Thame C PDF
Thame C PDF
Thame C PDF
By
Charlie Thame
A thesis presented to
The Department of International Politics,
Aberystwyth University
Charlie Thame
Aberystwyth University, 2012
Key Words
ii
Acknowledgements
iii
Howard Williams played an important supervisory role in the first eighteen
months of the thesis, after which Simona Rentea came onboard as a secondary. Her
enthusiasm and belief in the project, along with her encouragement were
invaluable in helping to carry the project through a difficult stage, and her
feedback on my work has consistently been challenging and illuminating. Helpful
feedback on earlier instantiations of some of the arguments presented here has also
been gratefully received from Tim Aistrope, Martin Weber, Shannon Brincat, Luis
Guilherme Pedro, Andreja Zevnik, Mike Shapiro, Kimberley Hutchings, and
Andrew Linklater.
Above all though, I thank Hidemi Suganami for his patience, persistence, and
generosity; for his intellectual rigour, for seeing my argument and its failings far
better than I could, and for never letting me get away with an ill-considered
argument or an unclear sentence. If the presentation of what are sometimes
difficult and complex arguments are anything close to lucid, Hidemi bears a large
responsibility; the thesis would be much poorer were it not for his supervision. Of
course, all remaining failings are my own.
Mae Sot,
September 2012
iv
Declarations
DECLARATION
This work has not previously been accepted in substance for any degree and is
not being concurrently submitted in candidature for any degree.
STATEMENT 1
This thesis is the result of my own investigations, except where otherwise stated.
Where *correction services have been used, the extent and nature of the
correction is clearly marked in a footnote(s).
[*this refers to the extent to which the text has been corrected by others]
STATEMENT 2
NB: Candidates on whose behalf a bar on access has been approved by the
University (see Note 9), should use the following version of Statement 2:
v
Table of Contents
FRONT PAGE.......................................................................................................................I
SUMMARY.........................................................................................................................II
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS.....................................................................................................III
DECLARATIONS.................................................................................................................V
TABLE OF CONTENTS.......................................................................................................VI
PREFACE ..........................................................................................................................IX
INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................1
Introduction. ...............................................................................................................26
'Ontological' Foundations in Normative (International) Political Theory.................28
'Ontological' Foundations in International Theory ....................................................40
'Ontological' Foundations in Critical International Thought ....................................53
A Note on Epistemology ..............................................................................................61
Conclusions .................................................................................................................65
CHAPTER 2.
ETHICAL SUBJECTIVITY IN ANDREW LINKLATER'S
CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL THEORY ...............................................................................70
Introduction. ...............................................................................................................70
Men and Citizens: the Bifurcated Subjectivity of Modern Man..................................72
Emancipation & the Reconstruction of Kantian Freedom. ........................................74
The Triple Transformation of Political Community ...................................................83
The Tripartite Structure of Critical Theory: Normativity, Sociology, & Praxeology 90
Ethical Subjectivity in Linklater's Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism ..........................95
Conclusions ...............................................................................................................100
vi
CHAPTER 3.
CRITICAL INTERNATIONAL THEORY AND THE
POLITICS OF SUBJECTIVITY ...........................................................................................102
Introduction ..............................................................................................................102
On the Achievements of Critical International Relations Theory.............................104
On Discourse Ethics .................................................................................................108
Linklater's Defence of Universality ..........................................................................116
Rationality, Freedom, Subjectivity: The Major Fault-line of CIRT .........................120
Freedom and Inter-Subjectivity ................................................................................129
Relational Individuality and Singularity...................................................................136
The Challenge to Dualism ........................................................................................141
The Politics of Subjectivity: the Subject/Object Split and the Politics of Reality. ....144
Conclusions. ..............................................................................................................148
PART 2.
WORLDS AND WORLD POLITICS ............................................................... 151
Introduction to Part 2 ...............................................................................................152
CHAPTER 4.
BEINGS & BEING: HEIDEGGER & FUNDAMENTAL ONTOLOGY.....................................159
Introduction ..............................................................................................................159
The Ontological Difference & the Leading Question of Philosophy ........................160
Being and Time .........................................................................................................166
Being and Time: Division Two .................................................................................175
Perspectival Presentation of the Whole: Overcoming Metaphysics. ........................182
‘Overcoming’ Metaphysics .......................................................................................189
Conclusions: From a Dualist to Non-Dualist Approach to Emancipatory Politics. 192
CHAPTER 5.
EK-SISTENCE, FREEDOM, AND
AN ETHICAL AND EMANCIPATORY POLITICS ................................................................198
Introduction ..............................................................................................................198
Humans as World-Relating Creatures. .....................................................................200
The Essence of Human Freedom: Heidegger's Ontological Reading of Kant .........209
An Ethical & Emancipatory Politics ........................................................................224
Conclusions: Towards a Politics of Singularity .......................................................236
Conclusions to Part 2 ...............................................................................................240
vii
PART 3.
LIFE, LOVE, AND EMANCIPATION ............................................................ 243
Introduction to Part 3 ...............................................................................................244
CHAPTER 6.
UNDERSTANDING THROUGH LOVE, NOT VIVISECTION:
REIFICATION, DE-REIFICATION, AND DEIFICATION ......................................................247
Introduction ..............................................................................................................247
Kant & Hegel ............................................................................................................249
The Subject-Object Relation from Kant to Hegel .....................................................252
The Problem of Life: Hegel's Monistic Philosophical Ontology ..............................269
‘Ontological’ Implications of the Foundational Subject ..........................................275
Hegelian 'Phenomenology' .......................................................................................284
Conclusions ...............................................................................................................287
CHAPTER 7.
EXPOSURE, TRANSCENDENCE, AND
THE COMMUNITY OF FATE ............................................................................................294
Introduction ..............................................................................................................294
The Philosophy of Love.............................................................................................299
Hegel and Love. ........................................................................................................305
The Struggle For Recognition...................................................................................310
Bound Together: The Community of Fate ................................................................319
Conclusions ...............................................................................................................330
CHAPTER 8.
THE LIVED CHARACTER OF ETHICS ..............................................................................334
Introduction ..............................................................................................................334
Love in Practical Philosophy ....................................................................................335
Love and Law: the Vertical Moral Geometry of Moral Law
and the Ethical Logic of Love ...................................................................................343
Moralität and Sittlichkeit ..........................................................................................354
The Lived Character of Ethics ..................................................................................362
Conclusions ...............................................................................................................366
CONCLUSIONS.
LOVE,
ETHICS,
AND
EMANCIPATION....................................................................................................370
BIBLIOGRAPHY........................................................................................................................................402
viii
Preface
Like all pieces of scholarly work this thesis has a personal history. In the
first semester of my second year as an undergraduate at Cardiff University, I took
David Boucher's course History of Ideas in International Relations, during which I
was introduced to both Francis Fukuyama's The End of History and the Last Man
and Samuel Huntington's The Clash of Civilisations and the Remaking of World
Order.1 I chose to write an essay comparing and contrasting these approaches as a
component of my coursework. This of course required me to engage in the
secondary literature on these texts; yet I found something quite unsatisfactory
about engaging with these discourses on their own terms. This is because it was not
their theoretical inadequacies that I found troubling, but the potentially pernicious
effects of these theoretical interventions. Against the backdrop of the post-Cold
War era, Fukuyama's thesis appeared to warrant the expansion of neo-liberal
political and economic ideology, whilst Huntington's seemed to risk making
potential sources of conflict actual, reinvigorating the military-industrial complex
and vivifying an oppositional sense of American identity through the perpetuation
of discourses of danger that serve to recreate imagined communities.2 It seemed to
me then that these were far from being politically neutral pieces of scholarship, and
that these scholars had a fundamental responsibility for the consequences of the
political imaginaries that they forged and lent credibility to.
1. Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Harper Perennial, 1993).
Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilisations and the Remaking of World Order (New York:
Simon & Schuster, 1997).
2. On the use of foreign policy and collective identity formation see David Campbell, Writing
Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity (Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 1998).; Michael J. Shapiro, Violent Cartographies: Mapping Cultures of War
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997).; Iver B. Neumann, “Self and Other in
International Relations,” European Journal of International Relations 2, no. 2 (1996): 139-74; Iver
B. Neumann, Uses of the Other: “the East” in European Identity Formation (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1999).
ix
It was for this reason that theoretical approaches to politics with a
specifically 'normative' intent resonated with me as an undergraduate; Mervyn
Frost's case for normative theory against 'value-free' social inquiry was particularly
influential, and I consistently found ethical questions in international relations to
be the most intriguing ones. 3 Yet I soon found the consequentialist and
deontological frameworks to which I was introduced to be talking at cross-
purposes. It became clear that these general moral conceptions were fundamentally
incompatible, and ultimately rested upon assumptions or commitments that were
neither transparently evident nor appropriately defended: assumptions and
commitments regarding the highest good, what is right, and the nature of human
beings and their place in the world, all of which provide the conditions of
intelligibility for these approaches. It seemed that the application of these
approaches to the cosmopolitical realm, such as the now-classical interventions
from Peter Singer or Charles Beitz, for instance, would simply serve to multiply
and intensify disagreements between competing perspectives on what properly
ethical relations between people might involve, since the international realm is the
realm where human differences are most pronounced.4 It seemed sensible then that
theories aspiring to a global purview should explicitly defend these underlying
assumptions before proceeding.
x
freedom, for instance. Despite the strengths of their positions, I felt that normative
theorists such as Frost, Walzer and Rawls relied on such commitments without
adequately defending them.5
5. This point will of course be elaborated on shortly.
6. See for instance: Ken Booth, et al., eds. How Might We Live? Global Ethics in a New Century
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001); Ken Booth, and Timothy Dunne, eds. Worlds in
Collision: Terror and the Future of Global Order (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002); Ken Booth, ed.
Critical Security Studies and World Politics (Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 2005); Ken Booth, Theory of
World Security (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); Ken Booth, ed. Realism and
World Politics (London: Routledge, 2011); Ken Booth and Timothy Dunne, eds. Terror in Our
Time (London: Routledge, 2012); Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of
International Relations, 2nd ed. (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990); Andrew Linklater,
Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations (Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, 1990); Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical
Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998); Andrew Linklater, “The
Harm Principle and Global Ethics,” Global Society 20, no. 3 (2006): 329-43; Andrew Linklater,
“Global Civilizing Processes and the Ambiguities of Human Interconnectedness,” European
Journal of International Relations 16, no. 2 (2010): 155; Andrew Linklater and Hidemi Suganami,
The English School of International Relations: A Contemporary Reassessment (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2006); Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World Politics.
Vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
7. Ken Booth, Theory of World Security.
xi
consciousness.'8 Influential in Gramscian-inspired critical theory, this is 'the idea
that a person or group cannot grasp their true interests because of indoctrination or
traditionalist socialisation.'9 As a result, knowledge, enlightenment is central to
freedom, because 'one cannot have one's own understanding (looking at a matter
with some critical distance) under conditions of indoctrination, traditionalist
socialisation, and inadequate relevant knowledge.'10 Booth then proceeds by stating
that 'we freely choose when our noumenal selves control our phenomenal selves;
in other words, when our actions are not the result of error or passion, but are fully
voluntary, founded on understanding and reason.'11
8. Ibid., 112.
9. Ibid. emphasis added
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., 113. emphasis added
xii
characterised my reading of Andrew Linklater's work; yet Linklater's conception of
freedom was harder to identify than Booth's and thus more intriguing to me. Whilst
receptive to some of the challenges to Linklater's position, I found none wholly
convincing, and I thought the readiness of some critics to simply reject the goal of
12
emancipation somewhat petulant. However, equally unsatisfactory was
Linklater's tendency to respond to criticism with a 'gesture of embrace,' a
characteristic response that appeared to indicate a blind-spot to the nature of the
challenges to his position.13 Given that such challenges often align according to the
divergent intellectual inheritances of various 'critical' approaches to politics, I came
to suspect that Linklater's blind-spot might be essentially related to the influence of
Kant and Marx on his position, and I thought it possible to trace an alternative
trajectory of thinking about freedom that might contribute to an even richer critical
approach to world politics. What follows is an attempt to shed light on this blind-
spot and an attempt to embolden and develop further a critical and emancipatory
approach to world politics.
12. In a graduate seminar that followed the publication of Theory of World Security Ken Booth
recounted an exchange with a prominent IR scholar, possibly Rob Walker, whom he credited with
claiming that ‘emancipation is the problem.’
13. The term ‘gesture of embrace’ is Martin Weber's. Martin Weber, “Engaging Globalization:
Critical Theory and Global Political Change,” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 27, no. 3
(2002), 302.
xiii
Introduction
World politics, in the modern era at least, has primarily been conceived as
relations between states. As Rob Walker notes, that the academic study of world
politics should be referred to as International Relations suggests that what happens
inside states is quite different from what happens outside states. 1 Yet the
distinction between domestic order and international anarchy, which has been
foundational to the discipline of International Relations but has always been
problematic, has become increasingly untenable over the past forty years as
dynamics of globalisation have placed increasing pressures on the nation-state as
an effective institution for managing the vicissitudes of contemporary political life.
1
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
democratic peace and the project of European integration, along with expressions
of cosmopolitan solidarity during the Arab Spring and in the Occupy movement, in
addition to the development of cosmopolitan norms such as R2P, appear to indicate
forms of community developing beyond the nation-state. On the other, the rise of
the far right in Europe, religious extremism, and the characterisation of some
conflicts as 'civilisational' seem to indicate the fragmentation of communities and
the realignment of forms of identity that might be regarded as constitutive of
individual human beings as political subjects.
In a context in which the factors which will determine whether the human species will
survive or perish, suffer or prosper, operate on a global scale, a good case can be made that
the polis which is ‘coterminous with the minimum self-sufficient human reality’ is the
planet itself. In short, the problems presently faced by the human species call out for the
identification of the idea of the polis with the planet as a whole: a truly global polis.3
2. See Susan Strange, The Retreat of the State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976).;
John Ruggie, Constructing the World Polity: Essays on International Institutionalisation (London:
Routledge, 1998), 174-175,195-197.; R.B.J. Walker, Inside/Outside: International Relations as
Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 183. Heikki Patomäki, After
International Relations: Critical Realism and the (Re)Construction of World Politics (London:
Routledge, 2002), 1.
3. Mark A. Neufeld, The Restructuring of International Relations Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995), 11.
2
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Echoing such a view, Fred Dallmayr suggests that we presently sit at the
twilight of the so-called Westphalian system, where the juncture of radical state
autonomy and a state of true and increasing human interdependence, wrought by
dynamics of globalisation, has given rise to 'two opposing tendencies: on one side,
ambitions to subject globalisation to global sovereignty (a global Leviathan)' and,
on the other, ambitions towards 'a democratic cosmopolis achieved through the
subordination of sovereignty to global interdependence.'6 Painting a starker picture,
this juncture is characterised by Barry Gills as a struggle between 'Cosmopolis' and
'Empire,' suggesting that global politics is today embroiled in a 'clash of
globalisations' between these two opposed approaches to world order, both
struggling to define the character of globalisation, where the experience of the
global community is drawing us to imagine a world characterised either by greater
collective human responsibility or one that remains ensnared in the naked pursuit
of power and wealth.7
4. Richard Beardsworth, “Assessing Cosmopolitan Theory in World Politics,” e-International
Relations, http://www.e-ir.info/2012/05/27/assessing-cosmopolitan-theory-in-world-politics/
(accessed 25/06/2012, 2012).
5. Richard Beardsworth, “The Future of Critical Philosophy and World Politics,” Millennium-
Journal of International Studies 34, no. 1 (2005), 210, 212.
6. Fred R. Dallmayr, Small Wonder: Global Power and Its Discontents (Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2005), 55.
7. Barry K. Gills, “Introduction,” in The Global Politics of Globalization: “Empire” Vs
“Cosmopolis”, ed. Barry K. Gills (London: Routledge, 2007).
3
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
4
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
particularity in space and time'.10 In simpler terms what is meant by this is that
differences between human beings (religious, political, ethical, etc.), differences
that have often led to violence or the forceful submission of one to another have for
the past few hundred years been managed through a spatial resolution where they
have essentially been treated as if they were the internal affairs of any given state.
Such a resolution was historically specific because it was established as a way to
resolve competing claims to fealty in Europe of the late middle ages, involving
what Jens Bartelson has called a 'sublimation of otherness' whereby order grows
out of disorder, harmony out of conflict, and identity out of difference. 11 In
summary then, the Westphalian system of sovereign states has essentially
functioned as a way of escaping the problem of difference rather than confronting
it, a strategy that Naeem Inayatullah and David Blaney refer to as the 'Westphalian
deferral:'
With the emergence of the states system, the differences constituting and complicating
each state as a particular political community are kept separate and managed within the
territorial boundaries of the state. This demarcation and policing of the boundary between
the 'inside' and 'outside' of the political community defines the problem of difference
principally as between and among states; difference is marked and contained as
international difference. This construction of difference allows us to claim to 'solve' the
problem by negotiating a modus vivendi among political communities.12
10. Ibid., 176.
11. Jens. Bartelson, A Genealogy of Sovereignty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995),
24-28.
12. Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney, International Relations and the Problem of Difference
(London: Routledge, 2004), 6-7. Inayatullah and Blaney discuss another prevalent strategy
deployed in the response to difference, the temporal strategy, whereby difference would be
mitigated as traditional societies modernise.
5
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
century has been geared towards recognising the radical particularity of ontological
and epistemological interests.
13. Hartmut Behr, A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).
14. Ibid., 2.
15. Patomäki's argument, however, is that the modern study of 'International Relations' is a
descendant of Hume's empiricist ontology/epistemology. See Heikki Patomäki, After International
Relations: Critical Realism and the (Re)Construction of World Politics, 21-41. Hartmut Behr, A
History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International, 2-3.
16. Ibid.
17. Ibid., 3. Realists often claim descent from Thucydides, but this claim has been challenged
elsewhere. Cf. Nicholas J. Rengger, “Realism, Tragedy, and the Anti-Pelagian Imagination in
6
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Ontology
International Political Thought,” in Realism Reconsidered: The Legacy of Hans Morgenthau in
International Relations, ed. Michael C. Williams (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 134-
135n6.; Richard Ned Lebow, “Texts, Paradigms, and Political Change,” in Realism Reconsidered:
The Legacy of Hans Morgenthau in International Relations, ed. Michael C. Williams (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2007).
18. Hartmut Behr, A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International, 246.
19. Ibid.
7
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Ontology, from the Greek 'ὄντος' (being), present participle of the verb
'εἰµί' (to be), and -λογία, (-logia) science, study, or theory, can be understood as a
form of philosophical inquiry into existence: about what exists, and about the
nature of existence, or, what it means to exist. Ontology can be deployed in
different ways but in IR it has tended to mean something quite facile, usually
interpreted simply as relating to what 'objects' are seen to exist in international
relations, whether those objects are states (realists), individuals (liberals), social
structures (Marxists), or 'intransitive objects' (critical realists). Besides the fact that
talking about 'ontology in IR' already limits ourselves to one small corner of the
empirical world, the elevation of some international phenomena over others to a
level of foundational objectivity often tells us more about the political/theoretical
commitments of the advocate than it does about the (empirical) world of
international relations. Indeed, since it ignores or leaves implicit the question of the
nature of the existence of those entities, what we consider to 'exist' in world
politics is hardly an ontological question at all, but rather a mere matter of
articulating our own (subjective) images of 'the world.'
8
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
that will become apparent, we are especially concerned with the concept of
'freedom' associated with the nature of human existence, and therefore, what it
means to be a free human being. It is on this understanding of ontology that we
proceed, and it is in this sense that we interpret Behr's call for more universalistic
ontological inquiry.
Universality
At the time of revising this introduction, the plight of so-called 'boat people'
seeking asylum in Australia, is, once again, in the news. There are a number
reasons for this: two weeks ago the Australian parliament enacted tough new laws
seeking to deter asylum seekers, often originating from war-torn countries such as
Afghanistan, Iraq and others in the Middle East, the second season of the popular
and award winning SBS documentary series Go Back to Where You Came From is
currently being aired, and a search and rescue operation is presently underway for
a boat carrying 150 asylum seekers, including women and children, which issued a
distress signal a few days ago off the coast of Indonesia.21
These tough new measures, coming into effect in September 2012, involve
the mandatory deportation of new asylum seekers arriving in Australia by boat to
the Pacific atoll of Nauru or Papua New Guinea. Besides over 300 lives being lost
on the same passage between Java (Indonesia) and Christmas Island (Australia)
since December 2011, the cost to detain asylum seekers since 2000 - removing the
costs for deterrence and anti-people smuggling activities - totalled over Aus$2bn.22
During this period just over 18,000 people arrived by boat, which meant that
Australian taxpayers spent around Aus$113,000 simply to detain each asylum
21. Neil Hume, “Australia Searches for Missing Boat People,” Financial Times. Thursday 30th
August 2012., http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/6a87bd78-f270-11e1-ac41-00144feabdc0.html
(accessed 30th August, 2012).
22. Ibid.; Bernard Keane, “Cost of Detention? $113,000 Per Asylum Seeker,” Crikey. 17th August,
2012 http://www.crikey.com.au/2011/08/17/detention-centre-cost-of-asylum-seekers/ (accessed
30th August, 2012).
9
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
seeker, on average, across the period.23 Not long after a popular Australian radio
talk-show host, Bob Francis, was publicly censured for telling his radio audience
'bugger the boat people, I say. As far as I'm concerned, I hope they bloody drown
out there on their way over here [sic.],' an Australian Commonwealth minister was
reported as saying that 'the only acceptable policy to my electorate would be for
the Navy to sink asylum boats on sight.'24
Our ways of thinking about such issues are outdated, partly because the
ways that we organise our political lives at a global scale are too. The Australian
case is indicative of a broader contemporary malaise that runs deep and betrays
some of the essential limitations of particularist thought. States are predicated on
the violent exclusion of others, and a global system organised around national
citizenship is simply not designed to deal with mass migrations of people. That
governments spend vast amounts of money on harsh policies of detainment and
deterrence is paradoxical, and such callous disregard for the lives of non-citizens
betrays an abhorrent solipsism that is, sadly, not uncommon.25
23. Ibid.
24. Michael Owen, “Radio ‘King’ Slammed Over Boatpeople Tirade,” The Australian. June 8th ,
http://www.theaustralian.com.au/national-affairs/immigration/radio-king-slammed-over-
boatpeople-tirade/story-fn9hm1gu-1226388100400 (accessed 30th August 2012, 2012).; Allan
Asher, “The Lies We Feed Ourselves to Paint Refugees as Villains,” The Punch. 27th August.
2012, http://www.thepunch.com.au/articles/The-lies-we-feed-ourselves-to-paint-refugees-as-
villains/ (accessed 28th August, 2012).
25. It the perception of difference that is key here, after all there are nearly 500,000 New
Zealanders living and working in Australia, who need no visa to do so.
26. Habermas's reformulation of the Kantian principle of universalisation is an example of a
contemporary application of the principle of universal respect. He writes: 'A norm is valid when the
foreseeable consequences and side effects of its general observance for the interests and value-
orientations of each individual could be jointly accepted by all concerned without coercion.' Jürgen
Habermas, The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory (Cambridge, MA: The MIT
Press, 1998), 42.
10
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
under international law, such as those to 'respect, protect, and fulfil' human rights.27
Although echoing these sentiments, our universalism, our cosmopolitanism,
pursues a different line of argument. We will not simply insist that people or states
must live up to some preconceived subjectivity and act as if they were good moral
or legal subjects, nor will we be relying on the evocation of a common human
community, as if we already faced such a collective singularity, 'mankind' as
such.28
11
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
12
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Left-Hegelian Thought
Defending the view that the future of critical theory lies in CIRT, we learn
that CIRT has developed along two paths since first making inroads into IR in the
early 1980s: a historical/sociological path, inaugurated by Robert W. Cox, that
highlights different futures for international politics, and a philosophical/normative
path, inaugurated by Richard K. Ashley, that uses freedom as a critical standard
with which to criticise the theory and practice of world politics and to indicate
ways forward. We see that the most comprehensive and compelling advocate of
CIRT, Andrew Linklater, has developed a 'twin-track' approach that is reflected in
his insistence of the necessarily 'tripartite structure' of critical theory, where any
critical theory is seen to remain incomplete unless it contains
philosophical/normative, sociological, and praxeological elements.
13
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
14
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
treated as if it were the essential nature of human beings qua human beings,
applying to human beings 'as such' and to human beings as a whole.
29. Following Heidegger, we understand metaphysics as a speculative activity that goes beyond
that which is immediately accessible to human beings, seeking to grasp the essence of entities (such
as human beings) in order that general claims may be made about them. Martin Heidegger, The
Essence of Human Freedom: An Introduction to Philosophy (London: Continuum, 2002), 106.
Although such a brief definition is inadequate, we request the reader's patience until Chapter 4
when a more thorough explanation will be given.
15
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Research Question
Our contention is that Heidegger and Hegel present two potent defences of
a non-dualist approach to the relation between self and world. Since both proceed
from non-dualist premises, both reject any foundational commitments to
subjectivity or objectivity, which they consider to contribute to an alienation of self
from world, and as serving to 'un-live' human existence. Consonant with our earlier
identification with the left-Hegelian tradition of thought, both Heidegger and Hegel
are motivated by foundational ontological commitments (in the fuller sense of the
term) to human freedom and, in contrast to Linklater's rationalist cosmopolitanism
where the relationship between self and world is ultimately mediated by moral
reason, both Heidegger and Hegel (respectively) are concerned with developing
pre- and post-theoretical, phenomenological, relations to reality, and their
16
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
17
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
18
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Heidegger's lies in his failure to explore for the interpersonal aspects of freedom
and individuality, a mistake he might have avoided had he been a better student of
Hegel; secondly, the discontinuity between politics and ethics heralded by
Heidegger's fundamental ontology is already there in Hegel's distinction between
Sittlichkeit (ethical life) and Moralität (ethical/moral reason), and Hegel gives a far
more adequate account of ethics than does Heidegger; thirdly, the
phenomenological impulse, an attempt to develop a non-theoretical relation to
reality, although foregrounded by Heidegger, is already there in Hegel (this has
unfortunately been obscured by more rationalist interpretations of Hegel); and
finally, Hegel offers us a phenomenological approach to epistemology that is more
persuasive than the renewed emphasis on the nature and function of language in
post-Husserlian phenomenology, and this provides us with the epistemological
defence of our emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
19
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Our last chapter, Chapter 8, picks up on this latter point, honing in on the
ethical aspect of our argument through a discussion of the distinction drawn by
Hegel between ethical life (Sittlichkeit) and moral reason (Moralität), and the
nature of the relation between these two approaches to society. Ethical life
(Sittlichkeit), we discover, operates according to an 'ethical logic of love,' while
moral reason (Moralität) proceeds according to general laws given through the
exercise of practical reason and is associated with a Kantian approach to ethics.
Learning that ethical society requires the recognition of the mutual dependency of
both perspectives, we demonstrate that, as a result of their foundational
commitments to ethical subjectivity, both Habermas and Linklater mistreat the
notion of ethical life (Sittlichkeit) by asserting the dominance of moral reason over
ethical life. Attempting to rebalance this bias we conclude by advocating the
importance of ethical life and engaged conscientious activity for an ethical and
emancipatory politics.
20
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
In light of our argument that a genuinely ethical relation to the other would
involve resisting the (characteristically dualist) tendency to project an
interpretation of the being of human beings onto others and engaging with others
as others (as unique singularities rather than as ethical subjects) and having learnt
that there are two aspects of human freedom obscured by Linklater's emancipatory
cosmopolitanism - freedom as the existential condition of any interpretation of the
being of human beings (as ethical subjects, for instance) and freedom as 'the
crossing of love,' where any given subjectivity is transcended through interactions
with others - we conclude that, in order to reflect the fact that human beings are
neither foundational ethical subjects, nor mind-independent cognitive objects, a
more universalistic approach to contemporary (global) politics and ethics must be
predicated on non-dualist meta-theoretical commitments.
21
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
it rests on a limited conception of freedom that equates freedom with the exercise
of ethical subjectivity, and is ethically deficient since ethical recognition is
extended to human beings qua ethical subjects. Instead, we argue that a fully
ethical and emancipatory approach to contemporary (global) politics and ethics
would involve self-consciously identifying with others beyond our immediate
circles of concern, taking their interests as not wholly distinct from our own, and
acting accordingly. To this end, displacing Linklater/Habermas's normative ideal of
universal communication, we outline ways in which love can be deployed as an
evaluative tool for critical social theory; how it can be deployed as a non-dualist
normative standard with which to indict forms of ethical habituation (institutions
and practices) that generate and sustain forms of indifference towards others.
32. On this point we follow Shannon Brincat. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory
Cosmopolitanism: Reconstructing the Concept of Emancipation in Critical International Relations
Theory” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Queensland, 2011), 312,314-315.
22
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
33. Our use of the verb 'overcoming' will be explained shortly.
34. See Nicholas J. Rengger, and Ben Thirkell-White., ed. Critical International Relations Theory
After 25 Years (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
35. Richard Beardsworth, Cosmopolitanism and International Relations Theory (Cambridge: Polity
Press, 2011).
23
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
36. On cosmopolitan proposals for reform see David Held's arguments for the reform of the
Security Council, the creation of a second chamber in the UN, the enhancement of political
regionalisation, the use of trans-national referenda, the creation of a new human rights court, the
foundation of a new co-ordinating economic agency at regional and global levels, and the
establishment of an effective, accountable, international military force. In the longer term Held
suggests such reforms should include the entrenchment of cosmopolitan democratic law in a new
Charter of Rights, a new Global Parliament, and an interconnected global legal system. Daniele
Archibugi, and David Held, eds. Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for a New World Order
(Cambridge: Polity, 1995); David Held, Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State
to Cosmopolitan Governance (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995); David Held, “Cosmopolitan
Democracy and the Global Order: A New Agenda,” in Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s
Cosmopolitan Ideal, ed. James Bohman and Mattias Lutz-Bachmann (Cambridge: The MIT Press,
1997).
37. Ken Booth, “Security and Emancipation,” Review of International Studies 17, no. 4 (1991):
313-26; Ken Booth, “Security in Anarchy: Utopian Realism in Theory and Practice,” International
Affairs 63, no. 3 (1991): 527-45; Ken Booth, Theory of World Security (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007). Keith Krause and Michael C. Williams, eds. Critical Security Studies:
Concepts and Cases (London: UCL Press, 1997). Robert W. Cox, “Social Forces, States and World
Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 10,
no. 2 (1981): 126-55; Robert W. Cox, Production, Power, and World Order: Social Forces in the
Making of History, vol. 1 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1987); Robert W. Cox,
Approaches to World Order (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Robert W. Cox,
“Civil Society At the Turn of the Millennium: Prospects for an Alternative World Order,” Review of
International Studies 25, no. 1 (1999): 3-28; Richard Price and Christian Reus-Smit, “Dangerous
Liaisons? Critical International Theory and Constructivism,” European Journal of International
Relations 4, no. 3 (1998), 264.
38. Andrew Linklater, “The Changing Contours of Critical International Relations Theory,” in
Critical Theory and World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn-Jones (Boulder: Lynne Reiner, 2001), 31-32.
24
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
A Note on Methodology
Sometimes it is hard to know where politics ends and metaphysics begins: when, that is,
the stakes of a political dispute concern not simply a clash of competing ideas and values
but a clash about what is real and what is not, what can be said to exist on its own and
what owes its existence to an other.39
25
INTRODUCTION/ Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
the conceptual principles and standards of an object, and unfolds their implications
and consequences. Then it re-examines and reassesses the object [...] in light of
these implications and consequences. Critique proceeds, so to speak, 'from
within.'44 CIRT is explicitly committed to a high degree of reflectivity about the
relationship between subject and object, to the process of human emancipation, and
to the justification of its position according to universalist and universalistic
ontologies; these are the standards in light of which our immanent critique assesses
CIRT. Our mode of reception is closer to Walter Benjamin's 'redemptive
hermeneutic' than it is to an Adornian 'absolute negation,' in that our aim is to
redeem and retain what we consider to be most valuable in Linklater's approach.45
44. Adorno and Horkheimer, quoted in Mark A. Neufeld, The Restructuring of International
Relations Theory, 5.
45. Mark A. Neufeld, “What’s Critical About Critical International Relations Theory?”, 128-29.
26
Part 1.
International Theory
25
Chapter 1.
'Ontological' Foundations in Contemporary
Approaches to International Thought
Introduction.
This leads us to a brief discussion of Hegel, for whom institutions such as the
state do not in themselves have an 'objective' existence, as their objectivity is
conditional upon the nature of the being of the being that encounters such entities
as 'objects.' Put differently, for Hegel the 'objectivity' of dominant practices and
institutions remains dependent upon the extent to which such institutions
contribute to the freedom of the human being: to the self-actualisation of freedom
in the world. We suggest that such a foundational ontological commitment (in the
fuller sense of the term) might represent a more universalistic ontological
foundation for contemporary (global) politics and ethics.
27
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
1. Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (Cambridge,
Mass.: The MIT Press, 1990), 321.
28
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
29
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
5. Ibid., xvi.
6. Ibid.
30
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
7. See: John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999)., and
Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1982).; Alasdair C. MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (London: Duckworth, 2007).;
Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books,
1983).; John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical, vol. 14(3), Philosophy &
Public Affairs (1985), 224.
31
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
In this discussion I shall make some general remarks about how I now understand the
conception of justice that I have called ‘justice as fairness’ (presented in my book A
Theory of Justice). I do this because it may seem that this conception depends on
philosophical claims I should like to avoid, for example, claims to universal truth, or
claims about the essential nature and identity of persons.
[...]
Thus, the aim of justice as fairness as a political conception is practical, and not
metaphysical or epistemological. That is, it presents itself not as a conception of justice
that is true, but one that can serve as a basis of informed and willing political agreement
between citizens viewed as free and equal persons.8
Rawls thus leaves the question open as to whether 'justice as fairness' can
be extended to different societies existing under different historical and social
traditions.9 Reasserting his particularism in his The Law of Peoples (1999), Rawls
explicitly states that his conception of international justice does not claim universal
scope, but applies only to the foreign policy of a liberal people:
[I]t is important to see that the Law of Peoples is developed within political liberalism and
is an extension of a liberal conception of justice for a domestic regime to a Society of
Peoples. I emphasize that, in developing the Law of Peoples within a liberal conception of
justice, we work out the ideals and principles of the foreign policy of a reasonably just
liberal people. This concern with the foreign policy of a liberal people is implicit
throughout. The reason we go on to consider the point of view of decent peoples is not to
prescribe principles of justice for them, but to assure ourselves that the ideals and
principles of the foreign policy of a liberal people are also reasonable from a decent
nonliberal point of view. The need for such assurance is a feature inherent in the liberal
conception. The Law of Peoples holds that decent nonliberal points of view exist, and that
the question of how far nonliberal peoples are to be tolerated is an essential question of
liberal foreign policy.10
32
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
By taking the state, the system of sovereign states, and global civil society
as his foundational ethical commitments, Mervyn Frost's 'secular' interpretation of
Hegel provides us with a second illustration of the tendency in modern political
theory to try to evade ontological questions and thereby reinforce visions of
politics and ethics that remain contained within the sovereign state.12
11. Bartelson argues that sovereignty functions according to the same logic as the paregon. The
parergon is a problem discussed in aesthetics, centring on the relationship between a frame, a work
of art itself, and its background. The solution, as explained by Bartelson is that: 'a frame, a line of
demarcation, an ontological divide, or geographical or chronological boundary all assert and
manifest class membership of a phenomena, but the frame or line itself cannot be a member of
either class. It is neither inside, nor outside, yet it is the condition of possibility of both. A parergon
does not exist in the same sense as that which it helps to constitute; there is a ceaseless activity of
framing, but the frame itself is never present, since it is itself unframed.' Jens. Bartelson, A
Genealogy of Sovereignty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 51.
12. On Frost's 'secular' Hegelianism see: Mervyn Frost, Ethics in International Relations: A
Constitutive Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 143-58.
13. Ibid.; Mervyn Frost, Constituting Human Rights: Global Civil Society and the Society of
Democratic States (London: Routledge, 2002).
33
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
We only 'have' human rights by virtue of our participation within these two
practices, and the context and scope of different types of rights claims therefore
correspond with the context and scope of these respective practices. First
generation rights such as freedom of speech, conscience, and the right not to be
killed or assaulted are negative rights that claim universal scope, applying
universally to all those who participate in global civil society, while second and
third generation rights, such as rights to employment, housing, health-care,
economic and social development, and group and collective rights, are positive
rights that depend on our participation in concrete political institutions such as the
state. Since these institutions are necessary for their provision, these positive rights
can only apply within their jurisdiction.
34
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
epistemological focus of her analysis: she is primarily concerned with the status of
normative claims. However, Cochran recognises that this shifts the burden of an
ethics back onto ontology. 15 Ironically then, despite attempting to evade
philosophical questions by emphasising the particularity of their normative claims
and taking dominant practices as their ethical foundations, treating such
commitments as 'objects' presupposed as the conditions of their normative claims
invites an ontological evaluation of such commitments. A properly ontological
evaluation of Rawls and Frost's ethical foundations would not simply consist in
debating which represents the better ethical foundation, but must involve
questioning the 'objectivity' of such foundations themselves: whether such
foundations have objective existence, what it means to take these ethical
foundations as objective, and what it says about the being of the entity that
encounters such institutions as objects.
15. Ibid., xvi.
35
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
their normative theories would hold only on the condition that they contribute to
human freedom.
The actual is always rational, but no existing social order is ever wholly actual. In its
existence, the rational Idea of an ethical order is always to some extent disfigured by
contingency, error, and wickedness.17 The present social order must be measured not by a
timeless standard, but by its own ethical Idea [...] There is plenty of room in Hegel’s
ethical theory for criticism of the existing order as an immature or imperfect embodiment
of its own Idea [...] The principles of an ethical order are valid only so long as that order is
rational [...] The foundation of the ethical is its actualisation of spirit's freedom. The cause
16. G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen Über Rechtsphilosophie (Lectures on the Philosophy of Right)
(Stuttgart: Frommann Verla, 1974), 19 51. emphasis added. G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the
Philosophy of Right, trans. H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 389-
390n22.
17. The Idea is freedom. On the understanding of 'Idea' in Hegel see Glenn Alexander Magee, The
Hegel Dictionary (London: Continuum, 2010), 111-15.
36
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
of that freedom is served not only by the structure of a rational social order, but also by the
destruction of an order that has lost its rationality [...] Inevitably Hegel's ethical theory
focuses critical attention on prevailing social institutions: Does the existing social order
actualise its Idea? Is the ethical order itself rational, or has it lost its foundation in spirit's
struggle to actualise freedom?18
Hegel's Philosophy of Right is a defence of the view that the ethical state is
the most rational modern form of the actualisation of objective freedom: the state's
rationality is dependent on it being effective at actualising human freedom; when it
no longer serves human freedom it will (presumably) be subject to revision.19 This
is the critical purchase of Hegel's argument. His attempts to show in the
Philosophy of Right how the institutions of modern society, such as the family,
civil society, and the state, actualise freedom in the modern world all presuppose
the possibility that modern society might fail to meet these critical standards: this is
the radical dimension of his ethical theory; the possibility of a radical Hegelian
'left' is immanent in his thought, as is an apologetic Hegelian 'right.'20
18. Allen W. Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990),
256. Emphasis added.
19. G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right.
20. Allen W. Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought, 257.
21. Ibid.
37
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
38
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
of the provision of second and third generation rights more universally, while the
'parergonal' logic of Rawls's theory of justice, its sharp inside/outside distinction,
means that 'outsiders' have few ethical claims on 'insiders,' and we must therefore
acquiesce to the violent and exclusionary practices associated with the exercise of
state sovereignty.
Both Rawls and Frost thereby reinforce visions of politics and ethics that
remain framed by the state, and offer inert approaches to contemporary (global)
politics and ethics that neglect the historical nature of (currently) hegemonic social
and political institutions, which are unable to provide any guide for future-directed
action, save for the effective management of the status quo. Despite both offering
eminently persuasive and practical approaches to normative questions in
international relations when accepted on their own terms, these terms themselves
rest upon questionable ontological assumptions that remain unresponsive to the
contemporary transformations of the Westphalian system, and leave us impotent in
the face of potentially progressive transformations of our political and social
arrangements.
39
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
central obstacle to such a task is that attempts to bring ontological reflection into
international theory have, so far, overwhelmingly been superficial.
International thought has not similarly retreated from confronting the meta-
theoretical aspects of political and social inquiry. This may in part be attributable
to the fact that IR is a derivative discipline that applies insights from other
disciplines such as political science, philosophy, sociology, economics, history,
linguistics, etc., but also because the increasingly heterodox and trans-disciplinary
nature of various studies of war, peace, order and change in the field might have
forced a greater degree of meta-theoretical reflexivity.23 However, owing to the
influence of dualist philosophical commitments on these meta-theoretical debates,
until very recently ontological debates in international theory have overwhelmingly
remained either very basic, or confused; concerned only with an ontology of
'things' that exist, rather than an ontology of being. Notable exceptions to this rule,
23. On IR as a derivative discipline see Ronen Palan, “Transnational Theories of Order and
Change: Heterodoxy in International Relations Scholarship,” in Critical International Theory After
25 Years, ed. Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2007).
40
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
which will be discussed in due course, are relatively recent contributions from
Patrick Thaddeus Jackson and Torsten Michel.24
24. See Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory,”
Review of International Studies 34, no. 1 (2008): 129-53; Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, The Conduct
of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of
World Politics (London: Routledge, 2011). and Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness: A
Phenomenological Path Towards a New Social Ontology in International Relations” (Ph.D Thesis,
St Andrews, 2008); Torsten Michel, “Pigs Can’t Fly, Or Can They? Ontology, Scientific Realism
and the Metaphysics of Presence in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 35
(2009): 379-419; Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow: A Phenomenological Critique of
Critical Realism,” Review of International Studies 38 (2012): 209-22.
25. Yosef Lapid coined the term 'Third Debate' to refer to the debate between positivist and post-
positivist theories of IR. Earlier debates in international theory are referred to as the 'First Great
Debate' (between Realism and Idealism) and the Second Great Debate (between scientific and
classical approaches to IR); what is considered to be the 'Third Great Debate' in IR (between
realism, liberalism and radical approaches) is also sometimes referred to as the 'Inter-Paradigm
Debate.' Consequently, what Lapid terms the 'Third Debate' would be considered to be the 'Fourth
Great Debate.' Yosef Lapid, “The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-
Positivist Era,” International Studies Quarterly 33 (1989): 235-54.
26. For a concise yet illuminating overview of the history of positivism and its influence on IR see
Steve Smith, “Positivism and Beyond,” in International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, ed. Steve
Smith, et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 14-18,31-35.
27. Habermas and Gramsci influenced the two pivotal texts in this debate, from Richard K. Ashley
and Robert Cox respectively. See Richard K. Ashley, “Political Realism and Human Interests,”
International Studies Quarterly 25 (1981): 204-36; Robert W. Cox, “Social Forces, States and
World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory,” Millennium: Journal of International
Studies 10, no. 2 (1981): 126-55. For a retrospective discussion of their influence see Nicholas J.
Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White., eds. Critical International Relations Theory After 25 Years
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
41
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Indeed, one of the reasons that positivism was dominant for so long lay in
the fact that by determining 'what kinds of things existed in international relations'
its empiricist epistemology had determined what could be studied in IR.30 In order
to challenge this orthodoxy, post-positivist debates were necessarily
31
epistemologically oriented. And yet, despite highlighting the importance of
28. Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, The Conduct of Inquiry, 72. I am aware that this account of the
development of 'the discipline' is not entirely neutral. However, it is a commonly accepted narrative
and it serves the purpose of situating the thesis as a contribution to meta-theoretical debates in IR.
For an alternative history of the discipline see Craig Murphy, “Critical Theory and the Democratic
Impulse: Understanding a Century-Old Tradition,” in Critical Theory and World Politics, ed.
Richard Wyn Jones (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2001); Craig Murphy, “The Promise of Critical
IR, Partially Kept,” in Critical International Relations Theory After 25 Years, ed. Nicholas Rengger
and Ben Thirkell-White (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
29. Steve Smith, “Positivism and Beyond,” 13. emphasis added. On the links between international
theory and practice, see also Marysia Zalewski, “’All These Theories Yet the Bodies Keep Piling
Up’: Theory, Theorists, Theorising,” in International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, ed. Ken
Booth, Steve Smith, and Marysia Zalewski (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
30. Steve Smith, “Positivism and Beyond,” 11.
31. Ashley and Cox's interventions are good examples of this. Richard K. Ashley, “Political
Realism and Human Interests.”; Robert W. Cox, “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond
International Relations Theory.” The 'great debates' in the discipline's history, between realism and
idealism in the 1930s and 1940s, between the 'scientific' and 'classical' (alternatively, 'traditional')
approaches in the 1960s, or the inter-paradigm debate between realism, pluralism and
globalism/structuralism, did not involve questions of epistemology. As Smith notes, 'the discipline
has tended to accept implicitly a rather simple and, crucially, an uncontested set of positivist
assumptions which have fundamentally stifled debate over both what the world is like and how we
42
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
theory and bringing dissident voices from out of the margins of the discipline, it
could be argued that the emphasis placed on the reflexive importance of
epistemology as constructive of the world of objects (of states and the states-
system, for instance) coupled with the diversification of epistemological
approaches to the study of IR, a degree of epistemological radicalism emerged
from the Third Debate. This, and increasingly unproductive epistemological
debates, were to occasion a shift back to 'ontology,' most prominently heralded by
Alexander Wendt in the mid-1990s.32
might explain it.' Although those working in the 'English School' or on the intersection of
international theory and political theory never really bought into the positivist assumptions that
dominated the discipline, it has been positivism that has dominated the overwhelming character of
the discipline of International Relations. Steve Smith, “Positivism and Beyond,” 11.
32. Alexander Wendt, “Constructing International Politics,” International Security 20, no. 1 (1995):
71-81; Alexander Wendt, “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory,”
International Organization 41, no. 3 (1987): 335-70; Alexander Wendt, “Anarchy is What States
Make of it: The Social Construction of Power Politics,” International Organization 46, no. 2
(1992): 391-425; Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999).
33. On Richard Falk and the World Order School, and peace studies/peace research, see Ken Booth,
Theory of World Security (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 58-69. On dissident
traditions of IR in the USA also see Craig Murphy, “The Promise of Critical IR, Partially Kept.” On
ontological commitments in political thought pre-dating the dominance of positivism or realism see
Hartmut Behr, A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).
34. Steve Smith, “Positivism and Beyond,” 11.
43
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
By arguing that 'what really matters is what there is rather than how we
know it,' Wendt's proposal was that the IR debate should move away from
epistemological questions (specifically, whether the methods of the natural
sciences could be validly applied to social reality) to questions concerning what
kind of things existed in world politics.35 The logic here is that if what really
matters is what kinds of things exist in world politics, then how we know those
things is not important. Wendt's compromise thus warranted an epistemological
pluralism, promising to accommodate positivists and dissidents alike. However,
such a compromise came at the cost of accepting a critical realist philosophy of
science, and it is this critical realist approach to IR that is currently ascending.36
35. Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics, 40.; Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, The
Conduct of Inquiry, 73.
36. See, for instance, a recent forum on critical realism in the Review of International Studies 38(1)
January 2012. See also the forum 'Scientific and Critical Realism in International Relations'
Millennium-Journal of International Studies 35(2) 2007
37. We will explain why such a distinction is contentious in due course. Ibid. Alexander Wendt,
“The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory,” 362.
38. Alexander Wendt, “Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power
Politics.” See also Alexander Wendt, “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations
Theory.”; Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics.
44
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Critical Realism
45
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
realism,' the view that objects exist independently of our knowledge of them.44 As
Wight explains: 'A commitment to depth realism presupposes that there are things,
entities, structures and/or mechanisms that operate and exist independently of our
ability to know or manipulate them.'45 As a result of this 'ontological' commitment
to the existence of objects that lie beyond our comprehension:
One of the basic tenets of a critical realist approach to explanation is that good theories
refer to a mind-independent world, and that this world therefore exercises a limiting effect
on those theories. Both Searle's 'brute facts' and Bhaskar's 'intransitive' objects of
knowledge serve to mark the role played by an external world in realist philosophy of
science: the world is out there, outside of human knowledge practices, and it stubbornly
resists efforts to conceptualise it in ways sharply at variance with itself.46
Critical realists take their cue from the 'ontological turn' in IR, from
Wendt's counter-ontology to structural realism.47 The aim of Wendt's intervention
into the postpositivist debate was to shift focus away from epistemological
questions to 'the kinds of things that exist' in world politics. However, such a move
44. Ibid., 217-18.
45. Colin Wight, Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2006), 29.
46. Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory,” 138.
47. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow,” 211.
46
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
requires the acceptance of a critical realist epistemology, and in particular 'its twin
presuppositions that knowledge reaches out to a mind-independent world, and that
knowledge can go beyond experience to grasp deeper levels of reality.' 48
Consequently, although Wendt's solution to the Third Debate lent credibility to
non-conventional philosophical approaches to the study of world politics, this
pluralism came with two related costs: 'the widespread promulgation of terms such
as "ontology" and "epistemology" with conceptually specific definitions that
preclude other alternatives, and the virtual disappearance of philosophical ontology
from IR debates.'49
48. Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, The Conduct of Inquiry, 73.
49. Ibid.
50. Ibid., 74.
51. Ibid., 74,73.
52. Ibid., 73.
53. For a defence of the scientific realism that informs critical realism see Roy Bhaskar, A Realist
Theory of Science (London: Verso, 1997). For a discussion of the relation between scientific
realism and critical realism see Jonathan Joseph and Colin Wight, “Scientific Realism and
International Relations.”
47
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
54. For a discussion of this point, see Friedrich Kratochwil, “Constructing a New Orthodoxy?
Wendt’s ‘Social Theory of International Politics’ and the Constructivist Challenge,” Millennium-
Journal of International Studies 29, no. 1 (2000): 73-101.
55. Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory,” 130.
Jackson's use of 'perspective' here is also problematic. 'Per-spective' means 'seeing through,' i.e., a
particular filter/angle/conceptual scheme through which we can see an aspect of the world as it is in
itself. I thank Hidemi Suganami for a discussion on this point. With this caveat, I will continue to
use the term 'perspective.'
56. Ibid., 131,130.
57. Ibid., 146.
58. Ibid.
48
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
The crux in Wendt's and Wight's arguments lies with the fact that they commit themselves
willingly or not to a foundationalist enterprise and whether based on ontology or
epistemology this move is indeed a very modern one. Wendt, of course would counter this
argument and insist that his re-conceptualisation is thoroughly anti-foundationalist. He
says: "... realism is anti-foundationalist. Thus, although it is common to conflate the two,
the correspondence theory of truth does not entail epistemological foundationalism. What
makes a theory true is the extent to which it reflects the causal structure of the world, but
theories are always tested against other theories, not against some pre-theoretical
'foundation' of correspondence." (Wendt, 1999: 58-9)
What Wendt shows here is not that his theory is anti-foundationalist but that his
epistemology is not monistic. For his whole account to work, as he admits and we have
shown, there must be a mind-independent ontological ground which does not depend on
any epistemological conception. If this ground exists independent of any epistemology, his
epistemology might be anti-foundational but his ontology is not. Apart from that, scientific
realism in the form Wendt and Wight present is not able to confirm the existence of this
ontologically given reality beyond human existence. As was shown by reference to
examples from the natural as well as social sciences above, any attempt to grasp these
"intransitive" objects unavoidably draws them into a web of linguistic meanings dependent
on social practices. Ontology and epistemology are always intertwined and cannot be
conceptualised independent of one another. Their attempt just to say and rely on what "is"
and then devise ex post epistemological tools to establish knowledge is as misguided as
any attempt to devise epistemological devices in order to discern what "is." Any
conceptualisation of what "is" already takes place within a system of social meanings and
knowledge in the same way as any conceptualisation of what can be known already exists
within a framework of assumptions about what "is."61
59. Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness.”; Torsten Michel, “Pigs Can’t Fly, Or Can They?
Ontology, Scientific Realism and the Metaphysics of Presence in International Relations.”; Torsten
Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow.”
60. Ibid., 210.
61. Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness,” 53-54.
49
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
62. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow,” 210.
63. Ibid., 213.
64. Ibid. It is worth noting that the debate between realism and idealism discussed here is one in the
philosophy of social science, rather than in international theory.
65. Ibid.
66. Ibid., 214.
67. Ibid., 213.
50
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
68. Ibid., 214.
69. Ibid. Michel quotes Heidegger, who regards the 'problem of reality' as the "scandal of
philosophy": 'The ''scandal of philosophy'' does not consist in the fact that this proof [of an external
world] is still lacking up to now, but in the fact that such proofs are expected and attempted again
and again. Such expectations, intentions, and demands grow out of an ontologically insufficient
way of positing what it is from which, independently and ''outside'' of which, a ''world'' is to be
proven as objectively present.' However, as we will see in Chapter 8 the same point is made
differently by Hegel in the first paragraph of the Phenomenology of Spirit, where he tries to make
us anxious about the idea of epistemology as first philosophy. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time,
trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 1962), 249; G.W.F.
Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), §73.
70. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow,” 221.
71. Ibid.
51
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
72. Ibid., 218.
73. Ibid., 220.
74. Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness.”; Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow.”
75. Ibid., 221-22.
52
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
76. Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness: A Phenomenological Path Towards a New Social
Ontology in International Relations [Abstract]” (Ph.D Thesis, St Andrews, 2008).
77. Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness,” 59.
53
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Critical Theory
Critical Theory and critical theory are related, though not equivalent, areas of
inquiry into the social sciences. In the narrow sense, Critical Theory is associated
with several generations of the west European Marxist tradition, known as the
Frankfurt School, which includes, but is not limited to, Max Horkheimer, Theodor
54
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Adorno, Jürgen Habermas, and Axel Honneth. First defined as such by Max
Horkheimer in his 1937 essay Traditional and Critical Theory, for Horkheimer,
theory might be considered 'critical' insofar as it seeks 'to liberate human beings
from the circumstances that enslave them.'78 Jürgen Habermas, a second generation
Frankfurt School social theorist, further develops this nascent epistemology in his
1968 Knowledge and Human Interests wherein he identifies three kinds of
knowledge - technical, practical, and emancipatory - before claiming that any
knowledge about society is incomplete if it does not involve an emancipatory
component.79
Due to this commitment to criticise and transform all the circumstances that
enslave human beings, many 'critical theories' in the broader sense have since been
developed. 80 For this reason, Jay Bernstein's definition of critical theory is
instructive.
Critical Theory started making inroads into international theory in the early
1980s with the publication of seminal articles by Richard K. Ashley and Robert W.
Cox; Ashley's Political Realism and Human Interests draws on Habermas, while
Cox's Social Forces, States and World Orders (1981) and his Gramsci, Hegemony
and International Relations (1983) draw on Gramsci.82 Although both were pivotal
in the development of critical international relations theory (CIRT), and both draw
78. Max Horkheimer, Critical Theory (New York: Seabury Press, 1982), 244.
79. Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests (Boston: Beacon Press, 1972).
80. James Bohman, “Critical Theory,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N.
Zalta (2012). In what follows, when referring to Critical Theory in the narrow sense, that associated
with the Frankfurt School, Critical Theory will be capitalised and/or abbreviated to "CT." When
referring to critical theories in the broader sense, no capitalisation or abbreviation will be employed.
81. J.M. Bernstein, Recovering Ethical Life: Jürgen Habermas and the Future of Critical Theory
(London: Routledge, 1995), 11.
82. Richard K. Ashley, “Political Realism and Human Interests.”; Robert W. Cox, “Social Forces,
States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory.”; Robert W. Cox, “Gramsci,
Hegemony and International Relations: An Essay in Method,” Millennium: Journal of International
Studies 12, no. 2 (1983): 162-75.
55
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
For Ronen Palan, writing twenty-five years after the publication of Cox and
Ashley's articles, one of the principal contributions of CIRT has been to radically
re-situate the discipline in relation to the other social sciences. He argues that the
critical tradition abandoned the efforts to establish the study of IR as a separate,
83. For a discussion of the roles of theory and theorists see Marysia Zalewski, “’All These Theories
Yet the Bodies Keep Piling Up’: Theory, Theorists, Theorising.”. For a critical theoretical account
of the relation between academics and practitioners see Ken Booth, “A Reply to Wallace,” Review
of International Studies 23, no. 3 (1997): 371-77; William Wallace, “Truth and Power, Monks and
Technocrats: Theory and Practice in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 22,
no. 3 (1996): 301-21.
56
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
84. Ronen Palan, “Transnational Theories of Order and Change: Heterodoxy in International
Relations Scholarship,” 50.
85. Ibid., 50,54.
86. Kimberley Hutchings, “Happy Anniversary! Time and Critique in International Relations
Theory,” in Critical International Theory After 25 Years, ed. Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-
White (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 72.
87. Ibid. Robert W. Cox, “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations
Theory,” 87-91.
88. Kimberley Hutchings, “Happy Anniversary!”, 76.
57
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Straddling both normative and empirical inquiry into world politics, what
unites these approaches is their commitment to the emancipatory purposes of
theory and the possibility of alternative global futures. Given its foundational
commitment to human freedom, to the emancipatory purposes of theory, critical
international theory can be regarded as a powerful contribution to left-Hegelian
thought. In contrast to Rawls and Frost, critical international theorists are not
content to treat dominant practices and institutions as 'objective' ethical
foundations, but are often motivated instead by the Marxian assumption that 'all
that is solid eventually melts into air,' and by 'the belief that human beings can
make more of their history under conditions of their own choosing.'90
Despite articulating critical theoretical concerns in his 1982 book Men and
Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, which drew on the voluntarist
tradition of political thought and Hegel's philosophical history, it was not until the
second edition of the book in 1990 that Linklater explicitly engaged with critical
theory by adding a postscript on Habermas and Foucault. Following the subsequent
publications of Beyond Realism and Marxism (1990), two important articles in
Millennium, and his influential The Transformation of Political Community (1998),
it is with good cause that Andrew Linklater is considered to be 'the foremost
critical theorist of international relations.'91 Given transformations in the material
89. Ibid. Andrew Linklater, “The Next Stage in International Relations Theory: A Critical-
Theoretical Point of View,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 21, no. 1 (1992): 77-98;
Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-
Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998).
90. Andrew Linklater, “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” in International Theory: Positivism
and Beyond, ed. Ken Booth Steve Smith, and Marysia Zalewski (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996), 280.
91. Andrew Linklater, “Dialogue, Dialectic and Emancipation in International Relations At the End
of the Post-War Age,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 23, no. 1 (1994): 119-31;
Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd ed. (Basingstoke:
58
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Palgrave Macmillan, 1990); Andrew Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and
International Relations (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990); Andrew Linklater, “The Next
Stage in International Relations Theory: A Critical-Theoretical Point of View.”; Andrew Linklater,
“The Achievements of Critical Theory.”; Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political
Community; Andrew Linklater, “The Changing Contours of Critical International Relations
Theory,” in Critical Theory and World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn-Jones (Boulder: Lynne Reiner,
2001).; Nicholas J. Rengger, “Negative Dialectic? The Two Modes of Critical Theory in World
Politics,” in Critical Theory in World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn Jones (Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner, 2001), 97. Similar sentiments are expressed by Brincat: Shannon Brincat, “Towards an
Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism: Reconstructing the Concept of Emancipation in Critical
International Relations Theory” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Queensland, 2011), 280.
92. Nicholas J. Rengger, “Negative Dialectic? The Two Modes of Critical Theory in World
Politics,” 97.
93. Ibid.
94. As we saw in the Introduction with reference to Australia's reception of 'boat people,' such a
self-regarding particularism extends to the popular imagination.
59
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
far more interesting than much of what passes for reflection (even theory) in
international relations more generally.'95
While Linklater is certainly not the only contributor to the critical project in
IR, the view taken here is that he is the most comprehensive, powerful, and
ultimately the most promising advocate of this position. However, despite being
perhaps the most persuasive international theorist writing today, since both his
conception of emancipation and his defence of moral universalism are predicated
on a foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, Linklater might fall foul of
the same mistake made by Rawls, Frost, and the critical realists: that is, to rely on
an ontology of 'things' presupposed as the condition of his international theory,
rather than an ontology of being. Whereas Frost and Rawls treat their foundational
ethical commitments as the 'ontological' foundation of their normative claims, and
critical realists rely on a mind-independent 'intransitive object' to provide the
'ontological' foundation that warrants their prioritisation of scientific claims about
world politics, we will argue that Linklater relies on the mind-independent
existence of the individual human being conceived as ethical subject as the
'ontological' condition of his approach to CIRT, which warrants his prioritisation of
universal ethical claims.
60
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
A Note on Epistemology
For this reason, as well as the Heideggerian ones he offers, we concur with
Michel's call for a deeper treatment of 'seemingly ontological primitives such as
subjectivity and objectivity.' 96 The strength of Jackson's position lies in his
demonstration that critical realism's approach to ontology, to the 'intransitive
object,' is premised on a mind-world dualism, a foundational split between the
subject and object that occurs between mind and world. The strength of Michel's
position lies in his criticism that dualist approaches to knowledge, approaches that
rely on an epistemological or ontological foundationalism, conflate the ontological
difference between entities and the being of entities. While ontological
foundationalist (realist) approaches treat the object as something that has a mind-
independent existence, epistemological foundationalist (idealist) approaches insist
that the subject is constructive of the world objects: both dualisms conflate the
ontological difference between the mind-independent existence of entities and our
mind-dependent understanding of these entities (the being of these entities).
61
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
we agree with Michel that Heidegger can most certainly can lead us to a deeper
appreciation of 'seemingly ontological primitives such as subjectivity and
objectivity.'97 However, since Heidegger claims to be uninterested in the problem
of knowledge, in what we now call epistemology, he cannot take us much further;
for that we need Hegel.98
97. Ibid.
98. On Heidegger and the problem of knowledge see Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011), 140-41.
99. Patrick Thaddeus Jackson, “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory,” 146.
100. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow,” 219.; Torsten Michel, “Shrouded in Darkness,” 53-
56.
101. Here I follow an argument developed by Tom Rockmore. See Tom Rockmore, Kant and
Phenomenology., especially pp209-215
62
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
63
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
106. Heikki Patomäki and Colin Wight, “After Postpositivism? The Promises of Critical Realism,”
216-19.
64
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Conclusions
107. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology, 213. According to his faculty website at Duquesne
University, Rockmore is currently preparing a manuscript on Epistemology and Phenomenology
that will likely explore these themes further.
108. Ibid., 215.
109. We will return to an extended discussion of the development of the relation between subject
and object from Kant to Hegel in Chapter 6, where we also discuss the inadequacy of the concept of
'subjectivity' in from a Hegelian perspective.
65
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
66
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
67
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
Taking its cues from the wrongs and ills of modern societies, critical theory
is often self-consciously motivated by a left-Hegelian commitment to human
freedom. For this reason, and by refusing to encounter dominant practices and
instructions such as the state as 'objective,' but treating this objectivity as
conditional upon human freedom, critical approaches to international theory might
be seen to overcome the central weakness of other normative approaches to
international theory. However, we concluded by suggesting that, by virtue of his
foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, Linklater might ultimately fall
foul of the same mistake as Rawls, Frost, and the critical realists: that is, to rely on
an ontological foundation of 'things' as the condition of his approach to
international theory, an ontology of the ethical subject, rather than of the human
being as a free being.
68
PART 1/ Ch.1. ‘Ontological’ Foundations in International Theory
For these reasons we concurred with Michel's call for a deeper treatment of
'subjectivity' and 'objectivity' in international thought; yet we claimed that Michel's
intervention is based on a critique and solution found in post-Husserlian
phenomenology, and that this overlooks a more fruitful phenomenological
approach to epistemology that can be found in Hegel. Since the separation of
epistemology from ontology is predicated on the questionable dualist commitment
to a foundational split between mind and world (a split that we will argue must be
regarded as non-foundational, or derivative), and given that Heidegger is
apparently uninterested in epistemology, while Heidegger can help us with a
deeper ontological appreciation of the relation between subject and object, both
epistemologically and ontologically, Hegel is able to take us further.
69
Chapter 2.
Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater's
Critical International Theory
Introduction.
We will recall that Linklater is not the only contributor to the critical project
in international theory, yet that he might be considered to be the most persuasive
and promising advocate of this position. We will also recall that since the early
1980s critical approaches to international theory have developed along two key
paths: a historical/sociological path inaugurated by Cox, and a
normative/philosophical path, inaugurated by Ashley; Linklater, we claimed, has
operated a 'twin track' approach, linking philosophical/normative,
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
1. Mark Hoffman, “Restructuring, Reconstruction, Reinscription, Rearticulation: Four Voices in
Critical International Theory,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 20, no. 2 (1991), 173.
2. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism: Reconstructing the Concept of
Emancipation in Critical International Relations Theory” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Queensland,
2011), 312,303. Linklater has also contributed to the English School. However, in the interests of
brevity we will not be engaging with this work here. See Andrew Linklater and Hidemi Suganami,
The English School of International Relations: A Contemporary Reassessment (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2006).
71
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
Central to Linklater's argument is the view that the modern subject leads a
bifurcated existence, between his simultaneous existence as a political being, a
citizen of a state, and his existence as a moral being by virtue of his humanity.
A very significant part of the history of modern international thought has centred upon
what may be termed the problem of the relationship between men and citizens. We may
characterise this problem in different ways as the issue of the proper relationship between
the obligations which men may be said to acquire qua men and the obligations to which
they are subject as citizens of particular associations; or, as the question of reconciling the
actual or potential universality of human nature with the diversity and division of the
political community.5
This notion of a bifurcated subjectivity, the division between man and citizen, is
crucial to understanding Linklater's approach to both international theory and
political theory, since he regards the moral conflict between the obligations of
3. Andrew Linklater, Critical Theory and World Politics: Citizenship, Sovereignty and Humanity
(London: Routledge, 2007), 30.
4. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd ed.
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990), xi.
5. Ibid., x.
72
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
Claiming that 'any political theory which ignores the problems created by our
double existence as men and citizens is no longer adequate to the conditions of
modern political life; for it fails to attempt to harmonise all aspects of modern
moral and political experience,' one of Linklater's central contentions, both in Men
and Citizens and in subsequent work, is that a crucial challenge posed to IR theory
in an era of globalisation is the need to reconcile this problematic.7 The posing and
answering of this question is seen to be central to the further development of
international theory, and it leads to 'the establishment of important connections
between a consolidated political theory of international relations and that
remarkable tradition of political thought, beginning essentially with Rousseau,
which is concerned with the enhancement of human freedom.'8 Linklater thus reads
the reconciliation of these rights to be a continuation of the emancipatory project of
the Enlightenment, part of the unfinished project of modernity, because it is in the
name of human freedom that the gap between the universal moral obligations that
we have as men, and the particular obligations that we have as citizens, may be
overcome.
73
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
social relations, comes at the expense of the duties that individuals owe to each
other as members of the larger society that encompasses the whole human race.10
Yet, for both Rousseau and Kant, modern men were more than simply members of
states and possessed the capacity to express their freedom in the fundamental
reorganisation of their international relations:
Their historical experience was not that of being unchanging and unchangeable insiders
condemned to live within particularistic social systems, but of being self-developing and
self-directing beings with the possibility of transforming existing relations of intersocietal
estrangement into relations of familiarity, so completing a process which had begun in the
ancient world. An unprecedented political project was made possible by the historically
developed notion of the rights and duties inherent in humans themselves, a concept which
produced the possibility of fundamentally extending the boundaries of moral and political
community.11
10. Andrew Linklater, “Hegel, the State and International Relations,” in Classical Theories of
International Relations, ed. Ian Clark and Iver B. Neumann (Basingstoke: Macmillan Press, 1996),
197.
11. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 26.
12. Ibid., xii.
13. Ibid.
14. Ibid.
74
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
It is in Pufendorf and Vattel's theories of natural law that Linklater finds the
most adequate philosophical defences of modern realist and pluralist international
society approaches to international politics respectively. He criticises both,
however, for failing to provide an adequate account of the relationship between the
contractual rights and duties of citizenship and the idea of humanity. While Vattel
overcomes weaknesses in Pufendorf's account, his own account of the state 'fails to
provide a coherent theory of the relationship between the moralities of men and
citizens.' 15 The various inconsistencies in both their approaches 'are finally
overcome in the Kantian theory of international relations.'16
It is our 'unsocial sociability' that for Kant provides the fillip to lift ourselves
from out of the state of nature and to establish a new kind of freedom, civil
freedom; a freedom that is expressed in 'legal guarantees for persons and their
15. Ibid., 60.
16. Ibid.
17. Immanuel Kant, “Towards Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch,” in Toward Perpetual
Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace, and History, ed. Pauline Kleingeld (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2006), 79. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 97.
18. Ibid., 97,99.
19. Ibid., 99.
75
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
property.'20 For Kant, the highest expression of human freedom however, is not in
the mere fact of choice (natural freedom), nor in the establishment of legal
constraints upon inclination (civil freedom), but in the capacity to exercise self-
constraint and act in conformity with moral imperatives legislated by human
reason (moral freedom).'21
20. Ibid., 142.
21. Ibid.
22. Ibid., 143.
23. Ibid., 112.
24. Ibid., 113.
25. Ibid., 208.
76
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
A theory of the historical development of human freedom offers good reasons for the
belief in obligations to humanity; it also provides the philosophical resources which enable
us to present a vision of a unified moral and political experience, one which can
accommodate the fact of obligations to humanity without permitting these to conflict with
the roles and responsibilities of other communities.'30
26. Ibid., 60.
27. Ibid.
28. Ibid., 140.
29. Ibid., 144,202.
30. Ibid., 202.
77
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
31. Ibid., 144.
32. Ibid., 147. Linklater's reading of Hegel is challenged in Part 3.
33. Ibid.
34. Andrew Linklater, “Hegel, the State and International Relations,” 200.
35. Ibid., 194.
78
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
As we saw above, Hegel's defence of the ethical state is based upon the view
that it was the most adequate actualisation of human freedom: this was its
rationality. However, in the context of international relations, 'the immediate
problem arises of the apparent contradiction between the principle of human
freedom, which demands the rational organisation of political life, and the actual
operations of the international states-system, the coercive or uncontrolled relations
which pertain to the life of states.'38 For this reason, 'when compared to Kant,
Hegel has often been accused of failing to support the ideal of a universal
community which could uphold the freedom of all humanity. The criticism is that
Hegel failed to acknowledge that the process of recognising the freedom of the
other could be extended further than he had realised into the domain of
international relations.'39
36. Ibid., 195-96.
37. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 149.
38. Ibid., 148.
39. Andrew Linklater, “Hegel, the State and International Relations,” 199.
79
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
institutions of the state, but also in the state's external relations.40 He later cites
more recent Hegelian thought, from Shlomo Avineri and Anne Paolucci, in
defence of this claim: for Avineri, Hegel envisaged a world in which 'sovereignty
would diminish and the resort to force would disappear,' while 'Paolucci credits
Hegel with envisaging a universal international society in which all free peoples
are treated as equals.'41 He goes on to note that in some accounts, 'Hegel appears as
a revolutionist precursor of Fukuyama. [For instance,] Smith's recent interpretation
notes that, for Hegel, history is the process of mankind's progressive emancipation
from those forces that inhibit the granting of respect to other individuals, peoples,
and cultures [...] Following Kojève, this interpretation maintains that Hegel
believed the modern state would come to encompass the whole of humanity, thus
ending Andersein, otherness.' 42 Linklater's central point is that Hegel looked
beyond the loosely organised society of states to the possibility of the future
dialectical development of freedom in international relations, although the form
and content of how it might happen is not clear. Rather than pursuing this line of
inquiry, Linklater criticises Hegel for his 'passive philosophical disposition,' and
swiftly moves onto a discussion of Marx.43
The Marxist challenge to Hegel and Kant draws attention to the fact that a
focus on legal and political practices in the development of human freedom is
insufficient, and that we also need to focus on the economic and social conditions
of freedom. This suggests that we need to investigate the nature of international
40. 'Among the rational practices developed in the modern world Hegel included the fact that states
extend recognition to one another and agree to conduct their hostilities without harming 'persons in
their private capacity' Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 148.
41. Andrew Linklater, “Hegel, the State and International Relations,” 193,199.
42. Ibid., 199.
43. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 155. If he had pursued this line, we might expect him to
explore the implications of Axel Honneth's reworking of Hegelian recognition theory for global
politics, as has been done recently in Brincat's excellent thesis. Axel Honneth, The Struggle for
Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1996);
Axel Honneth, Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory (London: Polity, 2007);
Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism:.”
80
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
economic life, and possibly transform the international economic system so that it
better satisfies the goals of human freedom, for '[i]f freedom refers to that set of
circumstances in which individuals collaborate to maintain conditions favourable
to their own development, then it ought to include cooperation to ensure individual
rights of access to a basic level of economic and social resources. For the freedom
of individuals or communities is simply formal in the absence of the capacity to
exercise that freedom.44
44. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 200.
45. Ibid., 159-60.
46. Linklater borrows the notion of a 'scale of forms' from Collingwood and, in hindsight,
recognises that it ‘smacked’ of nineteenth century ideas of civilisational superiority. He later
abandons it, replacing it with how the harm principle has been reflected in history. Shannon
81
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism:,” 297.Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens,
165. And, one would presume, a more solidarist conception of intentional society.
47. Ibid., xii.
48. Ibid., 195,xiii.
49. Ibid., 188.
50. Ibid., 199.
51. Ibid., 185,185,201.
52. Ibid., 199.
53. Ibid., 200.
82
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
obligations that Linklater hopes we may overcome 'the bifurcated nature of modern
moral and political experience,' and thereby lead 'morally unified lives.'54
While Men and Citizens was concerned with the problem of citizenship, and
specifically, how the benefits accrued through citizenship can be reconciled with
the universal obligations to humanity, Linklater's later work, The Transformation
of Political Community, is concerned with the problem of community; in
particular, with the normative, sociological, and praxeological analysis of practices
of inclusion and exclusion in international society. This move is foreshadowed in
the second edition of Men and Citizens, published in 1990, in which he adds a
postscript on Habermas and Foucault. As we saw in the previous chapter,
following the publication of the first edition in 1982, critical social theories started
making contributions to international theory, and this postscript explores the debate
between Critical Theory and anti-foundationalism through the work of Habermas
and Foucault.
54. Ibid., 38-39,25.
55. Ibid., 219.
83
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
The last word in Men and Citizens is given to 'the two great exponents of
moral or political universalism within the tradition of philosophical history,' Kant
and Marx. 58 Yet the subsequent cosmopolitan/communitarian debate and the
'postmodern' anti-foundationalism of writers such as Michel Foucault and Richard
Rorty leads Linklater to recognise that the universalist vision of international
society presented in Men and Citizens is too substantive and potentially exclusive
of difference. Responding to these challenges Linklater restates his position in The
Transformation of Political Community, a 'magisterial work' that is 'not simply the
best account yet available of the contribution critical theory can make to
International Relations, [but] the most impressive account of international theory in
general to have been produced in Britain since Bull's Anarchical Society.'59
56. Ibid., 220,209,219.
57. Ibid., 220-221,226.
58. Ibid., 205.
59. This acclaim is from Steve Smith and Chris Brown, and can be found on the back cover to
Transformation.
84
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
The Kantian and Marxian ideal of a universal society of moral and political
association remains, but Habermas's normative ideal of the universal
communication community replaces the philosophical history of the development
of human freedom as the standard of social criticism. Reflecting the dialogic turn
in critical society theory, which puts the normative ideal of expanding the realm of
social interaction governed by open dialogue front and centre, the goal of a
universal communication community, or, a 'universal dialogic community in which
the justice of all modes of exclusion is tested in open dialogue' is seen to at once
remain true to Kantian and Marxian ideals, and to do what is necessary to update
and extend them.63 Although Linklater concedes that such a universal community
might be an unattainable goal, it nonetheless serves as a standard of social
criticism, something to aspire to and to approach as nearly as we can.64 The
ultimate purpose is the goal of a future global society that rests upon the consent of
each and every member of the human race and furthers 'the autonomy of all human
60. Andrew Linklater, “Citizenship, Community, and Harm in World Politics. Interview With
Shannon Brincat,” in Critical Theory in International Relations and Security Studies: Interviews
and Reflections, ed. Shannon Brincat, Laura Lima, João Nunes (London: Routledge, 2011), 8.
61. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the
Post-Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 84,219-220,79,106,211-212.
62. Richard Shapcott, Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001), 86.
63. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 40-41,220. Norman Geras,
“The View From Everywhere,” Review of International Studies 25, no. 1 (1999): 157-63.
64. Ibid.
85
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
A Defence of Universalism
65. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 22,93,123,22.
66. Ibid., Ch2&3.
67. Ibid., 48.
68. Ibid., 48-49.
86
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
seek to incorporate all human beings into a single form of life because it would
‘support the development of wider communities of discourse which make new
articulations of universality and particularity possible.'69
Linklater takes issue with Rorty's argument that analyses of duties to others
that rest on some notion that others have rights simply by virtue of being human
are 'weak' and 'unconvincing,' arguing instead that sometimes the strongest defence
a culture can give for recognising the rights of outsiders involves nothing other
than an appeal to common humanity.73 Linklater wishes to suggest that there are
duties that members of states owe to others by virtue of their humanity alone and
that other cultures might also assent to this claim. He is aware that:
Writers such as Rorty argue that an ethic which is critical of exclusion may be significant
in the life of the liberal community but it cannot be assumed to have any binding authority
on the rest of the human race. Each community can work out the logic of its own cultural
beliefs and some may impose cosmopolitan checks upon the ethnocentric tendencies
69. Ibid.
70. Ibid., 72,73.
71. Ibid., 76.
72. Ibid.
73. Richard. Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1989), 191. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 78.
87
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
which reside within their own practices and are the source of profound moral unease. But
none can issue moral requirements which others are obliged to obey.74
Nonetheless, he wants to argue that certain appeals to shared humanity may indeed
be able to lay claim to transcultural validity; that there are duties that members of
states owe to others by virtue of their humanity alone, and that other cultures might
also assent to this universalist claim.75 Nevertheless, this shared ground could only
be established through dialogue, because 'what counts as a compelling reason for
resisting practices of exclusion in a Western society cannot be assumed to hold
automatically for all forms of life.'76
Kant believed that separate moral agents had a duty to ask if it was possible to universalise
the maxim underlying any action. Judgments concerning universalisability involved a
process of private ratiocination for individuals rather than any dialogic encounter with
others. Habermas argues that the test of universalisability is found not in private reason but
in associating with others in wider communities dedicated to open and unconstrained
dialogue.80
74. Ibid., 85.
75. Ibid., 79.
76. Ibid., 101.
77. Ibid., 101-02.
78. Ibid., 107.
79. Ibid., 101.
80. Ibid., 91-92.
88
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
89
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
no longer confront each other as geopolitical rivals in the condition of anarchy, and
where domination and force is replaced by dialogue and consent, so as to ensure
that 'global arrangements have the consent of a greater proportion of the human
race.'84
The emancipatory ethical vision initiated in Men and Citizens and updated
through Habermas also receives concrete analysis of the prospects of its realisation
in Transformation. Echoing Kant's recognition of the necessary passage from
ethics to sociology in his connection of 'the normative defence of perpetual peace
with a sociological account of the prospects for its realisation' in his essays
Perpetual Peace and Idea for a Universal History, Linklater argues that there are
three tasks for any critical theory: the normative or philosophical, the sociological,
and the practical or praxeological, which he later refers to as the tripartite structure
of critical theory.85
We have seen that the normative ideal of dialogue sets the trajectory of
Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism, but for Linklater critical theory requires
more; specifically, it requires 'modes of sociological investigation which analyse
the prospects for achieving progress towards higher levels of universality and
difference in the modern world' and it requires praxeological reflection on the
'resources within existing social arrangements which political actors can harness
for radical purposes.' 86 Praxeology, Linklater explains, is not concerned with
strategy or tactics, 'but with revealing that new forms of political community are
immanent within existing forms of life,' and turning these progressive dimensions
84. Ibid., 8.
85. Ibid., 4. Andrew Linklater, “Citizenship, Community, and Harm in World Politics. Interview
With Shannon Brincat,” 26-27.
86. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 4-5.
90
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
A New Medievalism
Linklater enlists Bull's notion of a 'New Medievalism,' 'a modern and secular
equivalent of the kind of universal political organisation that existed in Western
Christendom in the Middle Ages,' as an alternative to the Westphalian state; a
central characteristic of this form of organisation is 'a system of overlapping
authority and multiple loyalty.'89 According to Bull, 'we might imagine [...] that the
government of the United Kingdom had to share its authority on the one hand with
authorities in Scotland, Wales, Wessex and elsewhere, and on the other hand with
a European authority in Brussels and world authorities in New York and Geneva,
to such an extent that the notion of its supremacy over the territory and people of
the United Kingdom had no force.'90
87. Ibid., 5-6.
88. Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics, 3 ed. (Basingstoke:
Palgrave, 2002), 225-47.
89. Ibid., 245.
90. Ibid., 246.
91. Ibid.
91
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
92. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 182,193-198,204.
93. Ibid., 5,7.
94. Ibid., 181.
92
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
project the achievements of national citizenship out into the sphere of international
relations.' 95 While the transnational citizenship of European states is cited as
progress in the right direction, we are urged to look beyond transnational
citizenship rights found in Europe towards a form of cosmopolitan citizenship.
95. Ibid., 212.
96. Richard Falk, “The Making of Global Citizenship,” in The Condition of Citizenship, ed. Bart
van Steenbergen (London: Sage, 1994), 139. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political
Community, 204.
97. Ibid., 205.
98. Ibid., 206.
93
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
99. Ibid., 212.
100. Andrew Linklater, “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” in International Theory:
Positivism and Beyond, ed. Ken Booth Steve Smith, and Marysia Zalewski (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996), 284.
101. Andrew Linklater, “Citizenship, Community, and Harm in World Politics. Interview With
Shannon Brincat,” 1-2.
102. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism:,” 281,312,303.
94
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
95
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
'[I]n this sphere, they are involved in a process of moral-practical learning which differs
from the realm of technical-instrumental learning in which human beings increase their
mastery of nature. Moral-practical learning is key to the development of free social
relations.'103
96
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
That Linklater constantly uses the term 'human subjects' is not incidental; an
historically developing ethical subject with significant debts to Kant's original
formulation undergirds Linklater's CIRT. Linklater's 'Man' is perpetually
confronted by an objective material reality that negates his autonomy, an autonomy
that is conceived as the full appropriation of ethical subjectivity. Reminiscent of
Kant, what persists in Linklater's approach to CIRT is an ethical subject, although
in contrast to Kant, Linklater's ethical subject manifests itself historically. Across
his work, this ethical subject is variously negated by irrational social structures,
exclusionary practices, and parochial ethical discourses.105 In Linklater’s work
emancipation appears as a large scale historical process by which anything that
negates this subjectivity is itself progressively negated, ultimately leading to the
establishment of both the conditions of non-contradiction of ethical subjectivity,
and the gradual self-realisation of this ethical subject over the course of human
history. For Linklater, this involves increasing levels of self-consciousness, the
104. Immanuel Kant, “Perpetual Peace,” 8:357.
105. We will discuss the persistence of the ethical subject in Kant in Chapter 8, having discussed its
pernicious ontological implications in Chapter 6
97
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
rational mastery of self and world, and the development of species-capacities, such
as that of post-conventional reasoning.
We see this in Men and Citizens with the concern to reconcile modern man's
'bifurcated subjectivity,' the reconciliation of his political experience as a citizen
and his moral experience as a human being in order that he can live a 'morally
unified life.'106 More importantly though, this reconciliation is seen to be essential
to the possibility of self-determination. Although also influenced by Rousseau,
Linklater thus follows a Kantian typology of human freedom where natural
freedom in the state of nature is transcended by the civil freedom of political
society, which is itself transcended by the moral freedom of the ethical subject.
Moral rationality is therefore regarded to be the highest form of human freedom, as
this rationality allows the human being to transcend the determinism of the natural
order and act in accordance with universal moral principles. Ultimately then, as
with Kant, for Linklater men are most free when living under political conditions
that allow them to obey 'the laws which they themselves make.'107
106. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 38-39,25.
107. Ibid., 143.
108. Ibid., 102,144.
109. Ibid., 202.
98
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
In his later work, following his own classification of the 'tripartite structure
of critical theory' Linklater moves from both the philosophical / normative defence
of this ethical subject and the praxeological analysis of the possibilities for its
realisation, to an historical sociological analysis of the development of moral
subjectivity over the course of human history. Influenced by Habermas's
reconstruction of historical materialism (and specifically the idea of moral-
practical learning) Linklater engages in his own empirical analysis based upon
Elias's process sociology of civilising processes and the liberal notion of the harm
principle. The aim of such an analysis is to demonstrate both the human capacity
for moral-practical learning, the potential for moral progress in world politics, and
hence the possibility of the gradual pacification of human relations whereby
harmful constraints on human autonomy, such as war, might be removed. While
Kant and Marx's insufficiencies were originally overcome by Habermas's
reconstruction historical materialism and his cosmopolitan ethical ideal of a
discourse theory of morality, it is now Elias who takes centre stage as 'the real heir
to the tradition to which Kant and Marx belonged.111
110. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 2.
111. Andrew Linklater, “Citizenship, Community, and Harm in World Politics. Interview With
Shannon Brincat,” 6-7.
99
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
Conclusions
100
PART 1/ Ch.2. Ethical Subjectivity in Andrew Linklater’s CIRT
Since it requires of us that we encounter both the ethical subject and ethical
subjectivity as 'objective' foundations – that is, since it presupposes the ‘objective’
existence of the ethical subject – Linklater’s critical approach to international
theory rests on a conflation of the ontological difference, between entities that exist
(human beings) and the being of those entities (as ethical subjects). This submits
him to a form of metaphysical dualism: an ontological dualism by virtue of his
treatment of ethical subjectivity as the essential nature of the being of human
beings, and an epistemological dualism whereby the human being conceived as
ethical subject is treated as if it had a mind-independent ('objective') existence,
independent of Linklater's claim to know it.
101
Chapter 3.
Critical International Theory and the Politics of
Subjectivity
Introduction
We then highlight what has been the major fault-line of CIRT since the
1980s: drawn between those proceeding according to a foundational commitment
to a (potentially) rational, autonomous subject, and those that challenge such a
commitment. We see that a common weakness amongst dissidents is that, while
disputing the ontological commitments of foundationalist approaches, they often
leave their own ontological commitments in the dark. Suggesting that the
foundationalist/anti-foundationalist debate in normative theory bears striking
similarities with the realist/idealist dispute in the philosophy of science, we argue
that a greater degree of reflexivity about the relation between subject and object
might help us transcend this debate.
1. Shifting this analysis from epistemology to ethics does not entail a huge leap; especially given
that Habermas's account of discourse ethics insists on 'the cognitive "knowability" or rational
decidability of ethical principles and metaprinciples.' Fred R. Dallmayr, “Introduction,” in The
Communicative Ethics Controversy, ed. Seyla Benhabib and Fred Dallmayr (Cambridge MA: The
MIT Press, 1990), 2-3. On this claim, and for a recent critique of Rawls's constructivist approach to
justice from an epistemological angle, see Eric Thomas Weber, Rawls, Dewey, and Constructivism:
On the Epistemology of Justice (London: Continuum, 2010).
103
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
As we saw in Chapter 1, for the greater part of the latter half of the twentieth
century, positivism dominated the academic study of international relations. Its
methodological commitments dominated the 'neo-neo' orthodoxy of neo-realism
and neo-liberalism, both of which subscribed to what Brown calls the Rationalist
Actor Program, within which mainstream realist and liberal institutionalist scholars
such as Waltz, Keohane, and Axelrod looked to understand how rational actors
behave under conditions of anarchy.2 The first achievement of critical theory is to
take issue with positivism by arguing that knowledge does not arise from the
subject's neutral engagement with an objective reality, but reflects pre-existing
social purposes and interests; it then invites observers 'to reflect upon the social
construction and effects of knowledge and to consider how claims about neutrality
can conceal the role knowledge plays in reproducing unsatisfactory social
arrangements.'3 This meta-theoretical intervention has been crucial to both the
critique of neo-realism and to 'the gradual recovery of a project of enlightenment
and emancipation reworked to escape the familiar pitfalls of idealism.'4
Secondly, critical theory stands opposed to empirical claims about the social
world that assume existing structures to be immutable.5 The central objection is
that 'notions of immutability support structured inequalities of power and wealth
2. Chris Brown, “Situating Critical Realism,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 35, no. 2
(2007), 413.
3. Andrew Linklater, “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” in International Theory: Positivism
and Beyond, ed. Ken Booth Steve Smith, and Marysia Zalewski (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996), 279.
4. Ibid.
5. Ibid.
104
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
which are in principle alterable.'6 The immutability thesis, the idea that human
actions and social structures are 'natural and unchangeable rather than contingent
and renegotiable' is particularly important to neo-realism.7 Central to the neo-
realist position, most evident in the work of Kenneth Waltz, is the proposition that
the international system is made up of sovereign states that interact under a
condition of anarchy; that this structure of the international system is immutable,
and that the actions of international political actors are therefore constrained in a
fundamental way. Most notable in this regard are the constraining effects of an
immutable anarchy on the moral conduct of states in world politics, putative
constraints that Linklater notes 'have the consequence of absolving states of the
moral responsibility for devising practices which will bring more just forms of
world political organisation into existence.'8 From a Critical Theoretical point of
view, the problem with perspectives that subscribe to the immutability thesis is that
they serve to naturalise what is essentially social and historical; Critical Theorists
find this troubling because of their belief that human beings make their own history
and can in principle make it differently.9
105
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
international system, which has been remarkably similar across whole millennia,
will endure indefinitely. The second is that the anarchic system will thwart projects
of reform as in the past.'11 'The neo-realist riposte has been to insist that advancing
the moral case for a different world order will not prevent the recurrence of old
patterns of inter-state rivalry and war.'12 Although CT recognises that there are
constraints on emancipatory change, it avoids the neo-realist advocacy of
resignation to international political fate by examining prospects for greater
freedom immanent in existing social relations.13 Linklater's own contribution to
CIRT is to engage in an historical mode of analysis that aims to undermine the
neo-realist riposte to critical theory by highlighting philosophical contradictions
within the states-system, its historical contingency, an account of how we might
move beyond it, and a sociological analysis of historical processes that
demonstrates the potential for progressive change in human social relations in the
international realm.
106
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
[C]ritical theory judges social arrangements by their capacity to embrace open dialogue
with all others and envisages new forms of political community which break with
unjustified exclusion [...] Critical theory [...] envisages the use of unconstrained discourse
to determine the moral significance of national boundaries and to examine the possibility
of post-sovereign forms of political life.18
15. Ibid., 284-85.
16. Ibid., 280.
17. Ibid., 285-86.
18. Ibid., 280.
107
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
For reasons to be given in what follows, we affirm the first two contributions
of CT but remain sceptical regarding the third and the fourth. Linklater is correct to
reflect on the social construction and effects of knowledge, and to challenge the
immutability thesis in order to provide an opening for progressive and
emancipatory approaches to International Relations. He is also right to argue that a
challenging question for international political theory today is how to balance
between pluralist identities and necessary universalisations.19 The problem is that
the accounts of universality and freedom that emerge from Habermas's
reconstruction of historical materialism and the subsequent development of a
discourse theory of morality are based on a dualist commitment to the ethical
subject. Turning now to a discussion of discourse ethics, we will explore the nature
of this approach to morality, highlight some of its weaknesses before
demonstrating the role that it plays in Linklater's CIRT.
On Discourse Ethics
Moral Cognitivism
108
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
Sharing their commitment to the central role that the exercise of human
reason plays in relation to the attainment of moral autonomy, public justice and
progress, discourse ethics owes substantial debts to the philosophies of Kant,
Hegel, and Marx. Habermas's discourse theory of morality shares with Kant the
view that human autonomy involves the adoption of a universalist standpoint from
which to evaluate and justify our actions. However, rather than subjecting maxims
to monological reasoning to make sure they accord with the categorical imperative,
for Habermas a universal standpoint may be achieved through linguistically
mediated inter-subjective communication; his account thus represents a dialogical
account of moral reasoning.
Integrating Hegel's and Marx's insights that the autonomous subject was not an isolated
Cartesian ego, but a historically and socially situated, concrete, and embodied self, in the
early phases of their formulations, they extended this Enlightenment ideal into a general
critique of the material and social conditions which hindered its realisation. In this task,
they were inspired by Hegel's critique of Kant, which showed the necessity of developing
21. Fred R. Dallmayr, “Introduction,” 2-3.
22. William Rehg, Insight and Solidarity: The Discourse Ethics of Jürgen Habermas (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1997), 34.
23. David Hoy and Thomas McCarthy, Critical Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 148. 'Praxis, in
the old Aristotelian sense, referred to a dimension of action which was categorically 'ethical'
because it could not be separated from a person's essential being or character (ethos); it meant a
doing which was also a being. It also implied action directed towards a particular end (telos), but an
end immanent within the very means used to achieve it, the practice of 'virtue'.' John Milbank,
Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2005), 161.
109
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
a critique of pure reason into a phenomenology of human spirit - the story of reason's
historical and cultural becoming. Reason was thus given a historical, developmental core.24
24. Seyla Benhabib, Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), 344.
25. Lawrence Kohlberg, “The Claim to Moral Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral Judgement,”
Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973), 632. Jean Piaget, The Moral Judgement of the Child
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983).
26. Kohlberg's argument was first presented in his 1958 doctoral thesis under the title of The
Development of Modes of Moral Thinking and Choice in the Years 10 to 16
27. Andrew Linklater, “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” 285.
110
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
28. Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge, Mass.: The
MIT Press, 1992). Lawrence Kohlberg, “The Claim to Moral Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral
Judgement,” 632.
29. For an introduction to Habermas's moral and political theory, and Habermas's roots in, and
differences from Kant, see Thomas McCarthy, “Kantian Constructivism and Reconstructivism:
Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue,” Ethics 105 (1994): 44-63.
30. Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). David
Campbell, “Why Fight? Humanitarianism, Principles, and Post-Structuralism,” Millennium-Journal
of International Studies 27, no. 3 (1998), 504-10. Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney,
International Relations and the Problem of Difference (London: Routledge, 2004), 122-23. Richard
Shapcott, Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001). Beate Jahn, “One Step Forwards, Two Steps Back: Critical Theory as the
Latest Edition of Liberal Idealism,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 27 (1998): 613-41.
31. David Campbell, “Why Fight? Humanitarianism, Principles, and Post-Structuralism,” 504.
111
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
112
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
moral maturity: between care and justice; an insight that has led to the
development of both a feminist, and a phenomenological, ethics of care. 36 A
comparable notion is also supported by both Paul Ricoeur and Axel Honneth in
their respective essays Love and Justice and Love and Morality.37 That this insight
has resonated so profoundly with moral theorists is unsurprising, after all:
Most of us would consider such a person very odd who bases his or her morality solely on
the Kantian notion of duty and justice, like Abraham who would sacrifice his son in the
name of duty. Likewise, most of us would consider immature a person who always listens
to his or her moral sentiments and never considers duty, impartiality, and validly agreed
rules and laws.38
Philosophy and the Social Sciences, ed. Thomas E. Wren (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press,
1990).
36. Nel Noddings, Caring: A Feminist Approach to Ethics and Moral Education (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1984). Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and
Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (Oxford: Polity, 1992). Joan C. Tronto, Moral Boundaries:
A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care (London: Routledge, 1993). Virginia Held, Feminist
Morality: Transforming Culture, Society, and Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1993). Joanna Hodge, Heidegger and Ethics (London: Routledge, 1995). Patricia Benner, “The
Quest for Control and the Possibilities of Care,” in Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science:
Essays in Honour of Hubert L. Dreyfus, ed. Mark Wrathall and Jeff Malpas (Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press, 2000). John Paley, “Heidegger and the Ethics of Care,” Nursing Philosophy 1, no. 1
(2000): 64-75.
37. Paul Ricoeur, “Love and Justice,” in Paul Ricoeur: The Hermeneutics of Action (Thousand
Oaks: Sage, 1996). Axel Honneth, Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory
(London: Polity, 2007), 174.
38. Leena Kakkori and Rauno Huttunen, “The Gilligan-Kohlberg Controversy and Its
Philosophico-Historical Roots,” Encyclopaedia of Philosophy of Education (accessed 26th June,
2012), 19. As we shall see in Chapter 8 these arguments are both foreshadowed and outshone by
Hegel's simultaneous response to Kant's moral formalism and theories of moral sentiments from
members of the Scottish Enlightenment.
39. Seyla Benhabib, Critique, Norm, and Utopia, 340-41.
113
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
confirm in your person the rights of humanity, and I have a legitimate claim to
expect that you will do the same in relation to me.'40
This perspective is contrasted with that of the 'concrete other,' where each
and every human being is treated as 'an individual with a concrete history, identity,
and affective-emotional constitution,' and our relations are governed by the norm
of 'complimentary reciprocity,' where 'each is entitled to expect and to assume
from the other forms of behaviour through which the other feels recognised and
confirmed as a concrete, individual being with specific needs, talents, and
capacities.'41 The characteristic norms of such interaction are those of solidarity,
friendship, love and care, where our interactions go beyond what is strictly
required of us as rights-bearing persons.42 Treating each other in this way confirms
not just our respective humanity, abstractly conceived, but our individuality.43
40. Ibid.
41. Ibid.
42. Ibid.
43. Ibid.
44. David Hoy and Thomas McCarthy, Critical Theory, 201.
45. Ibid.
114
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
remains to be seen whether these 'rational presuppositions' are warranted; after all,
we can engage others in rational discussion without presupposing that there is
ultimately one true interpretation of morally correct conduct; yet these are the
conditions of Habermas's moral cognitivism and his commitment to the ethical
subject: without them moral principles cannot be considered 'objective.'
as is the similar appeal to a 'thin' proceduralism in liberal thinking generally, including that
in Grotius, Hobbes, and Locke. Rather than being neutral and thereby capable of being
embraced by all, regardless of ethical or political view, it is clear that procedural liberalism
entails a particularly liberal vision of the individual and the cultivation of a peculiarly
liberal set of virtues that may be at odds with and threaten alternative modes of life (see
Galston, 1986; Nandy, 1990; and Hopgood, 2000). Iris Marion Young (1996:123-124)
would also add that the idea of a dialogic community as a deliberative device also
presumes and privileges certain ways of speaking (formal, general, and rationalistic) [...]
Thus, the claim of neutrality or universal consent ‘misrecognizes the partisanship on which
it rests’ (Connolly, 1995:124), and Linklater’s universalism appears as only a particular
(relatively thick and substantive) vision among many. Interestingly, Linklater is quite
aware of this critique (see Linklater, 1996a:290-292; and 1998: 87-100), but he seems to
mostly brush such concerns aside as he returns to his single-minded pursuit of a
cosmopolitan view. Thus [...] Linklater's (global) liberal modernization appears, in
Nandy's terms, as the hegemonic framework within which all other forms of cultural life
46. Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney, International Relations and the Problem of
Difference, 110.
115
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
are judged. And [...] deviations from the global liberal vision are judged (at least
implicitly) as backward, regressive, or corrupt unless assimilated to the dominant vision.47
This criticism is on the right track, but it is a little overzealous and somewhat
lacking in nuance. In essence though, the problem with both Habermas’s discourse
theory of morality and Linklater’s adoption of it, is the relation of subject to
subject necessary for the rational reconstruction of universal norms – since this
subject-subject relation presupposes a faith in the reconciliatory potential of human
reason, a ‘thin’ conception of the subject regarding the communicative competence
to engage in discussion, and the subject’s inclination to both engage in such an
activity and to act according to principles thus derived.48 These presuppositions are
all implicated in Linklater’s emancipatory cosmopolitanism, and are necessary for
his defence of freedom and universality; yet it remains to be seen whether they are
necessary for, or even conducive to, an emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
We saw in Chapter 2 that the basic theme uniting Men and Citizens,
Transformation and Linklater’s later work on harm is the idea of moral inclusion
and the extension of rights to ‘outsiders,’ and that in Transformation this leads to
the normative, sociological and praxeological analysis of practices of exclusion in
international society – in short, that Linklater’s normative commitment to universal
inclusion is what drives his approach to CIRT, as it is this that leads him to
problematise practices of exclusion. While affirming his problematisation of
practices of exclusion, the problem with this strategy is that it is predicated on the
inclusion/exclusion of the subject. For practical and philosophical reasons
universal inclusion was not conceived politically, after all states are predicated on
the differential treatment of citizens and non-citizens, and Linklater’s argument
47. Ibid., 111-12.
48. On this point see the dispute between Schiller and Kant on the relation between duty and
inclination Friedrich Schiller, Werke. Nationalausgabe, vol. 1-42 (Weimar: Böhlau, 1943), 357.
Henry E. Allison, Kant’s Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 180-
184,275n3.
116
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
about post-Westphalian forms of community led not to the demise of the state but
its reconstruction. Rather, universal inclusion was conceived in moral terms, where
universality was reconceived as the universal responsibility to engage in dialogue.
49. Martin Weber, “Engaging Globalization: Critical Theory and Global Political Change.” Weber
cites Campbell as an example: David Campbell, “Why Fight? Humanitarianism, Principles, and
Post-Structuralism.” On the post-colonial criticism, see the quote from Inayatullah and Blaney
above.
50. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 48-49.
51. Andrew Linklater, “The Changing Contours of Critical International Relations Theory,” in
Critical Theory and World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn-Jones (Boulder: Lynne Reiner, 2001), 43.
52. Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney, International Relations and the Problem of
Difference, 122.
53. Richard Devetak, “Critical Theory,” 171.
117
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
The value of greater dialogue should not be at issue; Lyotard is surely correct
to argue that ‘the right to speak, and the right of the different not to be excluded
from the speech community, are fundamental rights.’54 What is at issue is the
nature and the function of dialogue. For instance, the concern for Brown is whether
any particular voices are heard louder than others: ‘[c]learly voices cannot be
excluded arbitrarily, and it would be wrong to suggest that either Habermas or his
followers employ Eurocentric or gender-based criteria to restrict the voices that can
be heard. The more compelling criticism is that although these and other dissenting
voices are heard, the cost is that dissenters are obliged to speak in a particular kind
of way, using, as it were, “received pronunciation” rather than the dialects they
employ in everyday life.’55
In regards the latter, the issue is the commitment to the function of dialogue
as a way of transcending moral particularity and extending moral inclusion. In
Chapter 2 we saw that Linklater responds to anti-foundational criticisms of
cosmopolitanism from the likes of Rorty by distinguishing between thick and thin
versions of cosmopolitanism, associating himself with a thin cosmopolitanism that
entails ‘no fixed and final vision of the future.’56 The validity of the latter claim
will not concern us here: the more pertinent issue is that this thin cosmopolitanism
does entail substantive commitments about how that future should be determined.
To put a finer point on it, we should be taking issue with Linklater’s claim that
discourse ethics involves ‘the willingness to engage wildly different human beings
qua human beings,’ because this future is not to be determined by human beings
qua human beings, but as human beings qua ethical subjects.57
54. Jean-François Lyotard, “The Other’s Rights,” in On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty
Lectures, ed. S. Shute and S. Hurley (New York: Basic Books, 1993). Quoted by Andrew Linklater,
The Transformation of Political Community, 98.
55. Chris Brown, “”Our Side”? Critical Theory and International Relations,” in Critical Theory and
World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn Jones (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2001), 198. This criticism
reflects Iris Marion Young's criticism, referred to in the Inayatullah and Blaney quote above.
56. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 48-49.
57. Ibid., 87. Indeed, in the phrase 'wildly different human beings' 'qua human beings' is quite
telling, since the adjective 'wildly different' drops from the latter. Rather than saying 'human beings
qua human beings,' to say 'wildly different human beings qua human beings' is precisely to neglect
the 'wildly different' feature of human beings and impose the idea of 'human beings' upon them:
different human beings are not then engaged as different human beings, but as similarly rational
human beings. I thank Hidemi Suganami for a discussion on this point.
118
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
119
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
120
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
While the subsequent paradigm shift from the production (or work) model of
action operative in Hegel and Marx to communicative interaction in Habermas
brought with it a change in the understanding of freedom that underwrites the
emancipatory aims of CT, we ultimately return to a form of neo-Kantianism.68
'[A]utonomy is no longer conceived of as self-legislation (Kant), self-actualisation
(Hegel and Marx), or reconciliation with otherness (Adorno and Horkheimer). It is
viewed instead as the capacity to adopt a universalist standpoint and act on this
66. This includes second and third generation Frankfurt School critical theorists, specifically
Habermas and Honneth.
67. Seyla Benhabib, Critique, Norm, and Utopia, 344. As we shall se in Chapter 6 Habermas's
emergent dualist commitment to the foundational subject represents a significant but an ill-advised
retreat from Hegel's own position.
68. Ibid., 346.
121
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
69. Ibid.
70. Ibid.
71. Andrew Linklater, “A European Civilising Process?,” in International Relations and the
European Union, ed. Christopher Hill and Michael Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005);
Andrew Linklater, “Civilizing Processes and International Societies,” in Globalization and Global
History, ed. Barry K. Gills and William R. Thompson (London: Routledge, 2006); Andrew
Linklater, “Towards a Sociology of Global Morals With an ‘Emancipatory Intent’,” in Critical
International Theory After 25 Years, ed. Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007); Andrew Linklater, “Global Civilizing Processes and the
Ambiguities of Human Interconnectedness,” European Journal of International Relations 16, no. 2
(2010): 155; Andrew Linklater, “Process Sociology and International Relations,” The Sociological
Review 59 (2011): 48-64; Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World Politics, vol. 1
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).
72. For instance, Hutchings identifies 'dangerous and unwarranted' temporal assumptions in CIRT
that 'distract attention from political plurality, and thereby risk repeating ‘the hubris of Western
political imaginaries.' Kimberley Hutchings, “Happy Anniversary! Time and Critique in
International Relations Theory,” in Critical International Theory After 25 Years, ed. Nicholas
Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 89.
122
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
73. Martha C. Nussbaum, “Kant and Cosmopolitanism,” in Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s
Cosmopolitan Ideal, ed. James Bohman (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1997), 25.
74. Ibid., 26.
75. Ibid., 27. See also Dallmayr's insightful reply: Fred R. Dallmayr, “Cosmopolitanism: Moral and
Political.”
76. Ibid., 430.
77. Nicholas J. Rengger, “Negative Dialectic? The Two Modes of Critical Theory in World
Politics,” in Critical Theory in World Politics, ed. Richard Wyn Jones (Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner, 2001), 100. Fred R. Dallmayr, “Cosmopolitanism: Moral and Political,” 430.
123
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
An Inconsistent Critique?
And so, while Linklater and Habermas are concerned about potentially
conservative implications of anti-foundationalism, and thereby seek to re-establish
a criteria of truth via Habermas' account of discourse ethics and communicative
action, anti-foundationalists are concerned about the potentially assimilatory,
exclusive, or violent response to difference that foundational commitments entail.82
For their part, anti-foundationalists robustly dispute the charge of conservatism,
and it is worth noting that the dispute here is not over the commitment to human
78. See, for example, Linklater's criticism of historicism, Erskine's criticism of Walzer, and
Cochran's criticism of Rortyian or Foucauldian poststructuralism. Andrew Linklater, Men and
Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd ed. (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990),
130-33. Toni Erskine, Embedded Cosmopolitanism: Duties to Strangers and Enemies in a World of
‘Dislocated Communities’ (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 137. Molly Cochran,
Normative Theory in International Relations: A Pragmatic Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999), 167-68.
79. Ibid.
80. Ibid.
81. Ibid., 167.
82. Jürgen Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action Vol. 1; Jürgen Habermas, Theory of
Communicative Action Vol. 2.
124
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
freedom.83 Ashley and Walker, for instance, explicitly claim that their theorising is
in a 'register of freedom,' although as Hutchings explains, this 'register of freedom
is identified with the Foucauldian notion of an imperative to constantly transgress
the boundaries of given limitation (in theory and practice) rather than with any
substantive ideal of a world without oppression.'84
We thus encounter what has been the major fault-line in critical theory since
the early 1980s: drawn 'between theories that are explicitly committed to the
legacy of the philosophy of history in the work of Kant, Hegel and Marx on the
one hand, and theories that deny the validity of the accounts of progress and
singularity inherent in that legacy on the other.'85 The mutual suspicion here is
justified, yet the two perspectives might not be incommensurable. Both are
motivated by a commitment to human freedom, but talk at cross-purposes because
their underlying philosophical (ontological and epistemological) commitments
remain opaque: whereas foundationalists associate freedom with the exercise of a
foundational (usually Kantian) subjectivity, anti-foundationalists demur the
universality of such a commitment, and hence question whether approaches to
politics that take it as a point of departure might constitute an abrogation of human
freedom rather than a defence of it.
125
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
We will recall from Chapter 1 that, while realists rightly observe that entities
exist independently of our claims to know them, the being of those entities does
not; idealists, on the other hand, who rightly maintain that the being of these
entities resides in human understanding, then make the problematic assumption
that this means that the entities themselves are also dependent upon human
understanding.86 The foundationalist/anti-foundationalist debate similarly conflates
the ontological difference. Foundationalists (such as Linklater and Habermas)
rightly recognise that human beings exist independent of our claims to know them,
but they then treat the being of those beings (as ethical subjects) as if it also had a
mind-independent existence; anti-foundationalists rightly recognise that the 'ethical
subject' is a mind-dependent construction, yet since a foundational commitment to
ethical subjectivity leads to potentially exclusive and violent responses to
difference, and due to their commitment to 'irony' or radical autonomy where
freedom is often equated with resistance, they fail to recognise that ethical
subjectivity is a significant historical achievement, and that 'acting as if' we were
ethical subjects is an important aspect of human freedom. We might then draw a
similar conclusion to Michel's concerning the realist/idealist debate: that the debate
86. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow: A Phenomenological Critique of Critical Realism,”
Review of International Studies 38 (2012), 213.
126
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
Yet in the passages to which Linklater refers, Foucault discusses the manner
in which persons form themselves as ethical subjects, a discussion that presents a
powerful challenge to Kohlberg, Habermas, and Linklater's foundational
commitments to subjectivity.90 In this passage Foucault distinguishes between a
'moral code' and moral conduct. Code morality is morality that relies on formal
moral rules, while moral conduct is itself differentiated into motivational guidance
and actual conduct. He writes: 'a rule of conduct is one thing; the conduct that may
87. Ibid., 214.
88. This apt phrase is Martin Weber's Martin Weber, “Engaging Globalization: Critical Theory and
Global Political Change,” 302.
89. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens, 220-221,226.
90. See Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, trans. Robert Hurley, vol. 2: The Use of Pleasure
(New York: Vintage, 1985), 25-28. See also Dallmayr's discussion of this passage Fred R.
Dallmayr, “Cosmopolitanism: Moral and Political,” 430.
127
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
be governed by this rule is another. But another thing still is the manner in which
(one thinks) one ought to conduct oneself,' where one 'forms oneself as an ethical
subject.'91 This adoption of a position of ethical subjectivity is, for Foucault, a
practice of self-formation, which he calls 'ethical work' (travail éthique).92 As
Dallmayr explains in his commentary, moral conduct is not 'rigidly standardised
but is necessarily differentiated among individuals acting in different times and
places,' for modes of self-formation 'do not differ any less from one morality to
another' than do systems of rules and interdictions.'93
The significance of Foucault's argument for our current purposes is not only
that he demonstrates ethical subjectivity to be a labour one performs on oneself in
order to bring oneself into conformity with rules of conduct rather than an innate
human capacity (Kant), or the highest expression of moral maturity (Kohlberg,
Habermas, Linklater).94 Rather, it lies in the fact that, like Heidegger before him,
Foucault acknowledges that freedom is not simply the possession of the subject,
but is also the premise of moral conduct through which one transforms oneself into
an ethical subject. 95 As Foucault explained in an interview before his death,
'freedom has to be seen as the 'ontological condition' of human-being-in-the-world
and as the basis of ethics - where ethics denotes not so much a theory or a codified
set of rules but rather a practice or way of life (ethos).'96
128
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
universalism,' and argues that 'the issue is not simply the slighting of difference as
particularity (which, as such, might still be subsumable under universal rules) [...]
The issue is more serious and has to do with the privileging of moral theory over
praxis, that is, of principles over moral conduct and self-formation grounded in
freedom.'97 This issue of praxis brings into view the domain of politics, a domain
that is unavoidable given the quandaries of moral rules: 'Even assuming
widespread acceptance of universal norms, we know at least since Aristotle that
rules do not directly translate into praxis but require careful interpretation and
application.'98
97. Fred R. Dallmayr, “Cosmopolitanism: Moral and Political,” 434.
98. Ibid.
129
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
Honneth.99 The relative balance of influence between Kant, Hegel and Marx shifts
in favour of Hegel in Honneth's work.100
99. Axel Honneth, The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts
(Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1996); Axel Honneth, Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of
Critical Theory. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism: Reconstructing
the Concept of Emancipation in Critical International Relations Theory” (Ph.D Thesis, University
of Queensland, 2011).
100. Although, as we shall see in Chapter 8, this does not go far enough, particularly in reference to
Honneth's Kantian view of morality.
101. Axel Honneth, The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, 120.
102. Ibid., 121.
103. Ibid., Ch5.
130
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
131
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
In light of Honneth and Joas's criticism of Elias, who demonstrate that Elias's
process sociology relies on the authoritarian and repressive structures of the state
as the 'necessary subjugating central authority for any gains toward "civilisation,"'
Brincat rightly questions the merits of Linklater's recent reliance on Elias's work.107
He notes that Linklater's focus on the reduction of harm for the pacification of
human social relations, as opposed to more positive forms of emancipation, is
surprising, and suggests that Honneth's intersubjective concept of autonomy offers
complimentary insights into Linklater's research agenda that can help further the
emancipatory project of CIRT.108 The problem with Linklater's reliance on Elias's
process sociology in relation to the harm principle is that it fails to take 'into
account the importance of recognitive acts implicit within this process and upon
which the normative potential of the harm principle is fundamentally reliant.'109
For this reason, Honneth's 'refinement' of Hegel's recognition theoretic approach
and the diagnosis of social pathologies are seen by Brincat to be 'broadly
supportive of Linklater's ideal of emancipation through the transformation of
political community and in ways more effective than Elias' process sociology.'110
Brincat then argues that 'it is only through recognition that the unequal moral
significance of proximate and distant suffering - the privilege given to the suffering
of the same “survival group” over all “others” - that has been the common concern
of Linklater's work, can be overcome,' and that hence it is only the combination of
107. Ibid., 308,326.
108. Ibid., 281.
109. Ibid., 298.
110. Ibid.
132
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
111. Ibid., 311
112. Ibid., 327.
113. Ibid., 312,314-315.
114. Robin Cohen and Robert Fine, “Four Cosmopolitan Moments,” in Conceiving
Cosmopolitanism: Theory, Context, and Practice, ed. Steven Vertovec and Robin Cohen (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2003), 142. Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The
Politics of Singularity,” 112.
133
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
For Hegel however, the subject and the individual are two very distinct
categories. The subject is not an individual consciousness formed in its interactions
with other individuals, but is a particular relation between individuals and
universals: this is a very different proposition.118 Honneth, as well as Linklater,
Habermas, and others, uncritically accept Kant’s identification of the individual
and the subject, and hence read Hegel through ‘the kaleidoscope of a Kantian
conception of the subject,’ a conception to which Hegel was profoundly
opposed.119 While Honneth is right to emphasise the importance of love in human
relationships and in the development of personality, as we shall see in Part 3, love
115. This questionable interpretation of Hegel's notion of recognition is not confined to Honneth.
Andy Blunden has shown that other pragmatic interpretations of Hegel, such as Francis Fukuyama
and Robert Williams also commit the same mistake. See Andy Blunden, “The Missing Mediation in
Pragmatic Interpretations of Hegel,” http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/missing-mediation.htm
(accessed 29th June 2012, 2012). We shall outline what we consider to be more powerful insights
of Hegel's in Part 3.
116. Ibid.
117. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991),
50/223.
118. Andy Blunden, “The Missing Mediation in Pragmatic Interpretations of Hegel.”
119. This is Blunden's term. Ibid.
134
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
For Hegel the autonomous subject is an institution, ‘an artefact created by the
practices of modern life: the intimate family, the market economy, and the liberal
state. Each of these social arrangements articulate and express the value and the
authority of the individual; they give to the individual a standing she would not
have without them.’120 These institutions manufacture the idea of an autonomous
individual, an ethical subject of its own actions. Honneth et al. thus read into Hegel
a ‘methodological individualism’ that not only finds no support in his writing, but
to which his whole project was an attempt to overcome.121
135
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
into social philosophy, the very first task must be the renovation of the concept of
“subject”, rejecting both naïve Cartesian or positivist conceptions and anti-
humanist conceptions like those of structuralism and poststructuralism.’124
Coexistentiality
124. Ibid.
125. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007). Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1991). Jean-Luc Nancy, Being Singular Plural
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001). Frederik Olafson's work and Stephen K. White's
survey of the 'weak ontological turn' in political theory are also worthy of note. Frederick A.
Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1995); Frederick A. Olafson, Heidegger and the Ground of Ethics: A Study of Mitsein (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998). Stephen K. White, Sustaining Affirmation: The Strengths of
Weak Ontology in Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
126. Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, xiii. This discussion of Nancy serves to
introduce us to his thought and contextualise him in relation to the overall argument, we will
engage in a more thorough engagement with his work, and Heidegger's, in Chapter 5. For an
overview of Nancy's relevance for IR see Martin Coward, “Jean-Luc Nancy,” in Critical Theorists
and International Relations, ed. Jenny Edkins and Nick Vaughan-Williams (London: Routledge,
2009).
136
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
127. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence.
137
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
Heteronomy
138
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
A Politics of Singularity
132. Ibid., xxii.
133. Ibid., xxiii.
134. Ibid. In regards the relational constitution of subjectivity and its importance for international
theory, it should be noted that Brincat makes similar claims of Honneth's recognition theoretic to
those Odysseos makes for her 'coexistential subjectivity.' Brincat's claim is that Honneth can help
us to understand social relations in a way that can expand the purview of IR theory: Honneth does
not allege that individual human-beings possess specific constitutive essences, an assumption that
underlies Hobbesian, Machiavellian, Liberal, 'First-Image' Realist and even Neo-Realist accounts.
This has allowed Honneth to focus on the role of conflict between social groups as the site of social
reproduction rather than as between individuals (as assumed by Hobbesian and rational choice
theorists), or between structural entities (as assumed in systems theorists, realism and neo-realism
and by structuralists and post-structuralists). Instead, human beings, as social actors, are regarded as
the product of ongoing, intersubjectively constitutive practices that are themselves part of the
ongoing interpretations and struggles of participants. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory
Cosmopolitanism:.” Cf. Louiza Odysseos, “Dangerous Ontologies: The Ethos of Survival and
Ethical Theorizing in International Relations,” Review of International Studies 28 (2002): 403-18.
Both claims seem entirely right, and there are notable similarities here with the relational view of
subjectivity that has been applied to an analysis of collective identity formation in the work of Iver
B. Neumann, David Campbell, and Maja Zehfuss. Iver B. Neumann, “Self and Other in
International Relations,” European Journal of International Relations 2, no. 2 (1996): 139-74; Iver
B. Neumann, Uses of the Other: “the East” in European Identity Formation (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1999). David Campbell, Writing Security: United States Foreign
Policy and the Politics of Identity (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1998). Maja Zehfuss,
“Constructivism in International Relations: The Politics of Reality,” International Politics 44, no. 1
(2007): 58-71.
139
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
135. Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The Politics of Singularity.”
136. Ibid., 118.
137. This argument is most pronounced in Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1996). David Held, Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to
Cosmopolitan Governance (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995), 244.
138. Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The Politics of Singularity,” 118-19.
139. Alex Thomson, Deconstruction and Democracy: Derrida’s Politics of Friendship (London:
Continuum, 2005), 67. Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The Politics of
Singularity,” 119.
140
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
We may venture the suggestion that what unites the approaches surveyed in
this section is the common challenge to the treatment of ‘subjectivity,’ and
especially ethical subjectivity, as in some sense foundational. Odysseos’s analysis
of the ‘subject of coexistence’ demonstrates that coexistent entities, such as
ideological systems, states, civilisations, and the modern political/ethical subject,
owe radical debts to alterity, while Vaughan-Williams’s identification of an
economy of violence at the heart of any ethical generality highlights the fact that
cosmopolitanism cannot simply be based on ethical universals, and has to be
motivated more by a political concern for the singularity of human beings and
political contexts.
Consequently, all the writers mentioned above may be read in some way as
contributions to what it might mean to approach international relations from non-
dualist assumptions. Moreover, they demonstrate that we cannot legitimately rely
on the idea of a foundational subject, ethical or political, to provide the ground for
140. Jacques Derrida, “Nietzsche and the Machine: An Interview With Jacques Derrida By Richard
Beardsworth,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 7 (1994), 240. Jacques Derrida, “Autoimmunity: Real
and Symbolic Suicides. A Dialogue With Jacques Derrida,” in Philosophy in a Time of Terror:
Dialogues With Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida, ed. Giovanna Borradori (Chicago:
Chicago University Press, 2003), 120.
141. Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The Politics of Singularity,” 108.
142. On CIRT as democratic impulse, see Craig Murphy, “Critical Theory and the Democratic
Impulse: Understanding a Century-Old Tradition,” in Critical Theory and World Politics, ed.
Richard Wyn Jones (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2001).
141
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
However, these approaches are largely concerned with critique, with reacting
against and resisting any foundational determination of the being of beings with
the aim of freeing us up for alternative possibilities, while those that do strive to be
more affirmative (Honneth, Brincat) remain reliant on an (intersubjective) subject.
This is not to say that a ‘politics of singularity’ is not affirmative: it is. However,
the relations between the emancipatory aspect of Derrida’s politics of singularity,
the argument in Spectres of Marx and Linklater’s emancipatory approach to
international relations, remain relatively untheorised. Our argument will attempt to
redress this.
142
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
As we have seen, the problem with Linklater’s approach is that he treats the
cognitive object (i.e., the ethical subject) as if it had a mind-independent existence,
which functions as the foundation of his universalism and hence also his
emancipatory cosmopolitanism. Yet if we proceed from non-dualist premises and
engage in a ‘philosophical ontology’ of what it means to be a free being (rather
than simply assume that this amounts to the exercise of ethical subjectivity), if
deemed persuasive, we might consider our ontological argument to represent a
contribution to the construction of our understanding of the human being as a
cognitive object (i.e., a mind-dependent interpretation of the human being as a free
being). This is our intent as we move into Parts 2 and 3. Such an exercise might
constitute a renewed defence of a characteristically ‘critical’ approach to
international theory due to a more persuasive philosophical defence of its
foundational commitments, commitments that are more universalistic than
alternatives (such as Frost’s) and hence more appropriate for contemporary
(global) politics and ethics.
143
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
144. On ethical frameworks producing the works they seek to transform see Brasset & Bulley's
summary of the contributors to a special issue of International Politics on ethics and world politics.
James Brassett and Dan Bulley, “Ethics in World Politics: Cosmopolitanism and Beyond?,”
International Politics 44 (2007), 14-15.
144
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
145
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
While this has resulted in 'human needs and purposes' being brought to the
fore of what counts as valuable knowledge, and it offers a cogent defence of the
normative aims of critical theory, the consequence has been that reflexivity
surrounding the relation between subject and object has been limited to
epistemology; to the problem of knowledge rather than that of being. 148 For
instance, when it comes to ethical theorising, Linklater falls back on a foundational
commitment to the ethical subject, and fails to consider the implications of this
commitment; implications that might even undermine the commitment to
emancipation. For this reason, along with the others given throughout this chapter
145. Andrew Linklater, “The Achievements of Critical Theory,” 295-96.
146. Ibid., 281.
147. Ibid.
148. Ibid.
146
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
and in Chapter 1, we proceed into Parts 2 and 3 with the intent of developing a
non-dualist approach to CIRT, one not predicated on a foundational commitment
to subjectivity or objectivity. In other words, an anti-foundational emancipatory
cosmopolitanism.
Given our discussions so far, it should be not be surprising that we will turn
to Heidegger and Hegel for such a task. Both depend on foundational ontological
commitments (in the fuller sense of the term) to human freedom, and both proceed
from non-dualist premises that can give us a deeper appreciation of seemingly
ontological primitives such as subjectivity and objectivity. Whereas dualists
suppose that the split between subject and object occurs between mind and world,
as is implied by the Kantian association of subjectivity with individuality, for
Hegel at least, the subject-object split occurs within consciousness. This introduces
a vertical dimension to both subjectivity and objectivity that has hitherto been
ignored.149 A non-dualist approach to understanding the human being as a free
being would recognise that dualism is not foundational but derivative, and that
claims to subjectivity and objectivity are essentially political exercises that must
remain open to contestation.
This does not involve rejecting the very many contributions that Linklater
has made to CIRT; rather it seeks to integrate his insights with those of his critics,
surveyed above. Whereas Linklater’s foundational commitment to ethical
subjectivity results in an essentially rationalist emancipatory cosmopolitanism,
where the relation between self and world is ultimately mediated by moral reason,
Heidegger and Hegel are keen to develop a non-mediated, phenomenological
relation to reality, and their arguments in this regard will help us to develop an
alternative praxeological emancipatory cosmopolitanism. We thus proceed into
Parts 2 and 3 with the research question:
149. This is a Hegelian insight, but for an example of such a split between subject and object
occurring within an individual self-consciousness, rather than simply between mind and world, see
G.H. Mead's famous distinction in social psychology between the "I" and the "Me," where the "I" is
the subject, the initiator of actions, and the "Me" represents the cognitive object, known only
retrospectively. George H. Mead, Mind, Self and Society From the Standpoint of a Social
Behaviouralist (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934), 173-78.
147
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
Conclusions.
148
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
149
PART 1/Ch.3. Critical International Theory and the Politics of Subjectivity
foundationalists such as Kant, Habermas, and Linklater assume), but is also about
inter-personal relations and emancipatory praxis. Linklater’s foundational
commitment to ethical subjectivity undermines this inter-personal, relational
aspect of human freedom, and thus represents an inappropriate basis for an
emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
That said, this does not require that we reject Linklater’s emancipatory
cosmopolitanism. Rather, we should recognise it as a potent defence of one aspect
of human freedom: i.e., the self-realisation and autonomy of the ethical subject.
The ideal of more inclusive dialogue in international relations, along with his
proposals for the triple transformation of political community in Transformation,
are basically sound. What we must realise, however, is that these arguments are
predicated on a one-sided conception of human freedom, and that social interaction
governed by open and rational dialogue cannot legitimately claim to be either an
essential expression of human freedom, or its highest form. Moreover, that moral
rationality is not an effective arbiter of difference. As a result, we must look
elsewhere for a reliable guide for emancipatory praxis and a more universalistic
evaluative tool for critical social theory; one that can offer a guide for an
emancipatory cosmopolitanism not based on a commitment to subjectivity.
150
Part 2.
151
PART 2/ Introduction
Introduction to Part 2
1. Hartmut Behr, A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 2.
2. Ibid., 3.
3. Ibid., 246.
4. Ibid.
152
PART 2/ Introduction
153
PART 2/ Introduction
154
PART 2/ Introduction
Nancy and Jacques Derrida for a ‘politics of singularity;’ this, we suggest, should
displace the politics of subjectivity that we argued in Part 1 characterises
Linklater’s emancipatory cosmopolitanism. The reason for this, which will become
clearer in Chapter 5, is that the recognition of the ontological difference heralds a
fundamental discontinuity between ethics and politics: while politics is the process
of projecting and contesting interpretations of the being of beings as a whole,
ethics concerns a relation to the other as ‘singularity’ (rather than subject). As a
result, we argue that a more universalistic approach to ethics would be one based
on the ethical relation: on a relation to the other as other, rather than as an ethical
subject.
We are all too well aware that, given the character of the man and his
political involvements, the suggestion that Heidegger can offer us important
contributions to an ethical and emancipatory cosmopolitanism is to court both
controversy and misunderstanding. As Nikolas Kompridis notes in his recent
Critique and Disclosure, a singularly important contribution to critical theory
based upon the thesis that reconciling Habermas and Heidegger is necessary for the
renewal of the critical tradition: ‘the idea of integrating Heidegger’s thought into
critical theory may be greeted with suspicious resistance if not outright revulsion
by some critical theorists. And the idea that Heidegger’s thought can contribute to
the renewal of critical theory is more likely to be greeted with disbelief (if not
derision) than with curiosity.’5 He continues ‘[t]he fact is, both Heidegger’s person
and his thought have played the role of critical theory’s “other:” he is the very
antithesis of the critical intellectual as critical theorists imagine “him.”’6 Kompridis
demonstrates, however, that Habermas badly misunderstands Heidegger’s insights
5. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future
(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2006).
6. Ibid., 32.
155
PART 2/ Introduction
into world-disclosure, and mishandles arguments that are vitally important for a
renewal of critical theory.7
As Dallmayr has noted, this has important implications for the notion of
inter-human recognition; implications that go beyond Honneth’s account of ‘inter-
subjective’ recognition.10 Whereas in the past recognition has been seen to operate
purely on a cerebral level – such as in the extension of moral community only to
post-conventional discourse agents (Habermas), or as a confrontation between two
independent subjects claiming recognition from one another (Honneth) –
Kompridis’s interpretation of Heidegger’s concepts of receptivity and solicitude
reconnects cognition with affect and sensibility.11 For Kompridis, what this brings
into view is not a ‘bland universalism or cosmopolitanism,’ but ‘an increased
sensitivity to the presence and endangered state of plural “local worlds” – plural
understandings not subsumable under a single notion of being.’12
7. Ibid. Preceding Kompridis's critique, Dallmayr has also demonstrated that Habermas has a very
poor grasp of the significance of Mitsein (being-with) in Heidegger's thought. See Fred R.
Dallmayr, The Other Heidegger (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1995), 59-60.
8. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, 59.
9. Ibid., 211,213.
10. Fred R. Dallmayr, “Nikolas Kompridis. Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past
and Future. (Review),” Notre Dame (2009).
11. Ibid.
12. Ibid.; Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future,
219.
156
PART 2/ Introduction
157
PART 2/ Introduction
Indeed, since one of the central contentions made here is that we may be
constitutively unable to build a valid emancipatory cosmopolitanism from dualist
premises, in order to contribute to a more universalistic philosophical ontology for
IR – especially one committed to emancipatory and ethical relations between
persons – we must take cues from Heidegger’s understanding of fundamental
ontology.16 Infact, given the profundity of his ontological insights and that he is
considered by many to be the twentieth century’s ‘greatest thinker,’ the onus of
justification should rather be on any philosophical ontology that does not engage
with Heidegger’s ‘fundamental ontology.’ With this in mind, we proceed in the
recent spirit of the reconciliation of what have seemed to be divergent trends in
critical theory: where Heidegger’s relation to the critical tradition is
complementary, rather than antagonistic.17
15. Whether or not Marx can be considered an ontological dualist is the subject of ongoing debate.
On Marx's ontological dualism see Anthony King, The Structure of Social Theory (London:
Routledge, 2004), 107-21., while for an opposing perspective, see Murray E.G. Smith, “Against
Dualism: Marxism and the Necessity of Dialectical Monism,” Science & Society 73, no. 3 (2009):
356-85.
16. Heidegger's apparent shift from a monistic to a pluralist ontology in a late seminar does not
negate this contribution. On this shift see Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical
Theory Between Past and Future, 219. Braver makes a convincing case that Heidegger should be
read as an ontological pluralist see Lee Braver, A Thing of This World: A History of Continental
Anti-Realism (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2007), 171-75.
17. Although Dallmayr's Between Freiburg and Frankfurt was an early attempt at this
reconciliation, for Dallmayr it is Critique and Disclosure that 'in a way signals the end of a period
marked by divergent, even opposite tendencies: on the one hand, the "postmodern" fascination with
"extraordinary" rupture (or rapture), and on the other, the streamlining of critical theory in the mold
of a rule-governed, rationalist normalcy.' Fred R. Dallmayr, “Nikolas Kompridis. Critique and
Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future. (Review).” See also Fred R. Dallmayr,
Between Freiburg & Frankfurt: Towards a Critical Ontology. On the reconciliation between
Derrida and Habermas see Richard Beardsworth, “The Future of Critical Philosophy and World
Politics,” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 34, no. 1 (2005): 201-35.
158
Chapter 4.
Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental
Ontology
Introduction
This chapter engages with Heidegger’s Being and Time, read in a way that
emphasises the profound challenges that it poses to dualism; specifically, to the
idea that we might encounter the world in a relation of (epistemological) subject to
(mind-independent) objects. Central in this regard is Heidegger’s argument that our
encounter with entities is never neutral: that ‘things’ never appear to us as they are
‘in-themselves,’ but are always encountered with subjective pre-understandings,
interpretations of the ‘object’ that we surreptitiously project onto it; entities that
include other human beings.
Heidegger’s guiding aim in his most influential work, Being and Time, is to
address the question of the meaning of Being. For Heidegger, this requires that we
distinguish between beings (Seiende) and Being (Sein), or, between entities and
their existence. Three kinds of entities are identified by Heidegger, each of which
1. On hermeneutics and phenomenology see John D. Caputo, “Husserl, Heidegger, and the
Question of a “Hermeneutic” Phenomenology,” Husserl Studies 1 (1984): 157-78. and Susann M.
Laverty, “Hermeneutic Phenomenology and Phenomenology: A Comparison of Historical and
Methodological Considerations,” International Journal of Qualitative Methods 2, no. 3 (2003): 21-
35.
160
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
having a different kind of existence. Mere things, such as rocks, the existence of
which is characterised by being ‘present-at-hand;’ tools, the existence of which is
characterised by their ‘readiness-to-hand;’ and human beings, whose existence is
characterised by Da-sein (there-being). Importantly then, entities and their being
are not coterminous, and the existential uniqueness of human beings lies not in
their subjectivity, but in their Da-sein (there-being). What is particularly unique
about human beings is that they have access to Being, ‘that which determines
entities as entities, that on the basis of which entities are already understood.’2
Being is thus related to the understanding, and so only human beings can have an
understanding of Being: rocks and tools clearly cannot.3 Importantly, contra the
dualist, human beings never encounter entities as knowing subject to mind-
independent object, as we always encounter the entity with a more or less
unconscious understanding of it, and project upon it meaning and possibilities.
2. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford:
Wiley-Blackwell, 1962), 25-26.
3. For a challenge to Heidegger's anthropocentrism here see Giorgio Agamben, The Open: Man and
Animal (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004).
161
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
meaning of Being’ in Being and Time is thus not directed towards an analysis of
the meaning of the entities that are encountered by Da-sein, and neither is it
directed towards the meaning of Da-sein itself, it is directed towards the meaning
of Being in general: the underlying current, the sine qua non of Da-sein’s
encounter with entities.’4
Arguably, the question of Being has been the fundamental question of both
philosophy and theology. Why is there something rather than nothing? Is there any
support for human or cosmic existence? Is the universe primarily composed of
matter, or spirit? Are human beings essentially rational or are they asocial beasts
that need to be subdued? Da-sein has interpreted Being in various ways, and these
various interpretations have influenced our political and ethical lives since they
inform our interpretations of the being of the entities that we encounter. What
would life be like in a ‘state of nature?’ What then justifies authority? Security
(Hobbes)? Protection of property? (Locke) Democratic legitimacy? (Rousseau) Is
man essentially rational? If so, then surely we should act in a way that allows him
to flourish as a rational being (Kant). In a theological register, Christians may
encounter other human beings as essentially all God’s children, fallen, but
endowed with reason and essentially good, and standing towards the earth as
stewards of God’s creation. Each understanding of Being will inform the way that
human beings (Da-sein) interpret their own existence, and will inform the
possibilities that they project for themselves and for others.5 These are all examples
of different interpretations of Being that serve as the sine qua non of Da-sein’s
encounter with entities in the world, both ‘things’ and other human beings. In each
case the encounter with entities occurs in the light of an understanding of Being,
‘that on the basis of which entities are already understood.’6
4. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow: A Phenomenological Critique of Critical Realism,”
Review of International Studies 38 (2012), 221.
5. 'As a nominalized infinitive, Dasein has no plural. It refers to any and every human being, in
much the way that das Seiende, lit. “that which is,” refers to any and every being. When more than
one person is in play Heidegger speaks of (the) other(s) or Dasein-wifh (Mitdasein). He revives the
original sense, “being there,” often writing Da-sein to stress this.' Michael Inwood, A Heidegger
Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 42.
6. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 25-26.
162
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
7. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future
(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2006), 219.
8. Paul Gorner, Twentieth Century German Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000),
116. Heidegger tells us from the start that Da-sein is being-in-the-world, but we are never directly
in the world; we are always thrown into a particular context that informs the way that we relate to
the world. Heidegger calls this situation a Lichtung (Clearing). This is an open space within which
we can encounter objects. 'Things show up in the light of our understanding of being.' Hubert
Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time (Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press, 1991), 163.
163
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
9. Dorothea Frede, “The Question of Being: Heidegger’s Project,” in The Cambridge Companion to
Heidegger, ed. Charles Guignon (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 45. emphasis
added
10. Ibid.
11. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007), 35.
12. Ibid.
164
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Being led Heidegger to conclude that reality is in fact framed by the subject’s
understanding.13 This leads to his attempt in Being and Time to find a way to
access a pre-theoretical attitude toward the world and reality.14
Heidegger’s engagement with Scotus led to his related argument that the
objectifying attitude of the subject towards the object originates in the theoretical
attitude itself.15 He thus wanted to inquire as to a method for ontology that would
avoid the imposition of subjective categories onto reality the way that modes of
theoretical thinking did.16 In short, for Heidegger, theoretical activity served to
‘un-live’ human experience and objectify existence.17 Although Heidegger was not
against theory he wanted to mitigate the inevitably subjectivist bias of the
theoretical orientation by grounding it in an holistic conception of human existence
as Da-sein; as being-in-the-world, with ‘care’ (Sorge) as the meaning of that
existence, and temporality as the transcendental horizon of any interpretation of
Being.18
Fundamental Ontology
165
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
In the terms of the overall argument presented here then, what Heidegger is
offering us in Being and Time is an account of the human being that goes deeper
than the dualist reliance on a foundational subject. This account has profound
implications for the emancipatory project of CIRT since it fundamentally alters the
way that we understand the nature of the relations between human beings and other
entities in world politics; this includes social objects such as states and the
international system, but most importantly, the nature of our relations with other
human beings.
Being and Time is divided into three sections: the Introduction, Division One,
and Division Two, each in turn divided into chapters. The Introduction establishes
the priority and necessity of the question of Being by rehearsing the argument
against metaphysical realism outlined above. As Heidegger puts it: ‘we always
conduct our activities in an understanding of Being,’ where Being is ‘that which
19. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 68.
20. Ibid., 61.
166
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Basic concepts determine the way in which we get an understanding beforehand of the
area of subject-matter underlying all the objects a science takes as its theme, and all
positive investigation is guided by this understanding. Only after the area itself has been
explored beforehand in a corresponding manner do these concepts become genuinely
demonstrated and “grounded.” But since every area is itself obtained from the domain of
entities themselves, this preliminary research, from which the basic concepts are drawn,
signifies nothing else but an interpretation of those entities with regard to their basic state
of Being.23
21. Ibid., 25.
22. See Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Continuum, 2004), 268-306. For
Heidegger's discussion of the hermeneutical circle: Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 362-63.
23. Ibid., 30.
24. Ibid., 31.
25. Ibid.
26. Torsten Michel, “In Heidegger’s Shadow.”
167
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
he identifies structures that inform the human experience of existence and that
constitute the structure of Dasein; these include ‘worldliness,’ ‘being-with,’ and
‘care.’ Division Two then offers a general interpretation of ‘the meaning of Being,’
which Heidegger identifies as ‘temporality:’ temporality is posited as the horizon
of any interpretation of existence. The final part of Division Two then returns to
the ontological structures identified in Division One in order to demonstrate their
existential-temporal nature. We will now proceed to discuss Divisions One and
Two in greater depth.
Worldhood (BT:91-149)
27. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 33.
28. On these four uses see Ibid., 93.
168
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Being-with (BT:149-169)
Care (BT:225-270)
The third existential structure of Da-sein is ‘care’ (Sorge). Care discloses the
concrete constitution of Da-sein’s existence and is itself constituted by three
elements: Da-sein’s facticity or thrownness, falling, and projection. These loosely
correspond to an individual’s past, present, and future, and presage the later
determination of time as the horizon of any interpretation of Being. Care thus
represents the ‘structural whole’ of Da-sein, which is to say that concernful
relations with the world represent the state of being of Da-sein:
29. Ibid., 149.
30. Ibid., 155.
31. Ibid., 153.
32. Ibid., 329-30.
169
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
[T]he Being of the “world” is, as it were, dictated to it in terms of a definite idea of Being
which lies veiled in the concept of substantiality, and in terms of the idea of a knowledge
by which such entities are cognized. The kind of Being which belongs to entities within-
the-world is something which they themselves might have been permitted to present; but
Descartes does not let them do so. Instead he prescribes for the world its real Being, as it
were, on the basis on an idea of Being whose source has not been unveiled and which has
not been demonstrated in its own right – an idea in which Being is equated with constant
presence-at-hand.35
170
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
encounter with things that are always already ready-to-hand, and which therefore
come laden with context-dependent significance. Perhaps his best statement of this
distinction comes later in Being and Time:
What we “first” hear is never noises or complexes of sounds, but the creaking wagon, the
motor-cycle. We hear the column on the march, the north wind, the woodpecker tapping,
the fire crackling [...] It requires a very artificial and complicated frame of mind to “hear”
a “pure noise.” The fact that motor-cycles and wagons are what we proximally hear is the
phenomenal evidence that in every case Dasein, as Being-in-the-world, already dwells
alongside what is ready-to-hand within-the-world; it certainly does not dwell proximally
alongside “sensations;” nor would it first have to give shape to the swirl of sensations to
provide a springboard from which the subject leaps off and finally arrives at a “world.”
Dasein, as essentially understanding, is proximally alongside what is understood.36
The difference then, is that rather than starting with pure present-at-hand
‘substances’ that appear simply as they are ‘in-themselves,’ Da-sein’s worldhood
means that it has always already conferred meaning upon the entities that it
encounters. Trying to adopt a more objective perspective on those entities involves
attempting to strip away the layers of meaning that we project upon them; a task
that can perhaps never be fully achieved.37 This projection of meaning is not
confined to things or tools, it will happen in our encounter with other persons too.
Mitsein / Intersubjectivity
36. Ibid., 207.
37. This is what happens during our constructions of cognitive objects. In the end though, cognitive
objects are never simply reflections of the mind-independent real but are more or less adequate
constructions of mind-independent entities.
38. See Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures
(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1990), 136-139,148-152.
171
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Lastly, rather than presenting the human being as a subject, Heidegger has
something altogether different in mind; namely, man as ‘ek-sistent’. The structural
totality of ‘care’ (Sorge) as Da-sein’s essential state of being reflects the view that
Da-sein has been ‘thrown;’ it has been brought into existence, but not of its own
accord. Importantly, Da-sein cannot come back behind its thrownness to have
power over its being from the ground up, so our understanding of existence is only
possible on the basis of our thrownness, a basis that is beyond our power or
control. Nonetheless, we understand ourselves in terms of possibilities and
continually project ourselves into different possible futures; Da-sein is then
nothing else but a constant becoming, right up to the point of death, when it ceases
to exist. Da-sein is that being that is ‘between’ birth and death; existence is
definitive for Da-sein, which exists as possibility rather than as ground.
172
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
that ‘existence precedes essence.’40 We should not confuse Sartre’s claim with
Heidegger’s, however. The difference between the two is most pronounced in
Heidegger’s response to Sartre’s claim that ‘existentialism is a humanism’ in his
Letter on Humanism, where Heidegger clarifies what is meant by his claim that
existence is definitive for Da-sein. This is not a question of existential priority
between existence and essence, since this would perpetuate the metaphysical
tradition that Heidegger is trying to overcome. Rather, the key lies in the
relationship between man and Being. Da-sein’s existence is thus distinguished not
by some essence, something that precedes, but by its ‘ek-sistence,’ a neologism
that is intended to distinguish his own view that existence is definitive of human
being from Sartre’s, and is meant to signify that man ‘stands out’ into the ‘truth of
Being.’
In Being and Time ‘ecstatic’ temporality (from the Greek ekstasis) signifies
the way that human being stands out the various moments of the temporality of
care, being ‘thrown’ out of a past and ‘projecting’ towards a future by way of the
present.41 Ek-sistence is both the ground of the possibility of reason (ratio) but also
the ‘essence’ of man, in that it relates to the human way ‘to be.’42 ‘As ek-sisting,
man sustains Da-sein in that he takes the Da, the clearing of Being, into “care.” But
Da-sein itself occurs essentially as “thrown.” It unfolds essentially in the throw of
Being as the fateful sending.’43 Distinguishing this view of man from those within
the metaphysical tradition, Heidegger writes:
The ecstatic essence of man consists in ek-sistence, which is different from the
metaphysically conceived essentia. Medieval philosophy conceives the latter as actualitas.
Kant represents existentia as actuality in the sense of the objectivity of experience. Hegel
defines existentia as the self-knowing Idea of absolute subjectivity. Nietzsche grasps
essentia as the eternal recurrence of the same.44
40. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism is a Humanism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007).
41. Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism,” in Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, ed. David F.
Krell (New York: Harper Collins, 1993), 204. cf. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 54.
42. Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism,” 204.
43. Ibid., 230-31. In Being and Time Heidegger writes: 'And how is Dasein this thrown basis? Only
in that it projects itself upon possibilities into which it has been thrown. The Self, which as such has
to lay the basis for itself, can never get that basis into its power; and yet, as existing, it must take
over Being-a-basis.' Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 330.
44. Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism,” 229.
173
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
45. Ibid., 230.
46. Ibid., 234.
47. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 371.
48. Ibid., 368.
174
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
view the entity which, in every case, it is itself. The everyday interpretation of the
Self, however, has a tendency to understand itself in terms of the “world” with
which it is concerned.’49 Understanding social relations as intersubjective relations
presupposes then a shared interpretation of Being, and hypostatises the process by
which Being itself is co-disclosed with others. ‘Both talking and hearing are based
upon understanding. And understanding arises neither through talking at length nor
through busily hearing something “all around.” Only he who already understands
can listen.’50 According to Heidegger then, Da-sein’s proper role is not to establish
the conditions of subjectivity but to ‘let Being be;’ to allow others to present
themselves in their uniqueness, not simply as ethical subjects engaging in dialogue.
Our political projects should aspire to allow the ‘here’, the ‘da’ of our Da-sein,
what Heidegger calls ‘the clearing’ to be a place where Being can be disclosed, can
come to presence.
Most poignantly experienced in the phenomenon of anxiety – which is not fear of anything
at hand but awareness of my being-in-the-world as such – “care” describes the sundry
ways I get involved in the issue of my birth, life, and death, whether by my projects,
inclinations, insights, or illusions. “Care” is the all-inclusive name for my concern for
other people, preoccupations with things, and awareness of my proper Being. It expresses
49. Ibid.
50. Ibid., 208.
51. Ibid., 273-74.
175
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
the movement of my life out of a past, into a future, through the present. In section 65 the
ontological meaning of the Being of care proves to be temporality.52
176
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
as the ‘upon which’ of any projection of Being. Temporality is the basis of our
concern with the world; our understanding of the world is both temporal and
temporary.
177
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
with time. The structures of concernful relations with the world explored in
Division One are thus ultimately subjected to finitude (Endlichkeit).
The indefiniteness of one’s own potentiality-for-Being, even when this potentiality has
become certain in a resolution, is first made wholly manifest in Being-towards-death.
Anticipation brings Dasein face to face with a possibility which is constantly certain but
which at any moment remains indefinite as to when that possibility will become an
impossibility. Anticipation makes it manifest that this entity has been thrown into the
indefiniteness of its “limit-Situation;” when resolved upon the latter, Dasein gains its
authentic potentiality-for-Being-a-whole. The indefiniteness of death is primordially
disclosed in anxiety. But this primordial anxiety strives to exact resoluteness of itself. It
moves out of the way everything which conceals the fact that Dasein is abandoned to
itself. The “nothing” with which anxiety brings us face to face, unveils the nullity by
which Dasein, in its very basis, is defined; and this basis itself is as thrownness into
death.60
In short, confronting our own mortality leads us to realise that ultimately we are
responsible for our own self-actualisation, which frees us from our absorption in
the present, our lostness in ‘the they’ (das Man).61 This freedom is ‘resoluteness’
(Entschlossenheit).
Resoluteness
60. Ibid., 356.
61. Ibid., 311.
62. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future,
51n11,58.
178
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
intended in Being and Time is not the deliberate action of a subject but the opening
up of human being, out of its captivity in beings, to the openness of Being.’63
[A]nticipation reveals to Dasein its lostness in the they-self, and brings it face to face with
the possibility of being itself, primarily unsupported by concernful solicitude, but of being
itself, rather, in an impassioned freedom towards death – a freedom which has been
released from the Illusions of the “they,” and which is factical, certain of itself, and
anxious.64
179
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Resoluteness, as authentic Being-one’s-Self, does not detach Dasein from its world, nor
does it isolate it so that it becomes a free-floating “I.” And how should it, when
resoluteness as authentic disclosedness, is authentically nothing else than Being-in-the-
world? Resoluteness brings the Self right into its current concernful Being-alongside what
is ready-to-hand, and pushes it into solicitous Being with Others.66
Solicitude
Solicitude (Fürsorge) itself is a neutral concept, and there are different types
of solicitous relations with others, ranging from the negative (indifference) to the
positive (‘active’). It is the mode of indifference that characterises everyday being-
with-one-another, and this mode of indifference often gets misinterpreted as the
66. Ibid., 344.
67. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future, 49.
68. Ibid.
69. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 344. emphasis added.
70. Ibid., 157.
180
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
[Positive solicitude] can, as it were, take away “care” from the Other and put itself in its
position of concern: it can leap in for him. This kind of solicitude takes over for the other
that with which he is to concern himself. The Other is thus thrown out of his own position;
he steps back so that afterwards, when the matter has been attended to, he can either take it
over as something finished and at his disposal, or disburden himself of it completely. In
such solicitude the Other can become one who is dominated and dependent, even if this
domination is a tacit one and remains hidden from him. This kind of solicitude, which
leaps in and takes away “care,” is to a large extent determinative for Being with one
another, and pertains for the most part to our concern with the ready-to-hand. In contrast to
this there is also the possibility of a kind of solicitude which does not so much leap in for
the other as leap ahead of him (ihm vorausspringt) in his existentiell potentiality-for-
Being, not in order to take away his “care” but rather to give it back to him authentically as
such for the first time. This kind of solicitude pertains essentially to authentic care – that
is, to the existence of the Other, not as a “what” with which he is concerned; it helps the
other to become transparent to himself in his care and to become free for it.72
71. Ibid., 158.
72. Ibid., 158-59.
73. 'In the light of the "for-the-sake-of-which" of one's self-chosen potentiality-for-Being, resolute
Dasein frees itself for its world. Dasein's resoluteness towards itself is what first makes it possible
to let the Others who are with it 'be' in their ownmost potentiality-for-Being, and to co-disclose this
potentiality in the solicitude which leaps forward and liberates ... Only by authentically Being-their-
Selves in resoluteness can people authentically be with one another.' Ibid., 344.
181
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
74. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future,
53,54,56.
182
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
183
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
ontological difference between entities and their being. Calling for such inquiry to
be grounded in fundamental ontology, on non-dualist premises, would contribute
to the recovery of the question of Being because it would involve the recognition
that any reliance on ethical subjectivity (as in the case of moral universality) or
claim to epistemological objectivity (to have access to a mind-independent object)
is itself dependent upon an interpretation of Being that is essentially contestable –
such as a philosophical history of human freedom (Linklater), or the
overestimation of science as a human potentiality (critical realists). It has been an
unwarranted faith in the nature of metaphysics that has led us to disregard the
ontological difference, and to forget that these are essentially contestable
perspectives on the world. This faith in metaphysics has been allied with a form of
representational thinking and relies upon a mind-world dualism.
184
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
The 'death of God' is a problem for our understanding of what human beings
are because European thought had essentially relied upon God as an anchor for
everything else. God was there to explain why the universe made sense, he was the
answer to the endless question: but why? ‘Why do we exist?’ Because God created
us. ‘But why should we trust our reason?’ Because God is rational and God came
first. As Yannaras explains, the historical self-consciousness of Europe had
77. Freidrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 120.
185
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
presupposed God as both 'a conceptual "first cause" of cosmology and as the
axiomatic "principle" of categorical morality.'78
Even as early as the ninth-century Carolingian "Renaissance," but especially with the
radical distortion of Aristotelian epistemology by scholasticism, European metaphysics has
been built upon by the presupposition of God's existence, while progressively excluding
his presence from the world. God is either identified with the conceptual notion of an
impersonal and abstract "first cause" of the universe (causa prima), or of an absolute
"authority" in ethical (principium auctoritatis). In both cases the existence of God is a
conceptual necessity, secured by demonstrative argument, but unrelated to historical
experience and the existential condition of human beings.79
78. Christos Yannaras, On the Absence and Unknowability of God: Heidegger and the Areopagite
(London: T&T Clark, 2005), 40.
79. Ibid., 22.
80. Ibid., 21.
81. For a discussion of the causes of this growing scepticism and disbelief see Andrew Norman
Wilson, God’s Funeral: The Decline of Faith in Western Civilisation (London: W.W. Norton,
1999).
82. Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, trans. David Farrell Krell, vol. One: The Will to Power as Art
(London: Routledge, 1981), 204-06; Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, trans. David Farrell Krell, vol.
Two: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same (San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1991), 199-203.
83. Gregory Bruce Smith, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and the Transition to Postmodernity (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1995), 229.
84. This distinguishes Heidegger from Rorty. See Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and
Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989). especially 46-121
186
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Man will inevitably still speculate as to the essence of man, the origins of the
universe, or the purpose of human existence; in Heidegger's words '[a]s long as
man remains the animal rationale he is also the animal metaphysicum. As long as
man understands himself as the rational animal, metaphysics belongs, as Kant said,
to the nature of man.'85 We will still project meaning, and we will still engage in
rational 'ontic' analysis of the entities that we encounter: causal analysis, for
instance, or similar epistemological analyses that suppose a subject facing an
object or objects; similarly, rational ethical analysis that supposes relations
between subjects. However, with the withdrawal of any transcendent authority, the
'death' of God, we can no longer consider these exercises to be reflections of a
mind-independent real and must recognise that they can only ever be perspectives
on it. Heidegger is, therefore, simply arguing that these 'reflections' of reality must
now be grounded in a pre-theoretical experience of reality: this is the task of Being
and Time, to ground such theoretical endeavours and thereby prepare for such an
overcoming of metaphysics.
85. Martin Heidegger, Introduction to ‘What is Metaphysics’, trans. Walter Kaufmann, Pathmarks
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 279.
86. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 276.
187
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Since the whole can never be fully illuminated, human intelligibility will
always be partial or horizonal as it depends on sites within the whole (of beings) to
act as orienting centres. The whole then can never be fully illuminated because we
can never escape our own situation within the whole, nor our own mortality. It is
therefore our finitude, our mortality, that characterises our relationship to Being:
both because our confrontation with our own mortality compels us into a state of
anticipatory resoluteness through which we participate in the disclosure and co-
disclosure of Being with others, and because our finitude means that our
intelligibility of Being as a whole is horizonal and temporal. This is what is meant
by Heidegger's claim that temporality (Zeitlichkeit) is the 'upon which' that any
interpretation of Being is based; 'temporariness' or 'temporaeity' is the
transcendental horizon of any understanding of Being.87
As Lewis puts it, the response to one's own birth and death introduces a 'site
of singularity into beings as a whole.'88 This singularity is not identical with Being
as a whole but is a precondition of its disclosure. In Heidegger’s words:
188
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Since human beings are finite, mortal creatures, our partial, horizonal,
interpretations of Being themselves are subject to a temporal horizon that we
cannot transcend. Universal statements about what makes a human being a human
being are constitutively unable to transcend our own perspectival relation to Being
because, as Heidegger puts it, if one is to take a position one must already have a
place to stand.
Any enunciated statement requires a place from which to enunciate. Given that the
statement [i.e., a metaphysical statement] attempts to determine beings as a whole and
without exception, it is constitutively unable to take account of its own placement within
this whole, its historical situatedness or "thrownness," the very givenness of the whole,
which constitutes an exception to its determination of this whole by providing something
which cannot be understood from within this "position." Metaphysics as a whole cannot
understand the inherence to the whole of perspectival presentation, otherwise it would fall
apart.90
‘Overcoming’ Metaphysics
189
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
The problem with the history of Western philosophy, for Heidegger then, is
that it has tried to understand beings as a whole by identifying properties or traits
that make beings beings 'as such'. Various attempts have been made by writers to
represent that which is most basic to humans thus allowing us to grasp the whole in
its essence. What this neglects is that these attempts to grasp the whole involve
projecting an understanding of the being of the entities that are to be grasped, an
understanding that is inevitably grounded in Dasein's own concernful relations
with the world, which are limited in scope and grounded in time. Such an
identification of properties that are distinctive to entities is always done on the
basis of some prior understanding of human existence: it is always done in the light
of Being.
91. Pierre Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice (Cambridge: Polity, 1990), 68.
190
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
possibilities, making it seem as if there are not multiple, but only a single
possibility.'92
Heidegger's Anti-Foundationalism
92. Pierre Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1977), 164.
93. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the
Post-Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 76.
94. Ibid., 78.
191
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
persisting as something that can be known, handled, and worked upon.'95 The
ground is that which is considered to be 'the ontic causation of the actual, the
transcendental making possible of the objectivity of objects.' 96 It has been
interpreted as 'the dialectical mediation of the movement of absolute spirit [Hegel]
and of the historical process of production [Marx], and the will to power positing
values. [Nietzsche]'97
192
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
existence, and the nature of human beings – upon which it relies.98 This chapter
has sought to initiate such a task. One of its central claims is that Heidegger's
fundamental ontology presents a profound challenge to the metaphysical dualism
that characterises Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism: a dualism comprised
of a foundational ontological commitment to ethical subjectivity, and a
foundational epistemological commitment to the individual (conceived as ethical
subject) as mind-independent cognitive object.
98. Hartmut Behr, A History of International Political Theory: Ontologies of the International
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 246.
99. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 351.
193
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Division One of Being and Time, as discussed in the first part of this chapter,
thus poses a profound challenge to the view of the individual as subject: a view
that underwrites the understanding of emancipation as the process whereby ethical
subjectivity can be exercised (as implicit in Linklater's account), but also the
moves in more recent critical theory that locate the emancipatory project in
relations of intersubjectivity (such as in Honneth and Brincat). The question
remains then as to what moves must the emancipatory project make from here.
Indications of how we might proceed were given in the second half of the chapter,
which followed Heidegger's discussion of how the existential structures of human
existence might be brought into an authentic relationship with time in Division
Two. Here we saw that Da-sein was 'freed' from its lostness in 'the they' (das Man)
through the recognition of its own finitude, which forces us into an anticipatory
resoluteness towards the future and into solicitous being-with others.
Since it related to the 'freeing up' of the future possibilities of any concretely
existing human beings, we suggested that Heidegger's notion of resoluteness
offered a more convincing account of the relationship between freedom and
194
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
195
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
Heidegger's argument that any claims about the nature of human existence
that aspire to apply to human beings in general – such as the ones relied upon by
Linklater in his defence of universality – must then be grounded in an analysis of
the experience of human existence if they are not to be considered metaphysical (or
grounded in metaphysics), is cogent. This is why we claim that Linklater submits
to a form of metaphysical dualism, even though he would likely dispute it.
Moreover, since it is based on an analysis of human existence that should be
familiar to all human beings regardless of political or ethical differences,
Heidegger's existential analytic of Da-sein should be considered to be a significant
contribution to a universalistic philosophical ontology for world politics and ethics,
since it provides us a more universalistic ontological foundation than does ethical
subjectivity.
196
PART 2/Ch4. Beings & Being: Heidegger & Fundamental Ontology
implications for the way that we understand human freedom – and hence also for
an ethical and emancipatory politics. Indeed, Heidegger's fundamental ontology
harbingers a shift in thinking about what politics and ethics themselves in fact are.
Consequently, before we proceed to develop the interpersonal aspect of
resoluteness and solicitude with the aid of Hegel in Part 3, the next chapter will
engage in a regional ontology of the person, freedom, ethics and politics, that
proceeds from Heidegger's fundamental ontology.
197
Chapter 5.
Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and
Emancipatory Politics
Introduction
For Heidegger, we learnt, what is most distinctive about 'man' is his ek-
sistence: he is the being that interprets Being. Since our own understanding of the
nature of an entity's existence always occurs in the light of a broader interpretation
of Being in general (an interpretation that is necessarily partial, horizonal, and
temporal), in contrast to Linklater's approach to critical theory, a recognition of the
ontological difference impels us to resist the (characteristically dualist) tendency to
treat our own interpretation of the being of human beings as an 'objective'
foundation for an ethical or emancipatory politics, and prompts us to base an
emancipatory cosmopolitanism on engaged being-with others instead. Thus for
Heidegger, what it means to be a free human being is to engage in resolute
solicitous being-with others.
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
The chapter closed with the suggestion that not only does Heidegger's
fundamental ontology have important implications for the way that we understand
human freedom, and hence also for any emancipatory cosmopolitanism, but that it
also it harbingers a shift in our understanding of what politics and ethics actually
are. We pick up on this point in this chapter by discussing four related areas that
are affected by Heidegger's fundamental ontology, all of which entail significant
implications for the development of an emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
We will recall from the last chapter that the existential analytic of human
existence provided in Division One of Being and Time posed a robust challenge to
the idea that the individual could be thought as subject. Proceeding from this
critique, we will draw on the work of Frederick Olafson who has applied
Heidegger's general ontology of Being (existence in general) to the philosophy of
mind and developed a regional ontology of the human being. Offering an
alternative to a foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, Olafson proposes
that we conceive human beings as essentially 'world-relating creatures,' whose
world-relation is the proximal fact their existence,
a constitutive perspectivality
that individuals are unable to transcend by adopting a position of subjectivity. We
then proceed to discuss three further central implications of Heidegger's general
ontology of Being and Olafson's regional ontology of the person; these relate to our
understandings of human freedom, politics, and ethics.
199
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
identification of the self as a singularity and argue that this means that ethics can
no longer be primarily about ethical principles (since these are necessarily
underwritten by an ethical subject) but amounts to an open and receptive relation to
the other as singularity rather than subject.
Heidegger's general ontology of Being has had both a direct and indirect
influence on contemporary political thought. Some of that influence has been
surveyed by Stephen K. White in his book Sustaining Affirmation, which engages
the work of George Kateb, Charles Taylor, Judith Butler and William Connolly,
and illuminates the crucial role that Heidegger's thought has played in the what he
refers to as the 'weak ontological turn' in political theory.1 'Weak ontology' is
understood by White as a field that entwines ontological reflection with political
affirmation, a theoretical turn that went hand in hand with a shift in the meaning of
ontology in analytic philosophy and philosophy of science that occurred in the
twentieth century; a shift from understanding ontology as relating to the existence
of entities presupposed by our scientific theories and towards a 'growing propensity
to interrogate more carefully those "entities" presupposed by our typical ways of
seeing and doing in the modern world.'2
The prime target of this challenge has been the assumption that we may
treat human beings as independent and autonomous, ontologically prior to their
relations. For this reason it has tended to be political theories that, even implicitly,
work from such assumptions that have been singled out for criticism. Most
1. Stephen K. White, Sustaining Affirmation: The Strengths of Weak Ontology in Political Theory
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
2. Ibid., 4.
200
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
prominent of these are the autonomous individual agent in liberalism and the
ideally autonomous collective agent in Marxism. As White explains:
At issue is the assertive, disengaged self who generates distance from its background
(tradition, embodiment) and foreground (external nature, other subjects) in the name of an
accelerating mastery of them. This Teflon subject has had a leading role on the modern
stage. Such subjectivity has been affirmed primarily at the individual level in Western
democracies, although within Marxism it had a career at the collective level as well. In
both cases, the relevant entity is envisioned as empowering itself through natural and
social obstacles; it dreams ultimately of frictionless motion. This modern ontology of the
Teflon subject has, of course, not usually been thematized in quite such stark terms. But
the lack of explicit thematization has been at least partially a measure of modernity's self-
confidence. It is precisely the waning of this self-confidence that engenders such a
widespread recourse to ontological reflection. Accordingly, the current turn might now be
seen as an attempt to think ourselves, and being in general, in ways that depart from the
dominant - but now more problematic - ontological investments of modernity.3
White notes that Heidegger's existential analysis of the human being and the
historical/temporal dimension of ontological reflection that he initiated is crucial to
this turn.4 While Heidegger's influence on recent French philosophy is particularly
noticeable, this is only one of several strands of thought that participate in the
ontological turn:
One finds similar countermodern, ontological themes in various locations across the
contemporary intellectual landscape: in communitarianism, in political theory influenced
by theology, in feminism, in post-Marxism, and even in some versions of liberalism itself
[...] In each of these initiatives, ontological concerns emerge in the form of deep
reconceptualizations of human being in relation to its world. More specifically, human
being is presented as in some way "stickier" than in prevailing modern conceptualizations.5
[w]eak ontologies do not proceed by categorical positing of, say, human nature or telos
[...] Rather what they offer are figurations of human being in terms of certain existential
realties, most notably language, mortality or finitude, natality, and the articulation of
"sources of the self." These figurations are accounts of what it is to be a certain sort of
creature.6
3. Ibid.
4. Ibid.
5. Ibid., 5. On Heidegger's influence on French philosophy see Tom Rockmore, Heidegger and
French Philosophy: Humanism, Antihumanism and Being (London: Routledge, 1995).
6. Stephen K. White, Sustaining Affirmation: The Strengths of Weak Ontology in Political Theory,
9.
201
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
Engaged Agents
Charles Taylor and Frederick Olafson dig deeper into the philosophical roots
of this scepticism in political theory with reference to the philosophy of mind. In a
short essay titled Engaged Agency and Background in Heidegger, Taylor presents
dualist and mechanist perspectives on the mind as two different ways that a
disengaged perspective has been 'ontologised.'7 These accounts of consciousness
involve a view of the human being similar to that of the Teflon subject since they
purport to discover reality out there, as it 'really is,' by freeing us from the
perspective of embodied existence.8 Inaugurated by Descartes, dualist perspectives
see human beings as essentially minds located in bodies, while mechanistic
perspectives, drawing on Hobbes, understand thinking as 'an event realized in a
body, mechanistically understood.'9
7. Charles Taylor, “Engaged Agency and Background in Heidegger,” in The Cambridge
Companion to Heidegger, ed. Charles B. Guignon (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).
8. Ibid.
9. Ibid., 323.
10. 'Reason has a history; it develops a determinate and progressive content from its expressions in
various forms of social life.' Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International
Relations, 2nd ed. (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990), 160. Arguing that Linklater's subject
attempts to transcend embodied existence is not the same as arguing that he ignores the material
conditions of the exercise of ethical subjectivity; due to his sympathies for Marx, the latter claim
would clearly be wrong.
202
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
Frederik Olafson's What is a Human Being: a Heideggerian View makes
similar arguments regarding the importance of deeper ontological reflection to the
ones surveyed by White and the non-rationalist approach to the philosophy of mind
that is sketched by Taylor, but his argument is far more extensive.11 For Olafson,
as for Heidegger, the question of Being is the central question of philosophy. He
illustrates this with the claim that the three questions that defined the domain of
philosophy for Immanuel Kant - 'What can I know?' 'What ought I to do?' and
‘What may I hope?’ – are aspects of the more general question, ‘What is man?’12
It will be recalled that for Heidegger all general claims about what human
beings are, must be brought into an authentic relationship with time and grounded
in fundamental ontology if they are not to be considered metaphysical. Although
Linklater does not explicitly identify what he takes the essence of the human being
to be, we saw that emancipation appears in his work as the gradual negation of that
which negates ethical subjectivity, and that his defence of universalism further
indicates a foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, since this mode of
11. Frederick A. Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1995).
12. Ibid., 1.
13. Ibid., 10-11.
14. Ibid., 12. Heidegger's existential analytic of Da-sein is an exercise in the regional ontology of
human experience, from which he seeks to draw conclusions regarding a general ontology of Being.
The problem, as Heidegger sees it, is that metaphysics has been preoccupied with regional
ontology, and has ignored general ontology. His overcoming of metaphysics is therefore intended to
ground regional ontology in general ontology.
203
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
being is projected upon the other and all other others in his conception of
university as the universal responsibility to engage in dialogue concerning shared
principles of coexistence. Since this ethical subject is what persists in his CIRT,
and is the foundation or the ground by which he justifies his universalism, from a
Heideggerian perspective this is a metaphysical commitment that must therefore be
recognised as a 'perspectival' claim regarding the essential being of human beings,
and thus subordinate to resolute solicitous being-with others.
World-Relating Creatures15
204
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
makes the case for a radical particularist understanding of human subjectivity,
suggesting that human beings should be understood as entities to which things are
present; since there are many human beings, there are many entities to which
things are present. Humans must then be understood as 'particulars,' as 'loci of
presence:' a position that readily lends itself to pluralisation.16
16. Frederick A. Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View, 133,141.
17. Ibid., 139.
18. Ibid.
19. Ibid., 166-67.
205
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
expresses the 'way things are with us,' in the sense that we are always 'subject to a
situation that in some way affects our interests.'20
Nevertheless, we are also active beings, and even if it is beyond our power to
effect a course of action, 'the situations in which we find ourselves are typically
ones that we do not merely suffer or enjoy, but [are ones] that we want to
terminate, modify, or maintain.' 21 Desire is the human response to these life
situations, acting as the intermediary between feeling and action. In this way desire
orients us towards the future by disclosing possible and particular futures to each
of us in a primordial way.22
'Polarity' then represents the field of presence of any given human being,
broadly corresponding to their spatial location and orientation. The counterpart to
which is agency, the human ability to intervene in the world to modify or terminate
actual or possible states of affairs. Not only do we ek-sist in the sense that entities
are present to us, but we also have the capacity to intervene in the world to make it
different from what it might have otherwise been.23 Indeed, as the counterpart to
presence, action is 'the fullest expression of ek-sistence.'24
20. Ibid., 178.
21. Ibid.
22. Ibid., 186.
23. Ibid., 187.
24. Ibid.
25. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford:
Wiley-Blackwell, 1962), 345.
206
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
for any meaningful action.26 Meaningful action, as we will recall, does not relate
simply to the autonomous self-direction of the subject, but is concernful Being-
alongside what is ready-to-hand: engagement in solicitous being with others.27
World/Worlds
Given that there are over seven billion human bodies in the world, and
proceeding from the claim that humans have worlds that largely coincide with the
location in space and time of their bodies, the way individuals make sense of the
world will vary greatly depending upon the variation in time and space of each
individual body. While individual worlds will overlap with others, resulting in a
high degree of congruence between worlds in certain circumstances, thus retaining
a commitment to the salience of particular communities and joint ventures such as
26. Frederick A. Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View, 166-67.
27. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 344.
28. Frederick A. Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View, 246.
29. Louiza Odysseos, “Radical Phenomenology, Ontology, and International Political Theory,”
Alternatives 27 (2002), 387.
207
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
states when thinking about the sources of individual agency, these worlds will
never coincide perfectly.
When talking of 'communities' one assumes that the entities within that
community at least on some level share a singular world, whether this is a nation
(Wales) a state (Britain) a supra-national community (the European Union) or even
a community of humankind (a universal dialogic community, or global recognitive
sphere). There is a prima facie case for elevating any given community to a
position of prominence in light of shared political objectives by encouraging the
disparate worlds of individuated human beings to coalesce around something that
they share in common (such as culture, language, state, or species) in order to
facilitate cooperation in some joint venture (such as the preservation of a national
or religious culture, to enjoy the benefits of citizenship, or to work towards
cosmopolitan goals such as combating climate change).
30. For a compelling account of the emancipatory role of the state in addressing global inequality
see Michael Walzer, Politics and Passion: Toward a More Egalitarian Liberalism (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2006), 131-41.
208
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
since what is most distinctive about man, his singular 'ek-sistence' is subordinated
to some shared subjectivity.31
31. There is a range of different, perhaps competing, subjectivities that persons can adopt, the
relative importance of which varies between persons. For instance, a Welsh speaker is a subject of
the Welsh language, and a British citizen is a subject of the British state. The two are not
incompatible, but if the policies of the British state do not do enough to help preserve the Welsh
language, we should not be surprised if the assertion of a more particularist subjectivity becomes
more forceful.
209
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
freedom; it is an historically developing ethical subject with significant debts to
Kant's original formulation undergirds Linklater's CIRT.
210
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
becomes an ethical subject, and in Foucault’s acknowledgement that freedom is not
the possession of the ethical subject but is the premise of moral conduct through
which one transforms oneself into an ethical subject. It is in this light that
Odysseos's claim that Linklater confuses freedom with the conditions of possibility
of a certain kind of subjectivity rings true.34 The following section responds to
these discussions with the aim of contributing greater depth to an understanding of
human freedom necessary for any emancipatory cosmopolitanism, one that moves
away from a principal association of freedom with subjectivity or intersubjectivity.
34. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007), xxx.
35. Heidegger's discussion Kantian subjectivity can be found in Martin Heidegger, Being and Time,
366-67.
211
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
deliverance to existence rather than autonomous self-control and mastery over
things in the world. This argument is important in two respects. Firstly it does not
involve contestable metaphysical presuppositions regarding what the human being
is, since 'the human' is not associated with some essential substance or property.
Secondly, it offers an understanding of freedom that respects the limitations and
constraints of human perspectivalism as presented in an understanding humans as
world-relating creatures.
36. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom: An Introduction to Philosophy (London:
Continuum, 2002), 15-16.
212
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
Enlightenment commitment to freedom and equality that leads directly (or
dialectically, in the case of Horkheimer and Adorno) to its opposite.37
37. Theodor W. Adorno, and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (London: Verso, 1986).
This common concern is likely due to the shared influence of Nietzsche on Heidegger, Horkheimer
and Adorno.
38. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom, 4.
39. Ibid., 5.
40. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Allen W. Wood and Paul Guyer (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), A534,B562.
213
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
In short, the essence of human freedom is for Kant 'the condition of the
possibility of the factuality of pure practical reason.'41 Kantian freedom therefore
establishes the individual as essentially independent from his world.
There are two paths to Kantian freedom, cosmological and practical – both
intersecting in the individual thought as subject. Referring to a 'free act' as an
'originary action,' freedom is determined in terms of cause and effect, and is
thereby posed as a problem of causality in Kant's third antinomy.42 For Kant, all
experience is subject to the law of causality, the law that 'everything that happens,
that is, begins, to be, presupposes something upon which it follows according to a
rule.'43 As Kant explains: 'the causality of the cause of that which happens or
comes into being must itself have come into being, and [...] in accordance with the
principle of understanding it must in its turn require a cause.'44 In the natural world,
the world of phenomena, nothing is the cause of itself: every cause of a cause itself
follows from a prior cause.
In the third antinomy this takes the form of the proposition of the necessity
of an uncaused cause (transcendental freedom), an absolute spontaneity of cause,
41. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom, 201.
42. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A544,B572.
43. Ibid., A189,B232.
44. Ibid., A532,B560.
45. This is the role that God plays in a mechanistic paradigm of nature: as the abstract 'first cause'
(causa prima) of the universe.
214
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
which of itself originates a series of phenomena which then proceed according to
natural laws. This distinction means that freedom and causality are no longer
mutually exclusive, since the concept of cause presupposes two kinds of causality,
where the causality of freedom does not contradict the laws of nature because it
lies outside of the realm of experience. The phenomenal-noumenal distinction thus
resolves the contradiction between freedom and mechanistic laws of nature:
transcendental freedom is cosmological freedom.
This variance reflects the divergent concerns of Kant's two Critiques: while
pure reason aims at truth, practical reason tells us what we must do. This is why
the first Critique cognises freedom in a purely negative way, as the pure possibility
of freedom as an independence from, while the second Critique thinks about
actually existing freedom, where freedom is regarded as the ability to will an
action for ourselves; and for that willing to be driven by reason alone, since reason
provides motivation for the will that transcends natural causality. It is, therefore,
46. In a metaphysics lecture Kant is quoted as saying: 'Freedom is practically necessary – man must
therefore act according to an idea of freedom, otherwise he cannot act. That does not, however,
prove freedom in the theoretical sense.' Henry E. Allison, Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant’s
Theoretical and Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 133-34.
215
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
ethical action driven by reason alone that allows us to consider the person to be
engaging in an original effecting. In short, freedom is, according to Kant 'a non-
empirical (intelligible) kind of causality'; a 'causality of reason' that practical
reason gives reality to.47
We saw in the last chapter that Heidegger argues that any encounter with
entities occurs 'in the light of Being'; Kant's account of freedom and ethical
subjectivity is an effective illustration of this.48 Kant, a committed Newtonian,
sought to apply Newton's insights in physics to metaphysics, a philosophical
discipline that, in promising to give us knowledge of entities existing beyond
experience, he regarded as a fledgling science. Newtonian physics had provided a
mechanical explanation of nature as governed by causally determining natural
laws; understanding freedom as non-empirical (intelligible) kind of causality
allows Kant to find a place for human freedom in a Newtonian universe by
reconciling the mechanical necessity of nature with the view of humans as beings
endowed with a distinctive kind of causality.49 Kant's encounter with human beings
thus occurs in the light of a mechanistic paradigm of nature; his positing of
freedom as a transcendental idea is at root an attempt to make sense of the unity of
nature given a commitment to a mechanistic understanding of the world. Hence, it
is only within a certain conditioned interpretation of Being that freedom becomes a
problem for Kant.
216
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
the individual. This notion then later finds practical expression in his second
Critique and in the Groundwork, before being expressed politically in his essays
Perpetual Peace and Idea for a Universal History. Kant's conception of ethical
subjectivity is thus a corollary to his understanding of freedom as transcendental
idea (cosmological freedom); both of which are metaphysical because they cannot
be validated by experience. Although the two are not the same – autonomy is the
self-legislation of a rational being according to its individual will, and absolute
spontaneity is the self-origination of a state – it is only on the basis of absolute
spontaneity that practical autonomy is possible. Practical autonomy is a kind of
absolute spontaneity, the latter delimiting the essence of the former:
The practical freedom associated with ethical subjectivity is not just about
rational activity, but also involves being responsible for our actions. While the
traditional definition of man as homo animale rationale recognises only two
elements: man as the animal endowed with reason, since an animal can be rational
without possessing the ability to act on behalf of itself, for Kant the humanity of
man must consist in more than this: '[r]eason could be purely theoretical, such that
man's actions were guided by reason, but with his impulses stemming entirely from
50. Ibid., 18.
217
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
sensibility, i.e., from his animality.'51 Consequently it is not simply rationality or
animality, but also personality that must be distinctive of man for Kant: our ability
to rise above our animal nature and be held accountable for our actions as persons.
In short, man is not just a rational being, but also an accountable being: '[t]he
essence of person, the personality, consists in self-responsibility.'52
The idea that we are responsible beings that can be held accountable for our
actions is crucial for a Kantian conception of freedom, since it is this experience of
individual responsibility or accountability that provides substance to the idea that
we are free. Such a view of freedom has become widely accepted, at least in
modern, liberal, societies. If we murder someone, we expect to be held accountable
for that crime. Similarly, when someone engages in supererogatory action we hold
that person in esteem. Kant's understanding of freedom is therefore crucial to our
modern self-understandings, without it we would have neither legal nor moral
personality; both of which are central to the functioning of our modern societies.
The problem however is that Kant treats this kind of freedom as something that
persists historically and trans-culturally: he treats this form of ethical subjectivity
as foundational.53
51. Ibid., 180.
52. Ibid.
53. Linklater's dialectical treatment of Kant's rationalism and Hegel's historicism in Men and
Citizens is a significant move away from this form of foundationalism, yet reconstructing ethical
subjectivity as an historical achievement does not fully extricate himself from this commitment.
54. Ibid., 367.
218
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
Despite resonating profoundly with a modern sensibility then, by
understanding freedom simply as the practical autonomy of a present being, of an
individual conceived as self-directing substance, Kant's understanding of freedom
betrays an essentially limited conception of the human being (as existent entity).
This is because it fails to engage with the being of that entity, with the nature of the
kind of existence that pertains to human beings; a form of existence that Heidegger
identifies as our 'ek-sistentiality' – the fact that we are the beings that interpret
Being. As a result, Kant's treatment of freedom and human existence is
ontologically shallow.
We shall recall from the last chapter that Heidegger rejects metaphysical
realism, arguing instead that our understanding of reality is not simply read off the
mind-independent real, but is at least partially imposed upon it; that, on the basis of
our prior experience we project out interpretations of existence onto entities
themselves: we give things meaning. Moreover, that Heidegger's complaint against
the Western philosophical tradition is that it has misinterpreted the nature of this
exercise: that, in part due to an overestimation of our rational faculties, we have
come to think that our constructions of the mind-independent real are in fact
reflections of reality as it is independent of our knowledge of it.
219
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
'lacks the metaphysical ground for the problem of freedom.'55 This leads him to
consider if it is, in fact, the reverse that is true.
The letting-be encountered of beings, comportment to beings in each and every mode of
manifestness, is only possible where freedom exists. Freedom is the condition of the
possibility of the manifestness of the being of beings, of the understanding of being.56
220
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
must effect a complete repositioning of freedom, so that what now emerges is that
the problem of freedom is not built into the leading and fundamental problems of
philosophy, but, on the contrary, the leading question of metaphysics is grounded
in the question concerning the essence of freedom.'59 Freedom then is no longer
conceived primarily in terms of a property of man, but it becomes 'superordinate
and governing in relation to the whole.'60
Dasein does not lay the ground or basis: it does not choose its entry into the world or the
range of possibilities that initially confront it. But it assumes these possibilities as its own
and makes them a spring-board for its subsequent trajectory. Its ability to do this depends
on its "ecstatic temporality:" "Even if concern remains restricted to the urgency of every-
day needs, Dasein is never a pure making present; it springs from a retention that awaits,
and exists in a world on the ground of this retention or as itself this "ground."'63
With freedom as the abyssal root of both Being and time, freedom is more
primordial than man, and so man can only be the administrator and not the owner
of freedom: 'he can only let-be the freedom which is accorded to him.'64 As the
administrator of freedom, man is the site where beings in the whole become
revealed, i.e., he is that particular being through which beings as such announce
59. Ibid.
60. Ibid.
61. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 284.
62. Ibid.
63. Ibid., 356 cf. 436. Michael Inwood, A Heidegger Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 83.
64. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom, 93.
221
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
themselves.'65 Hence, man is not just one being amongst other beings but he is the
being through which the being of beings - thus beings in the whole - are revealed.
He is that being that interprets Being.
An Emancipatory Humanism?
65. Ibid., 94.
66. ‘[I]f one understands humanism in general as a concern that man become free for his humanity
and find his worth in it, then humanism differs according to one's conception of the "freedom" and
"nature" of man. So too are there various paths toward the realization of such conceptions. The
humanism of Marx does not need to return to antiquity any more than the humanism which Sartre
conceives existentialism to be. In this broad sense Christianity is also a humanism, in that according
to its teaching everything depends on man's salvation (salus aeterna); the history of man appears in
the context of the history of redemption. However different these forms of humanism may be in
purpose and in principle, in the mode and means of their respective realizations, and in the form of
their teaching, they nonetheless all agree in this, that the humanitas of homo humanus is determined
with regard to an already established interpretation of nature, history, world, and the ground of the
world, that is, of beings as a whole. Every humanism is either grounded in metaphysics or is itself
made to be the ground of one. Every determination of the essence of man already presupposes an
interpretation of beings without asking about the truth of Being, whether knowingly or not, is
metaphysical.’ Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism,” in Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, ed.
David F. Krell (New York: Harper Collins, 1993), 225-26.
222
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
man's existential uniqueness for Heidegger: the way that man 'stands out' in the
various moments of the temporality of care, being 'thrown' out of a past and
'projecting' himself toward a future by way of the present.67
Thought in terms of ek-sistence, "world" is in a certain sense precisely "the beyond" within
existence and for it. Man is never first and foremost man on the hither side of the world, as
a "subject," whether this is taken as "I" or "We." Neither is he ever simply a mere subject
which always simultaneously is related to objects, so that his essence lies in the subject-
object relation. Rather, before all this, man in his essence is ek-sistent into the openness of
Being, into the open region that clears the "between" within which a "relation" of subject
to object can "be."'68
Freedom is not merely what common sense is content to let pass under this name: the
caprice, turning up occasionally in our choosing, of inclining in this or that direction.
Freedom is not mere absence of constraint with respect to what we can or cannot do. Nor
is it on the other hand mere readiness for what is required and necessary (and so somehow
a being). Prior to all this ("negative" and "positive" freedom), freedom is engagement in
the disclosedness of beings as such. Disclosedness itself is conserved in ek-sistent
engagement, through which the openness of the open region, i.e., the "there," "Da," is what
it is.'69
As the groundless ground of our existence, the Abgrund upon which the
ontological difference rests, freedom is not simply the self-direction of
individuated entities, and neither is it caprice or absence of restraint.70 Before it is
any of these, freedom is the existential condition of world-disclosure, and then a
67. Ibid., 228.
68. Ibid., 252.
69. Martin Heidegger, “On the Essence of Truth,” in Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, ed. David
F. Krell. (New York: Harper Collins, 1993), 126.
70. As Louis Blond explains: 'The "non-essence" that constitutes being and nothingness, as they are
not "things," is described as an abyss that functions as a "non-grounding ground" which gives the
freedom of possibilities (or rather existence) to beings. Freedom is not like an unchanging essence;
freedom provides the space for possibilities. The abyssal ground (Ab-grund) is the boundless
quality that is the counterpart of ground.' Louis P. Blond, Heidegger and Nietzsche: Overcoming
Metaphysics (London: Continuum, 2010), 78. For Heidegger's own (lengthier) explanation
of
freedom as 'groundless ground' see Martin Heidegger, “The Anaximander Fragment,” Arion 1, no. 4
(1973): 576-626.
223
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
state of being – a resolute, solicitous being-with others, where others are engaged
as others. This involves, in Heidegger's words, 'letting beings be,' allowing others
to appear as they are rather than on the basis of some preconceived notion of
subjectivity that is projected onto them. It is in this solicitous engagement that
Being is mutually co-disclosed with others, a mutual co-disclosure that is
hampered by the projection of a substantive interpretation of what human beings
are; such as by representing others as subjects, the strategy relied upon by
Linklater's defence of universalism.
224
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
state. Such a practice often involves the invocation of a shared identity as the
common ground for social cohesion or collective action. To claim that something
is 'un-American,' for instance, indicates this in the negative. Sometimes such social
cohesion is established through the identification of threats to the polity, both
internal or external, but it can also be effected through national celebrations, such
as Australia Day, the Queen's Diamond Jubilee, or more sombre occasions such as
Armistice Day.71
225
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
being as subject, we will recall that Heidegger identifies Mitsein (being-with) as a
fundamental existential structure of human existence, a basic state within which
human existence is 'co-determined by its relations with others.’72 While Olafson
develops Heidegger's idea that we are essentially ek-sistents by addressing our
thrownness and potentiality-for-being, he does not explore the notion of being-
with.73 This is a significant limitation, especially for thinking about an ethical and
emancipatory approach to world politics, because it means that he cannot examine
how one ek-sistent stands to another. Olafson recognizes this shortcoming and
suggests in his conclusion that his understanding of human being in terms of
presence and ek-sistence 'needs to be amplified by an account of the ways in which
the essential plurality of human being and the kind of community to which it gives
rise would be at the centre of the discussion.'74
72. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, 153.
73. Not until three years later, at least. See Frederick A. Olafson, Heidegger and the Ground of
Ethics: A Study of Mitsein (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
74. Frederick A. Olafson, What is a Human Being? A Heideggerian View, 255.
226
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
Coexistence
[O]thers are not encountered in the world as a "plurality" of subjects that, thanks to their
incarnation, arise as "person-things-present-at-hand" among other "things." The logic of
composition, with its conception of others as subjects and of their coexistence as the
coming together of self-sufficient subjects, is directly refuted by Heidegger. His
reformulation of the "with" beyond composition "unworks" the nonrelational character
assumed of the modern subject. The world of Dasein is a with-world [Mitwelt]. Being-in is
Being-with Others. Their Being in-themselves within-the-world is Dasein-with
[Mitdasein]. "With," then, shapes the very Being of Dasein as a worldly entity and cannot
be understood as signifying copresence.75
75. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence, 73.
76. Louiza Odysseos, “Radical Phenomenology, Ontology, and International Political Theory,”
396. A concept of shared interest can be seen as important to a social contractarian approach to the
227
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
ontology that draws from both Heidegger and Nancy, the individuality of a state or
a human being is radically dependent on the broader plurality within which it
arises. Odysseos’s hope is that the recognition of this existential condition might
'arrest a return to subject-driven politics,' serve as an 'ethical imperative
commanding respect for others's, and secure 'the open-endedness (a-teleology) of
political life.'77
state, and the perception that states must share a common interest in order for them to cooperate –
as in projects of collective security, for instance.
77. Ibid.
78. Jean-Luc Nancy, Being Singular Plural (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001), xv.
228
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
where humans are understood as the beings that have access to Being. In
Heideggerian thought it is through 'the event' that Da-sein is opened to Being:
Being is revealed to beings through personal experience that is characteristically
singular and unique. It is due to the facticity of human existence that human
experience is singular as opposed to general, and it is this singularity of human
experience that leads to the fact that our experience of Being is necessarily
multiple and differential.79 The singularity our experience necessarily implies the
multiplicity of Being because 'if the articulation of Being is always singular, Being
cannot be One, and it cannot be thought simply as gathering or collecting. And if
that to which Dasein opens is always already articulated [...] then Being must be
thought as differential or relational.80
Despite this insistence that Being cannot be One, there remains what Nancy
calls the 'political space,' the site of community, which is based upon the
differential structure of human existence. This political space is the place of human
sociality and is crucial to the nature of human existence, since it is that fact that we
experience our political existence as a question that differentiates us from other
animals. This 'political space' is also the place where we experience freedom;
freedom is experienced when thought is exposed to the 'fact of Being' the fact 'that
there are beings (and not nothing, Heidegger adds).'81
229
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
created by each and every one of us in our relations with others. Given its
emphasis on the importance of human sociality, Nancy's coexistential ontology
emphasises relationality over subjectivity, prioritising neither the individual nor the
community – because to focus on either the general or the particular would detract
from the coexistential nature of our sociality. Consequently, Nancy claims, just as
community is 'inoperative,' the individual is 'nonviable':
Some see in its invention and in the culture, if not in the cult built around the individual,
Europe's incontrovertible merit of having shown the world the sole path to emancipation
from tyranny, and the norm by which to measure all our collective or communitarian
undertakings. But the individual is merely the residue of the experience of the dissolution
of community. By its nature - as its name indicates, it is the atom, the indivisible - the
individual reveals that it is the abstract result of a decomposition. It is another, and
symmetrical, figure of immanence: the absolutely detached for-itself, taken as origin and
as certainty.83
Despite his talk of beings as 'origins' indicating that his position is affiliated
with a commitment to the aseity of the self, Nancy understands the self in a way
that does not involve treating it as essentially distinct from the experiences that
constitute it, but as deeply implicated in its relation to them.84 The self, according
83. Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, 3.
84. 'Aseity,' 'from-himself-ness,' deriving from the latin a (from) and se (self) is the property of a
being that exists in and of itself. It is traditionally used in Christian theology to affirm a qualitative
230
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
to Nancy, 'takes place as itself and/or as the other,' it's aseity 'anterior to the
distinction between a consciousness and its world. Before phenomenological
intentionality and the constitution of the ego, but also before thinglike consistency
as such,' there is for Nancy 'a co-originarity accorded to the with.'85 Nancy's
account of being singular plural is therefore not an account of human social
relations that anticipates the realisation of some primordial essence, but one which
shifts concern away from both the individual and the community to singularity and
the plural formation of singular worlds.
Nancy explains that 'singularity never has the nature or the structure of
individuality. Singularity never takes place at the level of atoms, those identifiable
if not identical entities; rather it takes place at the level of the clinamen, which is
unidentifiable.'86 Any given (individual, singular) world is formed 'in exposure to
others and thus is a relational world (or constituted in and through the relations that
are its (co)existential building blocks).'87 Crucially then, worlds are singular and
plural rather than general and universal as they are distinctively experienced and
formed by individuals in their social relations; they are, therefore, divisible and
constitutively exposed to other worlds, with which they intersect and overlap.
Hence:
The unity of a world is not one: it is made of a diversity, and even disparity and opposition
[...] The unity of a world is nothing other than its diversity, and this, in turn, is a diversity
of worlds. A world is a multiplicity of worlds; the world is a multiplicity of worlds, and its
unity is the mutual sharing and exposition of all its worlds - within this world.88
For Nancy then, as for Heidegger and for Odysseos, the proximal fact of
human existence is coexistence: the coexistence of singularities, individuated
selves that are co-originary or relational from the start and which are constituted
through their relations towards singular and multiple worlds. Significantly though,
difference between God and the creatures that he made. Nancy's use of the concept is meant to
indicate that we can rely on no transcendent source of meaning, and that we must now consider
aseity to inhere in individual human beings themselves.
85. Jean-Luc Nancy, Being Singular Plural, 40-41.
86. Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, 6-7.
87. Martin Coward, “Jean-Luc Nancy,” in Critical Theorists and International Relations, ed. Jenny
Edkins and Nick Vaughan-Williams (London: Routledge, 2009), 259.
88. Jean-Luc Nancy, Being Singular Plural, 185.
231
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
as with Odysseos, coexistence does not refer to the relations between preformed
subjects – it 'holds itself just as far from juxtaposition as it does from integration.'89
Coexistence does not supplement existence, and it cannot be subtracted out of
existence: existence is coexistence. 90 By stressing that coexistence is neither
integration nor juxtaposition Nancy distances himself from Hobbesian realism that
perceives the other as threatening and seeks to secure the self, just as he does from
the Kantian and Marxian goal of uniting a community of humankind.
89. Ibid., 187.
90. Ibid.
91. Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community, 3.
232
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
What cannot appear is both the other and communication. For the other of a
communication becomes the object of a subject - even and perhaps especially as
"suppressed object or concept" as in the Hegelian relation between consciousnesses [...]
This other is no longer an other, but an object of a subject's representation (or, in a more
complicated way, the representative object of another subject for the subject's
representation). Communication and the alterity that is its condition can, in principle, have
only an instrumental and not an ontological role and status in a thinking that views the
subject as the negative but specular identity of an object, that is, as an exteriority without
alterity. The subject cannot be outside itself: this is even what ultimately defines it - that its
outside and all its "alienations" or "extraneousness" should in the end be suppressed and
sublated in it. It is altogether different with the being of communication. The being-
communicating (and not the subject-representing), or if one wants to risk saying it,
communication as the predicament of being, as "transcendental," is above all being-
outside-itself.92
Relations to Singularity
92. Ibid., 24.
233
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
This is where Nancy's concept of singularity comes into its own, since it
captures the ontological fullness of a person in a way that a commitment to
subjectivity cannot. We saw above that Nancy first talks about the singularity of
Being in The Inoperative Community, but his use of the term in relation to the
individual is stated more clearly in Being Singular Plural. Simultaneously rejecting
a Rorty-esque pragmatism and defending against the familiar criticism levelled
against continental philosophy as leading to relativism or nihilism, Nancy asserts:
There is a common measure, which is not some one unique standard applied to everyone
and everything. It is the commensurability of incommensurable singularities, the equality
of all the origins-of-the-world, which, as origins, are strictly unexchangable.93
234
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
With this becoming-political, and with all the schemata that we will recognize therein [...]
the question of democracy thus opens, the question of the citizen or the subject as a
countable singularity. And that of a "universal fraternity." There is no democracy without
respect for irreducible singularity or alterity, but there is no democracy without the
"community of friends" (koína ta philōn), without the calculation of majorities, without
identifiable, stabilizable, representable subjects, all equal. These two laws are irreducible
to one another. Tragically irreconcilable and forever wounding [...] political desire is
forever borne by the disjunction of these two laws. It also bears the chance and the future
of a democracy whose ruin it constantly threatens but whose life, however, it sustains.95
Singularity
Although Heidegger does not spend much time discussing the ethical
implications of his existential analytic of Da-sein, representing other Da-seins as
singularities is entirely congruent with his philosophical ontology. The term
'singularity' originates in physics, designating the point of discontinuity in
phenomena such as black holes: that which is, and must remain, beyond the field
of vision. As we saw, an authentic relation between self and world involves letting
entities appear as they are, resisting our tendency to project our regional
interpretations of Being onto beings as a whole. The implication is that a genuinely
ethical relation to the other would resist our tendency to project an interpretation of
what the human subject is or should be, but would be a relation to that which must
essentially exceed our own representations of them – a relationship that does not
reduce the other simply to a particular case of the human species, but treats them as
a singular, irreplaceable being: as a unique ek-sistent Da-sein.
95. Ibid., 22.
96. We could also add Adorno and Horkheimer to this list.
235
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
and its Greek root ēthos. Whereas ethical norms and principles presuppose an
underlying ethical subject, as demonstrated by Cochran's analysis of the
foundational commitments implied in Frost and Linklater's approach to normative
theory, ‘ethos’ refers to an abode or dwelling place, the 'open region in which man
dwells.'97 Since Heidegger regards human dwelling to be authentic when it is
responsive to the ontological difference, the ethical cannot simply be about
theoretically constructed norms, principles, or practices, but must relate to our
concrete way of being in the world. It is in this way that Heidegger can be said to
be 'against ethics.'98 In the writings of those influenced by Heidegger, ethos is
preferred to ethics since the rules and principles of the latter are generally
incompatible with Da-sein. 99 Connolly, for instance, uses it to 'emphasize
continually that the orientation he seeks is vivified more by a spirit or sensibility
than by any set rules of conduct,' while Odysseos distinguishes ethos from the
nomos of moral principles and universal ethics to understand it as 'an attitude and
mode of relating to others.'100
236
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
deficient way of thinking the human being, this chapter has explored the
implications of this general ontology for a regional ontology of the person, and
suggested that we understand human beings as essentially world-relating creatures
instead of ethical subjects.
237
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
along with their relative importance in the constitution of any given individual's
personality. It thus represents a more nuanced way of understanding the
multifaceted, often conflicting influence of human cultures, identities and human
agency in world politics, and offers a particularist response to the cosmopolitan
trope that increasing interconnectedness between people as a result of processes of
globalisation undermines the exclusive nature of particularist positions, and thus
necessitates a cosmopolitan response that often involves the problematic
invocation of a universal human community.
Freedom
238
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
are presented as being deeply constituted by a relationality that is antecedent to any
subjectivity. The result is that a politics of generality, such as a politics based on
ethical principles, or universal rules of conduct, must exist in an essential tension
with the nature of man as an ek-sisting, world-relating creature. Moreover, Nancy
demonstrated that any attempt to establish community on the realisation of some
inherent essence or subjectivity, such as common political identity or ethical
subjectivity, was essentially bound to fail. This, we saw, heralded a fundamental
discontinuity between ethics and politics; the cause of which can be identified as
the rejection of the foundational commitment to the ethical subject.
101. Nikolas Kompridis, Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and Future
(Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2006), 59.
239
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
but must first involve freeing up the possibility of human existence as being-with
others.
Conclusions to Part 2
240
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
In Chapter 1 we explored some of the problems associated with approaches
to international theory that relied on dualistic premises, such as a commitment to
foundational subjectivity or an intransitive object. Echoing the strategy employed
by Hegel's phenomenological constructivism – where the split between subject and
object does not occur between mind and world, but occurs within consciousness,
where the cognitive object is constructed from conscious phenomena in an ongoing
historical process – we suggested (against Cochran's pragmatist anti-
foundationalism) that, conceived as a cognitive object, through a philosophical
ontology of the being of human beings we could construct a more universalistic
ontological foundation for a critical approach to international theory.
If the being of entities, such as human beings, is not intrinsic to an entity but
dependent upon meaning projected upon it by human beings themselves, then it
102. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence, 36.
241
PART 2/Ch5. Ek-sistence, Freedom, and an Ethical and Emancipatory Politics
stands to reason that a core concern of any emancipatory cosmopolitanism must be
to effect changes in the way that we encounter other human beings. Heidegger's
notion of resolute solicitude provides such an orientation; the notion of resolute,
solicitous being-with others holds great potential for the future of critical theory, as
Kompridis has already argued. It offers us a more convincing account of the
relation between freedom and dependence than one predicated on the subject, one
that serves as a nascent but fruitful alternative to relations of inter-subjectivity.
That said, we saw that Heidegger insists that resoluteness must precede solicitous
being with others, and he thereby fails to demonstrate that both freedom and self-
hood are ineluctably acquired in relation to others under conditions of cooperative
interaction. We also noted that had Heidegger been a better student of Hegel's, he
might have avoided this mistake; in this regard, Hegel's 'intersubjective' account of
freedom and subjectivity is both much more convincing, and both more consistent
with and more favourable to, Heidegger's account of positive solicitude. For this
reason, it is to Hegel's compelling contributions to an emancipatory
cosmopolitanism that we now turn.
242
Part 3.
243
PART 3/ Introduction
Introduction to Part 3
244
PART 3/ Introduction
a practical relation to reality by a mature personality. Chapter 7 develops this
claim, arguing that the experience of love can lead to a form of self-consciousness
whereby we recognise that we are not actually subjects, but that our individuality –
our sense of self and our individual autonomy – are ineluctably acquired through
participation in society, which leaves us fundamentally dependent on others for our
own 'subjectivity.' We then claim that properly ethical and emancipatory relations
with others require an attunement to the social conditions of our own self-hood,
and that we act accordingly.
Chapter 8 then sharpens our focus on the ethical and emancipatory aspects of
our argument. We discover that Kant casts a long shadow over contemporary
conceptions of the relationship between love and morality, since his insistence that
love must be subordinate to a rational morality if it is not to be considered
'pathological,' has several influential contemporaries. We explicitly reject this
view, siding instead with Hegel's view that the converse is true: that rational
morality not subordinate to loving relations must be considered pathological. We
discuss Hegel's essay The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate, which is formative in
the development of his notion of Sittlichkeit (ethical life), wherein he heralds a
fundamental discontinuity between the logics of love and law. These two separate
logics inform Hegel's conceptions of ethical life (Sittlichkeit) and morality
(Moralität) respectively, and they underlie a fundamental inequality between
ethical life and moral laws – a discontinuity that is reflected in more recent
'poststructuralist' approaches to the 'ethical relation,' of which Nancy's critique of
discourse ethics (discussed in Chapter 5) is an example.
We learn that for Hegel these two logics are mutually implicated; yet, as a
result of their dualist commitments to a foundational ethical subject, both
Habermas and Linklater dubiously affirm the sovereignty of ethical law
(Moralität) over ethical life (Sittlichkeit). This, we see, reflects a misunderstanding
of the nature of ethical life and its superordinate relation to ethical law. In contrast,
a central argument developed over the course of Part 3 is that it is our participation
in ethical life – engaging in conscientious activity proceeding from the knowledge
245
PART 3/ Introduction
of love – that represents the fullest appropriation of our own freedom, and can lead
to properly ethical relations between self and other. We conclude by suggesting
that an ethical and emancipatory cosmopolitanism must then be proximally
concerned with the cultivation of a more cosmopolitan international ethical life, an
argument that we outline and defend in the conclusion.
246
Chapter 6.
Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection:
Reification, De-Reification, and Deification
Introduction
Before proceeding it is worth clarifying the use of our terms 'dualism' and
'monism' in relation to Hegel. For Hegel, as for Schelling and Spinoza, there is one
substance, the 'absolute.'1 The absolute is that which is presupposed as the 'ground'
that underlies all the differentiated spheres of life. This is Hegel's metaphysical
(ontological) monism. Human consciousness develops out of these underlying
relations of life, and the mind-independent real 'appears' to consciousness:
appearances (phenomena) that consciousness splits into subject and object. This
split between subject and object is the condition of knowledge of the mind-
independent real, but for Hegel it occurs within consciousness rather than between
mind and world. Consequently, since mind and world are not independent, Hegel's
approach to epistemology is also monistic.
248
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
cognitive frameworks (on the activity of mind, Geist) and develop historically
through the interaction of human beings. For this reason dualism is seen as an
essentially limited and one-sided way of conceiving the relationship between self
and world. Consequently, despite their achievements, for Hegel object-oriented
forms of consciousness, and related conceptions of the self as subject, must
ultimately be overcome.
249
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
stand as obstacles to the realisation of a Kantian ideal of a universal moral
community.
That Hegel was Kant's most powerful critic is commonly known, and his
reaction to Kant is roughly significant as Aristotle's critique of Plato.4 However,
there is an unfortunate tendency to overemphasise the difference between Kant and
2. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom: An Introduction to Philosophy (London:
Continuum, 2002), 177.
3. See Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford:
Wiley-Blackwell, 1962), 77,239,438. Martin Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics, trans.
Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000), 187-88. For two
illuminating discussions on this topic see R.S. Sinnerbrink, “Sein Und Geist: Heidegger’s
Confrontation With Hegel’s Phenomenology,” Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and
Social Philosophy 3, no. 2-3 (2007): 132-52. Slavoj Žižek, “Hegel Versus Heidegger,” E-Flux 32,
no. 02 (2012). The similarity between Heidegger and Hegel's approaches to freedom – freedom as
Abgrund and freedom of the Absolute – is largely due to the influence of Schelling on both in this
regard.
4. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Idealism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007), 156.
250
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Hegel and, despite the title of his Phenomenology of Spirit, to ignore the fact that
Hegel is a phenomenologist.5 Hegel's critique of Kant, along with those of the
entire post-Kantian German idealist movement, is an essentially constructive
critique with the aim of working out and completing Kant's critical project. Despite
criticising Kant on nearly every page of his writings, Hegel's engagement with
Kant is not a rejection of Kantianism, but part of the development of his own
Kantianism.6 Perhaps Hegel's central point of contention with Kant lies in the
ontological status accorded to the individual human being and the nature of its
relation to the entities that it encounters. Specifically, what is contested is Kant's
view that the individual can be regarded as an ethical (moral) or epistemic
(knowing) subject: the view that the individual can be completely autonomous, or
stand in a transcendent and knowing relation to the entities that it encounters. The
first view informs Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism, while the second is
reflected in the representationalist approach to knowledge that underwrites critical
realist approaches to the study of world politics.
The sine qua non of this divergence is Hegel's rejection of the mechanistic
paradigm of nature, which serves as the ontological background to Kant's
philosophy, in favour of an organicist one: this amounts to a rejection of Kant's
dualism in favour of a monistic, holistic, organicist philosophical ontology. As we
saw in Chapter 3, although Habermas, Honneth and Linklater all develop from
Kant in important ways, drawing on Hegel in significant respects in the process,
their commitment to intersubjectivity shares with Kant the equation of individuality
and subjectivity, two categories that for Hegel are very distinct. Consequently,
while affirming Hegel's historicist view that 'reason has a history' and that the
individual is deeply implicated in his historical circumstances, they read Hegel
through a kaleidoscope of the Kantian subject: reading into Hegel an individualism
that not only finds no support in his work, but which his whole project is an
attempt to overcome.7
5. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011), 212.
6. For a discussion see Tom Rockmore, Kant and Idealism, 156. and Tom Rockmore, Kant and
Phenomenology, 212-13.
7. Andy Blunden, “The Missing Mediation in Pragmatic Interpretations of Hegel,”
http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/missing-mediation.htm (accessed 29th June 2012, 2012). We
251
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Philosophy has long been concerned with the general problem of knowledge;
all approaches to which 'share an interest in grasping, knowing, or cognising the
will recall from Chapter 3 that Blunden accuses Honneth of reading a methodological individualism
into Hegel, and that since methodological individualism in the social sciences denies the fact that
there are social forces etc. that this is a misleading term to apply to post-Marxist thinkers.
8. Martin Heidegger, The Essence of Human Freedom.
252
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
cognitive object or objects, sometimes also called nature, or the world, or the real.'9
This problem was initially understood in ancient philosophy through terms such as
reality, phenomena, and appearance, while modern philosophy is distinguished by
its insight that cognitive claims depend on the subject.10 Applied to epistemology,
this insight requires of knowledge 'an identity in difference between the
epistemological subject and the epistemological object, or between epistemology
and ontology.'11
9. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology, 3.
10. This shift to an idea of the epistemological subject is influenced by the Augustinian view of the
human subject as ethically responsible, but the transition from a religious question of individual
human responsibility that presupposes a subject to an epistemological conception of the subject
occurs much later in Montaigne and Descartes. Ibid., 10.
11. Ibid., 12.
12. Ibid., 11.
13. Ibid., 12.
253
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
constructivist approaches appear in Kant's critical philosophy, and Hegel
completes the constructivist approach to knowledge that Kant initiates.
Prior to Kant, the subject was regarded as essentially passive in regards to the
objects that it experiences, merely registering what impacts upon it. Starting with
Kant, and common to all post-Kantian German idealists, is the converse claim that
the subject is active in its experience of objects: that in some sense it shapes what it
knows. Insisting on the central importance of the subject in his Critique of Pure
Reason, Kant maintains that there can be no knowledge of objects without a
subject, without an 'I think' to which the object appears.14 For Kant therefore, the
subject is active in respect to the objects of experience, meaning that we never
perceive 'things in themselves,' how things are independent of our experience of
them. Rather, our perceptions of the object are dependent upon the way that our
perceptual apparatus is constituted, and this inevitably influences the givens of
experience.15
254
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
effect, has to be projected by the subject in order to make sense of phenomena that
are given to sensible intuition.
16. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology, 136.
17. Kant's transcendental deduction (TD) postulates twelve categories of four types: categories of
quantity, quality, relation, and modality. The most familiar of these is the category of causality: an a
priori category of relation between cause and effect that allows us to make sense of the appearance
of movement in the world. According to Kant these pure concepts of the understanding are
universal, applying to objects of intuition in general. Causality, unity, plurality, and negation are all
concepts that we presuppose before we face reality. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans.
Allen W. Wood and Paul Guyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), §79.
255
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
While Kant innovates with regard to the subject’s active role in its synthesis
of the cognitive object, he holds two contradictory positions regarding the nature of
this relation between the knowing subject and the cognitive object: between the
subject passively representing the object and actively constructing it. Most
dominant of the two is a representationalist approach, a metaphysical realist
position where representations of the cognitive object appear to the subject, having
their ontological cause in the mind-independent real, which leads to knowledge of
the world as it is in itself. However, Kant does also hint at a constructivist
approach to knowledge where the activity of the subject is not just confined to
synthesising the object, but is more active in constructing the cognitive object.
It is worth noting that the Kantian subject, the TUA, is not a finite human
being but is rather a subject reduced to its epistemological capacities. While this
subject is active as regards its synthetic activity, these epistemological capacities
are passive in the subject's relation to the world. This obscures the relation between
the epistemological subject and the finite human being, which leads to a split
between theoretical reason and practical reason, a split between the knowing
subject and the acting subject.18 Kant's representational account of the subject thus
opens a gulf that cannot be bridged between human understanding and human
activity.
18. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology, 137.
19. Ibid., 44.
256
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Kant's transcendental deduction cannot reconcile: the duality between subject and
object, and the duality between theoretical and practical reason; between the
knowing subject and the acting subject, and the knowing subject that might not
actually know its object. It is these essential contradictions in Kant's critical
philosophy to which post-Kantian German idealism responds.
257
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
provides Fichte the foundation for all knowledge. Fichte therefore abandons Kant's
representationalist approach to knowledge and develops Kant's constructivism in
its stead, emphasising the active role of the subject in its construction of the
cognitive object from out of the empirical content of experience.
258
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Essential to Fichte's account of knowledge then is a dynamic relation
between the Self (das Ich) and the Non-Self (das-Nicht-Ich), where the self at once
confronts and projects the not-self.22 Consequently, on the Fichtean account, nature
becomes an essential self-limitation on the universal 'I;' Northrope Frye provides a
beautiful image that illustrates Fichte’s representation of the dynamic between self
and other in his suggestion that the fundamental gesture of Western thought is the
transformation of the natural world into the farm. 23 Such a dynamic is thus
characterised by a process of de-reification, a process of taking something that is
thing-like, independent, and de-reifying it by withdrawing its independence so as
to bring it into accordance with the norms of reason, desire, and humanity.24 This
thought, that consciousness strives to take objective recalcitrance out of the world
and bring it into conformity with human desire, is hugely important to Marxist
thought, and there is a whole aspect of continental thought that attempts to
overcome the independence of the object by bringing it into conformity with the
norms of reason.25
22. Roger Cardinal, “Romantic Travel,” in Rewriting the Self: Histories From the Renaissance to
the Present, ed. Roy Porter (London: Routledge, 1997).
23. Northrop Frye, The Double Vision: Language and Meaning in Religion (Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, 1991), 22-39. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage,”
Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 8th November
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/19MasterSlaveA.mp3.
24. Ibid.
25. See Tom Rockmore, Fichte, Marx, and the German Philosophical Tradition (Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press, 1980). J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and
Bondage. (a).”
259
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
an adequate account of the object. The problem is that we want our subject-object
dualism, we want our experience of the world to be different from our experience
of ourselves, but Fichte’s account cannot provide this as he denies the object any
mind-independent reality.26 There thus remains a dualism between the knowing
subject and mind-independent real that neither Kant nor Fichte can reconcile.
Proceeding from a foundational subject, both rationalist accounts fail to give an
account of how we can know things in themselves.
It is for this reason that, in his (1799) open Letter to Fichte Jacobi charges
the transcendental idealism of both Kant and Fichte with leading us to the spectre
of sceptical nihilism. Nihilism is the inevitable conclusion of a reliance on the
foundational subject because if we can only know what we create or produce
according to the laws of our own activity, we cannot know anything beyond our
own consciousness. According to Kant we can only know appearances, not things
in themselves, and because we do not know things in themselves, Jacobi suggests
that that these representations might be representations of nothing at all.27 This
would make Kantianism a philosophy of nothingness, what we nowadays call
nihilism, since nihilism is the thought that we know nothing by knowing
appearances.28
The problem with both Kant and Fichte's accounts of human experience is
that they take the conscious subject as their point of departure. Responding to both,
Schelling's transcendental idealism moves away from the question of the 'I' as point
of departure, regarding consciousness not as a condition of our experience of the
world, but as a result. For Schelling, consciousness has its origins in nature, which
it transcends: this is why Schelling's idealism is referred to as a transcendental
26. Ibid.
27. 'Without the presupposition [of the 'thing in itself,'] I was unable to enter into [Kant's] system,
but with it I was unable to stay within it.' Friedrich Jacobi, David Hume Über Den Glauben, Oder
Idealismus Und Realismus. Ein Gespräch (Breslau: Gottlieb Löwe, 1787).
28. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage. (a).”
260
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
idealism as opposed to Fichte's subjective idealism. Whereas for Fichte nature was
seen as an essential limitation on the striving of practical reason, Schelling
recognises that nature has a reality in and of itself, and out of this reality, ideality,
consciousness, springs: nature begins unconsciously and results in conscious,
philosophical activity and knowledge. Subjective consciousness is grounded in,
and thus becomes the result of, the organic development of nature. Schelling
therefore also represents a broader shift away from the mechanistic paradigm of
nature, the sine qua non of Kant's account of ethical and epistemological
subjectivity, towards the Naturphilosophie central to understanding Hegel's
thought.
29. See Parvis Emad, “Heidegger on Schelling’s Concept of Freedom,” Man and World 8, no. 2
(1975): 157-74. and Martin Heidegger, Schelling’s Treatise: On the Essence of Human Freedom
(Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 1985).
30. Andrew Bowie, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Von Schelling, The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition) (2010).
261
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Self-Conscious Individuality: Hegel's Completion of Kant's Critical
Epistemology
Both Kant and Fichte take the subject as their point of departure; for Kant
this means that the mind-independent real cannot itself be known and that we can
only know 'appearances' or 'phenomena,' while Fichte resolves the dualism
between mind and world by simply doing away with the thing in itself. Hegel
wants to be able account for subject-object dualism, and his resolution is to argue
that the subject-object split does not occur between mind and world, but occurs
within consciousness. This entails a mind-world monism, but retains a duality
between subject/object and mind independent real; the mind-independent real is
that which lies beyond consciousness, and 'appears' at the level of consciousness.
Through a process of cognitive activity, the understanding splits what appears to
consciousness into subject and object, an ongoing historical process through which
the cognitive object is constructed from phenomena given to consciousness,
leading to the construction of increasingly adequate accounts of the mind-
independent real.
Hegel takes Jacobi's charge against Kantianism seriously, and his answer to
the spectre of sceptical nihilism is to shift from consciousness to self-
consciousness. Rather than arising from the persistence of the TUA over time, or
of the activity of the striving of the pure ego, Hegel's thought is that self-
knowledge is only possible through mutual recognition, and not through the
Cartesian view, of which Kantianism is a type, of the self-knowledge of a rational
subject. In short, without the recognition of the other, the self cannot have
knowledge of itself as a rational being. Because self-consciousness depends on
intersubjective recognition, reason is no longer confined to the activity of
individual subjective consciousness, but is exercised through intersubjective
activity, bringing both the individual and practical reason into a close relationship
with a historical community.
262
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
The Passage to Self-Consciousness.
One of the central moves of the Phenomenology of Spirit, a book that traces
the development of Geist, the self-conscious subject, is to provide an account of
the achievement of self-consciousness. The treatise is split into three main parts:
A) 'Consciousness'; B) 'Self-consciousness;' iii) and a final, unnamed part
comprising chapters on 'Reason,' 'Spirit,' 'Religion,' and culminating in 'Absolute
Knowing.' Part A) discusses three forms of object-oriented consciousness, sense-
certainty, perception, and the understanding. The construction of the cognitive
object, however, requires some sense of self, as subject, that is independent of the
object. As we have seen, Kant regards this sense of self as the consequence of the
persistence over time of the TUA, while Fichte thought it as something that came
over the course of subjective activity. Hegel's intervention is to insist that this self
is not foundational, and what is required for this sense of self, which is a
prerequisite of an encounter with objects, is a move from subjective consciousness
to self-consciousness.
Self-consciousness, for Hegel contra Kant and Fichte, only arises when
cognitive activity is turned in on itself. A sense of self, as an independent agent, is
not fully complete until one realises that one's self is also an object for other
subjects. Children and animals may well possess consciousness of things that are
external to them without having an awareness of themselves as an independent
consciousness aware of those things as objects. The achievement of a sense of self
is the key move played out in the passage from consciousness to self-
consciousness, a move that is explored in Hegel's famous account of the master
and slave. Self-consciousness, understanding ourselves as independent beings,
develops from consciousness's encounter with objects, but only comes about when
an object-oriented consciousness encounters another consciousness, i.e., through
human sociality. Crucially though, because the self-conscious 'subject' is
fundamentally dependent on others for its self-consciousness, the individual is no
longer regarded as a subject of the Kantian/Fichtean type, and subjectivity is
sublated into 'absolute' knowledge: an insight, or at least the implications of this
263
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
insight for our mode of being in the world, that is overlooked by kaleidoscopic
readings of Hegel as a theorist of intersubjectivity.
Absolute Knowledge
Absolute knowledge in [Hegel's] theory is not merely a later version of the Cartesian claim
to certainty; nor is it related to the Kantian idea that philosophical knowledge is absolutely
permanent and not subject to revision of any kind. On the contrary, the upshot of Hegel's
detailed and lengthy review of the different angles of vision on knowledge, or conceptual
perspectives that have historically emerged in the human search for knowledge, is that we
absolutely cannot escape from the perspectival approach to some angle of vision beyond
all perspective. For whenever we scrutinize experience, we necessarily do so from the
attitude due to our time and place. Absolute knowledge, if this reading of Hegel's theory is
correct, is, then, the consequence of thinking through the epistemological problem to the
end where we finally become aware that we cannot avoid an ever changing perspective
with respect to our experience. There is no absolute knowledge if that is interpreted to
mean knowledge beyond time and place. Rather, since claims to know are never beyond
time and place, they are, then, always and necessarily subject to revision as our experience
changes.31
31. Tom Rockmore, Before and After Hegel: A Historical Introduction to Hegel’s Thought, 102.
32. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Introduction,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology
of Spirit The New School. New York City. 10th October (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/09PhenomenologyIntroC.mp3.
264
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Hegel's Constructivism
Kant and Fichte's mistake is to take the foundational subject as their point of
departure. On both accounts this leads to a transcendental conception of the subject
where the subject exists in a hierarchical relation to the objects of its experience.
The transcendent subject is left essentially unconditioned by these experiences, and
objects are encountered in a way that presupposes their assimilation into subject-
object identity: these objects are never out of the subject's reach. Hegel takes from
Kant the essential role of the epistemological subject and he follows Fichte's
emphasis on the active and constructive role of the subject. However, he avoids
falling foul of Fichte's mistake of over-stressing the role of subjective activity by
following Schelling's argument that the subject-object split occurs within
consciousness rather than between mind and world; that the subject-object
distinction is not something prior to consciousness, but arises through conscious
activity. As a result, Hegel argues that subjectivity is derivative rather than
foundational: that the subject is immanent to the phenomenal realm, existing in a
mutually conditioning, dependent relationship with the object. Contra Kant and
Fichte, subject and object emerge through the interaction between self and world,
and neither subject or object is transcendent or unconditioned. This is what Hegel
means by the notion of subject-object unity, not that they are identical, but that
they are not independent.
265
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
reflecting a split between mind and world, it is consciousness that splits
appearances of the mind-independent real into subject and object, and the cognitive
object is constructed in light of our conscious experience of the mind-independent
real. Although we can never fully know this realm, we can develop increasingly
adequate accounts of it. Knowledge is thus a non-objective construction of the
world that is derived from a practical relation to reality.
266
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Hegelian Subjectivity
34. Levinas, for whom the 'not me' is simply opposed to 'me,' disputes this. For Hegel however, we
need more than difference, we need interruption. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit.
Lordship and Bondage. (a).”
35. On a reading of the struggle for recognition as a discourse on the nature and possibility of
freedom see Robert B. Pippin, “What is the Question for Which Hegel’s Theory of Recognition is
the Answer?,” European Journal of Philosophy 8, no. 2 (2000): 55-172. Love is the image of our
absolute dependence, whilst death demonstrates our absolute independence.
267
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
the logic of subject-object thinking by treating the other independent self-
consciousness simply as a subject, as a self-enclosed and independent ground of
action, thereby eschewing the mutually codependent constitution of any given
'subjectivity'.
268
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
fundamentally as an act by which the self overcomes itself in its passage toward
and into the world. The subject disperses itself into its world, and this self-
surpassing is precisely the operation of its negativity [...] the 'disquiet' of the self is
precisely its mode of becoming its final non-substantiality in time, and its specific
expression of freedom.38
For this reason, conceiving the individual human being as a subject is both
epistemological error and ontological insufficiency: it misunderstands what the
human being is and it misrepresents our mode of being in the world. Permitting
ourselves the indulgence, it would be more appropriate to write the Hegelian
subject sous rature – as subject – since 'subject' is necessary, but insufficient.39
From a Hegelian perspective, the problem with conceiving the human being as a
subject, and relations between beings as intersubjective relations, is that it makes it
harder for us to extirpate ourselves from the mechanistic paradigm of nature
against which Hegel was reacting.
38. Judith Butler, Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-Century France, xii. 'The
subject is - or makes up - the experience of its being-affected as the ordeal of what dissolves its
subsistence. But again: it is not "some thing" (pain, death, the other, or joy) that undoes this
subsistence from the exterior. It is not another subsistence that divides the subject; it is substance
that divides itself - that enters into relation, or that opens itself to it, or that manifests itself. The
subject is the experience of the power of division, of ex-position or abandonment of self.' Ibid.
Nancy continues: '"Self" "is" only this: negating itself as in-itself. Self in itself is nothing, is
immediately its own nothingness. Self is only fissure and fold, return upon self, departure from self,
and coming to self. That is why the Hegelian "self" has its concept only in the multiple and infinite
syntax of these expressions: in itself, for itself, right at itself, or near itself, unto itself, outside of
itself.' Jean-Luc Nancy, Hegel: The Restlessness of the Negative, 42-43.
39. Writing the 'subject' as subject, is meant to signify that it is necessary, but insufficient. The
technique was first used by Heidegger in his letter to Ernst Junger The Question of Being, and was
later used extensively by Derrida as a way of denouncing the metaphysics or 'presence' behind the
word used. As Spivak explains in her preface to Derrida's Of Grammatology 'Since the word is
inaccurate, it is crossed out. Since the word is necessary, it remains legible.' Jacques Derrida, Of
Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1998), xiv.
269
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Whereas Kant and Fichte take the epistemological subject as their points of
departure, an ontological commitment informed by Kant's approbation of
Newtonian physics, Hegel follows Schelling by taking 'life' as the starting point of
his philosophy: his thought proceeding from an organic vision of the world, a view
of the universe as a single living organism. 40 The main challenge to such a
monistic holism came from the old mechanistic paradigm of nature associated with
Newton, Hobbes, and Descartes, which was elevated into the very paradigm of
rationality by Kant and Jacobi. According to the mechanistic paradigm, the natural
world can be best explained mechanically in terms of cause and effect, as it is
governed by certain fundamental laws of nature.
Those encountering Hegel for the first time will likely find his use of
apparently contradictory terms such as 'infinitely finite,' 'unrestricted
restrictedness,' and later 'unity-in-difference,' perplexing to say the least. Indeed
40. Although this sounds implausible, besides Winnicott's example of the mother and child to be
discussed shortly, such an organicist approach is not too far-fetched (at least on planet Earth). See,
for instance, research into the Last Universal Common Ancestor (LUCA), a single cell existing
3/4billion years ago, from which all life has since evolved. Gary Hamilton, “Looking for Luca - the
Mother of All Life,” New Scientist 2515 (2005).
41. Frederick C. Beiser, Hegel, 81-82.
270
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Hegel has often been dismissed as nonsensical.42 However, Hegel's concepts and
dialectical logic are less incomprehensible when placed in the context of his
organicism, since they emerge as attempts to provide a non-reductive or non-
atomistic method of understanding living beings as self-generating and self-
organising concrete wholes.43 They represent a reaction against atomistic accounts
of our understanding of life, where focus begins with the particular, from which
universals are generalised.
While Habermas, Honneth, and Linklater all read Hegel through a Kantian
kaleidoscope, Hegel's philosophy of life had earlier found favour, influencing the
development of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche's Lebensphilosophie ('life-
philosophy'), hermeneutics, and Heideggerian phenomenology - the latter two at
least through the work of Wilhelm Dilthey. In contrast to other biographer's focus
42. Schopenhauer's many denunciations of Hegel along these lines reaches almost comic vigour.
An example: 'But the height of audacity in serving up pure nonsense, in stringing together senseless
and extravagant mazes of words, such as had previously been known only in madhouses, was
finally reached in Hegel, and became the instrument of the most barefaced general mystification
that has ever taken place, with a result which will appear fabulous to posterity, and will remain as a
monument to German stupidity.' Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea, vol. 2
(Edinburgh: The Edinburgh Press, 1906), 22.
43. Frederick C. Beiser, Hegel, 81-82.
271
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
on Hegel's 'mature' system, Dilthey's (1905) study The Young Hegel's History
considers Hegel's later thought as an inexorable expression of his earlier
metaphysical and theological concerns, which are most apparent in his essays
Fragment on Love (1797/1798), The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate (1799), and
his Fragment of a System (1800) – now published as his Early Theological
Writings.44 What emerged from Dilthey's (1905) study of Hegel was a principal
concern with the concept of 'life,' which is the holistic, temporal context of
meaning. Dilthey writes '[l]ife is the basic element or fact which must form the
starting point for philosophy. It is known from within. It is that behind which we
cannot go. Life cannot be brought before the bar of reason.'45 Palmer explains that
the significance lies in the implication that '[o]ur access to an understanding of 'life'
lies deeper than reason, for life is rendered understandable through its
objectifications.'46
44. This rescuing of Hegel's metaphysics is common to writers of the (first) 'Hegel Renaissance,'
which emerged at the end of the 19th century. G.W.F. Hegel, Early Theological Writings, trans.
T.M. Knox (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971). Alice Ormiston, Laura Werner,
and the author of this thesis also share this view. See Alice Ormiston, “”The Spirit of Christianity
and Its Fate:” Towards a Reconsideration of the Role of Love in Hegel,” Canadian Journal of
Political Science 35, no. 3 (2002): 499-525; Alice Ormiston, Love and Politics: Re-Interpreting
Hegel (New York: SUNY Press, 2004). Laura Werner, “The Restless Love of Thinking: The
Concept of Liebe in Hegel’s Philosophy” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Helsinki, 2007).
45. Quoted in Richard E. Palmer, Hermeneutics: Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher, Dilthey,
Heidegger, and Gadamer (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1969), 120.
46. Ibid.
47. On Dilthey's influence on Rosenzweig and Heidegger see Peter Eli Gordon, Rosenzweig and
Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy (Berkeley: University of California Press,
2003), 86. On his influence on hermeneutics see Richard E. Palmer, Hermeneutics: Interpretation
Theory in Schleiermacher, Dilthey, Heidegger, and Gadamer. Schopenhauer and Nietzsche's
Lebensphilosophie ('life-philosophy') proceeds in a similar vein, criticising the theoretical and
positivist focus of post-Kantian philosophy.
272
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
work, such as his 1920-1921 lectures on the philosophy of religion, he designates
this sphere as 'life.'48
48. In his History of the Concept of Time Heidegger writes that 'Dilthey was the first to understand
the "aims of phenomenology."' Quoted by Peter Eli Gordon, Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between
Judaism and German Philosophy, 87n12. See also Martin Heidegger, The Phenomenology of
Religious Life (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2004). Especially pp7-10
49. See Donald Woods Winnicott, Playing and Reality (London: Routledge, 1971).
50. Andy Blunden, “The Missing Mediation in Pragmatic Interpretations of Hegel.”
51. Ibid.
273
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Hegel's holism thus marks an important shift from thinking relations of
particular to universal to relations of parts to whole; a shift that plays out across his
work, with consequences for fields such as ethics, freedom, epistemology,
aesthetics and theology. His Science of Logic presents a 'logic of life,' an attempt to
understand the organic development of life in conceptual form, the Phenomenology
of Spirit is a philosophical study of the organic and phenomenological
development of different forms of consciousness, while his Philosophy of History
traces the historical development of different forms of human freedom, and his
Philosophy of Right is a study of the organic development of Recht (law/right).
Even in the expression "A son of the stem of Koresh," for example, which the Arabs use to
denote the individual, a single member of the clan, there is the implication that this
individual is not simply a part of the whole; the whole does not lie outside him; he himself
is just the whole which the entire clan is. As with any genuinely free people, so among the
Arabs, the individual is a part and at the same time the whole. It is true only of objects, of
things lifeless, that the whole is other than the parts; in the living thing, on the other hand,
the part of the whole is one and the same as the whole. If particular objects, as substances,
are linked together while each of them yet retains its character as an individual (as
52. Mervyn Frost, Ethics in International Relations: A Constitutive Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996).
274
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
numerically one), then their common characteristic, their unity, is only a concept, not an
essence, not something being.53
It is for this reason that Nancy is correct to claim that Hegel's world is a 'world in
which no generality subsists, only infinite singularities.'54
Neither generality nor particularity subsists, for the "particular" is still only the finite in an
extrinsic relation with the general, itself still exterior and therefore in its turn posited as
particular - the finite, therefore, in the relation of particular interests with a general
interest. The singular, on the contrary, is the finite in itself and for itself infinite, for which
there is no separate universality. If I say, "Socrates is a man," I take Socrates for a
particular case of the human species. But Socrates-the-singular is not a case: it is he and
nothing other. If one prefers, he is an absolute case, and the absolute in general is made up
solely of absolute cases and of all their absolute relations.55
53. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” in Early Theological Writings
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 260.
54. Jean-Luc Nancy, Hegel: The Restlessness of the Negative, 22.
55. Ibid.
275
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
a foundational subject that faces the world, remaining unconditioned by the objects
of its experience, Hegel's self-conscious subject is one that is dependent on others
for its subjectivity and is transformed in its interaction with the objects of its
experience. In contrast to Kant's dualist account of the relation between self and
world, where the individual (as subject) faces a world of objects, Hegel's monistic
perspective sees 'subject' and 'object' as categories that arise through the activity of
consciousness, subordinate to the relationship between self and world, where
consciousness splits experiences into 'subject' and 'object.' This leads to a very
different conception of the nature of the role of reason in the relations between self
and world, centring on the faculty of the understanding.
Whereas in Kant and Fichte theoretical and practical reason mediate the
encounter between mind (subject) and world (object), for Hegel practical reason is
necessarily retrospective, it occurs on the basis of prior experience, experiences
that it splits into subject and object. While for both Kant and Hegel the
understanding seeks to grasp the objects of experience intellectually, since for
Hegel the split between subject and object occurs within consciousness, rather than
corresponding to a primordial split between mind and world, the understanding is
56. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977),
§§132-65.
276
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
regarded as a source of difference and otherness. The mind-independent real
appears to consciousness, which the faculty of the understanding then splits into
relations of subject and object (other persons can be objects too), and relations are
understood negatively, through a form of dissolution and relation.57 So, whereas
for Kant and Fichte the subject-object split occurs between mind and world, for
Hegel it is the understanding that is the source of this split, and is therefore a
source of difference and otherness.
Reification
57. See Ibid., §§113-15.
58. This is the truth of Adorno's remark that, the more autonomously the subject ascends above the
ontic realm, the more it surreptitiously turns into an object, in ironic cancellation of its constitutive
role. Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London: Routledge, 1990), 176-77. It is also the idea
expressed by Nancy in his criticism of discourse ethics, quoted in Chapter 5: 'What cannot appear is
both the other and communication. For the other of a communication becomes the object of a
subject - even and perhaps especially as "suppressed object or concept" as in the Hegelian relation
between consciousnesses [...] This other is no longer an other, but an object of a subject's
277
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
representation (or, in a more complicated way, the representative object of another subject for the
subject's representation). Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1991), 24.
59. See Marx's discussion of 'commodity fetishism' in Chapter One of Capital. Karl Marx, Captial:
Critique of Political Economy, vol. 1 (London: Penguin, 1976).; Georg Lukács, Reification and the
Consciousness of the Proletariat, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics
(Pontypool: The Merlin Press, 1971). Axel Honneth, “Reification: A Recognition-Theoretic View”
(Paper presented at the Tanner Lectures on Human Values, University of California, Berkeley,
2005); Axel Honneth, Reification: A New Look At an Old Idea (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2008).
60. Georg Lukács, Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat.
61. Axel Honneth, Reification: A New Look At an Old Idea.
62. Axel Honneth, “Reification: A Recognition-Theoretic View,” 101-02.
63. Louiza Odysseos, The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007), 36.
278
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
death, as it fixes subject and object in their determinations: it is a hypostatisation of
beings that exist essentially in their becoming. As T.M. Knox explains in a note to
Hegel's Fragment of a System, for Hegel '[p]hilosophical reflection always 'kills'
life by distinguishing oppositions, and it cannot give up those distinctions without
killing itself.'64
For Hegel then, the understanding necessarily leads to the diremption and
reification of life, and it fosters several divisions that characterise the historical
conditions of modernity: such as those between individual and community, mind
and nature, reason and emotion. This diremption, these divisions, contribute to the
development of human life from an immature unity (being-in-itself) in the
absolute, but the mistake is to remain caught in the dualist frame that is wrought by
the understanding. Hegel wants us to transcend this framing by recognising a
higher unity between thought and being, a unity he thinks can be achieved by
overcoming the contemplative attitude, achieving self-conscious subjectivity, and
identifying with the broader wholes within which the self is situated: such as
epistemic or ethical communities.
Dereification
64. G.W.F. Hegel, “Fragment of a System,” in Early Theological Writings (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 312-313n6. translator's note.
279
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
the activity of taking something that is thing-like, independent of us, and
withdrawing its independence by bringing it into accord with the norms of reason,
desire, and humanity.
Deification
280
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Indeed, it is perhaps the overemphasis on the nature and role of reason that is
Hegel's central objection to the emergent subject of transcendental idealism. It is
reflective rationality, for Hegel, that splits subject from object, establishing
distance between the self and the objects of its experience, and alienating self from
world. He recognises that this diremption contributes to the development of life –
and importantly, the self-consciousness of life – but he insists that this dualism
between self and world is simply a moment on the path to truth, which requires the
subsequent reconciliation of consciousness and being.65 This, in short, is his way of
maintaining a commitment to subject-object non-identity: the fact that our
experience of the world is different from our experience of ourselves, a duality that
neither Kant nor Fichte can account for.
281
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
66. We will return to an extensive discussion of Hegel's notion of a 'unity-in-difference' and its
relation to love in the next chapter.
282
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
oppositions, are annulled.'67 Love is thus a living, non-conceptual bond that reacts
against the objectification of life through the adoption of philosophical or moral
standpoints, which it transcends in order to achieve a mature unity of subject and
object. As Frye puts it in Double Vision: 'the conscious subject is not really
perceiving until it recognises itself as part of what it perceives. The whole world is
humanised when such a perception takes place.'68
Since something dead here forms one term of the love relationship, love is girt by matter
alone, and this matter is quite indifferent to it. Love's essence at this level, then, is that the
individual in his innermost nature is something opposed [to objectivity]; he is an
independent unit for whom everything else is a world external to him. That world is as
eternal as he is, and, while the objects by which he is confronted change, they are never
absent; they are there, and his God is there, as surely as he is here; this is the ground of his
tranquility in face of loss and his sure confidence that his loss will be compensated,
because compensation here is possible. [trans. note: i.e., what is lost at this level of thought
is a material object and therefore something replaceable by something else.]70
Sharing a concern to challenge views of the relation between self and world as
relations of subjects to objects, what Hegel terms the 'love' relation bears striking
affinities with the relation between self and world that Heidegger seeks to foster
67. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” 278.
68. Northrop Frye, The Double Vision: Language and Meaning in Religion, 23.
69. In The Question Concerning Technology Heidegger contrasts technology's ‘challenging forth’
and poetry's ‘revealing.’ Technology's instrumental orientation to the world, where the world is
turned into a ‘standing-reserve,’ and the human relation to the world becomes one of ‘enframing,’ is
contrasted with poetic ‘revelation.’ Using the example of the Rhine, when a hydroelectric dam is
built on the river, the meaning of the Rhine changes; it becomes an energy reserve. This is
contrasted to the appearance of the Rhine in Höderlin's work, where it serves as a source of
philosophical inspiration and cultural pride. Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning
Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt (New York: Harper & Row, 1977), 16.
70. G.W.F. Hegel, “Fragment on Love,” in Early Theological Writings (Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 303.
283
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
with his notion of solicitous being-with. We saw in Chapter 4 that the latter is
Dasein's authentic mode of being in the world, and leads to a genuine appropriation
of human freedom. Similarly, the 'love' relation involves overcoming a theoretical
attitude through engaged praxis – the intention of both is the same: to overcome
the limitations and pernicious effects that each author regards as going hand in
hand with a dualistic 'philosophical ontology'. Heidegger's primary target is
Descartes, whereas Hegel's is Kant.
Hegelian 'Phenomenology'
Phenomenology
71. This is a key difference between Hegel's 'phenomenology' and Heidegger's phenomenology.
Heidegger's phenomenology, his fundamental ontology, seeks a pre-theoretical approach to reality.
284
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Phenomenology is not simply a method, but is best understood as an attitude
towards philosophical problems.72 For Scheler this attitude equates to a 'spiritual
seeing,' while for Heidegger it involves being open to 'the event' through which
Being is disclosed.73 Common to both is an attunement to original experience, an
engagement with phenomena as phenomena, and an openness to experience that
resists the assimilation of experience into a set of categories – resisting the
presupposition of essences given a priori.
72. On the misguided conception of phenomenology as a method see Tom Rockmore, Kant and
Phenomenology, 189-90.
73. Max Scheler, Selected Philosophical Essays (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
1973), 137.
74. The term appears for the first time in a book published by Kant's friend Lambert in 1764. Tom
Rockmore, Before and After Hegel: A Historical Introduction to Hegel’s Thought, 87.
75. For more on this see Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology. especially pp1-3
285
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Kant's epistemology starts and, as a phenomenologist, is perhaps even more
Kantian than Kant:
Since Kant maintains that without doubt all our knowledge comes from experience, he
opens the door wide to the possibility of knowledge that is not founded on experience [...]
[although he later closes this door]. Hegel immediately closes the door on this possibility,
or rather, he does not open it. According to Hegel, the only source of knowledge is
experience, namely what appears on the level of consciousness. The difference, however,
is clear. For where Kant speaks of experience, Hegel speaks of the experience of
consciousness. He goes, hence, further than Kant, since he elucidates what his illustrious
predecessor presupposes. According to Hegel, our experience of the external world is not
something that remains external to us. For experience presupposes that its object is, so to
speak, in consciousness.76
76. Tom Rockmore, Before and After Hegel: A Historical Introduction to Hegel’s Thought, 88.
77. Max Scheler, On the Eternal in Man, trans. Bernard Noble (New York: Harper & Brothers,
1960), 74.
78. Stanislaw Lem, Solaris (New York: Berkeley Books, 1982). The novel has inspired cinematic
adaptations by both Andrei Tarkovsky (1972) and Stephen Soderbergh (2002).
286
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
experimentation by bombarding the planet with X-rays, which elicits a response
from Solaris.
The novel serves to reveal the stark contrast between divergent responses to
attempted communication from an unfamiliar consciousness. The scientist's
dissection of the phenomena reflects the objectifying attitude of scientific inquiry,
an attitude that kills the object of inquiry and perverts the subject (the scientist)
into a monster, a lesser Dr Mengele. Kelvin, however, resists objectifying the
phenomena that he experiences, a response that reflects the phenomenological
attitude: what Hegel represents as the love relationship, and what Heidegger
discusses as positive solicitude. In short, phenomenology seeks to understand
through love, not vivisection.79
Conclusions
79. My characterisation of phenomenology is an adaptation of a blog post on Solaris. See Phil Hall,
“Solaris: Higher Sentience Communicates Through Love, Not Vivisection,”
http://xuitlacoche.blogspot.com/2008/07/solaris-higher-sentience-communicates.html (accessed
14/06/2012).
287
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
In light of our previous discussion, we can now return to the broader
argument that is being developed over the course of the thesis: that we are
constitutively unable to build an emancipatory cosmopolitanism from dualist
premises. The problem, to be precise, is foundational subject-object thinking, a
dualism that characterises Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism. Such
thinking is both epistemological error and ontological insufficiency: it
misunderstands the nature of the cognitive object as something that exists in the
mind-independent real rather than something that we construct on the basis of our
experiences, and it misrepresents our mode of being in the world by representing
ourselves as subjects, rather than as self-conscious subjects cognisant of the
limitations of the contemplative attitude, and open to the transcendence of
reflective rationality through an attunement to practical experience: what Hegel
understands as the love relationship, and Heidegger as engaged solicitous being-
with.
288
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
The trick then must be to situate subject-object thinking; this is the task of
philosophy. Hegel's challenge to dualism, for instance, solicits us to different
understandings of the cognitive object, the self, the relation between self and
world, and the nature and limitations of reflective rationality. For Hegel, we saw,
the cognitive object is not represented by the epistemological subject, but is
constructed on the basis of the mind-independent real appearing to consciousness.
From these phenomena that appear to consciousness we construct the cognitive
object; although corresponding entities exist in the mind-independent real, the
cognitive object itself does not, but is instead constructed through 'the interaction
between human beings situated within the historical process in which we come to
know the world and ourselves.' 80 Consequently, rather than being established
through a simple correspondence between mind and mind-independent real, 'truth,'
'objectivity,' subject-object unity, or what Hegel calls 'absolute knowledge,' is
never fully achieved, but is perpetually deferred in an ongoing process within
consciousness whereby increasingly adequate accounts of reality emerge; a process
that transforms both subject and object.
Proceeding from the view that 'knowledge does not concern the world in itself but
the world for us,' Hegel's approach situates knowledge within the historical process
and subordinates knowledge construction to the interaction between human
80. Tom Rockmore, Kant and Phenomenology, 215.
81. Ibid., 213.
82. Ibid.
289
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
beings.83 Reality, what we consider to be 'real,' emerges out of these relations, and
there are thus irrevocably plural and historical dimensions to 'subjectivity.'
83. Ibid., 215.
84. Jean-Luc Nancy, Being Singular Plural (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001), 75. See
also Nick Vaughan-Williams, “Beyond a Cosmopolitan Ideal: The Politics of Singularity,”
International Politics 44 (2007), 122.
290
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
ontological difference between entities and the being of entities; that is, while
human beings clearly exist independent of our knowledge of them, the being of
those beings does not. Our determination of the being of human beings as ethical
subjects, for instance, is dependent on a particular interpretation of the nature of
human beings that is projected onto them. We saw in Chapter 4 that Heidegger's
concern is to ensure that the being of beings remain open to contestation, that we
do not treat our regional ontologies of the person as general ontologies. Hegel's
constructivist epistemology can help us develop this further.
291
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
independent entity and mind-dependent cognitive object, with the being of human
beings an aspect of our understandings of human beings as cognitive object,
Hegel's constructivist approach to knowledge can lead us out of this impasse.
292
PART 3/Ch6. Understanding Through Love, Not Vivisection
Michel's renewed focus on language, and which stresses the essential limitations of
the contemplative attitude; emphasising instead the importance of a practical
relation to reality. One of the central contentions of this philosophical ontology is
the concern to avoid over-relying on subjectivity and reflective rationality as an
arbiter of difference, since these commitments are constitutively unable to
reconcile the divisions that they foster.
293
Chapter 7.
Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of
Fate
Introduction
295
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
In light of these prior discussions, the last chapter engaged with a reading of
the development of the subject-object relation from Kant to Hegel with three main
aims. Firstly, to destabilise readings of Hegel as a theorist of intersubjectivity, such
as those of Habermas, Linklater, and Honneth; all of whom read Hegel through a
kaleidoscope of the Kantian subject. Secondly, to outline the ontological and
epistemological groundwork for the alternative emancipatory cosmopolitanism that
will be developed in this chapter and the next; and finally, to provide a defence of
Hegel as a theorist of self-conscious subjectivity.
This chapter develops the latter point, turning what has largely been an
ontological and epistemological argument in an essentially ethical and
emancipatory direction. In so doing, we substantiate the claims made in Chapter 1
that Hegel's philosophy leads to a better way of conceiving human relationality
(relations to other persons, to our worlds, and to ourselves) than can Linklater's
reliance on Habermas's discursive account of moral reason. We also pick up and
develop the claim made in Chapter 4 that, while the notion of resolute solicitous
being with others has important implications for an account of inter-human
recognition that does not purely operate at a cerebral level, that Heidegger's
position lacks an account of the inter-personal conditions of freedom and
individuality – a deficiency that he might have avoided had he been a better
student of Hegel.
296
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
the achievement of self-conscious subjectivity where the self becomes cognisant of
the essential limitations of reflective rationality and attunes themselves to practical
experience: to the appearance of the mind-independent real, where other
consciousnesses (i.e., persons) are related to as singularities rather than subjects.
This chapter engages with Hegel's account of the master and slave in greater depth,
demonstrating the profoundly ethical and emancipatory aspects of this argument
that are, by and large, obscured by kaleidoscopic readings of Hegel.
297
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
The central argument of this chapter is that properly ethical and
emancipatory action is action that proceeds from the knowledge of love. By this
what is meant is that the experience of love is an experience that can lead to a
greater awareness of the nature of our existence as self-conscious beings, as
individual selves who are dependent on others for the very constitution of our own
subjectivity. This awareness solicits us to cultivate our practical relation to reality,
and leads us to engage with others as others rather than as ethical subjects.
298
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
subjected to the test of universalisability, our conception of self-conscious
subjectivity leads both to a different conception of self-other relations, and an
understanding of freedom as the transcendence of any prior determination of my
subjective being through concrete interaction with others. Finally, we argue that
self-conscious subjectivity involves cultivating an attunement to the existence of
others where the existence of others becomes part of a deeper fabric of our own
self-understandings, subsequently informing the way that we relate to ourselves, to
others, and to our worlds. We represent this orientation through the notion of our
participation with others in a community of fate, and argue that this self-conscious
awareness of the relational constitution of our own individuality augments
Heidegger's account of freedom as solicitous being-with others by demonstrating
the profoundly inter-personal and cooperative basis for own freedom and self-
hood.
299
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Love has been a mainstay in philosophy at least since the early Greeks, and
its discussion transcends many sub-disciplines, including metaphysics,
epistemology, theology, politics and ethics. There are a variety of approaches to
love ranging from the materialistic reduction to a physical phenomenon – an
animalistic or genetic urge – to idealist conceptions of love as the construction of
the mind that is the consequence of the body's release of endorphins, but also
spiritualist conceptions that associate it with the touch of divinity. Most of these
use Platonic and Aristotelian conceptions as a touchstone.1
1. For a concise overview of behaviouralist, physical determinist, and expressivist approaches to
love, see Alexander Moseley, “’Philosophy of Love’ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,”
http://www.iep.utm.edu/love/.
2. Plato, Plato’s Symposium, trans. Seth Benardete (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001).
See also Allan Bloom, “The Ladder of Love,” in Plato’s Symposium (Chicago: Chicago University
Press, 2001).
3. Alexander Moseley, “Philosophy of Love.”
4. As we shall see, the contention that love has a ‘nature’ would likely be disputed by Hegel, since
it presupposes that love can be described in rational propositions; a form of cognition that love
transcends.
300
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
individual reminds us of true beauty that exists in the world of Forms or Ideas.'5 On
this account, to love is to love the element of the ideal (true beauty) that the
particular element (a person, or piece of art) possesses. The implication is that the
object of love becomes interchangeable across people and things.
Contrasting with the yearning associated with eros, philia entails a fondness
and appreciation of the object, and is a derivative of eros that Aristotle
characterises as 'a sort of excess of feeling.'6 Philia is roughly captured by the
English concept of 'friendship,' although for the Greeks it also incorporated loyalty
to the family, to the polis, or to a job. Further distinguishing it from eros, philia
entails reciprocity between the subject and object of philic love. For Aristotle,
those with whom we share a philic love are only those who are worthy of it, and he
suggests that there is therefore an objective basis for philia. For instance, we would
share with them dispositions, and they would admire us appropriately as we admire
them, etc. Although it is not necessarily equal, and parental love can involve a one-
sided fondness, reciprocity is the condition of Aristotelian love and friendship.7
Aristotelian philia is a love of virtue. True lovers are those whom act out of virtue
or the other's interest; all other relationships are ones of pleasure or utility.8
Drawing on elements of both eros and philia, for the Greeks at least, agape is
the highest kind of love; a perfect kind of love that entails both the fondness of
philic love and the passion and transcendence of the particular object of love in
eros, as well as its non-requirement of reciprocity. Unlike philia, agape is not
directed towards particular persons but to all of humanity, and it is later
appropriated by Christian theology where it refers to the 'paternal love of God for
man and man for God,' and to a brotherly love for all humanity. For this reason
5. Ibid.
6. Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. David Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009),
VIII,6.
7. Aristotle writes: 'In all friendships implying inequality the love also should be proportional, i.e.
the better should be more loved than he loves.' Ibid., VIII, 7.
8. C.F. Cheung, “Between Myself and Others: Towards a Phenomenology of the Experience of
Love” (Paper presented at the Identity and Alterity: Phenomenology and Cultural Traditions, Hong
Kong, 24th May 2005).
301
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
agape is most commonly associated with the Christian sense of love as giving.9
The Biblical command to 'love thy neighbour as thyself' is a universalist command
that, if necessary, may be unilateral since the onus is on the extension of love to
others.10 That said, C.S. Lewis is misguided in his The Four Loves to claim agape
as a specifically Christian virtue since all the world's great religions assume and
teach the priority of love in religious practice.11
'... the ultimate essence of love and hatred cannot be defined but only exhibited'
Max Scheler
Between myself and the beloved object, there is love. But, the being of love is in loving
experience, i.e., my love for my mother is only meaningful if "loving my mother" is a
lived experience (Erlebnis) for me. This love cannot be abstracted from the "I" who is
loving my mother [...] I do not have something called love but I am loving something. This
loving as an irreducible unique in-between lived experience is the phenomenon of love.
9. Alexander Moseley, “Philosophy of Love.”
10. Matthew, 19:19; 22:39; Mark 12:31; Luke 10:27; Romans 13:9; Galatians 5:14; James 2:8 Ibid.
11. C.S. Lewis, The Four Loves (Boston: Mariner Books, 1960). See John Templeton, Agape Love:
A Tradition Found in Eight World Religions (Radnor: Templeton Foundation Press, 1999). The
Buddhist example of Mettā ("loving-kindness," active interest in others) is a case in point.
12. C.F. Cheung, “Between Myself and Others: Towards a Phenomenology of the Experience of
Love,” 5.
13. Ibid., 4.
302
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
The how of love as experienced by myself is phenomenologically more primordial than
the reason or cause of love.14
Consequently, we should change our focus from the eidos to the ethos of
love. Since even if love has a nature, the question remains as to whether we are
able to understand it, whether love can be an object of our knowledge. We can
perhaps catch glimpses of its essence as phenomena of our experience, meaning
that it can be hinted at even if not ever fully understood in and of itself. Although
fundamentally limited, this is the benefit of the eros-philia-agape schema, since it
reflects several shades of love that are exhibited in different kinds of relationships:
romantic love, love for friends, or love of photography, etc. Rather than imposing
these prescriptive meaning onto experiences, however, we must suspend the
definitional schema of agape-eros-agape in order to render the lived-experience of
love more transparent.
Towards the end of the last chapter we saw that Hegel considers 'love' to
represent an overcoming of the standpoint of reflective rationality, an experience
that represents a higher form of cognition through which the self becomes more
attuned to practical experience and where that which is encountered is no longer
simply a subject or an object. This is why we suggested that what Hegel calls
'love,' the achieved reconciliation between self and world, is best understood not as
something overly sentimental or romantic, but as a proto-phenomenological
relationship between self and world. We also learnt that phenomenology is not
simply a method, but is better understood as an attitude towards philosophical
problems, an attunement to practical experience and an openness to experiencing
prior to the assumption of a set of criteria or assimilation within a set of categories
or conceptual scheme.
14. Ibid., 5.
303
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Since Plato, grasping the meaning or essence of an object has involved
disengaging from the object, suspending that object's present and immediate
existence in order that it may be grasped as it is 'in itself.' In contrast,
phenomenology cultivates a shift in seeing so that the world is no longer taken for
granted, as is the assumption in treating something as a given object, but is
regarded critically and engaged with practically. Importantly, the
phenomenological attitude does not simply reject the objectification of the world,
where entities are treated as objects, but holds this objectified world in abeyance
out of a love of the world.15
Love makes it possible for us to receive the world as it is rather than as we want or wish it
to be. Love enables us to resist the (often violent) integration of others into the sameness
and comfort of the thinker's world. It acknowledges in a way that no other disposition or
activity can the integrity and the mystery of existence.17
15. Zachary Davis and Anthony Steinbock, Max Scheler, Winter 2011 ed., The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scheler/, 2011).
16. Ibid. Referring to Max Scheler, Gesammelte Werke (Bonn: Bouvier Verlag, 1986), V,83.
17. Norman Wirzba and Bruce Ellis Benson, Transforming Philosophy and Religion: Love’s
Wisdom (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2008), 18.
304
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Hegel and Love.
305
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
self-conscious subjectivity, whereby a living relation between self and world is re-
experienced, and the self recognises both its fundamental difference, and its
essential connection, to the rest of life: both physical processes of life, and the life
of Geist.
First appearing early in his career during his Frankfurt years, in his Fragment
on Love (1797/1798) and in The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate (1799), love
18. Just as Heidegger's 'being-in-the-world,' is hyphenated, 'identity-in-difference' or 'unity-in-
difference,' is hyphenated to denote that this recognition is a unitary phenomenon.
19. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage,” Lectures on Hegel’s
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 8th November (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/19MasterSlaveA.mp3.
306
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
plays a formative role in the development of Hegel's thought; three of Hegel's most
important ideas first emerge in these essays: his organicist conception of freedom,
his dialectical logic (the mutually conditioned nature of the relation between
subject and object), and his notion of ethical life (Sittlichkeit). Responding to
Kant's duality between freedom and nature, where freedom is thought of as the
freedom of the subject and the object as a limitation on the subject's freedom,
Hegel reworks the Kantian model of self and world. Here, the freedom of the self
is worked into a true freedom of the infinite, where the opposition between subject
and object is reworked into a living, mutually conditioned union of subject and
object in Geist, and the interaction between subject and object is governed by a
dialectical rather than a transcendental logic. Kant's transcendental morality,
governed by the categorical imperative, is thus situated within and subordinated to
the immanent structure of ethical life, and this leads to Hegel's well-known
distinction between Moralität and Sittlichkeit. All three of these responses to Kant
are based on the experience of love. Both love and freedom are defined by Hegel
as 'being with oneself in the other,' his dialectical logic is based upon the 'logic' of
love, and the experience of love is the experience of ethical life in its most basic
form. All three of these concepts developed in his Early Theological Writings are
central to the development of his subsequent thought.
307
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
the creation of their own world from a critical and rationalist perspective. In so
doing, Habermas reads the movement of Hegel's thought as a development from
the standpoint of love to the standpoint of reason. It is this reading of Hegel that
characterises Linklater's appropriation of his thought.
20. See, for example, Dilthey's biography of the young Hegel Wilhelm Dilthey, Die
Jugendgeschichte Hegels Und Andere Abhandlungen Zur Geschichte Des Deutschen Idealismus
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1990).
21. See David Boucher, ed. The British Idealists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997);
David Boucher and Andrew Vincent, British Idealism and Political Theory (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2000).
22. Axel Honneth, Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory (London: Polity,
2007), 164.
308
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
The consequence is that, during the last century at least, people writing about
Hegel have consistently emphasised the developmental understanding of reason in
his writings, suppressing the role of love. However, Hegel's 'absolute' – absolute
knowledge and absolute spirit – is achieved through a recognition that is not given
wholly conceptually but is based instead upon a reconciliation of concept and
being, where the latter operates as the privileged signifier. Because of this,
'secularised,' 'demythologised,' or 'pragmatic' interpretations of Hegel ultimately
elevate reason to a position from which Hegel consistently and insistently displaces
it, effectively severing or 'killing' the living relationship between subject and
object, self and world, that is absolutely central to Hegel's thought. Consequently,
this dominant interpretation of Hegel is at best debatable, and, as is the opinion of
this author, may even be fundamental distortion of Hegel's thought.23
What is at stake here is nothing less than a recognition of the proper nature of
the relationship between self and world, the role of praxis, and the questionable
authority of reason (along with its essential limitations). Fortunately though, there
are several recent attempts to redress this interpretation of Hegel, Jay Bernstein
(1994;2003) and Alice Ormiston (2002;2004) are the most significant of these, but
Richard Beardsworth (2006) and Laura Werner (2007) are also worthy of note.24
These all see in Hegel's early writing a potentially radical way of conceptualising
self-other relations that is not effectively reflected in the 'demythologised,'
'secular,' and 'mature' readings of Hegel.
23. An argument might even be made that the emphasis on the sovereignty of reason in rationalist
interpretations of Hegel actually contributes to the totalitarian charges made against him by Popper.
On this rationalist view, universality is something that might be achieved: hence the part can
ultimately be subordinated to the whole, as opposed to recognising that our ‘universals’ are always
conditioned and incomplete; our concepts constituted by a Derridean 'trace,' a constitutive exclusion
or blind-spot. Such a realisation enjoins us to recognise the essentially limited nature of our
understandings.
24. J.M. Bernstein, “Conscience and Transgression: The Persistence of Misrecognition,” Bulletin of
the Hegel Society of Great Britain 29 (1994): 55-70; J.M. Bernstein, “Love and Law: Hegel’s
Critique of Morality,” Social Research: An International Quarterly 70, no. 2 (2003): 393-431.
Alice Ormiston, “”The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate:” Towards a Reconsideration of the Role
of Love in Hegel,” Canadian Journal of Political Science 35, no. 3 (2002): 499-525; Alice
Ormiston, Love and Politics: Re-Interpreting Hegel (New York: SUNY Press, 2004). Laura
Werner, “The Restless Love of Thinking: The Concept of Liebe in Hegel’s Philosophy” (Ph.D
Thesis, University of Helsinki, 2007). Richard Beardsworth, “A Note to a Political Understanding
of Love in Our Global Age,” Contretemps (2006).
309
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
25. Judith Butler, Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-Century France (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1999), xv.
26. Hegel's account of the master and slave is found in the section of the Phenomenology of Spirit
on 'Lordship and Bondage,' commonly referred to as the master-slave dialectic or the struggle for
recognition. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1977), §§178-96.
27. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage,” Lectures on Hegel’s
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 8th November (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/20MasterSlaveB.mp3.
28. The struggle for recognition is commonly read as a discourse on the nature and possibility of
human freedom, but the establishment of subjective freedom is only the non-vital end of this
struggle. For a reading of this passage as a treatise on the nature and possibility of freedom see
Robert B. Pippin, “What is the Question for Which Hegel’s Theory of Recognition is the Answer?,”
European Journal of Philosophy 8, no. 2 (2000): 55-172.
310
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
want: it is their desire for absolute independence, subjectivity, that draws them into
the struggle in the first place.29 Treating each other as if they were subjects is a way
of resolving the ensuing struggle between life and death. The 'subjects' that face
each other make claims of freedom on one another, and ultimately resolve to
recognise each other as subjects; this is freedom as sociality. Freedom as
independence is problematic because it is part of a fantasy of freedom, the fantasy
that freedom is absolute independence from all conditionality.30 Hegel's move is to
reroute freedom and argue that it is only within dependent relations with others that
we can establish any independence.31 Importantly though, mutual recognition is a
way of mediating the fact that we are absolutely dependent on the other, and
consequently, our independence can only ever be a relative independence, relative
to the others on whom we depend.
Freedom is the non-vital end of the struggle for recognition because the
outcome of the account of the master and slave is not simply about the
'intersubjective' conditions of 'subjectivity' (purposefully written without the
strikethrough), but is the achievement of self-conscious subjectivity; achieving
awareness of the fact that the self is not a subject. The self-conscious subject
establishes itself as an independent entity, but at the same time recognises that its
subjectivity is dependent on others. Recognition is, therefore, a union of
separateness and connectedness: it leads to the recognition that we are both
absolutely dependent on the other for their recognition, and at the same time,
absolutely independent of them. In short, the self-conscious subject achieves a
recognition of their unity-in-difference. Self-consciousness – becoming aware of
the nature of our own existence, what we actually are, and our mode of being in the
world – involves recognising this unity-in-difference, recognising our simultaneous
dependence and independence on others.
29. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage. (B).”
30. Ibid.
31. Ibid.
311
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Love and Recognition: The Three Moments of the Re-cognitive Structure of
Self-Consciousness32
In short, what is being explored in the account of the master and slave is the
re-cognitive structure of self-consciousness. Becoming self-conscious, gaining a
higher level of self-awareness about the nature of our own individual existences as
human beings, as selves, involves overcoming object-oriented forms of
consciousness by realising that I am not a Kantian/Fichtean subject, and that I am
fundamentally and irrevocably reliant on others for the constitution of my own
subjectivity. In other words, that my own freedom and my self-understandings are
not purely own to me, but depend on the others with whom I interact.
There are three moments to this achievement, which are modelled on the
experience of love. Although stating that 'there are no parts, moments, types or
stages of love [...] only an infinity of shatters,' Nancy's discussion of the movement
of love mirrors the three moments of the re-cognitive structure of self-
consciousness discussed in Hegel's account of the master and slave, and dividing
Nancy's account of the movement of love into these moments can help us to better
grasp what Hegel is getting at in this part of the Phenomenology.33
Love is, for Nancy, 'the extreme movement, beyond the self, of a being
reaching completion,' which he later restates in Hegelian terms as 'having in an
other the moment of one's subsistence.'34 The first moment of love is that I do not
wish to exist as an independent person in my own right, since as this independent
existent I feel deficient and incomplete; in the second moment I then find myself
through the recognition of another person, and they find theirs in me. The
32. The discussion in this section follows Nancy's discussion in: Jean-Luc Nancy, “Shattered
Love,” in A Finite Thinking (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003). And Bernstein's discussion
in J.M. Bernstein, “Early Theological Writings,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit The
New School. New York City. 20th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/06EarlyTheologicalWritingD.mp3; J.M. Bernstein,
“Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage. (a).”; J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit.
Lordship and Bondage. (B).”
33. Jean-Luc Nancy, “Shattered Love,” in A Finite Thinking (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2003).
34. Ibid., 249.
312
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
combination of these two moments leads to the third moment, which is the
achievement of the recognition of unity-in-difference. This will now be unpacked.
35. Ibid., 258.
36. This is what Hegel means by 'infinite,' for example, when he says that, in love, finite life is
raised to infinite life: 'The partial character of the living being is transcended in religion; finite life
raises to infinite life.' G.W.F. Hegel, “Fragment of a System,” in Early Theological Writings
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 313.
37. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage. (a).”
313
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
This unity-in-difference does not require a spontaneous one-ness of will: the
self is still a self, an independent agent, but it does realise that this independence is
only relative, and that absolute independence, subjectivity, is illusory. The other
remains other because I cannot make it will things. Although I can will its will and
desire its desire, I cannot force either: I cannot get ahold of the other's freedom. If I
am lucky the other can will what I will and desire what I desire, and in this case I
am united with the other, and them with me. However, the other can stop loving
me at any time, and so remains and must remain other: it cannot be dominated by
either force or reason. This is why love is an immense contradiction that the
understanding simply cannot resolve: the understanding demands either internal
relations or external relations, it wants me to be either in myself (separate) or
immersed in this unity (from which I cannot separate myself from), but I am both,
and there is no whole either holistically or atomistically.38
We can readily admit that this discussion is not a straightforward one, and
the notion of recognising a unity-in-difference with something that is not-me does
seem foreign. But we can illuminate our discussion of love as the image of our
radical dependency, and its distinction from a model of self-other relations based
upon the subject, through a brief discussion of Ralph Waldo Emerson's essay,
Experience.
Emerson published two collections of essays, the first series in 1841 and the
second in 1844. Preceding the first was the death of his first wife Ellen in 1831.
The nature of Emerson's response to Ellen's death is reflected in the themes of his
first collection. These themes, best illustrated in the 1841 essay Circles, included
nature's forgetfulness, an overcoming of the past through casting off, and the
transcendence of pain and suffering by severing his relations to her. Essentially,
Circles sees Emerson responding to Ellen's death through acts of Stoic resignation
38. Ibid.
314
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
where he sheds his past and establishes himself as autonomous from it; an
individualism that is carried over to a fourth theme of the collection, the possibility
of self-perfection, where solace is sought by carrying the self to its highest possible
achievement.39
Preceding Emerson's second series of essays published in 1844 was the death
of his five-year-old son Waldo in 1842. Emerson is unable to react to his son's
death as he did to Ellen's, and this bind is reflected in his second collection in
which he adopts a radically different attitude to the autonomous individuality that
characterises the first: an attitude of embracing rather than forgetting; of relations
rather than individuality; and of mature acceptance rather than adolescent
rebellion.40
This shift in attitude is due to the fact that Emerson's stoicism simply does
not work with the passing of his son. He can neither forget Waldo, nor transcend
the experience of his death. Because he cannot achieve a visceral understanding of
Waldo's death, Emerson simply cannot comprehend the death of his son, and is
thus unable to pass through the experience to the other side. Waldo's ghost haunts
him. 41 There is 'no scar' from Waldo's death, there was no ripping apart; no
separation. Emerson writes '[s]ome thing which I fancied was a part of me, which
could not be torn away without tearing me, nor enlarged without enriching me,
falls off from me, and leaves no scar. It was caducous.'42 Emerson is saying to
himself that, if love was what he thought it was, which is what every lover, every
parent thinks love is, then he could not have survived this death; because they were
one. Yet he survived. And that is his terror: that he is absolutely separate.43
39. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Selections From Ralph Waldo Emerson (Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Company, 1960). Stephen Barnes, “Emerson: Death and Growth” (Paper presented at the Society
for the Advancement of American Philosophy, Las Vegas, 2001).
40. Ibid.
41. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Selections From Ralph Waldo Emerson. Stephen Barnes, “Emerson:
Death and Growth.”
42. Ralph Waldo Emerson, Selections From Ralph Waldo Emerson.
43. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Introduction,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology
of Spirit The New School. New York City. 27th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/07PhenomenologyIntroA.mp3.
315
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Clearly the death of a son is an extreme case, but it demonstrates what is for
Hegel a deeper truth about the nature of human existence; that is, the interruptive
condition of subjectivity. For Hegel, I can only gain awareness of myself as an
independent and free personality through the recognition of an other. 'Self-
consciousness exists only in and for itself when, and by the fact that, it so exists for
another; that is, it exists only in being acknowledged.'44 Since I cannot be assured
of being a self-conscious rational being without being recognised as such by the
other, Hegel's claim is that the other mediates my self-relation constitutively.45 For
this reason I remain bound to others on whom I come to depend on for my sense of
self.
44. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, §178.
45. An opposing view is given by Levinas, for whom the 'not me' is simply opposed to 'me,' but for
Hegel subjectivity requires more than difference: it requires interruption. J.M. Bernstein,
“Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage. (a).”
316
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
relations would not constitute our own subjectivity. The experience of love thus
discredits the idea that we can consider ourselves to be subjects because we are
fundamentally exposed to the existence to others, an exposure that constitutes the
condition of our own subjectivity.
46. Indeed, Nancy suggests that the Phenomenology can essentially be read as a tome that
ultimately leads to this exposure of the individual (i.e., the individual's exposure to absolute
knowledge). Jean-Luc Nancy, “Shattered Love.”
47. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, §178.
317
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Transcendence: The Crossing of Love
This exposure binds self to other, and transforms both in their interaction;
something of the 'I' is lost in the act of loving: I come back to myself, I come out of
the experience broken.
The "return" does not annul the break; it neither repairs it nor sublates it, for the return in
fact takes place only across the break itself, keeping it open. Love re-presents I to itself
broken (and this is not a representation). It presents this to it: he, this subject, was touched,
broken into, in his subjectivity, and he is from then on, for the time of love, opened by this
slice, broken or fractured, even if only slightly [...] the break is a break in his self-
possession as subject; it is, essentially, an interruption of the process of relating oneself to
oneself outside of oneself. From then on I is constituted broken. As soon as there is love,
the slightest act of love, the slightest spark, there is this ontological fissure that cuts across
and that disconnects the elements of the subject proper [...] The love break simply means
this: that I can no longer, whatever presence to myself I may maintain or that sustains me,
pro-pose myself to myself (nor im-pose myself on another) without remains, without
something of me remaining outside of me.48
It is the interaction between self and other that leads to the transcendence of
the self; it is through the movement of love that I transcend the immanence of my
'subjectivity' and overcome any prior determination of my being. The interruption
of subjectivity is the transcendence of this subjectivity, and the transcendence of
subjectivity is the operation of human freedom. This transcendence is not the
transcendence of the Kantian (knowing or ethical) subject that stands above the
objects of its experience, but is the transcendence of a being that becomes
something else as a result of its interaction with others.
48. Jean-Luc Nancy, “Shattered Love,” 260-61. Butler expresses the same idea differently: 'The
price of self-knowledge will be self-loss, and the Other poses the possibility of both securing and
undermining self-knowledge. What becomes clear, though, is that the self never returns to itself free
of the Other, that its "relationality" becomes constitutive of who the self is.' Judith Butler, “Longing
for Recognition: Commentary on the Work of Jessica Benjamin,” Studies in Gender and Sexuality
1, no. 3 (2000), 286.
318
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
I-Thou / I-It
49. Jean-Luc Nancy, “Shattered Love,” 262.
319
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
relationship between self and world.50 Referring to the nature of this relation as a
'between,' which we co-constitute before we know it, the nature of our relation to
the 'between' prefigures all subsequent relations that we have. In a similar vein to
Hegel's development of different forms of consciousness from an underlying unity
of life, Buber begins from a relational situation of all beings, akin to a prenatal
existence, out of which the establishment of a separate 'I' requires a fundamental
split. The establishment of this separate 'I' can then lead to the separateness of an I-
it relation, built on the schism of subject and object. This I-it relation is the typical
subject-object relationship 'in which one knows and uses other persons or things
without allowing them to exist for oneself in their uniqueness.'51
However, the I-it relation is not the only possible mode of interaction
between self and other, and Buber contrasts it to the I-Thou relation: a concrete
encounter between two persons that is characterised by openness, mutuality, and
presence.52 Whereas in the I-it relation I experience a detached thing (an object), in
the I-Thou relation self and other participate in a dynamic process in which we
exist as as polarities of relation, the centre of which is the ‘between’. Importantly,
the 'I' of man differs in these alternative modes of existence. The 'I' can be taken as
the sum of its attributes or acts, an abstracted essence that permits it to be
represented as a subject, or it can be taken as a singular, irreducible, finite being.
Only in the I-Thou relation is the other truly other, rather than existing as a
representative object for a subject, and only in this concrete encounter can the 'I'
develop as a whole being. Although Buber challenges Hegel in important respects
in his lecture What is Man, Buber's categorisation here can illuminate our response
to Linklater through Hegel, and help us to shed any latent religiosity, mysticism or
romanticism when discussing Hegel's notion of love – by foregrounding the ethical
logic that is reflected in the experience of love.
Since the establishment of a separate 'I' requires a split from a prior unity,
just as for Hegel, and in contrast to Kant, for Buber subjectivity is not
50. Martin Buber, Between Man and Man (London: Routledge, 2002).
51. Ibid., xii.
52. Martin Buber, I and Thou (London: Continuum, 2004).
320
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
foundational, but derivative. Moreover, this 'I' has different modes of interaction
with the world, Buber's I-it relation thus resonating with Hegel's analysis of object-
oriented forms of consciousness, both of which are inappropriate as relations to
persons. In this respect, as a relation between persons, Buber's I-Thou relation
echoes what Hegel seeks to achieve through the struggle for recognition: namely,
the transcendence of an object-oriented form of consciousness in the concrete
encounter with another human being. In Hegel's version, both 'subjects' actively
react against their reduction to objects, demonstrating right up to the pain of death
that they are underdetermined by their constitution as subjects in order to achieve
mutual recognition between mature personalities (i.e., self-conscious
subjectivities).
For both Buber and Hegel our mode of interaction with the world is
constitutive of the self. While for Buber the 'I' of man differs according to our
mode of interaction with the world, for Hegel subject and object are mutually
conditioning, and both are transformed in the interaction between self and world. It
is only in the I-Thou relation that both relata can develop as whole beings – just as
the interaction between mutually recognising self-consciousnesses is the condition
of a complete personality for Hegel. Although Buber's I and Thou is criticised for
denigrating I-it relations, he does not deny their usefulness and necessity. His point
is that one is only fully human to the extent that one can participate in the I-thou
relation. Similarly, Hegel would identify the I-it relation as a form of diremption of
life, epitomised by Kantian dualism between subject and object, a duality that is
transcended when the self achieves recognition of its own exposure.
Essentially what both Hegel and Buber recognise is that there is a different
kind of relation here, between I and Thou, and that it is this relation that constitutes
properly ethical relations between self and other. Since reflective thought
represents ethical relations as relations between ethical subjects, it constitutes a
321
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
retreat from the concrete relation between singular finite beings that are not
reducible to their ethical subjectivity. The problem is that in affirming the
sovereignty of reason in ethical subjectivity, we reinforce the split between self and
other and distort the nature of the 'between,' which adversely affects both self and
other. Moreover, as we have seen, by reducing persons to ethical subjects we
preclude the possibility of a genuine encounter with the other.
322
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
ground of action) before subsequently 'bridging' the relation between subject and
subject through the exercise of reason. In so doing Linklater effectively imposes a
vision of the ethical subject onto the human being. Not only can this imposition be
considered neither ethical nor emancipatory, but it serves to alienate self from
other.
323
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
to surmount that subjectivity through the exercise of discursive reason. By building
these walls around the subject freedom does not consist in the concrete interaction
between persons, but in the adoption of a universal perspective and acting
according to the rules given thereby. In addition to the problems associated with
the foundational ethical subject explored in the previous chapter, this involves an
alienation from our radical dependency, from the interruptive condition of our own
subjectivity, which leads to a limited account of human freedom and threatens to
alienate ourselves from the depth phenomena of human existence: from a genuine
experience of our own individual existences as selves, from a full appropriation
and experience of our freedom, and an from an authentic experience of
community. In short, the very experiences that make us human.53
53. Heidegger has a similar concern about the Western technological civilisation see Gregory Bruce
Smith, Martin Heidegger: Paths Opened, Paths Taken (Plymouth: Rowman & Littlefield, 2007), 3.
324
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
alternative to conceptualising interpersonal relations as intersubjective relations.
Nonetheless, we concluded that the weakness of Heidegger's account was that it
falls short when it comes to a demonstrating that both freedom and self-
intelligibility are ineluctably acquired in relations to others under conditions of
cooperative interaction, and that Hegel's intersubjective account of freedom and
self-hood is more convincing. We are now in a position to substantiate that claim,
and to suggest that an important aspect of any emancipatory cosmopolitanism
involves not just establishing the conditions for the exercise of subjectivity, but
engaging in resolute solicitous being-with others and cultivating the awareness of
our shared participation within a 'community of fate.'
We have seen that while both Kant and Fichte identify the self with reason
rather than the authority of someone else, Hegel thinks that this view of self-other
relations, where a sharp distinction is drawn between the rational self and
everything else, is a mode of escape or self-withdrawal from our condition of
radical dependency. Hegel follows Fichte in understanding the self as its own self-
positing activity, but the self is regarded as the outcome of this activity rather than
its condition. Selfhood is not achieved through an aloofness of subject to object,
but through engaged participation in the world of objects and other
consciousnesses. Self-conscious selfhood (subjectivity) is achieved when I
recognise that I exist in a condition of unity-in-difference with others on whom I
am dependent for the constitution of my own subjectivity.
The idea that is modelled in Hegel's account of the master and slave – the
interruptive condition of subjectivity, that were we are left fundamentally exposed
to the other as part of the very fabric of our being – leads to self and other being
bound together in a community of fate. This is not a community based upon an
abstraction, such as one in which we participate simply by virtue of being 'human'
rather than 'non-human' – where specific attributes or capacities, such as
compassion for others, or universal ethical reasoning, have to be used or developed
in order for us to become 'fully human' – but is an existential community that is
325
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
created and recreated through our own activity, constituting the social matrix
within which humans become the kinds of beings that we are.
The central idea here is that, ultimately, our self is not up to us: that we are
reliant on others not just for the things that we have and the things that we do, but
also for the very way that we are. This is not a psychological claim, but an
ontological one. Clearly we develop psychologically in relations to others. A child
is fundamentally dependent on their parents and other caregivers, and we all
develop at least initially in relation to others. As an ontological claim though, the
idea is not just that the self develops in relation to others, but that in some sense
that this relation precedes the self.
Co-dependent Arising
At least from the point of view of a Western cultural tradition, this is clearly
a paradoxical thought, which is why at least one commentator has suggested that
here Hegel perhaps reaches the end or limit of traditional Western thought and
approaches the East. 54 There are striking similarities here with a Buddhist
metaphysics of 'no thing' and dependent arising, for example. The latter (Sanskrit:
Pratītyasamutpāda) is a cardinal Buddhist doctrine that all phenomena arise
54. See the comments section on J.M. Bernstein, “An Interview With J.M. Bernstein,” The New
York Times Opinionator 21st November (2011).
326
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
together in a mutually dependent web of cause and effect. In the Madhyamaka
philosophy, founded by Nāgārjuna, this is synonymous with saying that all things
and persons are lacking in inherent existence and are without any enduring
essential nature; that there is no independently existing self and that all phenomena
depend on other things for their existence.55
Clearly this is a very different model of community from that which we are
accustomed to, but at its most basic it is simply a model of radical human
dependency at the level of self-consciousness. Hegel's idea is that the subject
(Geist, mind) is not in the head, but is in the social world, embodied in relations of
intersubjectivity, meaning that we are radically dependent on others for who we
are. The minimal unit for there to be self-conscious subjectivity is two, we cannot
have an immediate relationship to ourselves, our being is always mediated by the
other. But two is never enough; we always need the third: for an 'I think' we need a
'we think,' and this 'we think' is embodied in Geist.56
A key contention here is that rather than being something that bubbles up
from the ego or the id, the self is something that exists between you and me; i.e.,
that my subjectivity is essentially related to the way that people respond to me.57
Who I am is how I connect, how I get responded to, how I get recognised or fail to
get recognised by others. Others can harm, degrade, and devalue me, and it this is
in these relations of intersubjectivity that human life is lived. We are taught
independence since we need to separate from our parents, from our school, and
from our peer group. It is important to us that our lives are not pre-scripted, and
that we make our own way. Consequently, we seek to establish or secure our own
55. See Nāgārjuna, The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, trans. Jay L. Garfield (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995),
24:18,24:19. also Dalai Lama, How to Practice: The Way to a Meaningful Life, trans. Jeffrey
Hopkins (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2002), 137,149,156-159. Candrakīrti, Introduction to the
Middle Way: Chandrakirti’s Madhyamakavatara (Boston: Shambhala Publications, 2002).
Elizabeth Napper, Dependent-Arising and Emptiness: A Tibetan Buddhist Interpretation of
Mādhyamika Philosophy Emphasizing the Compatibility of Emptiness and Conventional
Phenomena (Somerville, MA: Wisdom Publications, 2003).
56. J.M. Bernstein, “Introduction,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit The New School.
New York City. 9th September (2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/01IntroA.mp3.
57. J.M. Bernstein, “An Interview With J.M. Bernstein.”
327
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
independence, and as a result freedom is often understood in terms of an individual
thought as subject participating with other subjects on mutually agreeable terms.58
Action that Follows from the Knowledge of Love: The Condition of Ethical
Relations and the Full Appropriation of Human Freedom.
Since it proceeds from the recognition of the nature of the self's dependency
on others, action that follows from the knowledge of love is ultimately the
condition of a truly ethical and emancipatory politics. Such an approach to an
58. These Hegelian insights are Jay Bernstein's. See J.M. Bernstein, “Introduction (a).” J.M.
Bernstein, “An Interview With J.M. Bernstein.”
59. Ibid.
328
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
ethical and emancipatory politics might lead to a form of cosmopolitanism based
upon the recognition that emancipatory political action is not simply about
defending other people's rights to engage in dialogue with us, but involves being
aware that my fate is bound with yours (at least when it comes to self-conscious
individuality). Such an approach to an emancipatory politics would not require that
we 'bridge' relations between subjects through the exercise of reason, but would
demand instead that we foster an attunement to the social conditions of our own
'subjectivity'. On this basis it would then require that the relationship between self
and world be characterised by relations of openness, mutuality and co-presence;
relations that would contribute to the liberation of both self and other.
60. Recognising the essential limitations of these forms of engagements does not deny that there
will be a great many situations in world politics where the management or control of political
differences will represent an ethically significant improvement on a previous state of affairs,
particularly in cases where the protagonists are in a violent confrontation with one another. The
point being made here is that pacification or control is more a politically expedient or pragmatic
resolution rather than a truly ethical one.
329
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
Conclusions
We began the chapter by arguing that love is not an object of knowledge, but
is a lived experience, and that we should therefore change our focus from the eidos
of love to the ethos of love. Understanding love as an ethos is to regard it as an
experience through which we transcend object-oriented forms of consciousness
thereby achieving a higher level of self-awareness of the living union between self
and world. Understood in this way,
we claimed that such an ethos of love can be
considered as a proto-phenomenological attitude that suspends the objectified
world in abeyance in order to attune the self to practical experience, thereby
making a more genuine encounter with the world possible.
We later discussed Hegel's account of the master and slave, which is not an
account of the interaction of two independent self-conscious subjects demanding
recognition from each other, but is an account whereby the respective protagonists
overcome object-oriented forms of consciousness and thereby achieve self-
conscious subjectivity as a result of their concrete interaction. For this reason, we
argued, the account of the master and slave is about our radical dependency on
330
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
others for our own sense of self, and that the mutual recognition between free
beings ('subjects') is only the non-vital end of this struggle.
331
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
moral principles, but should involve cultivation an attunement to a practical
relation to reality and to the existence of others.
This is not a community of ethical subjects, nor one based on the possibility
of mutual understanding, but is a community of mutually conditioning finite
singular beings co-existing in their becoming. In Chapter 4 we argued that an
authentic mode of being in the world involves solicitous being-with others, where
engaging with others as others, and in a way that 'frees up' their potentiality for
being. Hegel's contribution to this mode of being in the world involves self-
conscious subjects recognising that such an activity contributes to their own
liberation too, by overcoming forms of alienation between self and other that
seems to follow from object-oriented forms of consciousness.
332
PART 3/Ch7. Exposure, Transcendence, and the Community of Fate
ethos from these premises, fleshing out the essentially ethical logic of the
experience of love, and exploring the nature of this logic as a guide for
emancipatory praxis.
333
Chapter 8.
The Lived Character of Ethics
Introduction
We have seen that when it comes to the interactions between self and world,
both Heidegger and Hegel consider the theoretical attitude to lead to an
objectification of human experience and an alienation of self from world. This
leads them both to develop pre- and post-theoretical relations to reality.
Heidegger's pre-theoretical relation to reality entails human beings being enjoined
into resolute solicitous being-with others, while Hegel's pre- and post-theoretical
relation involves an overcoming of object-oriented forms of consciousness through
the achievement of self-conscious subjectivity – where the self recognises the
social conditions of its own individuality and acts accordingly. In the last chapter
we argued that the experience of love provides a demonstration of our exposure to
the existence of others, with phenomenological enquiry demonstrating that this is
so, and that fully ethical and emancipatory relations with others were relations that
proceeded from this knowledge rather than on the basis of some notion of
‘intersubjectivity’.
The subject of love has played a minor role in postwar philosophy, with
practical philosophy paying little attention to its concept and essence. There are
several reasons for this, but, as Honneth suggests, they ultimately 'derive from the
predominance of a concept of morality geared so strongly towards principles of
impartiality that personal relationships hardly seemed worthy of inquiry.' 1 He
further explains that in the postwar Anglo-Saxon world, practical philosophy did
not engage in any serious exploration of the experience of love largely as a
consequence of a 'narrow interpretation of Wittgenstein,' where focus lay on meta-
ethics and the logical status of moral statements; as the dominance of this approach
receded, 'the resurgent currents of utilitarianism and Kantianism then saw to it that
the subject remained in the margins of philosophical interest.'2 In the German-
speaking world, if we were to take the phenomenological tradition further beyond
Heidegger to Max Scheler, we would rediscover 'a work enormous current
importance in philosophy's treatment of the subject.'3 Yet Scheler's influence was
quickly overshadowed by that of Heidegger.
335
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
had failed to examine motives and the motivational structures of ethical life, and
thus dealt 'only with reasons, with values, with what justifies.'5 Stocker argued that
this exclusive concern with moral rationalism led to ethical theories ignoring the
fact that love, friendship, affection, fellow feeling and community are important
sources of moral action, and that by ignoring them modern ethical theories force
moral agents to live a bifurcated, schizophrenic life in order to achieve what is
good.6
With the possible exception of Andreas Wildt, who drew on Hegel's early
work to point out 'forms of moral awareness that could not be defined in legal or
contractual terms, thus setting them in opposition to the posture of impartial justice
favoured by Kant,' the vast majority of the subsequent treatment of love in
practical philosophy has remained trapped within a Kantian moral paradigm.7
Honneth's discussion of love in his essay Love and Morality is a case in point.8 We
have already seen how Honneth reads Hegel through a kaleidoscope of the Kantian
subject, reading into Hegel an individualism that obscures the ontological and
ethical significance of his account of love; this is reflected in his conclusion of his
survey of contemporary approaches to love and practical philosophy, where he
states that love 'does not lead us to abandon the idea of moral duty, but rather to
diversify it.'9
336
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
achieved, for Honneth love is simply an affective bind that we have to people close
to us, such as to our family – a relationship that must be appropriately balanced
with the respect that we owe to all.10 Pointing out that Honneth's ethic is 'very
"communitarian" in the bad sense of that word,' Blunden's critique of Honneth's
ethic of recognition illuminates the differences between Honneth's treatment of
love and the one developed here.11
Blunden reduces Honneth’s ethical claim to the claim that 'individuals are
entitled to expect appropriate love, respect and esteem from other people with
whom they interact.'12 A claim that is 'supplemented by the psychological claim
that people suffer injury to their moral development if they fail to receive the
affirmation that they expect from others by way of love, respect and esteem.'13 The
problem however is that, if 'solidarity' is given on the basis of the person's
contribution to the community, and 'rights' are what are owed to everyone as a
human being, then:
337
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
(such as family members) with the opposing moral demand that we treat everyone
as equals.15
Kant casts a long shadow over these discussions. Recognising that the
partiality of loving relations exist in tension with practical reason's principle of
universalisability, Kant distinguishes between two aspects of love in his
Groundwork and in the Metaphysics of Morals: 'practical' love and 'pathological'
love.16 Insisting that morality must override loving relations, practical love is love
that is grounded in and subordinate to reason; love recalcitrant to such
subordination is considered 'pathological.'17 Kant thus treats love essentially as
problem for morality, and in a way that asserts the sovereignty of reason over
desire, the priority of concept over being: both serving to affirm a foundational
commitment to the individual thought as ethical subject.
Hegel's famous critique of Kant's ethical theory proceeds from close readings
of both Kant's ethics of duty and the major alternative in moral theory at the time,
15. Axel Honneth, Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory, 178. See, for
example Michael A. Slote, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983). J.D. Velleman,
“Love as a Moral Emotion,” Ethics 109, no. 2 (1999): 338-74. Susan Wolf, “Morality and
Partiality,” Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 243-59.
16. It is worth noting that not all accounts of love see its universality and partiality as necessarily
contradictory. As Moseley explains: ‘The universalism of agape runs counter to the partialism of
Aristotle and poses a variety of ethical implications. Aquinas admits a partialism in love towards
those we are related while maintaining that we should be charitable to all, whereas others such as
Kierkegaard insist on impartiality. Recently, Hugh LaFallotte (1991) has noted that to love those
one is partial towards is not necessarily a negation of the impartiality principle, for impartialism
could admit loving those closer to one as an impartial principle, and, employing Aristotle's
conception of self-love, iterates that loving others requires an intimacy that can only be gained from
being partially intimate. Others would claim that the concept of universal love, of loving all equally,
is not only impracticable, but logically empty - Aristotle, for example, argues: "One cannot be a
friend to many people in the sense of having friendship of the perfect type with them, just as one
cannot be in love with many people at once (for love is a sort of excess of feeling, and it is the
nature of such only to be felt towards one person)"' Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. David
Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), VIII.6. Alexander Moseley, “’Philosophy of Love’
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,” http://www.iep.utm.edu/love/.
17. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A German-English Edition, trans.
Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge, 2011), 27,399,31. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of
Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 203,401.
338
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
the Scottish theory of moral sentiments. Hegel read Hume, Rousseau, Kant and
Smith carefully, and is concerned throughout his philosophy (not just in his early
works) to overcome the tension between love and reason. Eschewing the
foundational commitment to an ethical subject, Hegel sees a broader ontological
significance to the experience to love, and he reverses Kant's formulation of the
relation between love and morality. Explicitly responding to Kant's notion of a
pathological love in his Spirit essay, he writes:
On this view, love is not simply a special relationship between subjects who
love each other, but is an experience associated with a higher form of awareness of
the relation between self and world. Here, the self's independence is recognised as
only a relative independence; ultimately leading to the possibility of the sublation
of egoistic and object-oriented forms of consciousness into a form of other-
directedness, akin to what Gilligan identifies as 'care.' While for the Kantian love
must be grounded in the will if it not to be 'pathological,' for Hegel the converse is
true: the rational will must be grounded in love. And, as we shall see in our later
discussion of the Spirit essay, if not subordinate to this other-directedness, it is
18. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” in Early Theological Writings
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971), 247.
339
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
reason that becomes pathological. From a Hegelian perspective then, love is the
condition of morality.
The origins of normativity do not lie [...] either in the transient incitements of personal
feeling and desire [as some Humeans would have it], or in the severely anonymous
requirements of eternal reason [as some Kantians would have it]. They lie in the
contingent necessities of love. These move us, as feelings and desires do; but the
motivations that love engenders are not merely adventitious or (to use Kant's term)
heteronomous. Rather, like the universal laws of pure reason, they express something that
belongs to our most intimate and most fundamental nature. Unlike the necessities of
reason, however, those of love are not impersonal. They are constituted by and embedded
in structures of the will through which the specific identity of the individual is most
particularly defined.19
19. Harry G. Frankfurt, The Reasons of Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 48.
20. Ibid., 170. Harry G. Frankfurt, Taking Ourselves Seriously and Getting it Right (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2006).
340
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
fail to recognise the full ethical and ontological significance of Gilligan's
identification of the dual context of moral maturity. While Gilligan's criticism of
Kohlberg resembles that of Hegel's critique of Kant, Habermas and Linklater's
rationalist interpretations of Hegel essentially obscure the nature of Hegel's
position; similarly, their ontological commitment to a foundational ethical subject
means that they are unable to grasp the full implications of Gilligan's position. This
significance, we will argue, is that it reflects a fundamental discontinuity between
the logics of love and law: between ethics and politics.
The unique disposition of a particular case that calls for regulation, and the concrete
characteristics of the people involved, come into view only after problem of justification
have been resolved. It is only when it has to be established which of the prima facie valid
norms is the most appropriate to the given situation and the associated conflict that a
maximally complete description of all the relevant features of the particular context must
be given.21
341
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
yet, deploying his familiar strategy, Linklater simply surmises that we must be
more sensitive to difference.24
24. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 94-95.
25. Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World Politics, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011).
26. Ibid., 211-212,221.
27. Ibid., 222-31.
28. Ibid., 231.
342
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
discussion of the relation between compassion (i.e., 'love') and reason is largely
confined to footnotes, and he quickly returns to the importance of the rationality
and universality of moral principles for just relations between strangers.29 The
latter point is correct, but still misses the significance of Gilligan's argument about
the dual context of moral maturity. We hinted at this in Chapter 5 when discussing
Nancy's criticism of discourse ethics. This, we claimed, heralded a fundamental
discontinuity between ethics and politics, where ethics is understood as a relation
to the other, while politics is the domain of competing universal principles. This
discontinuity is also reflected in the work of Derrida, Nancy, and Levinas. While
the latter reformulates Heidegger's fundamental ontology, both Derrida and
Nancy's positions draw heavily on Hegel.30 We return to Hegel's discussion of this
discontinuity, his identification of an essential inequality between ethics and
politics, which will lead to our distinction between a cosmopolitan justice and a
cosmopolitan ethos in the next chapter.
We will recall that the claim was made in Chapter 7 that Hegel's central and
characteristic concepts first arise in his early works, in which the experience of
love plays a formative role, setting the trajectory of the future development of his
thought.31 This section sees us return to a discussion of Hegel's essay The Spirit of
Christianity and its Fate (1799) to illustrate the nature and significance of Hegel's
29. Ibid., 94-96.
30. Levinas reformulates Heidegger's Mitsein from being-with to being-in-front-of in order to
establish ethics as first philosophy. Derrida's ethical position develops most obviously in relation to
Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling in his Gift of Death, but before this he deals with Hegel's
identification of this discontinuity in The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate in his Glas, while we
saw that Nancy refers to Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit in our quote from The Inoperative
Community. Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority (Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press, 1999). Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1996). Jacques Derrida, Glas (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1990). Jean-
Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1991), 24.
31. For two strident defences of this reading of Hegel see Alice Ormiston, Love and Politics: Re-
Interpreting Hegel (New York: SUNY Press, 2004). Laura Werner, “The Restless Love of
Thinking: The Concept of Liebe in Hegel’s Philosophy” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Helsinki,
2007).
343
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
understanding of love and its relation to Kantian moral rationalism, before we draw
out what we consider to be the implications for an ethical and emancipatory
approach to world politics.
Although once prizing the Kantian ideal of autonomy in The Life of Jesus
(1795), by the time he wrote The Spirit of Christianity (1799) Hegel had distanced
himself from Kant's commitment to the notion that individual self-legislation under
the aegis of reason leads to freedom because he considered it to establish in the
subject a division between law and inclination, concluding that submitting to the
laws of one's own reason merely makes a man 'his own slave.'32
In his Sprit essay Hegel engages in a genealogy of moral reason with the aim
of establishing the theological origins of the rationalism that characterises Kant’s
approach to ethics. Hegel locates the emergence of Western rationality as a
response to the flood whereby humans might master a nature that they discovered
to be indifferent to themselves. 33 Through a discussion of Noah, Nimrod,
Deucalion and Pyrrah, and Abraham, Hegel sees in Judaism a vertical moral
32. 'For Kant, man remains a duality; reason tries to thwart desire, but the two are never
synthesised.' G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” 211n34.
33. Ibid., 182-87.
344
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
geometry in which the individual subject mediates his relation to the world through
a relation to a fictional transcendent object: God.
The implication of this mediated relation between self and world is illustrated
by the story of Abraham and Isaac, where Abraham's willingness to act on God's
command by sacrificing his son demonstrates a refusal of love in order to be free.
By being cold and indifferent to his son, Abraham's freedom consists in tearing
himself free from his family – from the most affective of loving relations. For
Hegel, this parable heralds a form of diremption between life and law that is
pervasive in Western thought, a diremption that is the source of discontinuity
between two different forms of social organisation: between family and state,
Sittlichkeit and Moralität.34
345
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
ways of relating to the object internalise a conception of the other – nature without
and nature within – as antagonist, making the assumption that the only possible
relationship between self and world is one of mastery, domination, and control.
Presumptive Dualism
We can illustrate the nature of the epistemological bind into which we are
cast with reference to the introduction to the Phenomenology, where Hegel is
trying to make us anxious about the idea of epistemology as first philosophy. Here,
in reference to theoretical reason, i.e., to the faculty of the understanding, the
problem is that from the moment that we become sceptics, as soon as we doubt the
validity of our knowledge of the external world, we find ourselves in trouble.
Hegel writes:
If cognition is the instrument for getting hold of absolute being, it is obvious that the use of
an instrument on a thing certainly does not let it be what it is for itself, but rather sets out
to reshape and alter it. If, on the other hand, cognition is not an instrument of our activity
but a more or less passive medium through which the light of truth reaches us, then again
we do not receive the truth as it is in itself, but only as it exists through and in this
medium. Either way we employ a means which immediately brings about the opposite of
its own end; or rather, what is really absurd is that we should make use of a means at all.35
35. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977),
§73.
346
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
dualism that casts us into a series of paradoxes. The first is that the idea of
knowledge as an instrument generates the very opposite of what it intends: if
knowledge is an instrument then it must alter the object, and by altering the object
it creates a categorial synthesis, thus leaves the object behind. The second is that if
we treat knowledge as a passive medium through which the world reaches us, then
we do not know the world as it is in itself, but only as it exists in and through this
medium; this generates a gap between the knower and what they hope to know.36
This is the logic applied to ethical reason in the Spirit essay. Here, in the
terms of practical reason, the problem is that from the instant that we perceive the
world to be hostile to us, that our relations to the world must be mediated by
reason, we establish ourselves a false independence that adversely affects our
relations to ourselves, to others, and to the natural world. From our position of
false independence we project outside of our shared lived experience with others
and submit ourselves to an ideal, which deforms internal relations of life because
moral law, the idea of the good, or God, does not exist.
36. This epistemological bind is pithily captured in the following rhyme:
'But for these and the rest, the greatest distress
trapped in a philosophers hell
For even the best, there's infinite regress
Which means you never can tell'
37. J.M. Bernstein, “Phenomenology of Spirit. Introduction,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology
of Spirit The New School. New York City. 27th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/08PhenomenologyIntroB.mp3.
347
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
Against the mediated relation between self and world implied by a
commitment to understanding human beings as subjects, Hegel contrasts living
relations with others. And these relations are modelled on the experience of love.
This discussion is crucial in the development of his notion of Sittlichkeit (ethical
life), which is understood in contrast to the formal, rule-governed approach of
Kantian Moralität (moral law); where properly ethical relations are ones
proceeding from the knowledge of love rather than from the authority of reason.
Essentially Hegel is heralding a fundamental discontinuity between ethics and
justice, the idea that there is an inequality between the logics of love and law: that
the two are separate orders.38
It is in this light that Hegel reads the teachings of Jesus. The central idea of
the Spirit essay is to demonstrate that there is a logic of ethical experience in early
Christianity that can be read as a guide to ethical conduct immanent to human
experience rather than transcendent to it. Against the objective models of positive
legislation of Judaism and Kantianism, where the self mediates its relation to the
world through an 'objective' law, by demonstrating that human need trumps
38. Derrida makes a similar argument in his Force of Law essay. Jacques Derrida, “Force of Law:
The Mystical Foundation of Authority,” in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed.
Rosenfeld and Carlson Cornell (London: Routledge, 1992).
348
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
religious command, Hegel claims that Jesus introduces something totally foreign:
the subjective.
Over against commands which required a bare service of the Lord, a direct slavery, an
obedience without joy, without pleasure or love, i.e., the commands in connection with the
service of God, Jesus set their precise opposite, a human urge and so a human need.39
Subverting Kant's account of the relation, for Hegel love is the feeling of
ethical life (Sittlichkeit) in its natural form. Whereas (moral) law is a kind of
practical reasoning that abstracts from context-specific particularity, involving the
deployment of reasons and arguments, in loving relations the law loses its form. In
other words, love is a living relation to reality that makes the (moral) law
superfluous. Hegel illustrates this difference with regard to the religious command
'Thou shalt not kill:'
The command "Thou shalt not kill" [Matthew v.21-22] is a maxim which is recognized as
valid for the will of every rational being and which can be valid as a principle of a
universal legislation. Against such a command Jesus sets the higher genius of
reconcilability (a modification of love) which not only does not act counter to this law but
makes it wholly superfluous; it has in itself a so much richer, more living, fullness that so
poor a thing as a law is nothing for it at all. In reconcilability the law loses its form, the
39. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” 206,209.
40. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, 243-244,449.
41. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” 230.
349
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
concept is displaced by life; but what reconcilability thereby loses in respect of the
universality which grips all particulars together in the concept is only a seeming loss and a
genuine infinite gain on account of the wealth of living relations with the individuals
(perhaps few) with whom it comes into connection. It excludes not a reality but only
thoughts and possibilities.42
For Hegel the essence of Christianity lies in this 'reconciliation,' where the
law 'loses its' form and 'the concept is displaced by life.' Reconciliation is not
achieved conceptually here, such as through the affirmation of a common
humanity, but is achieved through love, through action that makes the law
superfluous. The loving relation is congruous with both the law and the inclination:
it is their synthesis; one that express an attunement to our ethical immediacy,
dissolving the need for law.
To reiterate, Hegel is not denying the necessity of law, but is arguing that
love and law are mutually implicated, although they operate according to different
logics. However, in contrast to Kant, and also Habermas and Linklater, it is
ultimately love that is more binding than law, and it is the person’s participation in
the dynamic of ethical life that constitutes an ethical and emancipatory relationship
between self and world.43 By demonstrating that ethical life is lived independently
of moral laws, and that acting freely and ethically does not involve assuming the
perspective of an ethical subject but simply an attunement to practical experience,
Hegel 's critique of Kantian rationalism is supplemented by an immanent doctrine
of ethics.
For Hegel, what Jesus demonstrates practically is that our first question when
we see someone who is hungry should not be 'do they deserve food,' but to
recognise that they are hungry means to recognise that they need food, full stop:
the logic of ought has no role in ethical life. The notion of 'ought' is related to the
idea of moral law, and belongs to a mediated relation between self and world; to
42. Ibid., 215-16.
43. Ibid., 230.
350
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
act ethically what we need is not to obey the law, but to love thy neighbour. Ought
only enters into consideration in relations of authority: you ought to obey because
it is your duty, or because you will be punished if you do not.
Here relations between self and other are not external relations between
subjects bridged mechanically by notions of common interest or moral law, but
operate according to the logic of unity-in-difference, a logic that we discussed in
the previous chapter in relation to the idea of mutual exposure and co-dependent
arising, where the central idea is that my selfhood and freedom is essentially
related to the character of my relations with others.
Hegel's basic thought here is that we cannot harm others without ethically
harming ourselves; to act against some other person is not to break some
transcendent law, but to act against our own life. This sees him drawing a
distinction between punishment and what he calls 'fate,' which appears whenever
life is injured. The working of fate commences 'when the trespasser feels the
disruption of his own life [... and] The deficiency is recognised as a part of
himself.'44 While punishment is 'the effect of a transgressed law' that is enforced by
something alien, an external power that is opposed to the self, fate is experienced
as something internal to the person, taking the form of guilt or shame. Whereas
punishment presupposes a figure that inflicts the pain of punishment (and the fear
of punishment is fear of Him) in fate, the fear is not the fear of an alien being but
the fear of 'the power of life made hostile.'45 The appearance of 'fate' thus discloses
the fact that we are fundamentally connected to each other: a phenomenological
demonstration of the re-cognitive structure of self-consciousness.46
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid., 231.
46. Harris's commentary on 'fate,' community & forgiveness is worth reproducing here: 'Fate is the
understandable shape in which absolute Spirit finally emerges. Hegel speaks of "God appearing"
only when the community understands its own function of forgiveness. Until then, "God" (as a
subject-name) identifies only a necessary "transcendental illusion." Fate we must always reverence;
but rational beings do not worship the Big Bang. But when we arrive at the consciousness that "God
is Love," we are recognizing a divinity whose very being is constituted by our recognition. Nature
forgives nothing. There is no "spirit of forgiveness" anywhere except in human self-consciousness.
That is what God's necessary "Incarnation" conceptually signifies; and "nothing in fate is changed
by it" - any more than Fate could be changed by Zeus. H.S. Harris, Hegel’s Ladder, vol. 2: The
Odyssey of Spirit (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997), 540.
351
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
Deeper insight into the dynamic of ethical life, our connectedness and the
operation of fate, can be gained by applying the notion of love and fate to murder.
In this context, the significance of murder is not so much that it is a negation of
life; killing one life is not killing all life, and it does not sever my connection to
that other, at least not fully. Instead, this transgression effects the diremption of life
through a violent act of two-ing. In other words, by transforming life into an
enemy, the destruction of life in this transgression undermines the conditions of my
own life. In characteristically eloquent prose Hegel writes:
Only through a departure from that united life which is neither regulated by law nor at
variance with law, only through the killing of life, is something alien produced.
Destruction of life is not the nullification of life but its diremption, and the destruction
consists in its transformation into an enemy [i.e., the murderer thinks he has killed his
victim. But he has only turned life into an enemy, only produced a ghost to terrify him]. It
is immortal, and, if slain, it appears as it is terrifying ghost which vindicates every branch
of life and lets loose its Eumenides. The illusion of trespass, its belief that it destroys the
other's life and thinks itself enlarged thereby, is dissipated by the fact that the disembodied
spirit of the injured life comes on the scene against the trespass, just as Banquo who came
as a friend to Macbeth was not blotted out when he was murdered but immediately
thereafter took his seat, not as a guest at the feast but as an evil spirit. The trespasser
intended to have do with another's life, but he has only destroyed his own, for life is not
different from life, since life dwells in the single Godhead. In his arrogance he has
destroyed indeed, but only the friendliness of life; he has perverted life into an enemy. It is
the deed itself which has created a law whose domination now comes on the scene; this
law is the unification, in the concept, of the equality between the injured, apparently alien,
life and the trespasser's own forfeited life. It is now for the first time that the injured life
appears as a hostile power against the trespasser and maltreats him as he has maltreated the
other. Hence punishment as fate is the equal reaction of the trespasser's own deed, of a
power which he himself has armed, of an enemy made an enemy by himself.47
The disruption of my own life through the appearance of fate means that I
must recognise the prior transgression as my own, and acknowledge my own
answerability for it. By recognising my fate through guilt or shame, I face up to my
own responsibility for my transgression, and can then attempt to atone for my
transgression and reconcile with the other by seeking their forgiveness. There is no
external authority here: my transgression reveals that I am already situated within
an ethical community where I am bound together with others with whom I co-
participate within a community of fate: the trespass reveals the whole.
47. G.W.F. Hegel, “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate,” 229-30.
352
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
While the subjective, formal, freedom that I have by virtue of being an
individual ensures that I am able to deny this 'originary debt' to the other and cling
on to my own independence as a subject, or perhaps to suppose that the other
deserved whatever fortune became of him and to thereby eschew my responsibility
for his situation, this only establishes for myself a false independence. Causing
injury to another, and subsequently disavowing or ignoring my answerability to
them, considering my actions just or permissible, leaves me bound to my prior
subjectivity and constitutes an alienation from my own existence as a self-
actualising being. Similarly, hate is not a rejection of love but its inversion. Hating
someone, a person or even a group, does not deny my connection with them;
neither does it dissolve that community, it only perverts them. Hate is a tearing
apart, a terrible distortion of 'the between' that both perverts the hater and is
destructive of the self.
48. Ibid., 231.
353
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
Moralität and Sittlichkeit
Ethical life, experienced as love, both underwrites and transcends the law; it
may even be set against it. Such is the case with Antigone. Against the conscious
written law of the state, i.e., Creon's decree that, as a traitor of the state, Polynices'
body be left out in the open for the vultures, Hegel regards Antigone as the
personification of the unwritten ethical law that is society's unwritten foundation.49
In direct contrast to Habermas's moral cognitivism Hegel writes:
True ethical law is the unwritten, inerrant, unalterable divine law spoken of in the
Antigone. It is not anything that an individual can hope either to criticize or to justify, and
certainly not in terms of mere self-consistency.50
49. This ethical law corresponds with ethical life (Sittlichkeit) rather than moral law (Moralität).
50. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, 550n437.
51. H.S. Harris, Hegel’s Ladder, 168.
52. For an illuminating extended commentary on Hegel's Antigone see Kimberley Hutchings,
Hegel and Feminist Philosophy (Cambridge: Blackwell, 2003), 96. Also Kimberley Hutchings and
Tuija Pulkkinen, eds. Hegel’s Philosophy and Feminist Philosophy: Beyond Antigone?
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).
354
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
fact that Antigone and Creon can only act out their one-sided conviction in their
own right rather than recognise the rightness and mutual implication of the
opposing perspectives and achieve a reconciliation therefrom; the written law of
the state and Antigone's personification of the unwritten law of moral conviction
are thus tragically entwined because each can only act out one side of the synthetic
unity that would constitute truly ethical behaviour.
Demonstrating that love is not simply mere emotion, Hegel's point is that
ethical society needs the recognition of the mutual dependency of both
perspectives. He is not following the Humean or Smithean view that ethics are
based simply on the intuition, on feelings: his position is that it is the unity of
intuition and reason that is the ground of ethics. Ethical relations are not simply
individual preferences grounded in the intuition, they also have a conceptual
element: the 'thought of' human law. This 'thought of' law must be grounded in an
underlying ethical life, the extension of which is not correlative with the extension
of human law, a reconciliation or unification under the concept, because without
this underlying ethical life, the 'thought of' human law is simply an imposition on
those subject to it. This position, we shall see, has profound implications for an
ethical and emancipatory approach to world politics.
Although this ethical position does contain a relative aspect, it does not
subjectivise value. Ethics are not relative in the sense that anything goes, but
relative in the sense that ethical concepts are not universal, but are historically
grounded in the mores and practices that constitute ethical life. In the Philosophy
of Right (1820), Hegel's 'mature' work that builds on his earlier work by applying
his philosophical system to the actualisation of freedom in the world – to the
objective structures of right that represent the social conditions of human freedom,
institutions such as the family, civil society and the ethical state – Hegel formulates
the divergent logics of love and law through his distinction between Moralität and
Sittlichkeit.
355
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
Moralität and Sittlichkeit in Linklater's CIRT
Moralität is the approach to ethics which assumes that the solitary individual can use
autonomous reason to discover the normative foundations of a cosmopolitan society. It
abstracts individuals from concrete settings and credits them with innate powers for
apprehending universal moral truths. Sittlichkeit refers to the social institutions and norms
which precede the individual and lend shape to the subject's moral life.53
53. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 52.
54. Ibid., 55.
55. Ibid., 52.
56. Ibid.
57. Ibid.
356
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
mutually and inexorably implicated. As we have just seen, against the privilege
that Linklater ascribes to ethical reason, it is the mutual implication of ethical life
and ethical reason that constitutes Antigone's tragedy. While Creon's refusal to
bury Polynices is in accord with the 'thought of' human law (forbidding traitors a
proper burial), and overrides the Thebian custom (of burying the dead under
normal circumstances), the significance of this action is not just that it constitutes a
simple contravention of a local, particularist morality, but because it contravenes
an unwritten ethical law: it goes against what is right; what Douzinas refers to as
the law as dike (justice) as opposed to the law as reason and nomos.58
This ethical law, the 'unwritten, inerrant' law that is felt as love, and which
underwrites ethical life, is not the same as the 'thought of' moral law. Nor does it
simply consist of 'customs and conventions,' to be transcended by a rational
morality. Ethical society is dependent on the dialectical interaction of both.61
58. Costas Douzinas, “Law’s Birth and Antigone’s Death: On Ontological and Psychoanalytical
Ethics,” Cardozo Law Review 16, no. 3-4 (1995): 1325–62.
59. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, §437.
60. Ibid., 549-550n436.
61. While Antigone and Creon have different points of view on the matter of Polynices's burial, the
matter is not reducible to their contrasting perspectives: the facts that Antigone is Polynices's sister,
and Creon is the head of state are largely inconsequential. Rather, it revolves around the justice of
the Creon's decree. As Hegel explains 'Alteration of the point of view is not contradiction; for what
we are concerned with is not the point of view, but the object and the content, which ought not to be
self-contradictory.' Ibid., §437.
357
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
We saw in Part 1 that the basic theme uniting Men and Citizens,
Transformation and Linklater's later work on the harm principle is the normative
ideal of universal moral inclusion, where universality was conceived as the
universal responsibility to engage in dialogue. The problem, we claimed, was that
this defence of universalism against anti-foundationalism involved the projection
of an ethical subject, a strategy that conflates the ontological difference between
human beings and the being of human beings (conceived as ethical subjectivity).
Hence it should cause little surprise to learn that, while he affirms the social nature
of morality, he effectively treats ethical life as an anachronism that is subordinate
to the sovereignty of moral reason.
358
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
the previous chapter, the difference is that the Kantian form of transcendence
involves moral law rising above ethical life, while the Hegelian form involves the
mutual implication of ethical life and moral law, where moral law is immanent
within ethical life and manifests itself through the dialectical transformation of
ethical life, but cannot simply rise above it.64
359
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
morals had to be different to that presented by Kant, and he emphasised the role of
the sensuous, emotive side of human nature, and the cultivation of ethical
inclinations, in contrast to Kant's insistence that moral actions are ones that follow
from a dutiful respect for the moral law. What Schiller was attempting to show is
that, in a free human being, duty has to descend and become inclination, while
inclination has to ascend so that a natural inclination is developed for the content
of duty; in order that, acting out of inclination rather than rational respect for the
moral law, the free human being does what is right for the whole of mankind.
Although defending Kant against Schiller, Gerold Prauss argues that the
dispute highlights the fact that Kant overlooks a third source of motivation besides
inclination and duty; that is, love.69 As Rudolf Steiner puts it: '[i]f we look for the
roots of moral Intuitions in human nature, if we look for the actual impulse, the
ethical motivation in those moral Intuitions, we find love;' this love, he continues
'absorbs into itself the moral Intuitions, and we are moral human beings in so far as
we love our duty, in so far as duty has become something that arises out of the
human individuality itself as an immediate force.'70
In Hegel this all relates to the idea of conscientious activity. First arising in
his discussion of the activity of the conscience in the Phenomenology (§§632-671),
the conscience is understood as the finding of an appropriate response in a given
situation: 'it is in and through the activity of conscience that the knowledge of love
is actualised in the world,' the activity of the conscience represents 'the resurfacing
of the knowledge of love.'71
For that there is no other advice: you must try to despise them,
And then do with aversion what duty commands you.'
Cosmopolitans might read 'friends' here as pertaining to circle of moral concern beyond our
compatriots. Friedrich Schiller, Werke. Nationalausgabe, vol. 1-42 (Weimar: Böhlau, 1943), 357.
Quoted by Frederick C. Beiser, A Lament, Friedrich Schiller: Playwright, Poet, Philosopher,
Historian (Bern: Peter Lang, 2007), 237.; For a discussion see Herbert James Paton, The
Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1948), 47.; Henry E. Allison, Kant’s Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1990), 180-184,275n3. Frederick C. Beiser, A Lament.
69. Henry E. Allison, Kant’s Theory of Freedom, 275n3.; Gerold Prauss, Kant Über Freiheit Als
Autonomie (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1983), 240-77.
70. Rudolf Steiner, Fruits of Anthroposophy (London: Ruldolf Steiner Press, 1986), 59.
71. Alice Ormiston, Love and Politics: Re-Interpreting Hegel, 55-56.
360
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
By affirming the sovereignty of ethical reason over ethical life, Linklater not
only distorts Hegel's characteristic form of transcendence, where freedom is
associated with the activity of the conscience and the overcoming of any given
subjectivity, but in supposedly standing above the perspective of ethical
immediacy Linklater also denies himself a powerful evaluative tool with which to
engage in critical social theory. Per contra Linklater, rather than representing a
conservative or atavistic approach to ethics, Hegel's approach to ethical life, as
modelled on the experience of love, represents both a more primordial aspect of
our ethical experience, an aspect that Linklater's approach overlooks, and a
powerful tool for CIRT.76
72. Ibid., 71.
73. Ibid., 73.
74. Ibid., 78.
75. Ibid.
76. In a similar vein, Neuhouser argues that the concept of 'life' in Hegel's early philosophy can be
deployed as an evaluative tool to identify forms of social pathology. Frederik Neuhouser, “Hegel on
Life, Freedom, and Social Pathology” (Paper presented at the Philosophies of Right: Philosophical
Conceptions of Right from German Idealism to Critical Theory, New York, 2011).
361
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
In short, there is much more to the idea of ethical life than is reflected in
Linklater's treatment of Sittlichkeit; specifically the model of social relations
provided by the experience of love.77 While Linklater concurs with Hegel that the
standpoint of morality represents a higher form of freedom because it raises us
above the simple acceptance of norms and customs, and leads to the principle of
individuality that characterises modernity, Hegel quite rightly insists that this
perspective is itself inexorably entwined with ethical life, and that it is the
operation of ethical life that drives 'the moral point of view' forwards. While more
rationally based moral understandings and principles represent a higher form of
self-conscious freedom than do simple customs and norms, these moral principles
are themselves only developed and overcome through the operation of ethical life.
This does not entail rejecting moral rationalism, but recognising its pernicious
effects and limitations, and ultimately supplementing it.78
77. Indeed, it seems that our discussion of Linklater's treatment of the relation between Moralität
and Sittlichkeit affirms Walker's (brief) criticism of Transformation where he claims: 'in each and
every case Linklater's strategy is to take what he thinks is useful and then discard the rest. And what
is useful is always some sort of argument for a greater universalization, and what can be discarded
is the tattered residue of particularity.' R.B.J. Walker, “The Hierarchicalization of Political
Community,” Review of International Studies 25, no. 1 (1999), 152.
78. 'Although Hegel has quite often been taken to be rejecting Kantian, "individualistic" morality in
favour of something else – "social ethics," accepting one's community's norms, or some such view –
more recent work has argued that in fact he is best seen as extending Kant's "rationalist" morality
by critiquing it and supplementing it, but not rejecting it. This interpretation seems to me entirely
correct.' Terry Pinkard, “Virtues, Morality and Sittlichkeit: From Maxims to Practices,” 222.
362
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
Borrowing an argument of Heidegger's, it involves engaging in resolute solicitous
being-with, a form of conscientious activity that not only appropriates our freedom
as existential condition, but frees ourselves up for being-with others, and leads to
an entirely immanent form of transcendence: freedom as the crossing of love.
It is this prioritisation of our ethical immediacy that is the central point of the
distinction between Moralität and Sittlichkeit. Derrida makes similar point in
Glas.79 There he notes that the transition from Moralität to Sittlichkeit, from Part
Two to Part Three of the Philosophy of Right, is intended to reflect the transition
from Judaism to Christianity in the Spirit essay: from a religion based on command
and duty to a religion based on love and freedom.80 The idea of Sittlichkeit is thus
better understood – not as parochial ethical particularism, an anachronistic morality
of custom and conventions to be transcended by ethical reason – but as an attempt
to reflect an existential condition of ethical immediacy, a condition modelled on
the experience of love. The supplementary role given to moral reason over a
practical relation to reality is demonstrated in Hegel's discussion of the conscience
in the Phenomenology. Although superseded by chapters on religion and absolute
knowing, the activity of the conscience transcends the standpoint of reflective
rationality and represents the completion of the Phenomenology at the level of
personal experience, i.e., conscientious activity is the highest form of the activity
of individual human consciousness.
363
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
standing over sensuous being as something alien that commands it. Rather, through
conscientious activity, law and being are united and expressed through the
individual person. Here ethical action is not action that follows a rational
calculation (or even discussion) of our duties, but is conscientious action in a
contingent context that expresses something universal. If we see someone
drowning, we jump in and save them: we just act. This action is not mediated by
moral reason, reasons do not exist. This is ethical immediacy: moral reasons and
validations of that action come later. For instance, if asked why we jumped in to
save the person we might retrospectively justify our action in the form of a maxim
by saying that, if it were us drowning then we would want someone to save us; yet
we must recognise that this is a retroactive justification of an experience that tells
us something more fundamental about the structure of our life with others.
The problem is that as soon as we start to think in terms of rights and duties
associated with ethical subjectivity, as soon as we start to rely on our moral reason,
we are already in trouble. This frame of mind leads to an essential limitation on
what we think we owe to others, and we tend to mediate these relations with
reference to some overarching norm or rule, which we might dutifully observe.
However, arguments regarding duty have only a limited purchase: they only serve
to bolster or modify prior commitments.81 Philosophy is simply not that powerful,
81. To borrow Bernstein's metaphor, there is no use saying to the parent of a suicide bomber 'your
son ought not to blow up other people,' because once that primitive notion of empathy is gone, there
is little point arguing with them philosophically. J.M. Bernstein, “Early Theological Writings,”
364
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
pointing out logical mistakes or inconsistencies in the beliefs that people hold is
not going to make them change their position dramatically; philosophy only gives
non-sceptics and non-fanatics internal reasons to think that they are rationally
justified in holding the beliefs that they do: it is the scepticism or fanaticism that is
the barrier and, in ethical discourse, affirming the sovereignty of reason over love
is more likely to encourage that scepticism rather than eliminate it.
Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 13th September
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/04EarlyTheologicalWritingB.mp3.
82. This illustration is Giles Fraser's: Giles Fraser, “You’ve Got to Respect Sceptics,” The
Guardian Friday 29th June. (2012). For a discussion see Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason:
Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 451-96.
83. See Ben Blanchard, “Chinese Girl Dies in Hit-and-Run That Sparked Outrage,” Reuters,
http://www.reuters.com/article/2011/10/21/us-china-girl-idUSTRE79K0HM20111021 (accessed
12/03/2012.
365
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
parable of the Good Samaritan in which Jesus illustrates the injunction to love thy
neighbour. 84 Although the parable focusses on commending the Samaritan's
compassion, it can also be read as an indictment of both the priest and the Levite
who both cross the road in order to pass by the 'half dead man.' Read in this way,
both the parable and the Chinese episode function as a negative illustration of
Hegel's use of love as an image of human connectedness. In both cases, there was a
fundamental ethical responsibility to the other on the parts of the priest, the Levite,
and the Chinese public, and in both cases all failed in their responsibility.
Conclusions
366
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
claim was made in Chapter 6 that, despite being the most strident of Kant's critics,
Hegel's engagement with Kant is an essentially constructive critique with the aim
of developing his own Kantianism; accordingly our aim here has not been to reject
Kantian ethics, rather to demonstrate how Hegel completes it. Although Hegel's
criticism of Kantian ethics is certainly not new, Hegel's insights into the nature of
ethical life are often overlooked, and the tendency of twentieth century left-
Hegelian thought has been to read him as a philosopher of the concept, a reading
which obscures his most powerful insights.85 We have demonstrated this to be true
in the cases of both Habermas and Linklater with reference to their prioritisation of
Kantian Moralität.
The problem in both cases is that this simply asserts the sovereignty of the
ethical subject, leading to a dualism between self and world that we have sought to
demonstrate is profoundly misguided. In contrast, the position taken here is that, in
order to live up to the ethical and emancipatory ideals of CIRT, we need to eschew
this duality and follow the moves made in post-Kantian German idealism away
from the foundational commitment to the individual thought as ethical subject to a
conception of the human being as the being that has the potential for self-conscious
subjectivity.86 This not only entails a shift in our understanding of freedom, as
discussed in the previous chapter, but also in our understanding of the nature of
ethical relations.
Ethical relations, as they have been presented here, are not simply relations
of ethical subjects that proceed according to maxims that have been subjected to
the test of universalisability, whether that ratiocination is seen to be an individual
exercise (Kant) or a collective, communicative one (Habermas, Linklater). Rather,
they consist in the concrete interaction of conscientious self-conscious subjects
85. There are of course notable exceptions to this. Dean Moyar's recent Hegel's Conscience is a
good example. Dean Moyar, Hegel’s Conscience.
86. There are clearly similarities here with Linklater's account of emancipation as the historical
actualisation of the ethical subject. However, recalling our discussions from the previous chapter,
self-conscious subjectivity differs significantly from Linklater's treatment of this as a Kantian form
of subjectivity. Moreover, the problem is with Linklater's treatment of ethical subjectivity as a
foundational commitment. We will return to a discussion of our relation to Linklater in the
Conclusion.
367
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
proceeding from the knowledge of love. This is not to deny the need for ethical
reason or the postulation of moral laws. It does however insist that we recognise
that properly ethical relations must operate according to a different logic: a logic of
love, and that it is ultimately action that follows from the knowledge of love that
leads to a genuine reconciliation with the other, not the exercise of discursive
reason – as implied in Linklater's defence of universalism.
These examples might then lend further credence to Hegel's insistence on the
mutual dependency of moral law and ethical life. Without reiterated demands for
the recognition of human rights from those who have theirs violated, it would be
easier to decry universal human rights as Western impositions on non-Western
cultures. But these universal norms seem to be grounded in a nascent but
developing international ethical life; they are not impositions. We might then
venture to contend that rather than overextending our abstractive capabilities by
368
PART 3/Ch8. The Lived Character of Ethics
projecting ethical subjectivity on others in order that we may reach a consensus
regarding shared principles of coexistence, that Hegel's argument for the mutual
dependency of ethical life and ethical law can lend support to the argument that we
must also be concerned with cultivating a more cosmopolitan form of international
ethical life; indeed that this might need to come first. We shall defend such an
argument in the Conclusion.
369
Conclusions.
Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
We saw in the Introduction that several writers have suggested that, given
increasing global interdependence, we sit at the twilight of the Westphalian system,
confronting a material actuality that is drawing us into a struggle to define the
character of globalisation: a struggle between the development of a more
democratic cosmopolis that could be characterised by greater collective human
responsibility, where sovereignty might be subordinated to global interdependence,
or one where we remain increasingly ensnared in the naked pursuit of power and
wealth.1 We learnt, however, that the principle of state sovereignty has had an
enormous and lasting effect, not only on the objective structuring of human
political and social relations, but also on our political imagination; both of which
have conspired to produce a vision of politics that would be contained within the
state.2
1. Fred R. Dallmayr, Small Wonder: Global Power and Its Discontents (Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2005), 55. Barry K. Gills, “Introduction,” in The Global Politics of Globalization:
“Empire” Vs “Cosmopolis”, ed. Barry K. Gills (London: Routledge, 2007).
2. R.B.J. Walker, Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 63.
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
thought and practice, standing as further obstacles to the initiation of more
universalistic forms of ontological inquiry in world politics is the fact that attempts
to bring ontological reflection into international theory have largely been facile,
concerned only with 'things that exist' in international relations (as opposed to the
being of that entity which encounters such entities as 'objects'); furthermore, the
overwhelming trajectory of thought since the eighteenth century has been geared
towards recognising the particularity of philosophical (ontological and
epistemological) interests.
These claims were illustrated in Chapter 1: the first with reference to recent
meta-theoretical debates in international theory, and the second with relation to
two influential 'normative' approaches to international theory, those of Rawls and
Frost. Both Rawls and Frost assert the particularity of their claims, and attempt to
evade controversial philosophical questions by taking dominant practices and
institutions associated with the sovereign state as their ethical foundations. Their
attempts at evasion, however, were ultimately unsuccessful, since we are led to ask
whether we can consider such ethical foundations to have an 'objective' existence,
what it means to take such foundations as objective, and what it tells us about the
being of that entity that encounters such entities as 'objects.'
Left-Hegelian Thought
It was in this context that we introduced Hegel, for whom freedom serves as
the normative standard by which institutions and practices such as the sovereign
state are to be judged. According to this view, the 'objectivity' of institutions and
practices remains conditional upon the relation between these practices and the
being that encounters them as 'objects.' Put differently, the 'objectivity' of
institutions such as the state is conditional upon the extent to which they contribute
to the self-actualisation of the human being as a free being. Our contention was
that this foundational Hegelian commitment to human freedom, an ontological
commitment to the human being as a free being, might represent a more
371
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
universalistic ontological foundation for contemporary (global) ethics and politics,
applying to human beings qua human beings rather than to human beings qua
political subjects of dominant institutions such as the state.
It was for this reason that we identified with the left-Hegelian tradition of
thought. Motivated by an ontological commitment to the human being as a free
being, left-Hegelians, from Marx all the way down to contemporary critical
theorists and critical international theorists, have engaged in social inquiry with the
aim of foregrounding the possibilities for emancipatory change of the status quo.
After a discussion of the relation between critical theories and critical international
theories, where we outlined the two main paths of enquiry (historical/sociological
and normative/philosophical) into CIRT since the early 1980s, we defended the
view that the relevance of critical international theory is likely to grow and the
claim that Andrew Linklater's thought represents the most powerful, persuasive,
and promising version of CIRT.
3. As Neufeld explains 'International meta-theory [...] seeks an answer to the question: "what
constitutes good theory with regard to world politics?"' Mark A. Neufeld, The Restructuring of
International Relations Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 2.
372
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
By not treating dominant institutions as 'objective' ethical foundations, but
adopting a broad, philosophically, historically, and sociologically informed
vantage on these institutions instead, Linklater represents a marked improvement
on both Rawls and Frost. Nonetheless, we suggested that he might fall foul of the
same mistake made by Rawls, Frost, and the critical realists: that is, to rely on a
shallow ontology of 'things' as his ontological foundation, as opposed to a fuller
ontology of the human being as a free being.
373
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
and to human beings as a whole, and is dualist because it rests on a foundational
split between subject and object.
Part 1 thus made the case that more universalistic forms of ontological
inquiry were required for contemporary (global) politics and ethics, and established
that the central weakness of Linklater's critical approach to international theory lay
in his foundational (ontological and epistemological) commitments to subjectivity
and objectivity. These commitments, we suggested, indicated both a limited
philosophical ontology of the human being, and a shallow conception of human
4. It is worth noting that moral recognition is not the same as moral concern. Whereas moral
recognition is extended to those who can, and/or are willing, to engage in dialogue, there is no basis
whatsoever to question the universality of moral concern in Linklater's account.
374
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
freedom. This led us to the conclusion that, although CIRT professes a high degree
of reflexivity regarding the relation between subject and object, its focus lies on the
role that theorising plays in the recreation of social reality and the emancipatory
purposes of theory, rather than with the implications of any underlying
commitments to ethical subjectivity, or claims to know any mind-independent
objects, for our modes of being in the world.
Part 2
The central aims of Part 2 were to deepen the ontological foundations (in the
fuller sense of the term) of CIRT, and to begin our task of developing a richer
account of human freedom upon which an alternative emancipatory
cosmopolitanism might be based. Our claim was that, by eschewing a foundational
commitment to subjectivity and focussing instead on an existential analytic of
human existence, Heidegger's fundamental ontology could help us develop a more
universalistic ontological foundation for contemporary (global) politics and ethics.
In contrast to Rawls, Frost and Linklater, whose foundational ethical commitments
to 'objects' such as the state or the ethical subject led to normative claims that
applied only to human beings qua subjects of dominant political institutions, or
qua ethical subjects, Heidegger's existential analytic of human existence provides
375
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
us with a more universalistic ontological foundation, applying to human beings
qua human beings.
376
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
whole, ethics concerns an open, receptive relation to the other as other.
Consequently, the problem with foundationalist approaches such as Linklater's is
that, by treating ethical subjectivity as a foundational ethical commitment, a
(subjective) interpretation of the being of human beings that is projected as a
general ontology of human being, they effectively present their politics as an
ethics, raising it above political contestation. For this reason we resounded calls
from the likes of Nancy and Derrida for a 'politics of singularity' to displace the
'politics of subjectivity' that we argued characterised Linklater's emancipatory
cosmopolitanism.
Part 3
377
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
mind-independent real by a mature personality cognisant of the limitations of
reflective rationality. Misrecognising the nature of self-conscious subjectivity as a
Kantian form of subjectivity, we argued, leads to deleterious implications for our
mode of being in the world, contributing to diremption, reification and de-
reification. These implications are consequent of a conception of the self as
foundational subject that stands in a transcendent and assimilatory relation to the
entities of its experience, entities that include other human beings.
378
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
cooperative conditions of our own (subjective) freedom and self-hood that
augments Heidegger's account of resolute solicitous being-with.
Since the exercise of moral reason operates according to the logic of law,
requiring the subjection to a common authority that is absent in world politics, our
contention was that there is a fundamental problem with the deployment of
Moralität at the cosmopolitical level. While the underlying assumption of
Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism is that a shared commitment to ethical
subjectivity can provide such an authority, we have questioned the ethical and
emancipatory credentials of such a position. Having contended that ethical life
both underwrites and transcends the law, and that the ethical logic of love operates
in the absence of authority, we concluded by arguing that an ethical and
emancipatory approach to contemporary (global) politics and ethics must be based
upon the cultivation and extension of ethical life at a cosmopolitical level: the
development of a cosmopolitan ethos of love.
379
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
While this is to concur with the conclusion to Men and Citizens that
progressive change in world politics involves the development of a nascent
international ethical life and a more rational form of international political life, it
does take issue with Linklater's more recent claim in The Problem of Harm, in
which he states that what he calls 'moral emotions' 'might be more useful in
shaping ethical ideas rather than in trying to understand how radical change may
occur at a global level.'6 Our complaint here is that Linklater underestimates the
full ethical and emancipatory significance of ethical praxis: circumscribed by his
foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, he is unable to incorporate the
other two aspects of human freedom we have been discussing into his
emancipatory cosmopolitanism. With a view to clarifying the nature of our own
contribution, and shedding light on the nature of the shortcomings of Linklater's,
we can draw a distinction between cosmopolitan justice and a cosmopolitan ethos.
6. Andrew Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd ed.
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990), 195. Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World
Politics, vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 231.
380
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
cosmopolitanism is one primarily motivated by the ideal of justice.7 While this
remains an important aspect of an emancipatory cosmopolitanism, Linklater's
foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity undermines the significance of an
emancipatory cosmopolitan ethos.8 This leads to a neglect of the importance of
praxis (the deficit of moral universalism), an overemphasis on the significance of
moral rationality, and a reductive emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
Although both love and law are required for ethical society, we argued in
Chapter 8 that a logic of love is more appropriate in the absence of a common
authority. While we can try to foist a common authority onto others, ultimately this
can only lead to the establishment of the conditions of cooperation, preventing
7. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-
Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), 96.
8. We will clarify our relation to Linklater's emancipatory cosmopolitanism shortly.
9. Paul Ricoeur, “Love and Justice,” in Paul Ricoeur: The Hermeneutics of Action (Thousand Oaks:
Sage, 1996).
10. Ibid., 23-37.
11. Ibid., 31.
12. Norman Wirzba and Bruce Ellis Benson, Transforming Philosophy and Religion: Love’s
Wisdom (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2008), 5.
381
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
communities from disintegrating, rather than developing them. Although an
emancipatory cosmopolitanism needs both, given that a key aim of
cosmopolitanism is to overcome the duality of 'the domestic' and 'the global,' to
create more inclusive forms of communities and foster more universalistic forms of
common identification, love, compassion, and emancipatory praxis must come
first.
The objections that we have raised to Linklater's CIRT, especially our claim
that it rests on a foundational commitment to ethical subjectivity, are important to
our argument and our own emancipatory cosmopolitanism has been developed in
response to these perceived shortcomings. However, our claims have been made
through a meta-theoretical analysis of his work and there are limitations to this
form of argument.
382
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
13. For an explanation of differences between the two, and the weaknesses of Linklater's
deployment of Habermas see Martin Weber, “Engaging Globalization: Critical Theory and Global
Political Change,” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 27, no. 3 (2002): 301-25.
14. See the section on 'Dialogue and Discourse' in Transformation, especially his discussion of the
feminist critique of discourse ethics, and his search for common ground between Lyotard and
Habermas. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 87-100,93-95,96-98.
383
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
as the philosophical defence of his subsequent praxeological and sociological
analyses; any weaknesses in the philosophical/normative defence of his CIRT will
therefore be carried over. Nonetheless, given Linklater's insistence on the 'tripartite
structure' of any critical theory, save for the praxeological/sociological aspects of
our argument that are outlined below, our attempt to develop an emancipatory
cosmopolitanism on more convincing meta-theoretical foundations remains
incomplete according to Linklater's standards. This is an area for further work.
Our engagement with Linklater has obviously been a critical one; our
concern to outline the central weaknesses and shortcomings of his emancipatory
cosmopolitanism and develop our own has involved using his work as a critical
foil. While we stick by our criticisms, and insist that our own departs from his in
significant ways, our method of argumentation might ultimately be misleading, and
perhaps even at times, a little unfair; we can afford to be more conciliatory in
concluding our argument.
384
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
critical project. ‘Despite criticising Kant on nearly every page of his writings,
Hegel's engagement with Kant is not a rejection of Kantianism, but part of the
development of his own Kantianism.'15
385
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
non-dualist approach to knowledge, according to which our interpretation of the
being of human beings is a mind-dependent construction. From this point of view,
the problem with foundationalist approaches to ethics and politics is that their
universalism rests upon a conflation of what Heidegger identifies as the ontological
difference between the mind-independent existence of entities and our mind-
dependent interpretations of their being (as ethical subjects, for instance). By
treating a commitment to ethical subjectivity as a foundational commitment,
foundationalist approaches to politics and ethics misrepresent their (subjective)
interpretation of the being of human beings as objective, treating the ethical subject
(or anther interpretation of the being of human beings) as if it had a mind-
independent existence.
386
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
'dominated' themselves rather than civilising processes that take place 'above
them.'17 Nonetheless, following Odysseos's and Nancy's Heideggerian arguments,
we departed from Brincat's and Honneth's reliance on relations of 'intersubjectivity'
because this is unable to provide an adequate account of the relational nature of
individuality: the fact that relationality is antecedent to subjectivity, or, that
existence is coexistence.
17. Shannon Brincat, “Towards an Emancipatory Cosmopolitanism: Reconstructing the Concept of
Emancipation in Critical International Relations Theory” (Ph.D Thesis, University of Queensland,
2011), 312,314-315.
387
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
subjects most certainly does lead to the achievement of higher levels of self-
determination; ethical subjectivity helps bring the free being into being.
Similarly with Hegel, in Chapter 7 we saw that both master and slave enter
the struggle for recognition with the desire for absolute independence; it is their
desire for freedom from all conditionality, their desire for subjectivity, that draws
them into the struggle in the first place. The individuals that face each other make
claims of freedom on one another, and resolve to treat each other 'as if they were'
ethical subjects to avoid the ensuing struggle between life and death. Importantly
though, this mutual recognition between 'subjects' is simply a way of mediating the
fact that they are fundamentally dependent on each other for their freedom, and
hence their subjective freedom is only ever a relative independence.
18. In a metaphysics lecture Kant is quoted as saying: 'Freedom is practically necessary – man must
therefore act according to an idea of freedom, otherwise he cannot act. That does not, however,
prove freedom in the theoretical sense.' Henry E. Allison, Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant’s
Theoretical and Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 133-34.
388
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
foundational ethical commitments be subjected to further evaluation before we
accept their normative claims as binding, we are arguing that Linklater's normative
claims must be conditional upon the extent to which ethical subjectivity contributes
to human freedom; to be judged according to a more comprehensive account of
this normative ideal, such as ours.
389
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
our experience (Heidegger, Hegel, Scheler, Lem); by establishing the self as
transcendent, knowing, and assimilatory in its relations to the entities that it
experiences, it adversely affects the nature of the relation between self and world
(the problem with Kant and Fichte; Frye, Buber); it precludes the possibility of a
genuine encounter with the other (Nancy); and it alienates us from the depth
phenomena of our existence - our experiences of ourselves as self-actualising
beings, of our positive freedom gained through the transcendence of any given
subjectivity (the crossing of love), and from our experiences of authentic
community - communities in which we are not subjects relating to other subjects.
For all these reasons a foundational commitment to the ethical subject is
profoundly misguided, epistemologically, ontologically, and ethically.
390
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
identified with the left-Hegelian tradition of thought, our original contribution to
critical international theory has been to argue that it must be predicated, not on any
foundational commitments to subjectivity or objectivity, but on a fuller ontological
foundation: on an ontology of being, and of human being in particular. After
highlighting the essential weaknesses and contradictions latent within the most
compelling advocate of this approach to international theory, our move has been to
establish a 'critical' approach to international theory on a more persuasive and
universalistic meta-theoretical foundation. Our hope is that this represents a
contribution to a more adequate ethical and emancipatory approach to
contemporary (global) politics and ethics.
Our contention was that this epistemological aspect of our argument can help
us move beyond the foundationalist/anti-foundationalist schism in normative
theory. In contrast to the foundationalist approach, we recognise that our
interpretation of the being of beings is a mind-dependent interpretation of a reality
that we wish to construct, and thus does not have a mind-independent existence;
consequently, that an ethical and emancipatory politics cannot be predicated on an
interpretation of the being of human beings that is projected as a universal
ontology of human being. In contrast to the anti-foundationalist approach however,
we realise that we can give better or worse accounts of the being of human beings,
391
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
accounts that are to be evaluated according to the normative ideal of more ethical
and emancipatory relations between human beings.
Since every human being that we encounter is first and foremost an entity
that has a mind-independent existence that we must presume exceeds our
understanding or interpretation of them, we have argued that relations to others are
best conceived as relations to singularities, relations that do not reduce the other to
simply a particular case of the human species, but relations that aspire to treat them
as singular irreplaceable beings. Building on this premise, we have also sought to
contribute other non-subjectivist accounts of the being of human beings. These
accounts are not mutually exclusive: they all capture aspects of the being of human
beings. Moreover, while they do not deny our ability to 'act as if' we were subjects,
they do amount to a recognition that such an activity is essentially a fugitive way
of understanding the self.
392
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
forms of consciousness, which is characterised by an open, receptive attunement to
the existence of others, and to the disclosure of the mind-independent real.
Our argument that our interpretations of the being of human beings are mind-
dependent constructions means that an ethical and emancipatory politics cannot be
based upon some universal ground, a shared subjectivity, but must be premised
instead on a universal relation: an affective and receptive relation to the mind-
independent real where 'the other' can appear to us in their full singularity. Having
argued that freedom is not a property that drives our actions, but is appropriated in
praxis with others, and that what it means to be a free human being is to engage in
resolute solicitous being-with others, we concluded that an ethical and
emancipatory politics does not simply amount to the establishment of the political
conditions for the exercise of subjectivity, but must go beyond this.
Indeed, our fuller account of human freedom and the being of human beings
allow us to go beyond Linklater's praxeological arguments, which are seemingly
confined to the obligations of states to engage in different modes international
society to promote higher levels of universality and difference, or to project the
achievements of national citizenship out onto the sphere of international
19
relations. While not opposing Linklater's suggestions, our emancipatory
cosmopolitanism calls for a deeper and more demanding approach to an ethical and
emancipatory approach to contemporary (global) politics and ethics. Given the
material transformations of world politics outlined in the Introduction, it is
important that we make this move.
Our praxeological arguments are not just aimed at states and their agents, but
should also be received as a galvanising call to human beings qua human beings to
fully appropriate our own freedom by acting in ethical and emancipatory ways
towards others that we encounter. We might then return to our discussion of Bob
Francis and the Commonwealth minister's constituents from the Introduction and
ask again: what does it tell us about the being of those beings that encounter
19. Andrew Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community, 181,211-212.
393
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
refugees as others to be excluded? Does their prerogative as political subjects (as
citizens of the Australian state) to exclude others amount to an exercise of their
freedom as human beings? Does an ethical relation simply consist in their state's
non-contravention of cosmopolitan norms? In light of our previous discussions, the
answer to both is clearly a resounding 'no.'
One of the problems highlighted with Wight's ontological argument about the
relation between structure and agency is that, although he shows that ontology
matters, it is not clear how social practice is affected by this realisation, both
analytically and normatively.20 We should avoid such a mistake. Moreover, our
fuller account of human freedom allows us to look beyond Habermas's and
Linklater's deployment of the normative ideal of universal communication as an
evaluative tool for critical social theory and a guide for ethical and emancipatory
praxis.
Based upon our argument for the vivification of an international ethical life,
we will now discuss three key implications of our argument. These allow us to
adopt critical stances on cosmopolitan norms, institutions, and identities, and they
relate to love as a guide for praxis, love as an evaluative tool for critical social
theory, and love as a way of cultivating a common human identity.
It is worth noting at the outset that we are not arguing against Linklater in
what follows; Linklater's rationalist emancipatory cosmopolitanism and ours are
not mutually exclusive. Indeed, unsurprisingly, there is much overlap with
Linklater's concerns. However, Linklater's foundational commitments deny him
powerful philosophical and motivational resources for an ethical and emancipatory
cosmopolitanism, and our emancipatory cosmopolitanism can inform international
practice in ways that Linklater's cannot. In contrast to Linklater's rationalism, our
20. Corneliu Bjola, “Agents, Structures, and International Relations: Politics as Ontology By Colin
Wight,” International Studies Review 9(2), no. 2 (2008): 316-18.
394
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
applications of our argument all proceed from an affirmation of our ethical
immediacy, from the essentially lived character of ethics, and from a relation to the
other as singularity rather than subject.
21. See for instance Žižek's article on the purpose and meaning of the E.U. as an application of this
logic. He writes: 'Christ's "scandalous" words from Luke point in the direction of a universality
which ignores every social hierarchy: "If anyone comes to me and does not hate his father and his
mother, his wife and children, his brothers and sisters – yes even his own life – he cannot be my
disciple" (14:26). Family relations stand here for any particular ethnic or hierarchic social link that
determines our place in the global order of things. The "hatred" enjoined by Christ is therefore not
the opposite of Christian love, but its direct expression: it is love itself that enjoins us to
"disconnect" from our organic community into which we were born, or, as St Paul put it, for a
Christian, there are neither men nor women, neither Jews nor Greeks. No wonder that, for those
fully identified with a particular way of life, the appearance of Christ was perceived as ridiculous or
traumatic.' Slavoj Žižek, “I Have a Dream,” The Guardian 4th February (2011).
22. A recent anti-war initiative, 'Israel Loves Iran,' launched by Tel Aviv resident Ronny Edry and
his wife Michal Tamirm is a heartening example of such a venture. See www.israelovesiran.com;
Elizabeth Flock, “‘Israel Loves Iran’ Anti-War Initiative Takes Off,” The Washington Post. 19th
March 2012, http://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/blogpost/post/israel-loves-iran-anti-war-
initiative-takes-off/2012/03/19/gIQA1qWXNS_blog.html (accessed 20th June 2012). Ruth
Margalit, “Israel Loves Iran (on Facebook),” The New Yorker. March 23rd, 2012
http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/culture/2012/03/israel-loves-iran-on-facebook.html
(accessed 20th June 2012).
Indeed, given that Muhammad was a descendant of Ishmael, himself a son of Abraham (and half
brother of Isaac), Israel and Iran may be seen as branches from the same trunk; relations between
them might then prove to be an interesting example of Hegel's argument for the reconciliation in
love of differentiated spheres of life that have split from an underlying unity. See (Genesis 12:4-7;
13:12-18; 15:1-21; 17:1-22; 21:1-14; 25:19-26; 26:1-6; 35:9-12); (Sura 19:54; Sura 37:83-109 cf.
Genesis 22:1-19)
395
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
It also encourages us to actively participate in ethical life (domestic and
global) with the aim of ameliorating injustices, which might involve the
vindication of acts of conscience. As a recent article on the activities of the hacker
collective Anonymous succinctly states, 'in more naïve times, one might naturally
prefer a law-bound state deciding which power abuses should be reined in and
which information exposed. But these are no longer naïve times.'23 In a decade that
saw the normalisation of policies of lawless detention, torture, extraordinary
rendition, targeted assassinations, along with the instigation of wars of
questionable legitimacy or legality, and a persistent refusal to bring those now or
formerly in power, in both public and private sectors, to account for their
transgressions, and political systems that increasingly favour the rich and powerful,
it is unsurprising that there is growing public mistrust of authority and increasing
suspicion that those with formal authority cannot be trusted to decide what wrongs
should be righted, what social ills should be addressed, what information should be
shared, or what actions are in the best interests of either of their own constituents
or those of a broader humanity.24
23. Yochai Benkler, “Hacks of Valour: Why Anonymous is Not a Threat to National Security,”
Foreign Affairs, 4th April 2012 http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/137382/yochai-
benkler/hacks-of-valor. (accessed April 4, 2012).
24. Several of these examples are Benklers, several my own. Ibid.
25. See Moshahida Sultana Ritu, “Ethnic Cleansing in Myanmar,” New York Times, 12th July 2012
http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/13/opinion/ethnic-cleansing-of-myanmars-rohingyas.html
396
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
years (and perhaps centuries), have faced torture, neglect and repression since
Burma's independence from Britain in 1948. They are denied even the possibility
of citizenship by the country's constitution. Following recent unrest in Arakan
state, the Burmese are now trying to push them out of the country all together.
Rohingya people have been driven off their land, raped, beaten and starved to
death, and forced to flee to Bangladesh where they have simply been turned back
to Burma – the Burmese President Thein Sein even recently submitted a proposal
to the UN to have approximately all 800,000 Rohingya resettled in a third
country.26
(accessed 12th July 2012, 2012). and Benedict Rogers, “Is Burma Ready to Embrace Diversity?,”
Democratic Voice of Burma. 7th August, 2012 (accessed 12/08/2012).
26. Human Rights Watch, “The Government Could Have Stopped This,” Human Rights Watch. 1st
August (2012).
397
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
Love as Evaluative Tool27
Clearly actions do not occur outside of a social and historical context and
human freedom operates, at least partially, through social institutions and practices.
For this reason these institutions and practices should be subject to our own
standards of ethics and freedom; those that block or undermine the conditions of
our own freedom, or hamper fully ethical relations with others, are not fully
rational and should be subject to reform. This normative standard represents the
second practical application of our commitment to love as a cosmopolitan ethos:
love as a basis of critique.
One obvious target for such criticism would be the exclusivity of the
nation-state, since it relies on the exclusion of non-citizens in order to safeguard
the protections that it can provide its own subjects, often forcibly and violently.
Yet criticism would also be extended to other material and ideational structures
that foster divisions between people, alienate self from other, and stand as
obstacles to fully free and ethical relations between people. As well as the state,
poverty and extreme inequality are examples of the latter, while exclusive religions
or political ideologies that suppose self-regarding traditional communities and their
institutional expressions to be natural and eternal (structural realism, for instance)
or those which treat particularist identities as singular, exclusive and superordinate
27. Frederick Neuhouser makes a related argument for using Hegel's characteristic understanding of
freedom, which Neuhouser refers to as 'social freedom' as an evaluative tool for critical social
theory. See Frederik Neuhouser, Foundations of Hegel’s Social Theory: Actualizing Freedom
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000); Frederik Neuhouser, “Hegel on Life, Freedom,
and Social Pathology” (Paper presented at the Philosophies of Right: Philosophical Conceptions of
Right from German Idealism to Critical Theory, New York, 2011).
398
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
to the extension of empathy and solidarity across cultural boundaries, can also be
subject to critique.
When another person commits an act of hate or violence, the questions implied in
solidarity are how such acts are possible and how have I participated in creating a world
wherein such acts are possible. The existence of hate necessarily implies that I have not
loved enough.28
The central idea is that social space is always constituted ethically and
normatively, it is a space in which human beings are formed or deformed, freed or
oppressed, through the structures in which we interact with others. Within this
space we cannot ethically harm another without ethically harming ourselves, and
others cannot be harmed without ourselves bearing co-responsibility for that
harm.29
In light of this, material and ideational practices that disavow this radical
co-responsibility and foster feelings of indifference towards others, or discourage
us from feeling obliged to those beyond our immediate circle of concern, confining
28. Max Scheler. Gesammelte Werke. Edited by Maria Scheler and Manfred S. Frings., Bonn:
Bouvier Verlag, 1986., II,526. Zachary Davis and Anthony Steinbock, Max Scheler, Winter 2011
ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scheler/, 2011).
29. J.M. Bernstein, “Early Theological Writings,” Lectures on Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit
The New School. New York City. 13th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/03EarlyTheologicalWritingA.mp3.
399
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
our attentive care only to our local groups – towards compatriots or towards fellow
believers – are liable to censure. As are more individualistic social ideologies such
as libertarian ideas of absolute individual responsibility, extending even to those
cosmopolitanisms predicated on the idea of the individual as subject, where the
subject has to be moved into action in order to comply with universal duties or
obligations that have been theoretically derived.
No Stale Fraternity
30. Richard Beardsworth, “A Note to a Political Understanding of Love in Our Global Age,”
Contretemps (2006), 8.
400
CONCLUSIONS: Love, Ethics, and Emancipation
It should also be clear that this is not a pacifying and conciliatory vision of
human relations. Love does not lead to the preaching of a stale fraternity, nor does
it ignore the existence of relations of power and exploitation: rather, it demands
that 'the injustice and cowardice of power must be denounced and, in their turn,
negated.'31 Loving is risky, it involves linking ourselves to the interests of another,
'exposing oneself to another's vicissitudes,' and it manifests itself as struggle.32 Yet
it is love that constitutes perhaps the deepest phenomena of our existences, and we
have argued that it represents the highest appropriation of our freedom. This makes
it an integral, yet hitherto neglected, part of any emancipatory politics - a crucial
and central aspect of an emancipatory cosmopolitanism.
31. Jean-Luc Nancy, Hegel: The Restlessness of the Negative (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 2002), 62.
32. Harry G. Frankfurt, “Taking Ourselves Seriously and Getting it Right” (Paper presented at the
Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Stanford University, 2004), 195.
401
Bibliography
Aboulafia, Mitchell. Transcendence: On Self-Determination and
Cosmopolitanism., Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2010.
Adorno, Theodor. Negative Dialectics., London: Routledge, 1990.
———. Hegel: Three Studies., Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1993.
Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. Dialectic of Enlightenment., London:
Verso, 1986.
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life., Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1998.
———. The Open: Man and Animal., Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004.
———. State of Exception., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Agamben, Giorgio, Alain Badiou, Daniel Bensaid, Wendy Brown, Jean-Luc
Nancy, Jacques Ranciere, Kristin Ross, and Slavoj Žižek. Democracy in
What State?, New York: Columbia University Press, 2011.
Allison, Henry E. Kant's Theory of Freedom., Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1990.
———. Idealism and Freedom: Essays on Kant's Theoretical and Practical
Philosophy., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities., London: Verso, 1991.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. The Ethics of Identity., Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2005.
———. Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers., London: Allen Lane,
2006.
Archibugi, Daniele, (ed.) Debating Cosmopolitics. London: Verso, 2003.
Archibugi, Daniele, and David Held, (eds.) Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda
for a New World Order. Cambridge: Polity, 1995.
Archibugi, Daniele. The Global Commonwealth of Citizens: Toward Cosmopolitan
Democracy., Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.
Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition., Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1999.
Aristotle. Metaphysics. Translated by W.D. Ross., Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1924.
———. The Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by David Ross., Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2009.
Asher, Allan. 2012. The Lies We Feed Ourselves to Paint Refugees as Villains.
The Punch. 27th August. http://www.thepunch.com.au/articles/The-lies-we-
feed-ourselves-to-paint-refugees-as-villains/ [accessed 28th August].
Ashley, Richard K. “Political Realism and Human Interests.” International Studies
Quarterly 25 (1981): 204-36.
———. “The Geopolitics of Geopolitical Space: Toward a Critical Social Theory
of International Politics.” Alternatives 12, no. 4 (1987): 403-34.
———. “Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy
Problematique.” Millennium-Journal of International Studies 17, no. 2
(1988): 227-62.
Ashley, Richard K. and Walker, R.B.J. “Introduction: Speaking the Language of
Exile: Dissident Thought in International Studies.” International Studies
403
404
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/14ForceandUnderstandingB.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Force and Understanding.” Lectures on
Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 25th
October (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/15ForceandUnderstandingC.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Force and Understanding.” Lectures on
Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 25th
October (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/16ForceandUnderstandingD.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage.” Lectures on Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 8th November
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/19MasterSlaveA.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Lordship and Bondage.” Lectures on Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 8th November
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/20MasterSlaveB.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Self-Consciousness.” Lectures on Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 1st November
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/17SelfConsciousnessA.mp3.
———. “Phenomenology of Spirit. Self-Consciousness.” Lectures on Hegel's
Phenomenology of Spirit The New School. New York City. 1st November
(2006): http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/18SelfConsciousnessB.mp3.
———. “The Causality of Fate: Modernity and Modernism in Habermas.” Praxis
International 4 (1988): 407.
———. Recovering Ethical Life: Jürgen Habermas and the Future of Critical
Theory., London: Routledge, 1995.
———. “Confession and Forgiveness: Hegel's Poetics of Action.” In Beyond
Representation: Philosophy and Poetic Imagination, edited by Richard
Eldridge, 34–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
———. “Hegel's Ladder: The Ethical Presuppositions of Absolute Knowing.”
Dialogue 39 (2000): 808-18.
———. “Love and Law: Hegel's Critique of Morality.” Social Research: An
International Quarterly 70, no. 2 (2003): 393-431.
———. “Negative Dialectic as Fate: Adorno and Hegel.” In The Cambridge
Companion to Adorno, edited by Tom Huhn, 19-50. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004.
———. “Early Theological Writings.” Lectures on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit The New School. New York City. 13th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/03EarlyTheologicalWritingA.mp3.
———. “Early Theological Writings.” Lectures on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit The New School. New York City. 13th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/04EarlyTheologicalWritingB.mp3.
———. “Early Theological Writings.” Lectures on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit The New School. New York City. 20th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/05EarlyTheologicalWritingC.mp3.
———. “Early Theological Writings.” Lectures on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit The New School. New York City. 20th September (2006):
http://bernsteintapes.com/lectures/Hegel/06EarlyTheologicalWritingD.mp3.
———. “Introduction.” Lectures on Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit The New
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
Verso, 2012.
Cunningham, Conor. Genealogy of Nihilism: Philosophies of Nothing and the
Difference of Theology., London: Routledge, 2002.
Dahlstrom, Daniel O. “Thinking of Nothing: Heidegger's Criticism of Hegel's
Conception of Negativity.” In A Companion to Hegel, edited by Stephen
Houlgate and Michael Baur, 519-37. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011.
Dallmayr, Fred R. Twilight of Subjectivity: Contributions to a Postindividualist
Theory of Politics., Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981.
———. “Ontology of Freedom: Heidegger and Political Philosophy.” Political
Theory 12, no. 2 (1984): 204-34.
———. Polis and Praxis: Exercises in Contemporary Political Theory.,
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1984.
———. “Introduction.” In The Communicative Ethics Controversy, edited by
Seyla Benhabib and Fred Dallmayr, Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1990.
———. Between Freiburg & Frankfurt: Towards a Critical Ontology., Amherst:
University of Massachusetts Press, 1991.
———. Life-World, Modernity and Critique: Paths Between Heidegger and the
Frankfurt School., Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.
———. G.W.F.Hegel: Modernity and Politics., Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield,
1993.
———. The Other Heidegger., Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1995.
———. Beyond Orientalism: Essays on Cross-Cultural Encounter., New York:
SUNY Press, 1996.
———. Alternative Visions: Paths in the Global Village., Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1998.
———. “Heidegger on Macht and Machenschaft.” Continental Philosophy Review
34, no. 3 (2001): 247-67.
———. Dialogue Among Civilizations: Some Exemplary Voices., Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2002.
———. “Cosmopolitanism: Moral and Political.” Political Theory 31, no. 3
(2003): 421-42.
———. Small Wonder: Global Power and Its Discontents., Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield, 2005.
———. “Empire Or Cosmopolis: Civilisation At the Crossroads.” In The Global
Politics of Globalization: "Empire" Vs. "Cosmopolis", edited by Barry K.
Gills, London: Routledge, 2007.
———. “On Love With Distinction.” Dao 7, no. 1 (2008): 5-8.
———. The Promise of Democracy: Political Agency and Transformation.,
Albany: SUNY Press, 2010.
———. “Nikolas Kompridis. Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between
Past and Future. (Review).” Notre Dame (2009):
Dallmayr, Fred R., and Peter R. Moody. Non-Western Political Thought., Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1997.
Davis, Zachary and Steinbock, Anthony. Max Scheler. Edited by Edward N. Zalta.
Winter 2011 ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scheler/, 2011.
Deibert, Ronald J. “Black Code Redux: Censorship, Surveillance, and the
Militarisation of Cyberspace.” In Digital Media and Democracy: Tactics in
412
Hard Times, edited by Megan Boler, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press,
2008.
Deligiorgi, Katerina, (ed.) Hegel: New Directions. Chesham: Acumen, 2006.
Derian, James Der, and Michael J. Shapiro. International / Intertextual Relations:
Postmodern Readings of World Politics., Lexington, Mass.: Lexington
Publishers, 1989.
Derrida, Jacques. “The Ends of Man.” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 30, no. 1 (1969): 31-57.
———. Limited Inc., Evanston, Il.: Northwestern University Press, 1977.
———. Writing and Difference., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978.
———. Margins of Philosophy., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.
———. “Deconstruction and the Other.” In Dialogues With Contemporary
Continental Thinkers: The Phenomenological Heritage, edited by Richard
Kearney and Paul Ricoeur, 107–26. Manchester: Manchester University
Press, 1984.
———. Glas., Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1990.
———, “Letter to a Japanese Friend.” In A Derrida Reader: Between the Blinds,
edited by Peggy Kamuf, 269-76. New York: Columbia University Press,
1991.
———. Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question., Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1991.
———. “Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority.” In Deconstruction
and the Possibility of Justice, edited by Rosenfeld and Carlson Cornell,
London: Routledge, 1992.
———. The Other Heading: Reflections on Today's Europe., Bloomington, In.:
Indiana University Press, 1992.
———. “Nietzsche and the Machine: An Interview With Jacques Derrida By
Richard Beardsworth.” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 7 (1994): 7-66.
———. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the
New International., London: Routledge, 1994.
———. The Gift of Death., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
———. Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation With Jacques Derrida.,
New York: Fordham University Press, 1997.
———. Monolingualism of the Other, Or, the Prosthesis of Origin. Translated by
Patrick Mensah., Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.
———. Of Grammatology. Translated by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak., Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998.
———. Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas. Translated by Michael Nass and Pascale-
Anne Brault., Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999.
———. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness., London: Routledge, 2001.
———. Negotiations: Interventions and Interviews, 1971-2001. Edited by E.
Rottenberg., Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002.
———. “Autoimmunity: Real and Symbolic Suicides. A Dialogue With Jacques
Derrida.” In Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues With Jürgen
Habermas and Jacques Derrida, edited by Giovanna Borradori, Chicago:
Chicago University Press, 2003.
———. Dissemination. Translated by Barbara Johnson., London: Continuum,
2004.
413
414
415
416
Gaddis, John Lewis. “International Relations Theory and the End of the Cold
War.” International Security 17, no. Winter (1992): 5-58.
Gaita, Raimond. A Common Humanity: Thinking About Love and Truth and
Justice., London: Routledge, 2002.
Ganis, Richard. The Politics of Care in Habermas and Derrida., Plymouth:
Lexington, 2011.
Gaon, Stella. “Pluralizing Universal "Man": The Legacy of Transcendentalism and
Teleology in Habermas's Discourse Ethics.” Review of Politics 60 (1998):
685-718.
Gauchet, Marcel. The Disenchantment of the World: A Political History of
Religion. Translated by Oscar Burge., Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1999.
Geertz, Clifford. The Interpretation of Cultures., London: Hutchinson, 1975.
Gemes, Ken, and Simon May. Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy., Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2009.
George, Jim. Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introduction to
International Relations., Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1994.
George, Jim and David Campbell. “Patterns of Dissent and the Celebration of
Difference: Critical Social Theory and International Relations.” International
Studies Quarterly 34 (1990): 269-93.
Geras, Norman. “The View From Everywhere.” Review of International Studies
25, no. 1 (1999): 157-63.
Germain, Randall D., and Michael Kenny. The Idea of Global Civil Society:
Politics and Ethics in a Globalizing Era., London: Routledge, 2005.
Gillespie, Michael Allen. Hegel, Heidegger and the Ground of History., Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1984.
Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1993.
Gills, Barry K. “Introduction.” In The Global Politics of Globalization: "Empire"
Vs. "Cosmopolis", edited by Barry K. Gills, London: Routledge, 2007.
Gökay, Bulent, and R.B.J. Walker. 11 September 2001 War, Terror and
Judgement., London: Routledge, 2003.
Gordon, Peter E. Continental Divide: Heidegger, Cassirer, Davos., Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 2010.
Gordon, Peter Eli. Rosenzweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German
Philosophy., Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003.
Gorner, Paul. Twentieth Century German Philosophy., Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2000.
Gramsci, Antonio. Prison Notebooks., New York: Columbia University Press,
2011.
Guignon, Charles B. “Introduction.” In The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Guignon, Charles B., (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Guyer, Paul. “Thought and Being: Hegel's Critique of Kant's Theoretical
Philosophy.” edited by Frederik Beiser, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
Guzzoni, Ute. “Do We Still Want to be Subjects?” In Deconstructive
417
Subjectivities, edited by Simon Critchley and Peter Dews, New York: SUNY
Press, 1996.
Haacke, Jürgen. “Theory and Praxis in International Relations: Habermas, Self-
Reflection, Rational Argumentation.” Millennium-Journal of International
Studies 25, no. 2 (1996): 255-89.
Haar, Michel. “The Question of Human Freedom in the Later Heidegger.” The
Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement 28, no. 1 (1989): 1-16.
———. Heidegger and the Essence of Man. Translated by W. McNeill., New
York: SUNY Press, 1993.
Habermas, Jürgen. Communication and the Evolution of Society. Translated by
Thomas McCarthy., Boston: Beacon, 1979.
———. Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 1. Reason and the Rationalization
of Society, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1986.
———. “Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy From a German
Perspective.” Critical Inquiry 15, no. 2 (1989): 431-56.
———. “Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Programme of Philosophical Justification.”
In The Communicative Ethics Controversy, edited by Seyla Benhabib and
Fred Dallmayr, Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1990.
———. “Justice and Solidarity: On the Discussion Concerning Stage 6.” In The
Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion Between Philosophy and
the Social Sciences, edited by Thomas E. Wren, Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT
Press, 1990.
———. The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory., Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press, 1998.
———. Knowledge and Human Interests., Boston: Beacon Press, 1972.
———. Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. 2: Lifeworld and System: A
Critique of Functionalist Reason, London: Heinenmann, 1989.
———. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures., Cambridge,
Mass.: The MIT Press, 1990.
———. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action., Cambridge, Mass.: The
MIT Press, 1992.
———. “Morality and Ethical Life: Does Hegel's Critique of Kant Apply to
Discourse Ethics.” In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action,
Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1992.
———. Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics., Cambridge:
Polity Press, 1993.
———. Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays., Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press, 1994.
———. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law
and Democracy. Translated by William Rehg., Cambridge: Polity Press,
1996.
———. “From Kant to Hegel and Back Again–The Move Towards
Detranscendentalisation.” European Journal of Philosophy 7, no. 2 (1999):
129-57.
———. Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues With Jürgen Habermas and
Jacques Derrida., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003.
Hadreas, Peter J. A Phenomenology of Love and Hate., Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007.
Hall, Phil. 2008. Solaris: Higher Sentience Communicates Through Love, Not
418
Vivisection. http://xuitlacoche.blogspot.com/2008/07/solaris-higher-
sentience-communicates.html [accessed 14/06/2012].
Hamilton, Gary. “Looking for Luca - the Mother of All Life.” New Scientist 2515
(2005):
Hardimon, Michael. Hegel's Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Harris, H.S. Hegel's Development: Towards the Sunlight 1770-1801., Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1972.
———. Hegel's Ladder. Vol. 2: The Odyssey of Spirit, Indianapolis: Hackett,
1997.
———. Hegel's Ladder. Vol. 1: A Commentary on Hegel's Phenomenology of
Spirit, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997.
Hegel, G. W. F. Vorlesungen Über Rechtsphilosophie (Lectures on the Philosophy
of Right). Edited by K.H. Ilting., Stuttgart: Frommann Verla, 1974.
———. The Philosophy of History., New York: Dover Publications, 2004.
———. Early Theological Writings. Translated by T.M. Knox., Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971.
———. “Fragment of a System.” In Early Theological Writings, trans. T.M. Knox,
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971.
———. “Fragment on Love.” In Early Theological Writings, trans. T.M. Knox,
Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971.
———. “The Spirit of Christianity and Its Fate.” In Early Theological Writings,
trans. T.M. Knox, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1971.
———. Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by A.V. Miller., Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1977.
———. Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Translated by H.B. Nisbet.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
———. The Jena System, 1804-5: Logic and Metaphysics. Translated by George
di Giovanni., Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1986.
———. Hegel's System of Ethical Life and First Philosophy of Spirit., New York:
SUNY Press, 1988.
———. The Difference Between Fichte's and Schelling's System of Philosophy.,
New York: SUNY Press, 1988.
———. Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Translated by H.B. Nisbet.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
———. Hegel: Political Writings., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
———. “Hegel's Philosophy of Nature: Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences (1830), Part Ii (Hegel's Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences)
(Pt. 2).” (2004):
———. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Heidelberg Writings: Journal
Publications., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
———. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Science of Logic. Translated by
George di Giovanni., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Heidegger, Martin. The Question of Being. Translated by William Kluback and
Jean T. Wilde., London: Vision, 1956.
———. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson.,
Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 1962.
———. Hegel's Concept of Existence., New York: Harper & Row, 1970.
419
———. Hegel's Concept of Experience., New York: Harper & Row, 1970.
———. “The Anaximander Fragment.” Arion 1, no. 4 (1973): 576-626.
———. What is Called Thinking? Translated by J. Glenn Gray., New York:
Harper Perennial, 1976.
———. The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. Translated by
William Lovitt., New York: Harper & Row, 1977.
———. Nietzsche. Vol. One: The Will to Power as Art Translated by David
Farrell Krell., London: Routledge, 1981.
———. Schelling's Treatise: On the Essence of Human Freedom., Athens, OH:
Ohio University Press, 1985.
———. Nietzsche. Vol. Two: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same Translated by
David Farrell Krell., San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1991.
———. History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena. Translated by Theodore
Kisiel., Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1992.
———. “Letter on Humanism.” In Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, edited by
David F. Krell, New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
———, Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
———. “On the Essence of Truth.” In Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, edited
by David F. Krell., New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
———. “The Origin of the Work of Art.” In Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings,
edited by David F. Krell., New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
———. “What is Metaphysics?” In Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, edited by
David F. Krell., New York: Harper Collins, 1993.
———. Hegel's "Phenomenology of Spirit". Translated by Parvis Emad and
Kenneth Maly., Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1994.
———. Being and Time. Translated by Joan Stambaugh., New York: SUNY
Press, 1996.
———. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Translated by Richard Taft.,
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1997.
———. Basic Concepts., Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1998.
———. Introduction to 'What is Metaphysics'. Translated by Walter Kaufmann.
Edited by William McNeill., Pathmarks. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1998.
———. An Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Gregory Fried and Richard
Polt., New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000.
———. Towards the Definition of Philosophy., London: Continuum, 2000.
———. The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude.,
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2001.
———. The Essence of Human Freedom: An Introduction to Philosophy., London:
Continuum, 2002.
———. The Essence of Truth: On Plato's Cave Allegory and Theaetus., London:
Continuum, 2002.
———. Philosophical and Political Writings. Edited by Manfred Stassen.,
London: Continuum, 2003.
———. The End of Philosophy. Translated by Joan Stambaugh., Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2003.
———. The Phenomenology of Religious Life., Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 2004.
420
———. “The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking.” In Martin Heidegger:
Basic Writings From Being and Time (1927) to the Task of Thinking (1964),
edited by David Farrell Krell, London: Routledge, 2007.
———. Country Path Conversations. Translated by Bret W. Davis., Indianapolis:
Indiana University Press, 2010.
———. “Only a God Can Save Us: The Spiegel Interview (1966).” edited by
Thomas Sheehan, New Jersey: Transaction, 2010.
Held, David. “Cosmopolitan Democracy and the Global Order: A New Agenda.”
In Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant's Cosmopolitan Ideal, edited by James
Bohman and Mattias Lutz-Bachmann, Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1997.
———. Global Covenant: The Democratic Alternative to the Washington
Consensus., Cambridge: Polity, 2004.
———. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to
Cosmopolitan Governance., Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.
———. Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas., Cambridge:
Polity, 1990.
———. Political Theory Today., Cambridge: Polity, 1991.
Held, David and McGrew, Anthony. “The End of the Old Order? Globalization
and the Prospects for World Order.” In 'The Eighty Years' Crisis:
International Relations 1919-1999, edited by Tim Dunne Ken Booth, and
Michael Cox, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Held, Virginia. Feminist Morality: Transforming Culture, Society, and Politics.,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Henrich, Dieter. “Ethics of Autonomy.” In The Unity of Reason: Essays on Kant's
Philosophy, edited by Richard Velkey, trans. Louis Hunt, Cambridge, Mass:
Harvard University Press, 1994.
———. Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism., Cambridge.:
Harvard University Press, 2008.
Hobson, John M. “Is Critical Theory Always for the White West and for Western
Imperialism? Beyond Westphilian Towards a Post-Racist Critical IR.” In
Critical International Relations Theory After 25 Years, edited by Nicholas
and Ben Thirkell-White Rengger, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2007.
Hodge, Joanna. Heidegger and Ethics., London: Routledge, 1995.
Hoffman, Mark. “Critical Theory and the Inter-Paradigm Debate.” Millennium-
Journal of International Studies 16 (1987): 231-49.
———. “Restructuring, Reconstruction, Reinscription, Rearticulation: Four
Voices in Critical International Theory.” Millennium-Journal of International
Studies 20, no. 2 (1991): 169-85.
Honneth, Axel. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social
Conflicts., Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1996.
———. Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory., London:
Polity, 2007.
———. Reification: A New Look At an Old Idea., Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2008.
———. Pathologies of Reason: On the Legacy of Critical Theory. Translated by
James Ingram., New York: Columbia University Press, 2009.
———. The Pathologies of Individual Freedom: Hegel's Social Theory. Translated
421
422
423
424
Routledge, 2002.
Kohlberg, Lawrence. “The Claim to Moral Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral
Judgement.” Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 532-633.
Kojève, Alexandre. Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the
"Phenomenology of Spirit"., New York: Cornell, 1980.
Kolb, David. The Critique of Pure Modernity: Hegel, Heidegger and After.,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.
Kompridis, Nikolas. Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory Between Past and
Future., Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 2006.
Kosh, Michelle. Freedom and Reason in Kant, Schelling and Kierkegaard.,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006.
Krasnoff, Larry. Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit: An Introduction., Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. Rules, Norms and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical
and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
———. “Constructing a New Orthodoxy? Wendt's 'Social Theory of International
Politics' and the Constructivist Challenge.” Millennium-Journal of
International Studies 29, no. 1 (2000): 73-101.
———. “History, Action and Identity: Revisiting the "Second" Great Debate and
Assessing Its Importance for Social Theory.” European Journal of
International Relations 12, no. 1 (2006): 5-29.
———. “Looking Back From Somewhere: Reflections on What Remains 'Critical'
in Critical Theory.” In Critical International Relations Theory After 25
Years, edited by Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Krause, Keith and Michael C. Williams, (ed.) Critical Security Studies: Concepts
and Cases. London: UCL Press, 1997.
Kurki, Milja. “Causes of a Divided Discipline: Rethinking the Concept of Cause in
International Relations Theory.” Review of International Studies 32, no. 2
(2006): 189-216.
———. “Critical Realism and Causal Analysis in International Relations.”
Millennium-Journal of International Studies 35, no. 2 (2007): 361-78.
———. Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
———. “Critical Realism and the Analysis of Democratisation: Does Philosophy
of Science Matter?” In Scientific Realism and International Relations, edited
by Jonathan Joseph and Colin Wight, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan,
2010.
———. “The Limitations of the Critical Edge: Reflections on Critical and
Philosophical IR Scholarship Today.” Millennium - Journal of International
Studies 40, no. 1 (2011): 129-46.
Kymlicka, Will. Liberalism, Community and Culture., Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1989.
Lama, Dalai. How to Practice: The Way to a Meaningful Life. Translated by
Jeffrey Hopkins., New York: Simon & Schuster, 2002.
Lambier, Josh. “The Organismic State Against Itself: Schelling, Hegel and the Life
of Right.” European Romantic Review 19, no. 2 (2008): 131-37.
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
the Role of Love in Hegel.” Canadian Journal of Political Science 35, no. 3
(2002): 499-525.
Ott, Hugo. Martin Heidegger. A Political Life. Translated by Allan Blunden., New
York: Basic Books, 1993.
Outhwaite, William. Habermas: A Critical Introduction., Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 1994.
Outka, Gene. Agape: An Ethical Analysis., New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977.
Owen, Michael. 2012. Radio 'King' Slammed Over Boatpeople Tirade. The
Australian. June 8th. http://www.theaustralian.com.au/national-
affairs/immigration/radio-king-slammed-over-boatpeople-tirade/story-
fn9hm1gu-1226388100400 [accessed 30th August 2012].
Palan, Ronen. “Transnational Theories of Order and Change: Heterodoxy in
International Relations Scholarship.” In Critical International Theory After
25 Years, edited by Nicholas Rengger and Ben Thirkell-White, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Paley, John. “Heidegger and the Ethics of Care.” Nursing Philosophy 1, no. 1
(2000): 64-75.
Palmer, Richard E. Hermeneutics: Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher,
Dilthey, Heidegger, and Gadamer., Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Press, 1969.
Patomäki, Heikki. After International Relations: Critical Realism and the
(Re)Construction of World Politics., London: Routledge, 2002.
———. “Problems of Democratizing Global Governance.” European Journal of
International Relations 9, no. 3 (2003): 347-76.
Patomäki, Heikki and Colin Wight. “After Postpositivism? The Promises of
Critical Realism.” International Studies Quarterly 44 (2000): 213-37.
Paton, Herbert James. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant's Moral
Philosophy., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1948.
Patten, Alan. Hegel's Idea of Freedom., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
Pavel, Thomas G. “The Heidegger Affair.” MLN 103, no. 4 (1988): 887-901.
Philpott, Daniel. Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern
International Relations., Princeton.: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Piaget, Jean. The Moral Judgement of the Child., Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1983.
Piercey, Robert. “Not Choosing Between Morality and Ethics.” The Philosophical
Forum 32, no. 1 (2001): 53-72.
Pin-Fat, Veronique. “(Im)Possible Universalism: Reading Human Rights in World
Politics.” Review of International Studies 26, no. 4 (2000): 663-74.
———. Universality, Ethics, and International Relations., London: Routledge,
2010.
———. “Cosmopolitanism and the End of Humanity.” Paper presented at the
Critical and Cultural Politics Group, Department of International Politics,
Aberystwyth, 29th May 2012.
———. “Cosmopolitanism Without Foundations.” In Politics in the Global Age:
Critical Reflections on Cosmopolitanism, edited by Sonika Gupta, London:
Routledge, 2012.
Pin-Fat, Veronique, Jenny Edkins, and Michael Shapiro, (eds.) Sovereign Lives:
Power in an Era of Globalisation. London: Routledge, 2004.
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
———. “Five Questions About Terrorism.” Dissent 49, no. 1 (2002): 5-11.
———. Arguing About War., New Haven: Yale University Press, 2004.
———. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations.,
New York: Basic Books, 2006.
———. Politics and Passion: Toward a More Egalitarian Liberalism., New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2006.
———. Thinking Politically: Essays in Political Theory., Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007.
Ward, Ian. Justice, Humanity and the New World Order., Aldershot: Ashgate,
2003.
Warner, Daniel. “Levinas, Buber and the Concept of Otherness in International
Relations: A Reply to David Campbell.” Millennium-Journal of International
Studies 25, no. 1 (1996): 111.
Weber, Cynthia. International Relations Theory: A Critical Introduction. 2nd ed.,
London: Routledge, 2005.
Weber, Eric Thomas. Rawls, Dewey, and Constructivism: On the Epistemology of
Justice., London: Continuum, 2010.
Weber, Martin. “Engaging Globalization: Critical Theory and Global Political
Change.” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 27, no. 3 (2002): 301-25.
———. “Hegel Beyond the State? Left-Hegelian Thought and Global Politics.”
Paper presented at the ISA Annual Convention, Chicago, 2007.
———. “The Concept of Solidarity in the Study of World Politics: Towards a
Critical Theoretic Understanding.” Review of International Studies 33, no. 4
(2007): 693.
———. “Critical Theory and Contemporary World Politics.” International Studies
Review 12, no. 3 (2010): 444-50.
———. “Ontologies, Depth and Otherwise: Critical Notes on Wight's Meta-
Theoretical Proposal of a Scientific Realist IR.” Review of International
Studies 38, no. 1 (2012): 223-34.
Weil, Simone. The Need for Roots: Prelude to a Declaration of Duties to
Mankind., London: Routledge, 1952.
Welz, Claudia. Love's Transcendence and the Problem of Theodicy. Vol. 30,
Tuebingen: Mohr Siebrek Ek, 2008.
Wendt, Alexander. “The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations
Theory.” International Organization 41, no. 3 (1987): 335-70.
———. “Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power
Politics.” International Organization 46, no. 2 (1992): 391-425.
———. “Constructing International Politics.” International Security 20, no. 1
(1995): 71-81.
———. Social Theory of International Politics., Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999.
———. “What is International Relations for? Notes Towards a Postcritical View.”
In Critical Theory and World Politics, edited by Richard Wyn Jones,
Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2001.
Werner, Laura. “The Restless Love of Thinking: The Concept of Liebe in Hegel's
Philosophy.” Department of Social and Moral Philosophy, Ph.D. Thesis,
University of Helsinki, 2007.
White, Stephen K. Political Theory and Post-Modernism., Cambridge: Cambridge
442
443
444
445