantum theory predicts correlations that violate particular
Bell inequalities by an experimentally significant amount. Thus Bell shows (see the entry
on Bell’s Theorem) that the quantum statistics are inconsistent with the given assumptions.
Prominent among these is an assumption of locality, similar to the locality assumptions
tacitly assumed in EPR and (explicitly) in the one-variable and many-variable arguments of
Einstein. One important difference is that for Einstein locality restricts factors that might
influence the (assumed) real physical states of spatially separated systems (separability). For
Bell, locality is focused instead on factors that might influence outcomes of measurements in
experiments where both systems are measured. (See Fine 1996, Chapter 4.) These
differences are not usually attended to and Bell’s theorem is often characterized simply as
showing that quantum theory is nonlocal. Even so, since assumptions other then locality are
needed in any derivation of the Bell inequalities (roughly, assumptions guaranteeing a
classical representation of the quantum probabilities; see Fine 1982a, and Malley 2004), one
should be cautious about singling out locality (in Bell’s sense, or Einstein’s) as necessarily in
conflict with the quantum theory, or refuted by experiment.
Bell’s results have been explored and deepened by various theoretical investigations and they
have stimulated a number of increasingly sophisticated and delicate EPRB-type experiments
designed to test whether the Bell inequalities hold where quantum theory predicts they
should fail. With a few anomalous exceptions, the experiments appear to confirm the
quantum violations of the inequalities. (Brunner et al 2014 is a comprehensive technical
review.) The confirmation is quantitatively impressive, although not fully conclusive. There
are a number of significant requirements on the experiments whose failures (generally
downplayed as “loopholes”) allow for models of the experimental data that embody locality
(in Bell’s sense), so-called local realist models. One family of “loopholes” (sampling) arises
from possible losses (inefficiency) between emission and detection and from the delicate
coincidence timing required to compute correlations. All the early experiments to test the
Bell inequalities were subject to this loophole, so all could be modeled locally and
realistically. (The prism and synchronization models in Fine 1982b are early models of this
sort. Larsson 2014 is a general review.) Another “loophole” (locality) concerns whether
Niels’ system, in one wing, could learn about what measurements are set to be performed in
Albert’s wing in time to adjust its behavior. Experiments insuring locality need to separate
the wings and this can allow losses or timing glitches that open them to models exploiting
sampling error. Perversely, experiments to address sampling may require the wings to be
fairly close together, close enough generally, it turns out, to allow information sharing and
hence local realist models. There are now a few experiments that claim to close both
loopholes together. They too have problems. (See Bednorz 2017 for a critical discussion.)
There is also a third major complication or “loophole”. It arises from the need to ensure that
causal factors affecting measurement outcomes are not correlated with the choices of
measurement settings. Known as “measurement independence” or sometimes “free choice”,
it turns out that even statistically small violations of this independence requirement allow for
local realism (Putz and Gisin 2016). Since connections between outcomes and settings might
occur anywhere in the causal past of the experiment, there is really no way to insure
measurement independence completely. Suitably random choices of settings might avoid this
loophole within the time frame of the experiment, or even extend that time some years into
the past. An impressive, recent experiment pushes the time frame back about six hundred
years by using the color of Milky Way starlight (blue or red photons) to choose the
measurement settings. (Handsteiner et al 2017). Of course traveling between the Milky Way
and the detectors in Vienna a lot of starlight is lost (over seventy per cent), which leaves the
experiment wide open to the sampling loophole. Moreover, there is an obvious common
cause for settings and outcomes (and all); namely, the big bang. With that in mind one might
be inclined to dismiss free choice as not serious even for a “loophole”. It may seem like
an ad hoc hypothesis that postulates a cosmic conspiracy on the part of Nature just to the
save the Bell inequalities. Note, however, that ordinary inefficiency can also be modeled
locally as a violation of free choice, because an individual measurement that produces no
usable result can just as well be regarded as not currently available. Since inefficiency is not
generally counted as a violation of local causality or a restriction on free will, nor as a
conspiracy (well, not a cosmic one), measurement dependence should not be dismissed so
quickly. Instead, one might see measurement dependent correlations as normal limitations in
a system subject to dynamical constraints or boundary conditions, and thus use them as clues,
along with other guideposts, in searching for a covering local theory. (See Weinstein 2009.)
Experimental tests of the Bell inequalities continue to be refined. Their analysis is delicate,
employing sophisticated statistical models and simulations. (See Elkouss and Wehner 2016
and Graft 2016.) The significance of the tests remains a lively area for critical discussion.
Meanwhile the techniques developed in the experiments, and related ideas for utilizing the
entanglement associated with EPRB-type interactions, have become important in their own
right. These techniques and ideas, stemming from EPRB and the Bell theorem, have
applications now being advanced in the field of quantum information theory — which
includes quantum cryptography, teleportation and computing (see Quantum Entanglement
and Information).
To go back to the EPR dilemma between locality and completeness, it would appear from the
Bell theorem that Einstein’s preference for locality at the expense of completeness may have
fixed on the wrong horn. Even though the Bell theorem does not rule out locality conditions
conclusively, it should certainly make one wary of assuming them. On the other hand, since
Einstein’s exploding gunpowder argument (or Schrödinger’s cat), along with his later
arguments over macro-systems, support incompleteness without assuming locality, one
should be wary of adopting the other horn of the dilemma, affirming that the quantum state
descriptions are complete and “therefore” that the theory is nonlocal. It may well turn out
that both horns need to be rejected: that the state functions do not provide a complete
description and that the theory is also nonlocal (although possibly still separable; see
Winsberg and Fine 2003). There is at least one well-known approach to the quantum theory
that makes a choice of this sort, the de Broglie-Bohm approach (Bohmian Mechanics). Of
course it may also be possible to break the EPR argument for the dilemma plausibly by
questioning some of its other assumptions (e.g., separability, the reduction postulate,
the eigenvalue-eigenstate link, or measurement independence). That might free up the
remaining option, to regard the theory as both local and complete. Perhaps some version of
the Everett Interpretation would come to occupy this branch of the interpretive tree, or
perhaps Relational Quantum Mechanics.

Bibliography
 Bacciagaluppi, G., 2015, “Did Bohr understand EPR?” in F. Aaserud and H. Kragh
(eds.), One Hundred Years of the Bohr Atom (Scientia Danica, Series M, Mathematica et
physica, Volume 1), Copenhagen: Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters, pp. 377–
396.
 Bacciagaluppi, G. and A. Valentini, 2009, Quantum Theory at the Crossroads:
Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 Bednorz, A., 2017, “Analysis of assumptions of recent tests of local realism”, Physical
Review A, 95: 042118.
 Bell, J. S., 1964, “On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox”, Physics, 1: 195–200, reprinted
in Bell 1987.
 –––, 1987, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, New York: Cambridge
University Press.
 Beller, M., 1999, Quantum Dialogue: The Making of a Revolution, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
 Belousek, D. W., 1996, “Einstein’s 1927 unpublished hidden-variable theory: its
background, context and significance”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern
Physics, 27: 437–461.
 Bohm, D., 1951, Quantum Theory, New York: Prentice Hall.
 Bohm, D., and Y. Aharonov, 1957, “Discussion of experimental proof for the paradox of
Einstein, Rosen and Podolski”, Physical Review, 108: 1070–1076.
 Bohr, N., 1935a, “Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered
complete?”, Physical Review, 48: 696–702.
 –––, 1935b, “Space and time in nuclear physics”, Ms. 14, March 21, Manuscript Collection,
Archive for the History of Quantum Physics, American Philosophical Society, Philadelphia.
 –––, 1939, “The causality problem in atomic physics” in Bohr, 1996, pp. 303–322.
 –––, 1949, “Discussions with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics” in
Schilpp, 1949, pp. 199–241. Reprinted in Bohr, 1996, pp. 339–381.
 –––, 1996, Collected Works, Vol. 7, Amsterdam: North Holland.
 Born, M., (ed.), 1971, The Born-Einstein Letters, New York: Walker.
 Brunner, N. et al., 2014, “Bell nonlocality”, Reviews of Modern Physics, 86: 419–478.
 Dickson, M., 2004, “Quantum reference frames in the context of EPR”, Philosophy of
Science, 71: 655–668.
 Einstein, A. 1936, “Physik und Realität”, Journal of the Franklin Institute, 221: 313–347,
reprinted in translation in Einstein 1954.
 –––, 1948, “ Quanten-Mechanik und Wirklichkeit ”, Dialectica, 2: 320–324. Translated in
Born 1971, pp. 168–173.
 –––, 1953a, “Einleitende Bemerkungen über Grundbegriffe ”, in A. George, ed., Louis de
Broglie: Physicien et penseur, Paris: Editions Albin Michel, pp. 5–15.
 –––, 1953b, “Elementare Überlegungen zur Interpretation der Grundlagen der Quanten-
Mechanik ”, in Scientific Papers Presented to Max Born, New York: Hafner, pp. 33–40.
 –––, 1954, Ideas and Opinions, New York: Crown.
 Einstein, A., B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, 1935, “Can quantum-mechanical description of
physical reality be considered complete?”, Physical Review, 47: 777–780 [available online].
 Elkouss, D and S. Wehner, 2016, “ (Nearly) optimal P values for all Bell inequalities ”, NPJ
Quantum Information, 2: 16026.
 Faye, J. and H. Folse, 2017, Niels Bohr and the Philosophy of Physics, London: Bloomsbury
Academic.
 Fine, A., 1996, The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory, 2nd Edition,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
 –––, 1982a, “Hidden variables, joint probability and the Bell inequalities”, Physical Review
Letters, 48: 291–295.
 –––, 1982b, “Some local models for correlation experiments”, Synthese 50: 279–94.
 –––, 2007, “Bohr’s response to EPR: Criticism and defense”, Iyyun, The Jerusalem
Philosophical Quarterly, 56: 31–56.
 Gilton, M. J. R., 2016, “Whence the eigenstate-eigenvalue link?”, Studies in History and
Philosophy of Modern Physics, 55: 92–100.
 Graft, D. A., 2016, “ Clauser-Horne/Eberhard inequality violation by a local
model”, Advanced Science, Engineering and Medicine, 8: 496–502.
 Halvorson, H., 2000, “The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen state maximally violates Bell’s
inequality”,Letters in Mathematical Physics, 53: 321–329.
 Halvorson, H. and R. Clifton, 2004, “Reconsidering Bohr’s reply to EPR.” In J. Butterfield
and H. Halvorson, eds., Quantum Entanglements: Selected Papers of Rob Clifton, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 369–393.
 Handsteiner, J. et al , 2017, “ Cosmic Bell test: Measurement settings from Milky Way
stars”, Physical Review Letters, 118: 060401.
 Harrigan, N. and R. W., Spekkens, 2010, “Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view
of quantum states”, Foundations of Physics, 40: 125–157.
 Held, C., 1998, Die Bohr-Einstein-Debatte: Quantenmechanik und Physikalische
Wirklichkeit, Paderborn: Schöningh.
 Holland, P., 2005, “What’s wrong with Einstein’s 1927 hidden-variable interpretation of
quantum mechanics?”, Foundations of Physics, 35: 177–196.
 Hooker, C. A., 1972, “The nature of quantum mechanical reality: Einstein versus Bohr”, in
R. G. Colodny, ed., Paradigms and Paradoxes, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press,
pp. 67–302.
 Howard, D., 1985, “Einstein on locality and separability.” Studies in History and Philosophy
of Science 16: 171–201.
 Howard, D., 1990, “‘Nicht Sein Kann Was Nicht Sein Darf’, or the Prehistory of EPR, 1909–
1935”, in A. I. Miller (ed.), Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty, New York: Plenum Press, pp.
61–111.
 Jammer, M., 1974, The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics, New York: Wiley.
 Larsson, J.-A., 2014, “Loopholes in Bell inequality tests of local realism”, Journal of Physics
A, 47: 424003.
 Malley, J., 2004, “All Quantum observables in a hidden-variable model must commute
simultaneously”, Physical Review A, 69 (022118): 1–3.
 Putz, G. and N. Gisin, 2016, “Measurement dependent locality”, New Journal of Physics, 18:
05506.
 Ryckman, T., 2017, Einstein, New York and London: Routledge.
 Sauer, T., 2007, “An Einstein manuscript on the EPR paradox for spin observables”, Studies
in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38: 879–887.
 Schilpp, P.A., (ed.), 1949, Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, La Salle, IL: Open Court.
 Schlosshauer, M., 2007, Decoherence and the Quantum-to-Classical Transition,
Heidelberg/Berlin: Springer.
 Schrödinger, E., 1935a, “Die gegenwärtige Situation in der
Quantenmechanik”, Naturwissenschaften, 23: 807–812, 823–828, 844–849; English
translation in Trimmer, 1980.
 –––, 1935b, “Discussion of probability relations between separated systems”, Proceedings of
the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 31: 555–562.
 Trimmer, J. D., 1980, “The present situation in quantum mechanics: A translation of
Schrödinger’s ‘cat paradox’ paper”, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 124:
323–338
 Weinstein, S. 2009, “Nonlocality without nonlocality”, Foundations of Physics, 39: 921–936.
 Whitaker, M. A. B., 2004, “The EPR Paper and Bohr’s response: A re-
assessment”, Foundations of Physics, 34: 1305–1340.
 Winsberg, E., and A. Fine, 2003, “Quantum life: Interaction, entanglement and
separation”, Journal of Philosophy, C: 80–97.

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources


 Einstein on Line, maintained by S. Morgan Friedman.
 Niels Bohr Archive, website of the Niels Bohr Archive, supported by the Ministry of
Science, Technology and Innovation, Denmark.
 The Present Situation in Quantum Mechanics, by Erwin Schrödinger, translation by
John D. Trimmer.
 Discussions with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics, by Niels
Bohr.
Related Entries
Bell’s Theorem | Einstein, Albert: philosophy of science | quantum mechanics: action at a
distance in | quantum mechanics: Bohmian mechanics | quantum mechanics: Copenhagen
interpretation of |quantum mechanics: Everett’s relative-state formulation of | quantum
mechanics: modal interpretations of | quantum mechanics: relational | quantum mechanics:
the role of decoherence in |quantum theory: philosophical issues in | quantum theory:
quantum entanglement and information |Uncertainty Principle

You might also like