Hardie - The Speech of Pythagoras in Ovid Metamorphoses 15
Hardie - The Speech of Pythagoras in Ovid Metamorphoses 15
Hardie - The Speech of Pythagoras in Ovid Metamorphoses 15
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to The Classical Quarterly.
http://www.jstor.org
Ovidians continue to be puzzled by the 404-line speech put into the mouth of
Pythagoras in book 15 of the Metamorphoses. Questions of literary decorum and
quality are insistently raised: how does the philosopher's popular science consort with
the predominantly mythological matter of the preceding fourteen books? Do
Pythagoras' revelations provide some kind of unifying ground, a 'key', for the endless
variety of the poem?' Can one take the Speech as a serious essay in philosophical
didactic, or is it all a mighty spoof, as intentionally laughable, perhaps, as the imperial
panegyric with which the narrative of book 15 concludes ? Or should we beware of
imposing modern tastes on Ovid's original audience, and respect the Hellenistic and
Roman predilection for scientific poetry? This article seeks to establish further
contexts for the evaluation of the Speech of Pythagoras through a study of Ovid's
allusive practice within the Greco-Roman tradition of hexameter epos. The figure
who provides a foundation for Ovid's construction of his own poetic genealogy turns
out to be the Greek philosophical poet Empedocles. The resulting reflections on
Ovid's manipulation of generic conventions may be timely in the light of the recent
appearance of sophisticated and fresh approaches to the question of whether the
Metamorphoses is, or is not, an epic.3
I. EMPEDOCLES IN OVID
In 1924 A. Rostagni attempted to reconstruct an esoteric Pythagorean Hieros Logos.4
One of the chief witnesses in his case was Ovid's Pythagoras; Rostagni, arguing
against the theory that the Speech was derived mainly from Varro,5 pointed to the
6 Cf. W. Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (E. L. Miner, transl.,
Cambridge,MA, 1972),pp. 218-20. The parallelsbetweenEmpedoclesand the cosmogonyof
Met. 1, as well as the Speechof Pythagoras,werelistedby C. Pascal,GraeciaCapta(Florence,
1905), pp. 129-51; F. E. Robbins, CPh 8 (1913), 403-4 dismissed Pascal's Empedoclean
parallelson the groundsthat they were all mediatedthroughLucretius;this was excessively
sceptical,but the Lucretiancolouringis also important(seebelow).The Empedocleanparallels
in the Speechof Pythagorasare also discussedby E. Bignone,Empedocle(Turin,1916),p. 272;
R. Segl, Die Pythagorasrede im 15. Buch von Ovids Metamorphosen (diss. Salzburg, 1970); F.
della Corte, 'Gli Empedocleae Ovidio', Maia 37 (1985), 3-12 (who airs the possibilitythat
Sallustius'Empedocleawas an intermediarymodel for Ovid, but is otherwisesilent on the
relationof the Speechof Pythagorasto the Latinhexametertradition).
7 I list the Empedocleanparallels(varyingin their degree of closeness):Met. 15.60-64:
Emped.B 129 DK; 15.63-4: B 17.21; 15.75-6, 459-68: B 136, 137; 15.93: B 139.2 (cf. Od. 9.295);
15.96-103 (Golden Age): B 128; 15.102: B 130; 15.111-26: B 128.8; 15.143-52: cf. B 112;
15.153: cf. B 124; 15.192: cf. B 47; 15.239-51 (four elements): B 6.1; 15.252-8: B 8, 12, 17.6-13,
26.8-12; 15.340-55 (Etna): cf. B 52. Many of these parallels are discussed by F. B6mer, P.
Ovidius Naso. Metamorphosen Buch XIV-XV (Heidelberg, 1986): p. 323 for a list. The
Empedocleancolour is virtuallyabsent in the long section of admirandaand paradoxaat
259-452.
8 B6mer (n. 7), p. 271; B. Otis, Ovid as an Epic Poet (Cambridge, 19702), pp. 296-9.
9 CQ n.s. 37 (1987),24-50.
kaleidoscopic principle of imitation; but behind the plurality a unifying ground may
be found in the use of Empedocles to redefine the history of Latin epos, and to
establish Ovid's place at the culmination of that tradition.
In terms of the structure of the Metamorphoses the Speech of Pythagoras does two
things: firstly, it introduces a philosophical section at a climactic point of the
Metamorphoses, and secondly it associates that philosophical doctrine with material
on the history of Rome, preluding the Roman stories in the last part of 15. The
literary-historical reasons for this conjunction of philosophy and national history I
shall return to; here I make the point that the conjunction is very tidily catered for
by using the old, if apocryphal, story about the meeting between the south Italian
philosopher Pythagoras and Numa, the second king of Rome.1o That meeting is
emblematic of the encounter between Rome and Greece which forms one of the major
themes of the last book of the Metamorphoses, and of which we shall find another,
metapoetic, example in the adoption in Latin by Ennius of the Greek (Empedoclean)
hexameter tradition of didactic poetry.
We may assume that there will have been no central text ascribed to Pythagoras
that Ovid would automatically have turned to (and according to some ancient
testimonia Pythagoras like Socrates left no writings at all);" Empedocles' poem (or
poems) would be a most acceptable substitute given the belief, widespread in
antiquity, that Empedocles was a Pythagorean, or even a pupil of Pythagoras."'
As well as providing Pythagorean-type doctrines on metempsychosis and
vegetarianism, Empedocles also teaches that the universe is in a state of constant
change; here is another reason for his attraction as a model for Ovid. Ovid's central
statement of this idea at 15.252-8 is close to Empedoclean formulations, above all
fragment 8 (cf. also B12, 17.6-13, 26.8-12):"1
nec speciessua cuiquemanet,rerumquenouatrix
ex aliis alias reparatnaturafiguras,
nec peritin toto quicquam,mihi credite,mundo,
sed uariatfaciemquenouat, nasciqueuocatur
incipereesse aliud,quamquod fuit ante, morique
desinereillud idem.cum sint huc forsitanilla,
haec translatailluc, summatamenomnia constant.
'AAo8 rTOL 0qVCLOVSEVO6
?pEW" 'T&7VTWV
EUTrLV
Ov'qrrCV, otAoj/IoVOavr7oLo
otE rTS" TEAEUVr?,
d&AA&AdL
VLVOV TE LLyEVTWV
/LLS tE LdQAAaLt
q
EUL,0u 8'8T&L
'TOZC6VE1QL
oVO dvOpc*ToLuw.14
Empedocles taught that cosmic history was governed by the alternating sway of the
principles of Love and Strife, Love joining things together and Strife drawing them
apart; at one point in the cosmic cycle Empedocles claims that the earth brings forth
monsters with limbs joined at random, a bizarre picture that has an affinity with the
unpredictability of the Ovidian world of metamorphosis (B 61):
IToAAAcL
/LEVa4L'7TrpoUwcrcL KQl Qp41LUCTEpva 1%EULL,
3ovyEv?7&v8pd6rrpqJpa, r&8' •E'prraaLvavaTr-aELV
dvI3poOkn 17'aT-LV
/ovKpava,tEtLELY~ytVa aVIPC?JV
q
V?, yvlvLKOO/'1 UKLEPOL9 7 UK1~/.EVa (T7.
yvL'o.
15 See W. Spoerri, SpiithellenistischeBerichte iiber Welt, Kulturund G5tter (Basel, 1959), p. 50.
For other Empedoclean echoes in Apollonius see Livrea on 4.672-81; R. L. Hunter, Apollonius
of Rhodes. Argonautica Book III (Cambridge, 1989), index s.v. 'Empedocles'.
16 Pascal (n. 6), pp. 129ff.; L. Alfonsi, 'L'inquadramento filosofico delle Metamorfosi
ovidiane', in N. I. Herescu (ed.), Ovidiana(Paris, 1958), p. 266; see also n. 26 below. Spoerri (n.
15), pp. 37-8 is sceptical about the direct use of Empedocles in Met. 1.
17 op. cit., pp. 70ff.
18 G. F. Else, Aristotle's Poetics: The Argument(Cambridge, MA, 1957), pp. 50-52 reconciles
the two Aristotelian statements through the assertion that in the Poetics the main issue is
mimesis.
19 J. Longrigg, '"Ice of Bronze" (Lucretius 1.493)', CR 20 (1970), 8-9; I. Cazzaniga, 'Le
metafore enniane relative a cielo e stelle ed alcuni placita di tradizione Anassimeno-Empedoclea',
PP 26 (1971), 102-19, at 104 on caeli clipeus (see also Rostagni (n. 4), p. 289 n. 1).
20 Empedocles and Aeschylus: S. Goldhill, Language, Sexuality, Narrative (Cambridge,
1984), p. 121 n. 32; W. R6sler, Reflexe vorsokratischen Denkens bei Aischylos (Meisenheim,
1970); M. Griffith, The Authenticity of the Prometheus Bound (Cambridge, 1977), pp. 222-3;
Cazzaniga (n. 19), 111-17.
21 'Lukrez und Empedokles', Die Neue Rundschau
(1959), 656-86, at 685. Other discussions
of Lucretius' debt to Empedocles: F. Jobst, Ober das Verhiiltnis zwischen Lucretius und
Empedocles(diss. Munich, 1907); W. Kranz,' Lukrez und Empedokles', Philologus 96 (1943/4),
68-107; D. Furley, 'Variations on Themes from Empedocles in Lucretius' Proem', BICS 17
(1970), 55-64 (= Cosmic Problems, Cambridge, 1989, pp. 172-82); C. J. Castner 'De Rerum
Natura 5.101-3: Lucretius' Application of Empedoclean Language to Epicurean Doctrine',
Phoenix 41 (1987), 40-49; M. J. Edwards 'Lucretius, Empedocles and Epicurean Polemics',
Antike und Abendland35 (1989), 104-15; G. B. Conte, Generi e lettori (Milan, 1991), pp. 17-26;
D. N. Sedley, 'The Proems of Empedocles and Lucretius', GRBS 30 (1989), 269-96 (this
important, if speculative, article argues that the whole of Lucr. 1.1-145 closely reproduces the
structure of an Empedoclean proem; if this is true, the whole Empedoclean complex is also one
that lies close to the surface of the Ovidian Speech of Pythagoras); and cf. other works cited by
Dalzell in CW 67 (1973/4), 98-9, and W. J. Tatum, TAPhA 114 (1984), 178 n. 5.
22 For a list of Lucretian allusions see B6mer on Met. 15.6. In general on Ovid's imitation of
Lucretius see 0. S. Due, Changing Forms. Studies in the Metamorphoses of Ovid (Copenhagen,
1974), pp. 29-33.
23 On 'double allusion' see J. C. Mckeown, OvidAmores i. Text and Prolegomena (Liverpool,
1987), pp. 37-45. The phenomenon has come to the centre of recent criticism of Latin poetry;
cf. e.g. R. F. Thomas, HSCPh 90 (1986), 188-9, using the label 'window reference'.
24 Met. 15.60-68 'uir fuit hic, ortu Samius; sed fugerat una I et Samon et dominos odioque
tyrannidis exul I sponte erat; isque, licet caeli regione remotus, I mente deos adiit et, quae natura
negabat I uisibus humanis, oculis ea pectoris hausit. I cumque animo et uigili perspexerat omnia
cura, I in medium discenda dabat coetusque silentum I dictaque mirantum magni primordia
mundi I et rerum causas et, quid natura, docebat.' Emped. DK B 129 ?Iv8d TL 4 KELVOLULVLV7p
TTEptoULCa I 87)
El8W6,;O /L7KLTov7TpaLT'8ov 7TAofTov,
EIKT7)caTo I7TavToL'Ov 7EpaALUTQ co6C)v
7' &tur pavo I
Epy•,V dr7T7TTE I
yap TCamlUcv dpEaLTO r7TpaLrrl8EaaLV, pEL
0' I
yE 7TOv dvTWv
Lucr. 1.66-75
ITCVrwTv AEaGUEGKEV EKaGUTOV KaL 7E 8EK dLvOp07Wlrv Kal 7' ELKOULvalWVEEuv.
'primum Graius homo mortalis tollere contra I est oculos ausus primusque obsistere contra, I
quem neque fama deum nec fulmina nec minitanti I murmure compressit caelum, sed eo magis
acrem I irritat animi uirtutem, effringere ut arta I naturae primus portarum claustra cupiret. I
ergo uiuida uis animi peruicit, et extra I processit longe flammantia moenia mundi I atque omne
immensum peragrauit mente animoque, I unde refert nobis uictor quid possit oriri.' Empedocles'
wise man is most likely to be Pythagoras, as Porphyry claimed (cf. Burkert [n. 6], pp. 137-8).
Ovid's passage is closer to Empedocles than to Lucretius in the details of the opening 'uir fuit
hic', and in the notion of the mental 'seeing' of the master.
25 Emped. B 137/iopcfiv8' &AAad6av-ra TaTr'ipL'Aovvtiv dElpagIcodaE,Et EvXOdEVOg ya
p
Vr7TLOSo. 8' 9PEVTa I Ae 03V7TEs 6 8' aeEmvovTdOKAEC *oW andI a iv
O tIhactBEvov
pT,
tLEyatpoLat KaK.qV dAEyvaT-o ai-a. I e' a'st vtn
Ta-rip' •jAu v Kati I
rTaiseOvuixv
TrroppaLcaav)TE qt'Aa KaTa% aadpKagc•E8ovaLtv.Aesch. Ag. 228-37 t•rTEpa
8% KaltKiA7)8dva
iraTpo0tov
I rcrap' o68Esv ai) TIE EOEVTO ktLAdkaXOL ALTrd•
qOpcdauEv 8' dcolt
PLETEXdlavI 8KLavXqi-Xapag 7TQpOVEtovELOoI I7TE7TAoLTL f3paf3•g'I
7TraTQ7p vTEpOE flWpoLOV 7TcaVT%OV/j I
Aa3Edv aCdTLxaTdOS I TE KahAAL7Trpqpov 7rEpTrrE-IE v 1TrPOVW71T7
I Odyyov apatov OLKoto.LS... See
cvkaKal KaTcaaXE6V
Ep8TlvEmpedocles: The Extant
M. R. Wright, Fragments (New Haven and London, 1981), pp. 286-7.
Sedley (n. 21), 293, 295 argues that B 137 comes from the Empedoclean proem, and is the
structural model for the Lucretian sacrifice of Iphianassa. In Ovid's outburst against meat-
eating at Met. 15.88-90 'heu quantum scelus est in uiscera uiscera condi I congestoque auidum
29
P. R. Hardie, Virgil'sAeneid: CosmosandImperium(Oxford,1986),pp. 17-22.
3o Ennius and Empedocles:E. Norden, Enniusund Vergilius(Leipzig, 1915), pp. 10-18;
E. Bignone,'Ennioed Empedocle',RFIC57 (1929), 10-30;0. Skutsch,TheAnnalsof Quintus
Ennius(Oxford,1985),pp. 160, 164n. 18 (expressingsome scepticismabout Bignone'sclaim),
260, 394-7, 758.
31
On Ennian elements in the Met. see H. Hofmann, 'Ovids Metamorphoses.- Carmen
Perpetuum, Carmen Deductum', PLLS 5 (1986), 223-41, at 223-6.
32 But probablynot the story of the meetingof Numa and Pythagoras: cf. Skutsch(n. 30),
pp. 263-4.
33 See O. Skutsch,Studia Enniana (London,1968),pp. 24-7; id., Annals (n. 30), pp. 147-53.
34 Newman(n. 27), pp. 189-90 points out that the Ennianring that bindsMet. 1 and 15 is
reinforcedby the imitationof the Ennianconciliumdeorumin Met. 1.
3 In this respectthe Speechof Pythagorasmay be seen as a microcosmicrecapitulation
of the wholeof the Annals,as also of thewhole of the Met. in its spanof timefromthememory
of the GoldenAge (cf. 1.89-112)to prophecyof the greatnessof Rome.
36 For a discussionsee Hardie(n. 29), pp. 76-83.
7 See P. R. Hardie, The Epic Successors of Virgil (Cambridge, 1992), pp. 103-5.