Reading 3.1. Miller Introduction To Aesthetics PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

http://users.rowan.edu/~millere/Introduction%20to%20Aesthetics.

htm

INTRODUCTION TO AESTHETICS
By Ellen Miller
Theories of art and art itself exist within a context—philosophical, cultural, class and
gender specific—from which it emerges and without which it does not exist. Philosophers and art
theorists cannot escape the influence of past philosophers and theorists any more than they can
remain untouched by current trends in film, technology, and architecture. Art and culture and
theories of art and culture are inseparably and organically linked together. Furthermore, this is not
a static or eternal pattern but one that is dynamic, fluid, constantly changing historically over time.

Principal changes in philosophy (generally) are likely to become more influential in the
philosophy of art. There is a profound convergence between general philosophy and philosophy
of art. Let me express three general trends that are important to keep in mind as we discuss pre-
aesthetic, aesthetic, and postmodern theories over the duration of this course. As Sartwell points
out, Europe only developed the concept of the aesthetic in the 18 th century.

Here are the three broad movements in philosophy that are important to remember when
we reflect upon questions concerning art:

1. Deep suspicion that we cannot hope to fix any single ontology, any universally
adequate unchanging account of human cognition or human interests or human
concerns.
2. We must reflect upon the contingent and tacit practices of human life. These are central
to philosophical reflection
3. There cannot be any canon or principles or conceptual priorities in accord with which
philosophical theories may be shown to be approaching systematic closure on any
questions.

Aesthetics (as the study of art and beauty), aesthetic experience (the proper way of
approach and experience art and beauty), and modern art (art for art’s sake) all arose together at
approx. the same time as expressions of modernist culture (somewhere between the Renaissance
and the middle of the 20th century). Aesthetics is the name of the philosophical study of art and
natural beauty. It is a relatively new branch of philosophy that arose in the early 18 th century (early
1700’s )in England and Germany, over 2000 years after the beginnings of other branches of
Western philosophy (which began in Greece around 600 B.C.E.)

Aesthetics is closely related to the concept of aesthetic experience. Baumgarten who coined
the term aesthetics, claimed that humans experience the world in two fundamentally ways—
logically and aesthetically. Logically—that is a thorn, it will hurt if it pricks me. Aesthetically—
enjoying a sunset, looking at seashells, enjoying a work of art. These things are beautiful because
you are looking at them aesthetically.

What we call art, or more properly fine art, is therefore, according to the 18 th +19th century
tradition of the aesthetic, those objects made by humans to be enjoyed aesthetically. So, Paleolithic
European cave paintings, Native American wood carvings are not really art according to some
because they were made by people before the emergence of aesthetic experience.

So, art created as art, aesthetic exp. And aesthetics are notions that all arose together. These
human ways of interpreting the world have not always existed since the dawn of human society
and not even since the beginning of Western civilization. Philosophy is often thought of as a kind
of systematic reflection of our ordinary commonsense intuitions and deeply rooted beliefs and
assumptions. This would mean that aesthetics is a reflection on ideas we already have about art,
artists. If aesthetics is a branch of philosophy and philosophy is a reflection of our ordinary
commonsense intuition, then, in a sense, we already know what art, aesthetics, and artists are.

But these commonsense intuitions may be so deeply engrained and internalized that we
may take them for granted. Perhaps we can more fully experience artworks if we enlarge our
perspective. How do we do this?

Our way of viewing art from an aesthetic point of view is only one way of looking at things.
It appears at a certain point in the history of certain cultures and may just was easily disappear and
be replaced by another way of viewing things.

The ideas of aesthetic enjoyment and fine art and artist arose in what we call the modern
period (end of 17th century to middle of 20th). Main points of modernist aesthetics

1. Aesthetic experience is non-utilitarian


2. AE is detached from ordinary self-interested pursuits (is disinterested)
3. Works of art are made to be viewed aesthetically—and so just to be enjoyed (For no
other purpose)
4. Everyone can appreciate art just by adopting the aesthetic point of view
5. Artists see things in a unique way and creatively find innovative ways of
communicating that vision to us
6. Artists show us how to look at the world, how to understand ourselves, who we are
7. Works of art express these unusual ideas of artists
8. Great works of art must be innovative and creative, expressing new ideas in new ways
9. The history of art is the history of these great innovations by these great artists
10. Art is not hard to understand—it just requires that we adopt the aesthetic point of view

The story of aesthetics begins with Hobbes’ claim that all human perception is self
interested. Many people disagreed with Hobbes and though that some human actions were
disinterested, that is, done for their own sake, enjoyed and appreciated for their own sake. And one
large subset of such disinterested actions were those associated with art and natural beauty.

The reaction began in Britain with the Earl of Shaftesbury (1671-1713) who said we can
love things for themselves (good wine, a beautiful sunset, a painting). Deciding what we should
love and appreciate in this way is a matter of taste, a kind of inner sensation, or feeling. It is not
something you can learn from a book.
In the 1750’s Alexander Baumgarten pursued this idea by dividing all human thought into
two broad categories—logic and aesthetics. After Baumgarten, the British worked on the idea of
good taste as kind of refined sensibility available to anyone who would adopt the detached,
disinterested aesthetic point of view. And still later, at the very end of the 18 th century, the German
philosopher, Immanuel Kant synthesized the work of the British taste theorists and the German
attempts to define the aesthetic as differentiated from the logical, and Kant’s efforts pretty well
defined and stabilized the tradition of the aesthetic attitude for the next 150 years.

Questions:

1. We can ask whether at the end of the 20th century and beginning of the 21st, are we still
in the modernist period or are we moving beyond that into a postmodern place, a post-
aesthetic phase?
2. One of the most interesting issues in this ongoing debate is whether art merely reflects
the existing politics of the status quo or whether art can create new ways of looking at
things that may challenge the status quo. Does art have its own voice, can it generate
its own point of view, or is it merely the expression, symptom, reflex of a larger
political system?

This second question leads us back Plato’s theory of art which can be classified under the
general heading “Theories of Imitation”. Plato explored two fundamental aspects of imitation: the
nature of imitation itself and the bad effects of imitation. First, we turn to the nature of imitation.

Plato approached this point analytically and logically. Take an object in the sensory world,
a bed for example. An observer can pick out its unity or commonality as a type or kind of thing,
and its diversity as multiple instances of that thing. Beds are identifiable as beads and yet are
different from trees. Logically, Plato argues, there must be a single ideal form that accounts for
the unity (it is the philosopher who is able to apprehend the forms—understood through the mind’s
eye—not our physical eyes). Plato assigned priority to the single form which comes logically
before sensory instances of that form.

Plato’s analysis of imitation as a concept results in a threefold distinction in reality.


Forms—mind’s eye, sensory objects/physical objects, images/pictures/poems about beds. Plato
thought that the sensory world imitated the world of forms. So, poems/art are doubly removed
from reality since they mirror the physical world. So, art is an illusion of an illusion. Images and
pictures are only imitations of imitations.

Plato distinguished in a fundamental way between appearance and reality. Reality is not
found in the immediate present, but in an accessible but protected sacred realm of forms that the
present imitates. An imitation can be more or less true depending on how close it is to the original.
Painting is an art that will produce only inferior imitative instances on this scheme. Plato shows
poetry to belong to the same imitative scheme, so the poet is in no better position than the painter
or naive imitator who holds up a mirror to the world. None of the arts can claim knowledge because
of where they stand in the imitative hierarchy.
Historical Introduction to Aesthetics

The problems, questions, and concepts included in aesthetics and philosophy of art are
many and this sometimes makes a study of the literature of aesthetics a difficult and perplexing
matter. However, the problems of aesthetics when studied historically (As I hope this short sketch
of the origins of aesthetic questions will indicate) and the questions of philosophers are actually
closely related. The questions included within the study of aesthetics have developed out of twin
concerns in the history of thought: the theory of beauty and the theory of art. These 2 concerns
were first discussed by Plato. Even though philosophers have disagreed about how art should be
defined, they have continued to debate the theory of art in roughly similar terms as Plato until very
recently. However, the theory of beauty underwent an important and monumental change in the
18th century. (Kant). Thinkers, instead of only taking about the nature of beauty, added additional
concepts, the sublime, the picturesque. They added additional concepts to the study of beauty.

At the same time, another development was taking place and this is that the concept of the
aesthetic was being worked out (Hutcheson, Burke, Alison, Kant). Generally speaking, these
philosophers were concerned to develop a theory of taste that would allow them to explain
the experience of the beautiful

The notion of disinteredness is at the core of these analyses and is the center of these
philosophers’s concept of the aesthetic. What happened is that the idea of beauty was broken up
and fragmented and gradually was replaced by the concept of the aesthetic. After the 18 th century,
the word beautiful came to be seen as equivalent to “having aesthetic value”.

Since the 18th century then, the twin concerns of aestheticians have been the theory of the
aesthetic and the theory of art. First I will sketch out some major theories of beauty in the tradition
and then I will move onto the theories of taste as they developed in the 18 th century. Following
these two sections, we can explore theories of art beginning again with Plato’s imitation theory
that you witnessed in his allegory of the cave reading.

Plato. A good example of Plato’s understanding of beauty can be found in the Symposium.
This dialogue devoted to praising and exploring love, ultimately gives us a definition of beauty as
understood by Plato. He explains that it is the Form of Beauty that is the object of love. Diotima’s
teachings describe a ladder of love that moves from the appreciation of singular beautiful bodies
on up to the ultimate and higher contemplation of the Form of Beauty that makes it possible for us
to discern individual cases of beauty at all. Those who have ascended the ladder of love learn that
the beauty of the soul is superior to the beauty of bodies.

The Platonic philosophy of beauty does not have much interest in the world of sense and
considers it from a philosophical point of view to be a kind of illusion and a potential source of
error. According to Plato, beauty transcends the world of sense experience, which means that the
experience of beauty is different from what would be described as aesthetic experience today. His
theory dismisses sights and sounds as illusory.

Plato does however take an interest in the beautiful things of the world of sense. He does
try to figure out what all beautiful things share in common. But for Plato, beauty is a simple,
unanalyzable property and is logically similar to a primitive term such as red (cannot be defined—
can only be understood by direct sense experience).

If we look at Plato’s theory of art, we see that he held an imitation theory of art that focuses
attention on the objective properties of the work of art. The theory of art in Plato is object centered.
This leads to Plato’s negative estimation of art as twice removed from reality and a poor source of
knowledge. Art is doubly unreal and is an inferior product and poor model for moral conduct.
Plato’s characterization of paintings as untrue appearances may be understood as the origin of the
view that art is illusion, a view held by a number of present day theorists.

Plotinus. Plotinus, like Plato, thought that the experience of beauty itself is not a sensuous
experience but an intellectual one. One of the most important results of both these theories of
beauty was the establishment of contemplation as a central idea in the theory of beauty and
consequently in the theory of aesthetic experience. Almost all aesthetic theories have maintained
that the exp. Of beauty, or more generally, aesthetic exp., involves contemplation. When Plato and
Plotinus thought of contemplation, they meant that a person had an awareness of a nonsensous
object. Of course, meditation can also be linked to the sensory world.

St. Thomas Aquinas (354-430 AD). Aquinas’ understanding of beauty is not an unworldly
one; he defines beauty as that which pleases when seen. Objects please when they have the
conditions of beauty which are perfection, proportion and brightness or clarity. Importantly, his
theory has both objective and subjective aspects. The idea of pleasing brings in the notion of the
subject who is pleased. Being pleased is a property of a subject. This is a significant step away
from the objective Platonic conception of beauty toward a subjective account. This subjective
concept of beauty will reach its high point in the theories of 18th century philosophers.

As we progress towards the Renaissance, we find a great interest in more concrete and
specific topics such as the theory of painting and the theory of architecture. There is also a
resurgence of Neoplatonism at this time.

The 18th Century: Taste and the Decline of Beauty. The 18th century brings us into a
critical and important time in the history of aesthetics. It is during this time that philosophers
provided the basis for aesthetics in its modern form. During the middle of the century, the German
philosopher, Alexander Baumgarten coined the term aesthetics. It is at this time that the
philosophical tradition tried to explain behavior and mental phenomena by attributing each kind
of phenomenon to a distinct faculty of the mind. For example, the vegetative faculty (explains
nutrition and procreation), the locomotive faculty explains movement, the rational faculty explains
mental behavior, the sensory faculties explain perception, imagination, etc.

Prior to the 18th century, it was generally assumed that beauty named an objective property
of things. But in the 18th century, there was a shift to talking about taste and thus a shift onto the
subjective faculties of the perceiver. In the hands of these philosophers, philosophy, philosophy of
art became subjectivized. What this means is that philosophers turned their attention towards the
subject and analyzed the states of the subject’s mind and his mental faculties. For example, British
philosophers thought that they had discovered a new internal sense—the sense of beauty.
The establishment of aesthetic theory as the theory that unifies the problems of the theory
of beauty and the philosophy of taste was not completed in the 18 th century. However, Kant’s
views near the end of the 18th century incorporated the insights of the British aestheticians and
came close to being a unified aesthetic theory. By aesthetic theory I mean a theory that makes the
concept of the aesthetic basic and defines other concepts of the theory in terms of the aesthetic.

First I will describe Hume’s views because they serve as the best contrast to Kant’s and
then I will move onto discuss Kant. We will read selections from both for next week’s classes.
In Hume’s Standard of Taste he makes it clear that his investigation into the nature of taste is an
empirical investigation of certain aspects of human nature.

Hume denies that we rationality intuit beauty or the rules that govern it. For him, the
foundation of our understanding of taste is to be found in experience. His claim then is that the
normative question of what is correct to call beautiful can be solved by a comprehensive empirical
survey of the taste of men. This is the feature of Hume’s view that most vividly contrasts with
Kant. Hume concludes that beauty is not in objects but is a feeling. These feelings are linked by
the nature of our human constitution to certain qualities in objects. So, it is possible to have
objective judgments about beauty in the sense that there might be universal agreement among
normal subjects. (Hume—experiential account of beauty and taste)

Kant. Kant tried to show how it is possible for us to have some knowledge which is certain
unlike Hume who thought that since knowledge derives from experience we cannot be certain of
anything. The differences between Hume and Kant show up in their different philosophies of taste.
The empiricists (Hume) understood the philosophy of taste as an empirical inquiry into the object
which can lead to a psychological generalization about human nature. Kant conceives of the
philosophy of taste as an inquiry into the a priori foundations of knowledge which will show why
judgments of beauty are universal and necessary.

For Kant, all aesthetic judgments focus on pleasure, which is a property of the experiencing
rather than of the objective world. But even if judgments about beauty are subjective, Kant does
also thing that they are stable and universal in a way that other pleasures are not. (pleasure felt
with beauty is different than with other pleasures of taste like our pleasure of taste involved in
consuming chocolate for example).

Kant's theory of beauty can be summarized in a sentence: A judgment of beauty is a


disinterested, universal, and necessary judgment concerning the pleasure which everyone ought to
derive from the experience of form. Disinterestedness—perceivers are indifferent to the real
existence of the object. The judgment of beauty is independent of the interest in real existence.
Interest in the object is a secondary and different kind of judgment.

All of these qualities are primarily involved with the experiencing subject. Kant asserts that
it is the recognition of the form of purpose which evokes the beauty experience. Only form is
beautiful. (the design of a painting or the compositional structure of a music piece—these are the
result of purposive activity of a human agent). The form of a work of art is the result of purposive
activity of a human agent.
Kant’s views can be understood as a link between 18 thcentury theories of taste and
19th century aesthetic theories. These 19th century aesthetic theories were totally subjectivized. An
object is beautiful because it is an object of our aesthetic contemplation. The significance of the
18th century for aesthetics can be summarized in the following way: Before the 18th century, beauty
was a central concept; during the century it was replaced by the concept of taste and finally by the
end of the century we open onto a concept of the aesthetic.

Other strain in the history of aesthetics—the philosophy of art. It was not until shortly
before the start of the 19th century, that the imitation theory of art found in Plato and Aristotle was
called into question. During the 19th century, the theory that art is the expression of the emotion of
the artist came to be the dominant view. The doctrines of the expression theory of art has its roots
in Kant’s theory of knowledge. This viewpoint was a reaction against empiricist philosophy and
an attempt to reach behind the sensuous screen of ordinary knowledge to something thought to be
vital and important. This generated a new role for the artists a new interest in artistic creation.

This new role of the artist is pointed up by the following passage from Nietzsche’s will to
power: Our aesthetics have hitherto been women’s aesthetics, inasmuch as they have only
formulated the experiences of what is beautiful, from the point of view of the receivers in art. In
the whole of philosophy hitherto the artist has been lacking.

The expression theory of art explains that art is the expression of the emotion of its creator.
This theory tries to show that art can also do something important for people. It attempts to related
art to the lives of people. And finally it attempts to account for the emotional qualities of art and
the way in which art moves people.

You might also like