The Role of Beliefs in The Practice of Teaching: Journal of Curriculum Studies
The Role of Beliefs in The Practice of Teaching: Journal of Curriculum Studies
Jan Nespor
Jan Nespor
University of Texas at Austin
It has become an accepted idea that teachers' ways of thinking and understanding are
vital components of their practice. This has spurred a considerable amount of
research on teacher decision-making and information processing.1 However, in spite
of arguments that people's 'beliefs' are important influences on the ways they
conceptualize tasks and learn from experience,2 relatively little attention has been
accorded to the structures and functions of teachers' beliefs about their roles, their
students, the subject matter areas they teach, and the schools they work in.
Moreover, the research that does exist on these issues has relied either on very broad
and inclusive concepts (e.g., the 'traditional/progressive' beliefs dichotomy)3 or on
descriptive frameworks closely bound to specific cases and of limited use for
generalization or comparison.4
We need a theoretically-grounded model of 'belief systems' that can serve as a
framework for systematic and comparative investigations. The present paper is a
preliminary (and admittedly incomplete) attempt to provide such a model. Rather
than enumerating or describing beliefs and attempting to correlate them to specific
behaviour patterns, the paper develops a conceptualization of beliefs grounded in
current research in cognitive psychology and cognitive science, and suggests several
key functions of beliefs in teachers' thinking. While primarily theoretical in nature,
the framework presented here is grounded in a body of field-based research on
teacher thinking, the Teacher Beliefs Study (TBS).5 AS this study will be referred to in
the course of the paper, its general outlines are described below.
The TBS followed eight teachers across the course of a semester, videotaping
their classrooms and using the videotapes to construct verbatim records of classroom
action. Two types of interviews were used to generate data on the teachers' beliefs.
First, four long, semi-structured, and wide ranging interviews (called 'repertory
grid' interviews)6 focused on the teachers' general principles and beliefs about
teaching, about their students, about student behaviour, and about the community
and organizational contexts in which they worked. Second, four subsequent
interviews focused on the teachers' explanations of their teaching practices. In these
'stimulated recall' interviews,7 teachers were shown videotapes of their classrooms
and asked to describe and comment on the on-going activity.8
Because these interviews were time-consuming both for teachers (who spent an
average of 20 hours talking to us) and researchers (who had to analyse thousands of
pages of interview data), there were only eight teachers in the sample (two each in
eighth-grade mathematics, eighth-grade English, eighth-grade American history,
and seventh-grade Texas history). All of the teachers had at least two years of
experience in the classroom (teachers in three schools were observed).9 Pseudonyms
are used throughout to refer to schools, communities, and teachers.
318 JOURNAL OF CURRICULUM STUDIES 1 9 : 4
The paper begins by delineating six structural features of beliefs that serve to
distinguish them from other forms of knowledge. The functions and uses of beliefs
are then examined.
Existential presumption
Alternativity
Abelson makes the point that beliefs often include representations of 'alternative
worlds' or 'alternative realities'.12 Extreme examples of this feature come easily to
mind (e.g., the social or cosmic orders envisioned by Utopian political or religious
movements), but it is also exemplified in many of our common beliefs about
everyday life. Several of the teachers in the study, for example, envisioned and tried
to establish instructional formats or systems of classroom relations of which they had
no direct experience or knowledge (nor were these based on abstract models they had
learned in their formal training).
To give one instance, an English teacher in the study, Ms Skylark, drew her
ideal of teaching from a model of what she had wanted classes to be like when she was
a child-friendly and fun. Although she worked to shape her class to that ideal, she
BELIEFS IN TEACHING 319
had never achieved it; nor had she experienced it as a child. Rather, this was a sort of
Utopian alternative to the sorts of classrooms she was familiar with: she would
sometimes explain her actions in the stimulated recall interviews by recalling
mortifying experiences as a student and expressing her desire to spare her students
such traumas.
Beliefs of this sort can be of great importance in the classroom. They are, in a
strict sense, overriding concerns, and any number of shortcomings and problems can
be justified in terms of their pursuit. Thus it was more important for Ms Skylark to
maintain a friendly and relaxed classroom environment-which for her meant
repeating and re-explaining assignments at length, and allowing students to initiate
digressive lines of action-than to finish an assignment: her classes almost always
ended with the lesson half-covered .Such beliefs are not amenable to falsification - or
even challenge — and failures to translate them into reality in no way diminish their
value.
In essence, then, 'alternativity' refers to conceptualizations of ideal situations
differing significantly from present realities. In this respect, beliefs serve as means of
defining goals and tasks, whereas knowledge systems come into play where goals and
the paths to their attainment are well-defined.13
Belief systems can be said to rely much more heavily on affective and evaluative
components than knowledge systems.14 In some respects, feelings, moods, and
subjective evaluations based on personal preferences seem to operate more or less
independently of other forms of cognition typically associated with knowledge
systems,15 though there is clearly a great deal of interaction between the systems.
Thus, knowledge of a domain can be conceptually distinguished from feelings about
that domain. One's knowledge of the rules of chess and various lines of play does not
depend upon whether one likes or dislikes chess, whether it excites or bores one,
whether one thinks it trivial and decadent or sublime and mystical (though these
attitudes and beliefs would be important influences on how or whether one acquired
such knowledge in the first place, and on how one might be inclined to use it).
Some of the influences of affect and evaluation on teaching are well documented:
much of the literature on teacher expectations, for example, concerns the conse-
quences of teachers' sometimes unrecognized feelings about students. A less obvious
arena in which affect is important is that of teachers' conceptions of subject matter.
The values placed on course content by the teachers in the TBS study often influenced
how they taught the content.
For example, three of the four history teachers felt that teaching the 'facts' and
details of history should not be a primary goal of their courses because, in their
evaluation, students could not be expected to remember such information for any
significant length of time: the content was 'short-term memory stuff as one teacher
put it. They also knew that the content would either never reappear in later grades (in
the case of Texas history) or would be thoroughly re-taught in high school history
classes (in the case of American history). Rather than focusing their energies on
imparting historical facts and details, then, the teachers developed other types of
teaching goals, which, in their view, might have some lasting impact on students: for
example, teaching students 'manners' and how to behave in the classroom, or
320 JOURNAL OF CURRICULUM STUDIES 1 9 : 4
Episodic storage
Non-consensuality
a consequence of the features described above. Simply put, it refers to the fact that
belief systems consist of propositions, concepts, arguments, or whatever that are
recognized — by those who hold them or by outsiders—as being in dispute or as in
principle disputable.
One might well ask how a situation of non-consensuality differs from a situation
in which people simply differ in the amount or quality of their knowledge about some
event or process. One way to answer this is to suggest that belief systems are less
malleable or dynamic than knowledge systems. Knowledge accumulates and
changes according to relatively well-established canons of argument.24 Beliefs, by
contrast, are relatively static (at least in terms of their core applications —see the
discussion of 'unboundedness' below). When beliefs change, it is more likely to be a
matter of a conversion or gestalt shift than the result of argumentation or a
marshalling of evidence. One can say, then, that part of the consensus characterizing
knowledge systems is a consensus about the ways in which knowledge can be
evaluated or judged. By contrast, much of the non-consensuality of beliefs derives
from a lack of agreement over how they are to be evaluated. As already suggested,
belief systems often include affective feelings and evaluations, vivid memories of
personal experiences, and assumptions about the existence of entities and alternative
worlds, all of which are simply not open to outside evaluation or critical examination
in the same sense that the components of knowledge systems are.
Unboundedness
Belief systems can be described as loosely-bounded systems with highly variable and
uncertain linkages to events, situations, and knowledge systems.25 In other words,
there are no clear logical rules for determining the relevance of beliefs to real-world
events and situations. Moreover, these linkages and definitions of relevance may well
be bound up with the personal, episodic, and emotional experiences of the believer.
One way of looking at this feature of belief systems is to say that beliefs have stable
core applications26 (a domain of events and situations to which they are consistently
held to be applicable-these could derive from the 'critical episodes' described above
in the discussion of the episodic underpinnings of beliefs) but that they can be
extended in radical and unpredictable ways to apply to very different types of
phenomena. Knowledge systems, by contrast, generally have relatively well-defined
domains of application, and can be expanded to encompass other phenomena only
through the application of strict rules of argument. What the concept of unbounded-
ness means, then, is that people read belief-based meanings into situations where
others would not see their relevance.
The preceding discussion raises the questions of why beliefs about teaching
with these structural characteristics exist and what role they play in teaching. The
research of the TBS suggests that beliefs and belief systems have two important uses
for teachers —(a) task definition and cognitive strategy selection; and (b) facilitation
of retrieval and reconstruction in memory processes-while serving the overall
function of allowing teachers to deal with ill-structured domains.
322 JOURNAL OF CURRICULUM STUDIES 1 9 : 4
Task definition
refer to the ways in which individuals with different resources and domain-specific
knowledge interpret the surface configurations of components in a well-defined
problem space. Experts, so to speak, perceive basic deep structures underlying a vast
range of possible surface structures. But the key here is that these individuals —
whether experts or novices —are dealing with a task environment where goals,
constraints, and operations are clearly defined. It is, for example, a question of
relative skill or knowledge in a known domain (e.g., chess) rather than a question of
trying to define the game being played, and to decide why one is playing it or what
kinds of consequences might stem from winning or losing. These latter issues are
those with which belief systems are concerned.
We can thus think of cognitive resources, metacognitive control strategies, and
belief systems as progressively more encompassing systems of thought. Task
environments are defined in terms of belief systems. Metacognitive strategies are
employed to select among the available cognitive resources to carry out the task.
(This is, of course, a simplification: there will almost certainly be some feedback and
interaction among the various levels of thought).
The importance of this point for understanding teaching and teacher education
has already been suggested: to understand teaching from teachers' perspectives we have
to understand the beliefs with which they define their work. Consider two of the history
teachers in the sample. One, Mr Larson, saw teaching mainly as a job, a form of
labour, a way of making a living. Ms Marsh, by contrast, looked at teaching as a sort
of moral mission to socialize children and better the community; money for her was
secondary.36 Teaching, in short, took on completely different meanings for these two
teachers, and failure to recognize this would vitiate any attempt to make sense of
what they did in the classroom or why they did it. Similarly, it would be difficult if
not impossible to teach teachers with such different orientations using the same
methods and expect similar results, or any results at all.
It can certainly be argued that teachers' beliefs play a major role in defining teaching
tasks and organizing the knowledge and information relevant to those tasks. But why •
should this be so? Why wouldn't research-based knowledge or academic theory serve
this purpose just as well? The answer suggested here is that the contexts and
environments within which teachers work, and many of the problems they
encounter, are ill-defined and deeply entangled, and that beliefs are peculiarly suited
for making sense of such contexts.
The terms 'ill-structured problems' and 'entangled domains' require- some expla-
nation. As Simon suggests, there is no precise boundary separating well-structured
and ill-structured problems.43 Instead, problems may be seen as fitting into a
continuum as they vary along the following dimensions.
First, problems differ according to the nature of their goals. Is there a precisely-
definable goal state? Is there a single goal or a set of related goals, or are there a variety
of inconsistent or unrelated goals? Are there criteria available for determining
whether and when a goal has been attained?
Second, how well defined is the 'technology' or set of procedures for attaining
the goal or goals? Can a set of actions be defined that will invariably lead to desired
consequences (or can a probability be assigned to the likelihood of the goal being
attained through a given course of action)? Can one determine, even in retrospect,
what course of action led to an observed outcome?
Third, ill-structured problems are problems that require people to go beyond
the information contained in the problem instruction and use background knowl-
edge or make guesses or assumptions in order to solve the problem. There are no
search strategies that allow one to identify the information relevant to the problem.44
Finally, in ill-structured problems, alternative courses of action at different
points of the problem-solving process are not clearly-defined: it is impossible to
BELIEFS IN TEACHING • 325
define or identify the complete range of optional courses of action at each point in the
process.45 Not only is the problem-solver uncertain of what should be done, he or
she is uncertain of what can be done.
The concept of an entangled domain has to do with instances or examples or
entities which can be identified by some criteria as belonging to a given domain, but
which at the same time do not all share some important sets of criteria and do not fall
into relationships of dominance and subsumption with each other. Thematic
features overlap only partially and incompletely across the domain.46
When people encounter entangled domains or ill-structured problems, many
standard cognitive processing strategies — for example, schema-abstraction or ana-
lytical reduction - are no longer viable.47 Instead, because one could never be sure
just what information would be needed to deal in an adaptive manner with such
domains, one would need to encode as much information as possible in as many ways
as possible. Such knowledge would take the form of rich, contextualized, highly
multivariate descriptions of large numbers of individual cases—knowledge that
could be examined and reexamined from many different perspectives.48 The
episodic cores of belief systems would seem to be good candidates for these types of
knowledge structures. Because belief systems are unbounded, these cases could be
mapped onto a vast range of new events or experiences. Because belief systems are
non-consensually held and often involve ideals of alternative arrangements of reality,
the mappings of these cases onto new settings would be relatively immune to easy
falsification or contradiction. Finally, the structural feature of existential presump-
tion would serve the function of importing stable and predictable contextual
characteristics into ill-defined settings (e.g., allowing the mathematics teachers
described earlier to interpret student actions across many classes or school contexts -
they would not have to invent new theories of student action each time the student
population changes).
The argument that teaching is ill-structured or entangled is by no means new.49
However, it should be stressed that some aspects of teaching in some situations may
be well defined. That much of a teacher's work outside the classroom (as a member of
the school organization or interacting with parents or community members) may be
ill-defined as well (obviously the type of school system a teacher works in, the type of
subject matter a teacher teaches, and the career path of the teacher has much to do
with whether and to what extent the teacher will experience teaching and schooling
as entangled or ill-defined).50
Implications
The model of beliefs presented here has a number of implications for our
understanding of teaching and teacher education. Most obviously, it suggests that if
we are interested in why teachers organize and run classrooms as they do we must pay
much more attention to the goals they pursue (which may be multiple, conflicting,
and not at all related to optimizing student learning) and to their subjective
interpretations of classroom processes. This applies not only to behaviourist-
326 JOURNAL OF CURRICULUM STUDIES 1 9 : 4
Acknowledgements
This study was supported by the US National Institute of Education under Grant
NIE-G-83-006, Research and Development Center for Teacher Education, Univer-
sity of Texas at Austin. The opinions expressed herein do not necessarily reflect the
position or policy of the National Institute of Education, and no official endorsement
by that office should be inferred.
References
1. CLARK, C. M., and PETERSON, P. (1986) Teachers' thought processes. In Wittrock, M. C. (ed.),
Handbook of Research on Teaching, 3rd edn (Macmillan, New York), pp. 255-296; SHAVELSON, R. J.,
and STERN, P. (1981) Research on teachers' pedagogical thoughts, judgments, decisions, and
behaviour. Review of Educational Research, 51 (4), pp. 455-498.
2. FENSTERMACHER, G. (1979) A philosophical consideration of recent research on teacher effectiveness.
In Shulman, L. S. (ed.), Review of Research in Education, vol. 6 (F. E. Peacock, Itasca, IL), pp. 157-
185; SCHOENFELD, A. (1983) Beyond the purely cognitive: belief systems, social cognitions, and
metacognitions as driving forces in intellectual performance. Cognitive Science, 7, pp. 329-363.
3. BORKO, H. (1978) An examination of some factors contributing to teachers' preinstructional
classroom organization and management problems. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the
American Educational Research Association. Toronto, Canada.
4. ELBAZ, F. (1983) Teacher Thinking: A study of practical knowledge (Nichols Publishing Company,
New York); JANESICK, V. (1977) An ethnographic study of a teacher's classroom perspective. Doctoral
dissertation, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI.
5. NESPOR, J. (1984) The interaction of school context and teachers' beliefs, R&D Rep. No. 8023,
Research and Development Center for Teacher Education, University of Texas, AustinTX,ERICED
260079; NESPOR, J., (1985) The role of beliefs in the practice of teaching: final report of the Teacher
Beliefs Study, R&D Rep. No. 8024. Research and Development Center for Teacher Education,
University of Texas, Austin, TX.
6. KELLY, G. A. (1955) The Psychology of Personal Constructs (W. W. Norton, New York).
7. KING, L. and TUCKWELL, N. (1983) Stimulated Recall Methodology. Issues in Educational Research
IX (The Western Australian Institute for Educational Research, Perth, WA).
8. NESPOR (1985), pp. 193-214 (see note 5).
9. NESPOR (1985), pp. 29-66 (see note 5).
10. Cf., ABELSON, R. (1979) Differences between belief systems and knowledge systems. Cognitive
Science, 3, pp. 355-366.
11. Ibid., p. 357.
12. Ibid., pp. 357-358.
13. Cf., ibid., pp. 357-358.
14. Ibid., p. 358.
15. ZAJONC, R. (1980) Feeling and thinking: preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist, 35,
pp. 151-175.
16. ABELSON (1979), pp. 358-359 (see note 10).
17. SCHANK, R. and ABELSON, R. (1977) Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding: An Inquiry into Human
Knowledge Structures (Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ), p. 17.
18. See e.g., TULVING, E. (1983) Elements of Episodic Memory (Oxford University Press, New York).
19. SCHANK and ABELSON (1977) (see note 17).
20. AYEROFF, F. and ABELSON, R. (1976) ESP and ESB: belief in personal success at mental telepathy.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 34, pp. 240-247; NISBETT, R., BORGIDA, E., CRANDALL,
R., and REED, H. (1976) Popular induction: information is not necessarily informative. In Carroll, J.
and Payne, J. (eds.), Cognitive and Social Behavior (Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ), pp. 113-134;
TVERSKY, A. and KAHNEMAN, D. (1973) Availability: a heuristic for judging frequency and
probability. Cognitive Psychology, 4, pp. 207-232.
21. LORTIE, D. (1975) Schoolteacher: A Sociological Study (University of Chicago Press, Chicago).
22. EDDY, E. (1969) Becoming a Teacher: The Passage to Professional Status (Teachers College Press, New
York).
23. NEWELL, A. (1969) Heuristic programming: ill-structured problems. In Aronofsky, J. (ed.), Progress
in Operations Research, vol. 3 (John Wiley, New York); SIMON, H. (1973) The structure of ill-
structured problems. Artificial Intelligence, 4, pp. 181-202.
328 BELIEFS IN TEACHING
24. TOULMIN, S. (1972) Human Understanding, vol. 1 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ); cf.
FEYERABEND, P. (1978) Against Method (Verso, London); KUHN, T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions (University of Chicago Press, Chicago).
25. ABELSON (1979), pp. 359-360 (see note 10).
26. STEGMULLER, W. (1976) The Structure and Dynamics of Theories (Springer, New York).
27. BEAUGRANDE, R. (1980) Text, Discourse and Process (Ablex, Norwood, NJ); SIMON, H. (1978)
Information-processing theory of human problem-solving. In Estes, W. (ed.), Handbook of Learning
and Cognitive Processes, vol. 5 (Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ), pp. 271-296.
28. COLE, M. and SCRIBNER, S. (1974) Culture and Thought (John Wiley, New York), p. 168; see also
NEISSER, U. (1976) General, academic, and artificial intelligence. In Resnick, L. (ed.), The Nature of
Intelligence. (Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum), p. 136.
29. SCHOENFELD, (1983), pp. 336-337 (see note 2).
30. SCHOENFELD (1983), pp. 330-337 (see note 2).
31. See discussions by BEAUGRANDE, R. (1981) Design criteria for process models of reading. Reading
Research Quarterly, 16 (2), pp. 261—315. MONSELL, S. (1981) Representations, processes, memory
mechanisms: the basic components of cognition. Journal of the American Society for Information
Science, 32 (5), pp. 357-363.
32. SCHOENFELD (1983), p. 331 (see note 2).
33. Ibid., pp. 332-333.
34. BROWN, A. (1980) Metacognitive development and reading. In Spiro, R., Bruce, B. and Brewer, W.
(eds.), Theoretical Issues in Reading Comprehension (Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ), pp. 453—454;
FLAVELL, J. (1976) Metacognitive aspects of problem-solving. In Resnick, L. (ed.), The Nature of
Intelligence. (Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ); SCHOENFELD (1983), pp. 333-335 (see note 2).
35. CHI, M., GLASER, R. and REES, E. (1981) Expertise in Problem-Solving (Learning Research and
Development Center, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh).
36. See NESPOR (1984) (see note 5).
37. SPIRO, R. (1982) Subjectivity and memory. In Le Ny, J.-F. and Kintsch, W. (eds.), Language and
Comprehension (North-Holland, New York), pp. 29-34.
38. Ibid., p. 31.
39. Ibid., p. 31.
40. Ibid., pp. 31-32.
41. See LOFTUS, E. F. (1979) Eyewitness Testimony. (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA); SPIRO,
R. (1977) Remembering information from text: the 'State of Schema' approach. In Anderson, R.,
Spiro, R. and Montague, W. (eds.), Schooling and the Acquisition of Knowledge (Lawrence Erlbaum,
Hillsdale, NJ), pp. 137-166.
42. SPIRO, (1982), p. 32 (see note 37).
43. SIMON (1978), p. 286 (see note 27).
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid.
46. SPIRO, R. and MYERS, A. (1984) Individual differences and underlying cognitive processes in reading.
In Pearson, P. D. (eds.), Handbook of Reading Research (Longman, New York), pp. 492-493.
47. See SPIRO and MYERS (1984), pp. 492-496 (see note 46).
48. Ibid.
49. GREENE, M. (1979) Teaching: the question of personal reality. In Lieberman, A. and Miller, L. (eds.),
Staff Development: New Demands, New Realities, New Perspectives (Teachers College Press, New
York), pp. 27-28; MARCH, J. and OLSEN, J. (eds.), (1976) Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations
(Universitetsforlaget, Bergen, Norway); WEICK, K. (1979) The Social Psychology of Organizing 2nd
edition (Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA).
50. NESPOR (1984, 1985) (see note 5).
51. E.g., SHAVELSON and STERN (1981), p. 471 (see note 1).
52. FENSTERMACHER (1979) (see note 2).
53. STEGMULLER (1976), pp. 196-202 (see note 26).
54. Ibid., p. 19.
55. See NESPOR (1984) (see note 5).