Helm On Beckwith On The Trinity

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

350

Of God, and of the Holy Trinity:


A Response to Dr. Beckwith
Paul Helm

Although it may be claimed that the doctrine of the Trinity is present in an


anticipatory form in the Old Testament, all that we know of the Trinity in
its developed form comes to us from the New Testament, where the work
of the Father, Son and Holy Spirit in our salvation is revealed, most notably
in the Gospel of John. We learn there that he who was in the beginning
with God and who was God became flesh for our salvation (John 1:14),
and that he (and the Father) have sent the Spirit, another Comforter, to
dwell with the church (John 14:26, 15:26). The doctrine of the Trinity as it
is to be found in the credal and conciliar statements of the church is a set of
inferences drawn from such data the basic purpose of which is not to reveal
God as he is in himself but which record how he is revealed to us in the
economy of salvation.

The Nicene formulation of the Trinity (A.D. 325) states that the Son of God
is eternally begotten of the Father, God from God, and confesses belief in the
Holy Spirit. The Athanasian Creed (c. A.D. 500) (never formally adopted)
refers to the Holy Ghost’s proceeding from the Father and the Son. The
Constantinopolitan Creed (A.D. 381) refers to the Holy Spirit proceeding
from the Father. So the classical conciliar Trinitarian position is that the Son
is eternally begotten of the Father, and that the Spirit eternally proceeds from
the Father and (perhaps) from the Son.

The Begottenness of the Son


However mysterious this begetting – for those who drew up the credal and
conciliar formulae held that it is a timelessly eternal, completed act of the
Father, not an act in time – if the word ‘begotten’ is to retain any meaning
then it must carry the implication that the Father caused the Son to be. Thus
an asymmetry between the being and agency of the Father (who begets) and
the being and agency of the Son (who is begotten) is implied, and in some
undeniable sense the Son is subordinate to the Father. But how could the Son
of God, who is fully God, be caused to be? How could the Son be begotten
and nevertheless be unqualifiedly divine?
Of God and of the Holy Trinity: A Response to Dr. Beckwith 351

There is no question but those who formulated the doctrine of the Trinity in
terms of the begetting of the Son and the processing of the Spirit were
influenced by Neoplatonism, particularly by the idea that from the One
emanated Mind and Soul (corresponding to the begottenness and procession
of the Son and the Spirit), with the important difference that in the Trinity,
Son and Spirit are hypostases in their own right, forming (with the Father) a
Tri-unity.1

A closer look at the Nicene and Constantinopolitan formulations shows that


there is, in fact, a tension within them between a hierarchical view of the
Son’s existence, being begotten from the Father, in which the Son is caused to
be, and a more egalitarian view, in which the equality and consubstantiality
of the persons is stressed.2 The (so-called) Athanasian Creed emphasises the
equality of the persons as well as the begottenness of the Son. We find that the
idea of the equality of the persons is recognised by some of the Greek Fathers.
Thus Gregory Nazianzen’s statement that the Son’s relation to the Father is
without origin or cause3 surely carries the implication that the Son and the
Father are equal, the Son being unbegotten. For it would be hard to maintain
that the Son was both begotten and yet not caused to be, if the word
‘begotten’ is to carry any meaning at all.

The begetting of the Son is, of course, not a creating of the Son: otherwise the
Son would be a creature. The nature of the begetting on the traditional
subordinationist understanding must be something like the following: there is
no state of the Father that is not a begetting of the Son, and no state of the
Son which is not a being begotten by the Father and necessarily there is no
time when the Father had not begotten the Son, and no time when the Son
had not been begotten by the Father. One cannot sensibly state that if the
Father had not begotten the Son the Son would not have existed, because the
antecedent is necessarily false. There is no possibility of the Father existing
and the Son not existing. But do these claims not take us far from the New
Testament, and give rise to unnecessary speculation?

It is an intense dislike of the idea of the divinity of the Son being

1 On the influence of neo-Platonism see the helpful summaries in G. Bray, The


Doctrine of God, (London: IVP, 1993), pp. 146-7 and elsewhere.
2 These tensions are briefly discussed in G. Bray, The Doctrine of God, p. 156f.
3 Theological Oration 3:2-3, 16; 4; 11, 19ff.; 5:9, 16.
352 Churchman

compromised by his being said to be begotten by the Father that led John
Calvin and later theologians such as B.B. Warfield4 and in our own day such
as John Murray,5 Robert Reymond,6 and Millard Erickson,7 to modify or
abandon the idea of begottenness in expounding the Trinity, and to favour a
view of the three divine persons as co-equal, equal in every respect as regards
their divine nature. In terms of the historic creeds, they favour those
expressions in them which stress the equality of the persons, and avoid those
which favour a hierarchical view. They do this in the interests of expressing in
a completely unqualified way the full deity of the Son. Whether or not this
position is accurately described as ‘The Calvinist Doctrine of the Trinity’, it is
clearly not a novelty.

The Procession of the Spirit


What of the procession of the Holy Spirit? What is the biblical evidence for
this doctrine? Those in search of such evidence usually point to John 14:26
and 15:26. But of course these verses refer to the role of the Holy Spirit in the
economy of salvation; they say nothing about the eternal relationship of the
Father and the Son to the Spirit as it is in itself.

Further, it may be asked, does the Spirit proceed from the Father alone, or
from the Father and the Son? And if the procession of the Spirit is from the
Father and the Son, is it from the Father through the Son? Or is it from the
Father and Son conjointly? Here we witness the ludicrous and painful

4 ‘Calvin’s Doctrine of the Trinity’ reprinted in Calvin and Calvinism (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1931), and in Calvin and Augustine (Philadelphia:
Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co., 1956). ‘The Biblical Doctrine of the
Trinity’ in Biblical Doctrines (New York: Oxford University Press, 1929) in Biblical
and Theological Studies (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Co.
1952) and in Biblical Foundations (with an Introduction by Rev. Dr. D. Martyn
Lloyd-Jones) (London: The Tyndale Press, 1958.)
5 Collected Writings (Edinburgh: Banner of Truth Trust, 1982) 4, Studies in Theology,
pp. 67-8.
6 Robert L. Reymond, A New Systematic Theology of the Christian Faith (Nashville:
Thomas Nelson, 1998). See the criticism of Reymond’s interpretation of Calvin by
Paul Owen, ‘Calvin and Catholic Trinitarianism’ (Calvin Theoloical Journal,
November, 2000).
7 ‘I would propose that there are no references to the Father begetting the Son or the
Father (and the Son) sending the Spirit that cannot be understood in terms of the
temporal role assumed by the second and third persons of the Trinity respectively.
They do not indicate any intrinsic relationships among the three’, God in Three
Persons (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1995), p. 309.
Of God and of the Holy Trinity: A Response to Dr. Beckwith 353

spectacle of the Western and Eastern churches splitting over the issue of
whether the Spirit proceeds from the Father alone (the East) or from the
Father and the Son (the West), the notorious filioque clause. This split, which
has had the most serious ecclesiastical and political consequences is, in fact,
over differences about one or two verses of the New Testament which it is
highly likely have been misinterpreted from the outset! Failing appeal to these
texts, from where else in the New Testament might one derive the doctrine of
the eternal procession of the Spirit from the Father or (alternatively) from the
Father and the Son together? It is not at all clear.

The supposed procession of the Spirit gives rise to another set of speculative
questions. For example, the Son is allegedly begotten by the Father, while the
Spirit proceeds from the Father (and possibly from the Son). What is the
difference between these two expressions? Who could possibly know or tell?
What is the value of maintaining that there is a difference between them but
that we cannot begin to explain what it is, but only speculate? And does not
the raising of such questions as these take us far from the context of John
14:26, 15:26?

It might be said, both with respect to the begottenness of the Son, and the
procession of the Spirit, that our reasoning about such matters should be
based upon the following principle: that God reveals himself to us as he is in
himself. (Let us call this Principle A). We should not, it may be said, put a
wedge between God as God and God as he is revealed to us, otherwise God
as God becomes a hidden God whose nature and activities are totally
arbitrary and inscrutable and who may, in fact, bear no relation to the God
revealed in Jesus. Adopting Principle A, it is said, we must conclude that the
temporal missions of the Father, Son and Spirit will and must reflect their
eternal relations in the godhead. That if God reveals himself to us as the
Father who sends the Son, and as the Father and the Son who send the Spirit,
then this must correspond to how things are in the godhead. So the Son must
be eternally begotten, and the Spirit must eternally process.

It would certainly be difficult to deny Principle A, for it is implausible to


suppose that God reveals his part in the economy of redemption in a way that
contradicts how he is in himself, or that in his revelation he is manifestly
misleading as to his real nature, or that he reveals himself in a way that is
irrelevant to how he is in himself. And this is because immutability, wisdom
354 Churchman

and faithfulness are among God’s essential attributes or perfections, as we


know from Scripture quite apart from any considerations concerning the
Trinity. It is undoubtedly true that, in Scripture, God reveals to us something
of what he is in himself even though we cannot fully comprehend how God is
in himself. (As Calvin says, God reveals his essence sparingly.)8 How God is
in himself is never represented to us in Scripture as a black hole, as it is in
Kantian and post-Kantian theologies. In view of the fact that God reveals
himself to us as one who is in himself a loving, just and faithful God, we can
be assured that God’s revelation of himself and of the economy of redemption
is not arbitrary, but fully reflects this divine character.

So Principle A is certainly plausible. However, it would be easy to show that


Principle A can be applied with such stringency as to reduce it to absurdity.
Thus, in the economy of redemption, the Son is revealed as utterly submissive
to his Father’s good pleasure. Does it follow that in his eternal relation the
Son is utterly submissive to the Father? Does it not rather follow that there is
something in the eternal relations of the Trinity that make the incarnation of
the Word an appropriate and faithful expression of the divine nature?9

According to the New Testament the Son is the form, image, word of God.
These are highly mysterious, indeed unfathomable expressions. Who can say
what they mean? Don’t they reinforce the basic biblical affirmation that we
cannot, and cannot expect to, get our minds around the nature and the
operations of God himself? Their meaning only becomes focused and
clarified, as far as human understanding is concerned, as God is pleased to
reveal himself in the economy of redemption. The mysterious terms ‘form’,
‘image’, ‘word’ are personalised for us in the coming of the Word of God in
the Incarnation, in the Word becoming flesh, and in the person and work of
Jesus Christ and the new relationships formed by him. The terms come into
focus in the same way that a blurred image may become bright and sharp by
an adjustment of a lens, or an enigmatic form may become clearly that of a

8 Institutes 1.13.1.
9 ‘The use of temporal manifestations of God as models from which to draw analogies
of the eternal nature of the trinitarian relationships, while it doubtless was a move in
the right direction, had serious drawbacks of its own which Origen did not fully
appreciate. In his earthly life and work, the Son had obviously been in submission to
the Father. It followed therefore that submission was a basic ingredient of his divine
personhood – hence the Son was eternally subordinate to the Father’, G. Bray in
Peter Toon and James Spiceland (eds.), One God in Trinity (London: Marshall,
Morgan and Scott 1980), p. 55.
Of God and of the Holy Trinity: A Response to Dr. Beckwith 355

person when it speaks.

It might be argued that the Son is the Son of the Father without being
begotten by him, the Spirit the Spirit of the Father and (possibly) of the Son
without processing from one or both of them. But then words start to lose
their meaning. For how could the Son be the Son without being begotten, or
the Spirit the Spirit without processing? What, under this proposal, do the
words ‘Son’ and ‘Spirit’ come to mean? Is it not more in keeping with the
New Testament revelation to reserve the concepts of divine Sonship and
Spirithood to the economy of redemption?

Dr. Beckwith’s claims


In common with a number of other people I have been surprised by the
amount of attention that Roger Beckwith has chosen to give to part of an
audio tape of a seminar, the purpose of which was to provoke theological
reflection, in an informal setting, on the mystery of the Holy Trinity. It may
be that the ideas expressed in that part of the seminar which Dr. Beckwith
identifies in his printed lecture (now reprinted in this issue of Churchman)
will prove to be untenable. But if so, this will not be for any of the reasons
which Roger Beckwith adduces, as I will (briefly) attempt to show.

Roger provides three arguments against the view which I advanced. First, he
claims that on the proposal I canvassed, namely that a large element in the
doctrine of the Trinity in its Nicene formulation is owing to a reading back
into the eternal, immanent Trinity of those inter-trinitarian relations known
to us from the economy of redemption, it is hard to avoid Sabellianism, the
view that God is eternally one but not eternally three.

I am not sure why this is. Dr. Beckwith does not tell us. The Trinity
without the relations of eternal begetting and eternal procession would
nevertheless remain a Trinity. The language of the New Testament about
our redemption is the language of three distinct (yet fully co-operating and
coinhering) divine centres of agency and activity. After all, it is only by
reference to this language of the New Testament that any of us knows
anything about the triune nature of God (in any developed form) in the
first place. In this connection it is interesting to note how in the New
Testament, particularly in Paul, there is a great variety of ways in which
356 Churchman

the trinitarian character of God is expressed. Sometimes it is expressed as a


relation between Father, Son and Spirit; at other times as between Father,
Spirit and Son, at other times as between Son, Spirit and Father, and once
as between Spirit, Father and Son. This suggests that the Apostle’s
approach to the Trinity was more flexible than that imposed by the later
rigidities of begottenness and procession.10

Second, Dr. Beckwith’s piece, in effect, implies that the proposal of Calvin and
(following him) of B.B. Warfield that our thinking about the Trinity as such
should be freed from every kind of subordinationism does not do justice to
the full range of biblical data. Readers must judge for themselves how
convincing this claim is. He then argues that the further suggestion, namely
that Principle A may be applied in such a way that the ideas of the
Fatherhood, the Sonship and the Spirithood of the three persons of the Trinity
ought not to be carried back into the Trinity as it is in itself, is ‘radical’.11 In
effect, he claims that if Warfield’s approach fails, this further suggestion must
certainly fail. 12 But as we have seen Warfield’s approach has much to
commend it. And Dr. Beckwith has very little to say by way of direct criticism
of the further suggestion. Let us look at what he does say.

First, he claims that if what I have just said was correct, we know nothing
about the eternal relationships of the three Persons, but only about their
activities within the world. This takes us back to the point discussed earlier,
the question of how closely the activities of Father, Son and Spirit in creation
and redemption mirror the trinitarian godhead. Dr. Beckwith clearly implies,
without giving any argument, that the mirroring must be extremely close. But
how close?

10 On this point, see both Bray, The Doctrine of God pp. 146-7 and Warfield, ‘The
Biblical Doctrine of the Trinity’.
11 How far Warfield himself was attracted to endorsing such a further proposal is an
interesting question. In his article ‘The Biblical Doctrine of the Trinity’ he raises the
question whether (given their equality in respect of deity) the Father, Son and Spirit
are descriptions of the persons of the trinity as they are in themselves, and gives a
firm, positive answer. Yet in a piece which provides detailed biblical support for the
various other positions he defends, he offers no biblical support for this view.
12 Some may think that this view carries the consequence that it is possible that some
other person than the Word could have become incarnate. But it is not clear that it
does. And in any case those whose thinking about the Trinity is of a more traditional
hue have speculated on this point. So the traditional view itself does not positively
exclude such speculation. (e.g., Aquinas, Summa Theologiae IIIa. 3. 5).
Of God and of the Holy Trinity: A Response to Dr. Beckwith 357

Dr Beckwith also says that if the very name of the ‘Spirit’ means being
breathed out, then the idea of proceeding from God is essential to the Spirit’s
nature. That is, that person who is the Spirit could not but be breathed out,
processing from Father and (in the case of what the Western churches have
traditionally taught) also from the Son. But this argument seems to prove too
much, since God himself is ‘spirit’ (John 4:24), yet God himself can hardly be
said to be breathed out. From whom or what could God himself have been
breathed out?

As for the verses regarding the relationship between Father and Son which Dr.
Beckwith alludes to, such as John 17:5, I believe that they may all be
understood, without exception, in the references they make to ‘Father’ and
‘Son’, as reading back into the eternal relationships of the godhead what
became true at the Incarnation. At the Incarnation he who was in the form of
God, who was God, took on the role of Sonship (with the subordination and
submission that this implies) by uniting to human nature and, as the God-
man, obtained eternal redemption for us, calling God his Father. So (to take
Paul’s teaching in Colossians 1), the world was created and is sustained by
that divine person, the image of the invisible God, who was to become united
to human nature for our redemption, becoming subordinate to God his
Father in doing so. In fact, is this not what Paul says? God has translated us
into the kingdom of his dear Son, in whom we have redemption...who is the
image of the invisible God...by him were all things created...he is the head of
the body, the church (Col. 1:13-18). In Paul’s reasoning, the phrase ‘Son of
God’ gets its meaning from the condescension and obedience of the one who
is the image of the invisible God.

Finally, it may seem ironic that both the original lecture which called forth Dr.
Beckwith’s response, and this response to him, is from a philosopher who is
making a plea for the removal from our understanding of the doctrine of the
Trinity of certain concepts which derive not from the New Testament but
from pagan philosophy, from Neoplatonism. The plea is made in order that
our understanding of the Trinity may be more faithful to Scripture, and less
open to speculative distraction.

PAUL HELM is Professor Emeritus, King’s College, London and visiting


professor at Regent College, Vancouver.

You might also like