A Dialectic of Morals - Mortimer J. Adler
A Dialectic of Morals - Mortimer J. Adler
A Dialectic of Morals - Mortimer J. Adler
THE STUDENTS
WHO HAVE HELPED ME TO LEARN
DURING MY YEARS
OF TEACHING
A DIALECTIC OF MORALS
Towards the Foundations of Political Philosophy
2
by
Mortimer J. Adler
Associate Professor of the Philosophy of
Law at the University of Chicago
Table of Contents
Chapter I. Introduction: The Dialectical Task.........................8
Chapter II: Preference and Pleasure: Induction of a Principle
................................................................................................20
Chapter III: Pleasure and the Order of Goods........................38
Chapter IV: The Order of Goods and Happiness ...................54
Chapter V: Psychological Presuppositions: Limitations of the
Dialectic .................................................................................75
Chapter VI: Real vs. Apparent Goods: The Reality of Virtue.
................................................................................................80
Chapter VII: From Ethics to Politics: The Common Good and
Democracy ...........................................................................117
(2) The kinds of goods as means and ends, 85; primary and sec-
ondary objects of desire, 85; distinction between enjoyment and use,
86; distinction between extrinsic and intrinsic goods, in relation to the
traditional distinction between bonum utile and bonum honestum, 86;
happiness is strictly neither a bonum utile nor a bonum honestum, nei-
ther used nor enjoyed, 87; the problem of bodily goods in the Aristote-
lian tripartite classification of goods, 88; the problem of sensual pleas-
ure in the Thomistic tripartite classification of goods, 88; three sets of
criteria required for an adequate classification of goods, 89; using the-
se criteria, the adequate classification is fourfold, not tripartite, 89; re-
view of an earlier enumeration of five types of partial goods in the
light of this fourfold classification, 91; the problem of the goodness of
good habits and good acts, 91; solution of this problem in terms of
natural desire, 92; distinction between constitutive and functional
means, 93; distinction between universal and particular goods, be-
tween constitutive means-in-general and -in-particular, 95; generative
and productive means, 96; the fourfold classification of means and
ends in relation to one another, 97.
The reason for this is the failure to see precisely the way in
which modern culture imposes upon the philosopher a situation
analogous to, not the same as, the one in which Plato and Aristotle
did their work. It is not merely that the cultural aggrandizement of
the investigative or phenomenological sciences has gradually threat-
ened the very existence of philosophy and has progressively worked
to dispossess it of its ancient home; worse, and in consequence, the
prevalence of positivism today requires the philosopher to face an
audience radically skeptical of anything he may say, doubtful even
that he can say anything worth listening to at all.
There are many other topics which offer similar occasions for
dialectical work and, in every case, there is a parallelism between
the contemporary situation and that of fifth century Greece. Thus,
where the ancient sophists denied knowledge and said that every-
thing was a matter of opinion, the modern positivists deny that there
is any knowledge beyond or outside of the so-called positive scienc-
es, or, in other words, they say that philosophy is opinion. As, in the
ancient world, there were those who said that the truth was merely
what appeared to be the case, and hence relative to each individual,
so today there are similar relativists about truth. As then there were
those who denied any way of knowing except by the senses, so now
the intellect is denied as a distinct faculty of knowing. As among the
pre-Socratic physicists there were those who regarded the sensible
world as exclusively an affair of flux and becoming, in which there
were no enduring entities, such as substances, so those who regard
themselves as philosophical interpreters of modern physics also de-
ny substances, and view the sensible world as nothing but a process
of events.
The issue is quite clear. The dialectical task is set. It will not do
for the philosopher simply to reiterate their claims concerning the
universality of moral truths, the self-evidence or demonstrability of
the principles and conclusions of ethics and politics. Nor is it suffi-
cient for them to be passive in their defense of them, however will-
ing they may be to answer objections; for the moral skeptic, espe-
cially if he is a positivist, is not entirely wrong in charging that eve-
ry answer begs the ultimate question—the question whether any-
thing the philosopher says is more than opinion. In this situation,
philosophers must be aggressive. They must engage the moral skep-
tic on his own grounds. They must open their adversary’s mind to a
perception of the truth—if not to the whole truth, at least to certain
aspects of the truth which will function as seed to be cultivated. This
is what I mean by an inductive use of dialectic.
1a. (p. 11) In St. Thomas and the Gentiles, I wrote: “Far from making
every effort to join issue with those who differ from us, we have, in
my judgment, not even begun to make an effort properly directed
and properly proportionate to the task at hand. We have been loath
to absent ourselves from the felicity of moving further into the inte-
rior of philosophical thought, when there is pressing work to be
done on the border, the arduous and lowly work of the pioneer. The
borderland I speak of is marked by the issue between those who
hold, as we do, that philosophy is a field of knowledge in which
there can be perennial truth and those who deny it” (p. 20). In this
earlier work I tried to find a parallel for our task in the sort of dia-
lectical work St. Thomas did against the gentiles in the sphere of
faith. I now think a better parallel is to be found in the dialectic of
Plato and Aristotle against the sophists, because the ancient effort
was, and the modern effort must be, entirely within the sphere of
reason.
In saying that the modern effort must be entirely within the
sphere of reason, I am thinking of what I regard as the primary task
of philosophy in the contemporary world—to win respect for itself
in a culture that is predominantly positivist. I hope it will be under-
stood that this is not incompatible with the general notion of a char-
acteristically Christian philosophy—the work of reason elevated by
faith—for although faith seems to have been indispensable for the
mediaeval discovery of truths not known to the ancient pagans, the
truths, once discovered, are possessed by reason and can, therefore,
be made acceptable to the reason of modern pagans. For the most
part, Christian philosophy, because its truths are rational, can be
taught to pagans even though it could not have been initially devel-
oped by them. There is, however, one profound limitation on the
foregoing statement, which is crucially relevant to the present un-
dertaking, namely, the fact that Christian moral philosophy is not,
and cannot be, purely a possession of reason, because as practical
wisdom it is necessarily guided by faith and subalternated to moral
theology. (M. Maritain has completely analyzed this point in Sci-
ence and Wisdom, New York, 1940: Part II).
17
2. (p. 11) I am not forgetting that this process cannot occur, today, in
exactly the same mood or manner as in the Middle Ages. Since the
aim is certainly not just to repeat the mediaeval construction, we
must attempt further and more detailed analyses, and these must
take account of every genuine advance in knowledge, and every
sound critical insight, which the modern world has gained. We may
even find it necessary to tear down some parts of the mediaeval
building and to reconstruct it, in order to let modern light in, to ven-
tilate it properly and to make it truly habitable by a modern mind.
And in emphasizing here the demonstrative and expository character
of such constructive, or reconstructive, work, I do not mean to ex-
clude dialectical procedures entirely, for they are necessarily in-
volved. But the kind of dialectic by which a living Thomism contin-
ues to grow is mediaeval rather than Greek in type—that is, it is not
primary and inductive but secondary and auxiliary to the deeper
penetration of truths already known.
3. (p. 12) Here, too, there is a difference in the mood and manner in
which a similar task is undertaken; for whereas Aristotle was genu-
inely exploring the philosophical field by dialectical methods, and
discovering truths by inductive procedures, we are not learning the-
18
se elementary truths for the first time, but rather are trying to teach
them to a world which denies their possibility. We must, therefore,
use the dialectical method and the inductive procedure as instru-
ments of instruction rather than of discovery. It is highly probable,
of course, that what occurs as a discovery of truth for those whom
we try to teach may be more than a mere re-discovery for us, the
teachers. Since the cultural context of the modern world is different,
since the steps we must take in reaching the same truths are not pre-
cisely those which Aristotle took, the truths themselves may be seen
in a new light; and it is even possible that, as a result of such efforts,
new truths may be discovered.
4. (p. 14) It should be noted that what is being denied is not politics as
one of the social sciences, but politics as a branch of practical, or
moral philosophy.
6. (p. 15) Two other denials are implicit here: (1) the denial of a natural
moral law, in consequence of which morality becomes entirely con-
ventional; and (2) the denial that moral judgments are expressions
of reason, rather than of will or passion.
Let me add here that all the facts of cultural anthropology must be
admitted. The moral skeptic often supposes these facts to be abso-
lutely incompatible with the position that some moral judgments are
true for all people everywhere. But this is not the case. The truths of
moral philosophy, the principles of ethics and politics, do not re-
quire us to shut our eyes to any facts about human life and human
society. The precise relation between the universality and absolute-
ness of moral truth, on the one hand, and the diversity and relativity
of the mores, on the other hand will become apparent, I hope, in the
course of the dialectic.
10. (p. 16) The position of Thrasymachus in The Republic, and the
views attributed to Protagoras and other sophists, in the writings of
Plato and Aristotle, are perfect expressions of moral skepticism.
Although the thing we call “positivism” is typically modern, be-
cause it arises in modern times with the gradual distinction of sci-
ence from philosophy, there is a Greek analogue in so far as the
sophists were not total skeptics. All but the most extreme among
them, such as Cratylus, were willing to admit that we had
knowledge of the physical world; in fact, they used such knowledge
to make their point that in moral matters only opinions prevailed.
They were fond of saying that fire burns in the same way in both
Greece and Persia, both a hundred years ago and today, but the laws
of Greece and Persia are not the same nor are the customs of antiq-
uity and of the present. Of nature, because it is nature and has a per-
sistent uniformity independent of human will, there can be
knowledge, but there can be only opinions on moral matters, be-
cause they are not natural, because they are entirely conventional,
entirely dependent on human institution, entirely expressions of
will. The sophists knew a great deal about the variety of customs;
obviously impressed by the relativity of mores, they made the same
false supposition that is made today, namely, the incompatibility of
such facts with the possibility of universal moral principles.
Finally, it can even be said that the sophists’ view of human nature,
without benefit of experimental research or clinical investigation,
emphasized, as does our current scientific psychology, the will or
passions, rather than the reason, and made the sensitive faculty the
primary, if not the exclusive, principle of human knowledge. The
20
main points of this analogy between the ancient sophists and the
contemporary moral skeptics is confirmed, from the other side, by
the late Professor F. C. S. Schiller, the follower of William James
and John Dewey who, more explicitly than they, avowed the moral
skepticism which is implicit in pragmatism. cf. his essay, “From
Plato to Protagoras” in which Schiller sides with Protagoras (in
Studies in Humanism, N. Y., 1907: Ch. II).
11. I should like to observe here that the fact of preference plays a role in
the dialectic of morals like the role played by the fact of change in the dia-
lectic of substance. If anyone persist in denying the existence of change, it
will be impossible, I think, to induce that person to see the necessity for
there being a multiplicity of individual substances. So, too, if anyone really
persist in denying that people exercise preferences, it will be impossible to
carry him or her any distance at all into the field of morals.
But a student may object, of course, that he does not know what
“better-than” means; he has admitted the fact of preference, but he
has not admitted that there is anything really good and bad, or better
and worse. If “better-than” means no more than “preferred-by-me,”
says the student, then the equivalence of the fact of preference with
the judgment of better-than can be conceded; but not otherwise.
At this point let us focus the whole issue on the fact of prefer-
ence. Let us consider two people, X and Y, both of whom, as a mat-
ter of fact, prefer A to B. Let X be a moral skeptic, such as the stu-
dent is, who claims that in expressing this preference he is express-
ing nothing more than his private opinion; X, furthermore, denies
that there are any principles behind this judgment of preference
which might lead any other person, in the same situation, to judge in
the same way. And, for the sake of contrast, let Y be a moralist who
claims that his reasons for preferring A to B include universally val-
id principles which set up an order of goods, of things as better and
worse, for any person at any time and place.
Now it will be observed that the two people, X and Y, agree up-
on the fact of preference, though they disagree in the explanation
they give in answer to the question, Why do you prefer A to B? We
have not yet heard the moral skeptic’s explanation of his preference,
but we know it must be different from the moralist’s. It should be
noted, moreover, that it makes no difference whether X and Y both
22
prefer A to B, or whether they make opposite choices here, for in
either case the fact of preference remains to be explained, and it is
the difference in the explanations which matters. Let there be no
doubt on this point, for if the explanation given by the moral skeptic
is not radically and irreducibly different from the explanation given
by the moralist, there is no issue.
If, now, we ask the student why he likes A, why it pleases him,
he may protest the question. There is no why for liking. The feeling
of pleasure is an immediate experience which determines prefer-
ence, and that is all there is to it. The student may even tell us that
we have no right to ask why, for the very question implies that there
are reasons; whereas he has already told us there are none unless the
feeling of pleasure itself be called a “reason” for preference. If we
wish to use the word “reason” that way, then pleasure and displeas-
ure, he reiterates, are the only reasons for preference.
But there is still some room for inquiry about these feelings of
pleasure and displeasure. We admit that there is no problem if A
pleases and B displeases. In this simple case, the principle of prefer-
ence is clear: pleasure is preferred to displeasure. And no further
explanation need be given of this principle, for we can agree with
the student that it is a principle of animal conduct: animals embrace
what they like, and avoid what they dislike. That can be taken as a
scientific fact. And although with some of the lower animals their
likes and dislikes are instinctive (and so common to all members of
the species), in the case of humankind, instinct is either weak or
non-existent, and human likes and dislikes are matters of individual
conditioning. Hence, we cannot as a matter of scientific knowledge
declare what all people will like or dislike. Therefore, on moral mat-
ters there is only opinion.
24
All cases are not, however, so simple. We must ask the student
to consider a situation in which he has often found himself; he likes
both A and B. Whereas in the simple case first given, B was posi-
tively displeasing, here B is pleasing. Now what is the principle of
preference? The student will answer, as it seems he must, that in this
case he prefers A because A is more pleasing—he likes A more than
B.
Would any other person make the same judgment? we ask. Yes,
says the student, faced by a choice between more and less pleas-
ure—whether the greater quantity be simply the greater intensity of
one pleasure over another, or the summation of two pleasures which
exceeds a single pleasure—any person would prefer more or less. Is
this, we ask, a matter of human instinct or of human reason? Why is
more of what we like better than less? The student replies that he
doesn’t know whether it is instinct or reason, but that it makes no
difference. Animals not only seek pleasure and avoid displeasure,
but they also prefer more pleasure to less. This is simply the fact,
and it applies to human beings as well as other animals. It is an ul-
timate fact, about which no further whys can be asked.
Not so fast, says the student. Either you did not need the criteri-
on of quantity to make this point, or I do not understand its signifi-
cance. You could have made the same point, he goes on to explain,
in terms of pleasure and displeasure. For if A stands for “source of
pleasure” and B for “source of displeasure,” then the words “for
me” can also be omitted from the statement that A is better than B.
By such objections, the student has brought the issue into clear-
er focus. He has raised two questions, not one, and these must be
separated. The first has to do with the point about the violability of
moral rules. In a sense he is right that an inviolable moral rule is not
28
a statement of what should be done, but of what in fact is the case
about the nature of human conduct. There must be some distinction,
he rightly insists, between moral and natural necessity, between a
moral statement and one made by the psychologist as a descriptive
scientist. The second question concerns the subjectivity of any actu-
al preference; and here again the student is right if the preference is
solely determined by how he feels about A and B. Even if the judg-
ment, that people should always prefer a greater good, were truly a
moral rule, because violable, it would have no significance practi-
cally if, as between A and B, preference were entirely determined
by how an individual felt about A and B, which he liked more, for
example. Let us consider these two points in order.
Will the student deny that a person who made such calculations
as these might sometimes violate the universal rule, and choose the
lesser pleasure? The student will undoubtedly admit that he has
made such a foolish choice himself; he will remember moments of
repentance for having made the wrong choice, moments of resolu-
tion not to be so foolish again. But wherein lies the folly, unless it is
wisdom to follow a true rule of conduct? And how could one ever
repent, in cases of this sort, if the rule we have stated is strictly invi-
olable?
Shall we not, therefore, now ask the student to admit that by his
own criterion of preference we have formulated a universally true
rule of conduct, true for any person and yet also frequently violated?
The student may still demur, saying that at the time of the choice,
the lesser pleasure actually seemed the greater; and that repentance,
with its recognition of folly, occurred at a later time when a more
accurate calculation of the opposed pleasures was made. Thus, he
may continue, it remains true as a matter of fact that people always
prefer what at the time appears to them to be the greater pleasure,
although the apparently greater may not be really so.
Much that the student has said is right, and yet his conclusion is
wrong. Let us concede at once that, so far as our discussion has
gone, all particular moral judgments, which express an individual’s
preference for A over B because more pleasing to him or her in the
light of all calculable circumstances, are subjective, are opinions
true for that individual only at the time they are made. Let us, fur-
thermore, admit that such particular judgments are the most practi-
cal in the sense that they directly determine a choice and ensuing
conduct. But instead of saying that they are the only really practical
judgments, and that universal judgments are not practical at all, let
us see if we can show the student that the universal judgments are
also practical, though in a sense not so obviously or directly.
33
Here are two people, facing the same alternatives under the
same circumstances. The two people differ as individuals in many
ways, and so whereas one likes this A better than this B, the other
likes this B better than this A. Now suppose the situation to be com-
plicated by the fact that both A and B involve future as well as pre-
sent pleasures. What, then, does it mean to say that A is liked better
than B, or B better than A? It must mean that each person, according
to his or her individual nature, has made a different calculation here
of which is the greater-good-for-him-or-her. But, as we have already
seen, a person can act contrary to such a calculation, and in so doing
violate the universal moral rule that the greater good should be cho-
sen. Hence, there are the following possibilities: (1) if both people
violate the universal moral rule, it can be truly said that each should
have made the opposite choice; (2) if the first person obeys the uni-
versal rule, and the second transgresses it, then it can be said that the
second person’s judgment is wrong, even though it now will agree
with the first person’s. The first person’s judgment is not right be-
cause this A in fact gives a greater pleasure than this B to anyone;
on the contrary, this B gives a greater pleasure to the second person;
so that if the second person had acted wisely in his or her own be-
half he or she should have chosen B rather than A.
But, the student persists, how does the universal judgment have
any practical bearing? The question can be answered in two ways.
The first is difficult to imagine, though possible: the case of a per-
son who actually was in error about the universal principle, who
somehow thought that the greater pleasure ought not to be preferred.
34
Such a person, however accurately they calculated their present and
future pleasures in any particular situation, would, if they put their
universal and their particular judgment together into practice, make
a choice which could be called wrong—and objectively so, in the
sense that it was not only wrong for them, but wrong for any person,
because their error lay in an erroneous general principle.
If that is so, the student then asks, why did you admit earlier in
this discussion that one person can prefer this A to this B, and an-
other prefer this B to this A, and both be quite right? Was not that
admission tantamount to conceding the subjectivity of actual prefer-
ences? Again, we must repeat that actual preferences, expressed in
the particular judgments which immediately precede action, are sub-
jective in the sense indicated, namely, that two people can make
opposite judgments in the same situation and still both be right. The
only point the student failed to see, when he asked the question, was
that these opposite judgments are not entirely subjective, for both
can be wrong if both were reached in the wrong way, i.e., in reliance
upon a false universal rule, or in violation of a true one, through
miscalculation or willful transgression.
With both errors removed, what can teacher and student (or
moralist and moral skeptic) now positively agree upon? If they will
examine together the two truths, stated above as corrections of the
two extreme errors, they will find an explanation for these truths.
On the one hand, the reason why two people can make opposite
preferences in the same situation, and both be wrong, is that each
can violate in his or her own way a rule that is equally obligatory on
both. That there can be any universal moral truths at all, such as the
rule for always preferring the greater pleasure, arises from the fact
that, in so far as they are human, all people are the same, at any time
or place.
On the other hand, the reason why two people can make oppo-
site preferences in the same situation, and both be right, is that both
36
are not simply human beings, for each is a uniquely differing indi-
vidual person, whose individual nature, constituted by the accidents
of birth, biography, and environment, belongs to him or her alone.
That two people, both adhering to the same universal moral rules
and following them equally well, should be able to reach different
conclusions arises from the fact that they differ as individuals; and
the rightness of their opposite conclusions is a rightness relative to
their individual natures.
One thing the student says is false, but one thing is true. The
falsity arises from his failure to remember that something was
gained by introducing the notion of pleasure into our discussion.
That, with the addition of considerations about quantity of pleasure,
enabled us to formulate a universal rule of conduct, which he him-
self admitted should direct people’s choices, though in fact people
do not always choose as they should, according to this rule. This
very discrepancy, between what should be and what is, certified the
character of the rule we formulated as moral rather than descriptive.
There are three terms, then, which any careful analysis of pref-
erence must distinguish. They are irreducible to one another. And it
is in the light of this fundamental distinction that the student can be
made to see the difference between saying “A is a pleasure” and “A
is pleasing.” The latter statement means that A is pleasurable or a
source of pleasure. The former statement means that A is itself iden-
tical with pleasure. But if A is both, then we are saying that that
which is itself pleasure is a source of pleasure. If A is not both, then
we must decide which A is, and upon this decision will depend
whether we regard pleasure as the object of desire, or as the satisfac-
tion which results from attaining the object of desire, for the object
of desire is, when possessed, the source of satisfaction.
But, says the student, why cannot pleasure be both object and
satisfaction? And even if we decided that pleasure was always one
and not the other, what difference would it make?
But, says the student, I still don’t see why pleasure cannot be
the object of desire, as well as its satisfaction. I see nothing wrong
in saying that I desire or like pleasure and that pleasure pleases me.
Before you go on to any further explanations, I’d like this point
cleared up.
If the only rule of conduct were the one we have so far formu-
lated, the student would be right, for the most part, in maintaining
his moral relativism, and his skepticism about moral knowledge;
different people might abide by this one rule and yet in every partic-
ular seek different things or make different choices. So far as this
rule goes, it does not prevent us from supposing that one person
could maximize pleasure by a set of actual choices quite different
from those made by another person following the same rule; one
person might always prefer wealth to sensual pleasure and honor,
and another always prefer virtue to fame and fortune, and yet it
would be conceivable that both could maximize pleasure in the
sense of satisfying their differently oriented desires. When we say
that pleasure is insufficient to explain preference, we mean, of
course, not merely that it is insufficient to describe the fact of pref-
erence, but more fundamentally that, unless we go beyond pleasure,
we can never say, of two objects different in kind, which should be
preferred. Failing to do this, we fail to establish a practically signifi-
cant body of moral rules, both universally valid and also violable.
Unless we can correct two errors which the student has made,
we are barred from proceeding. The first may have been a slip of the
tongue. The student spoke of “people’s desiring as much satisfac-
tion as they can get.” This statement seems to regard satisfaction as
an object of desire, which is strictly impossible. If satisfaction were
an object of desire, then satisfaction would result from fulfilling
such desire, but the resultant satisfaction could not be the same as
the satisfaction which, being desired and then possessed, gave rise
to it. And there would be nothing to prevent the second satisfaction
from being in turn an object of desire, thus giving rise to a third sat-
isfaction in the same way, and so on in an endless progression. To
make satisfaction an object of desire is, paradoxically, to condemn
desire to endless dissatisfaction. Satisfaction, then, can never be an
object of desire; nor can it ever explain why we desire one object
rather than another, since given the desire for either object, its pos-
session produces satisfaction.
The student’s second error was his failure to note that our dis-
cussion has expanded to take in two new factors, namely, objects of
desire other than sensual pleasure and pain, and a variety of desires
of different strength. Pleasure is no longer the only criterion of pref-
erence; in fact, as object, it is only one among many things to be
chosen; and as satisfaction, it is entirely insufficient as a criterion,
since what will satisfy us depends upon our desires.
To make this clear, let us now introduce the word “good” to
name any object of desire. The relation between good and pleasure
is at once clear: sensual pleasure is a good, but not the only one; and
every good is a source of pleasure in the sense of satisfying a desire
when possessed. Hence, the earlier formula, that A is preferable to B
47
whenever A is more pleasurable than B, must now be restated as
follows: treating A and B as goods, both of which are desired, A is
the greater good, and hence preferred, whenever the desire for A is
greater than the desire for B. In short, the good is the desirable, and
the better of two goods is the more desirable.
No, says the student, your last way of putting the matter is mis-
leading. You have made it sound as if one object were in fact better
than another, and your desire was determined accordingly; whereas
so far as you have been able to show, one object is better than an-
other only in so far as it is the object of a stronger desire. Thus you
have not escaped the criterion of pleasure, since the preferred object,
as the object of the stronger desire, is always the more pleasurable.
Unless you can explain why all people should desire one object
more strongly than another, you cannot avoid subjectivity and rela-
tivism. And how will you be able to show what people should desire
and what they should prefer, unless you can show that the objects
themselves are intrinsically good and bad, better and worse?
Yes, says the student, people do in fact seem to desire all these
objects, and I will admit that it is possible to divide them into the
groups you have named. But I am not sure I understand why there is
this variety of goods; or to put my question another way, is there
any reason why this variety is the same for all people? Unless it is,
you are not going to be able to show that all people should exercise
the same preferences in choosing among goods of these various
sorts. And even if it is, an objective ordering of these goods still
remains to be shown, for people do in fact seem to make quite dif-
ferent choices—some people desire health and knowledge for the
50
sake of wealth and power; others desire wealth for the sake of sen-
sual pleasure and fame; and there may even be some who desire
wealth and the social goods for the sake of habits and efficient activ-
ity.
One thing at a time. Let us first explain to the student why some
such variety of goods is the same for all people. The first part of the
answer should be obvious at once. As human beings, having human
nature, all people are the same, even though they differ in many
subordinate ways as individuals. The deeper question, however, is
why there is a variety of goods, not why it is the same for all people.
If the good is simply any object—whether an external thing or an
aspect of human nature itself—which a person desires, then the plu-
rality of diverse objects, which we have classified as a variety of
goods, must be due to a plurality of diverse desires. What the stu-
dent really wants to know is why all people should have the same
set of desires. We cannot rely upon the fact that all people do have
the same plurality of desires, for the fact may be questionable, and
even if it is not, the student is justified in asking why he, for one,
should not make an exception of himself and limit his desires to
fewer objects. If there is no reason why he should not do this, then
regardless of the facts about what most people desire, the variety of
goods is a subjective, not an objective, enumeration.
Yes, says the student, I’ll admit that fact. Even if there were ex-
ceptions, it would certainly be true that a person who does not desire
to live desires nothing else, and for him or her there is no further
problem.
Will you admit one further thing? we must ask. Will you admit
that all people desire to live well, or as well as possible?
51
Yes again, says the student, although I am not sure I know what
is meant by “living well” nor do I think that all people would agree
about what living well consisted in. I’ll say Yes, therefore, if all you
mean is that every person wants as much satisfaction as he or she
can get. To say this is to say no more than what we have already
agreed upon—that every person wishes to maximize pleasure, or, in
our new terms, every person seeks the utmost satisfaction of which
he or she is capable.
I may have helped you make all these points by mentioning ca-
pacity, the student says, but you have gone much further than I can
follow. I am not quarreling with your point of view that, in general,
human capacities are the same—so far as they are rooted in a human
nature which is the same. But, remember, I did not agree that all
people meant the same thing by such words as “living well.” Even if
the variety of goods is the same for all people in some sense, the
fact remains that different people place different values on the vari-
ous goods; and although you may have shown that all people should
desire them, you have not shown that all people should concur in
desiring them in the same way—with the same emphasis, to the
same extent, in the same order. And you must show this, since you
have to admit the contrary fact—namely that people do in fact differ
in the way they exercise desire with respect to the same variety of
goods. My guess is that they differ because they mean quite differ-
ent things when they all admit they want to live well. Furthermore,
if the various goods we have been talking about are objects we
should desire because they are indispensable means to the end we
do desire, they why should we desire the end itself? If you tell me
that there is no point to this question, and we can rest in the fact that
we do desire something as an end, then I say, in terms of all your
reasoning so far, that the end is not desired because it is good, but
rather good only because it is desired. Unless you can show it is good
apart from being actually desired, you cannot show that people should
desire it.
But, as the student rightly points out, three questions remain. (1)
Why should any end be desired, simply as an end and not as a
means? (2) Why should all people desire the same end, not only
verbally named in the same way, by such a phrase as “living well,”
but really understood in the same way. (3) Why should all people
desire the means (consisting of whatever kinds of goods should be
desired for the sake of the end) in the same way—i.e., in the same
order, with the same emphasis upon each kind, etc.?
The first question to answer is the one about the end. Beginning
with the fact of preference, our discussion began with a considera-
tion of means—alternative goods between which choice must be
exercised. But now we see that we cannot solve the problem of any
preference unless we first solve the problem of the ultimate criterion
of all preferences, namely, the end, which is itself never preferred,
because it is not a good, opposed by alternative goods, but the good,
having no alternatives. It is necessary, therefore, to make another
fresh start.
54
“I suppose so”, the student will probably say, “but I don’t see
why.”
The reason is not hard to find. You admit that whatever is de-
sired as a means is sought for the sake of its end, and unless the end
is desired, whatever may be a means to it is not desirable. Now alt-
hough an end is the last thing we actually achieve in the course of
our conduct (for if an end could be achieved before some of its
means, those means would be utterly dispensable), the end must be
the first thing we actually desire, for unless we desire the end, we
have no reason for desiring things which are good only as means to
it. Hence if every good which we regard as an end could also be re-
55
garded as a means to some further end, and so on indefinitely, there
would be no beginning. Just as you cannot begin to walk in a defi-
nite direction unless you know where you are going before you
start, so you cannot desire anything all as a means unless you desire
something simply as an end.
“You are going too fast for me”, the student confesses. “I am
particularly bothered by two things. One is that you seem to be as-
suming that all the partial goods are always compatible with one
another, so that it is always possible for a person to have all of them.
The other is that you seem to be reverting to an earlier position, or
even worse than that, you seem to be saying the opposite of what
you said before. You said before that satisfaction cannot be an ob-
ject of desire, and yet now you seem to be saying that X must be
taken as the end, rather than A or B, because it is more satisfying
than they are. Furthermore, if the totality of goods is always the end,
then it is silly to say that people should seek to achieve this totality,
since they cannot seek otherwise. In fact, I don’t see that we are say-
ing now any more than we said before when we said that a person
57
should seek to maximize pleasure, or satisfaction—only it now ap-
pears there is no should about it.”
Let us meet the student’s first point by reminding him how the
diversity of partial goods is generated. There are many different
kinds of good because human beings have different capacities to be
fulfilled. Now, of course, it is possible for human capacities to be so
related that any attempt to fulfill one would necessarily interfere
with the fulfillment of one or more of the others. But that, as a mat-
ter of fact, does not seem to be the case. In the light of the facts
about human nature, we can say, then, that so long as the variety of
goods corresponds somehow to the diversity in human capacities,
this variety will include no incompatible partial goods. Hence, a
variety so constituted can always be summated in a totality. If A, B,
C, D . . . . N represents an exhaustive enumeration of partial goods,
each can be a part of the totality, X, for they can be taken together
as means to constitute that whole.
“I am still not sure I understand what you are driving at”, says
the student. “For one thing, what makes you think it is possible for a
person to get all good things? Everyone may want as much pleasure
as possible, but unless as much as possible can really be obtained, I
don’t see that the end you have envisaged is any better than the pot
of gold at the end of the rainbow. You’ll have to show the man from
Missouri how he can get all good things. And, in the second place,
the rule which directs a person to seek the end, as you have defined
it, no longer seems to be a moral rule by your own criterion, for it is
obviously inviolable. A person could not seek anything else. You
have really admitted what I have always suspected—that it is a nat-
ural law, not a moral law, of human nature, for people to try to get
as much as they can. You have simply described human behavior,
and so far as I can see it is no different from animal behavior.”
“The reasoning is all right”, says the student. “It should have
been obvious to me, I suppose, that if you could prove there is only
one end for each person, you could also show that the end is the
same for every person, for in both cases the reasoning depends on
human nature. But the joke is on you, because you have now
strengthened my point that the end as you have defined it simply
61
describes what in fact everyone seeks. If there is any truth in what
you have been saying, it is a psychological truth, not a moral truth.
Remember that you yourself told me that a moral rule had to be vio-
lable. Well, if you were to phrase a rule about the end—such as,
Seek all good things—it couldn’t be violated.”
Some time back the student admitted that all people desire to
live. (Those who do not have no moral problems!) He was even
willing to say that all people desire to live well, though he added the
qualification that what one person meant by “living well” might dif-
fer considerably from what another meant. He should now be pre-
pared, however, to relax that qualification somewhat; for if the
words “living well” name the end which all people seek, and be un-
derstood as equivalent to “a life enriched by the possession of all
good things,” then it would appear that, in one sense at least, all
people must agree about what they mean by “living well.” Let us
call the sense in which all people agree about the end a formal con-
ception of it. All people subscribe to the same formula: a totality of
diverse goods, a maximum of diverse satisfactions. But the student
would be quite right in insisting that, though people may not differ
about this formula, they appear to differ considerably about how
they interpret it. Far from disputing with the student on this point,
we, too, insist upon it, because herein lies the clue to the violable,
hence moral, character of the first principle—the rule about the end.
62
To carry the analysis further, it might prove useful here to intro-
duce a new term—happiness. The way in which people ordinarily
use the word “happiness” justifies us in identifying happiness with
the end. They regard happiness as something desirable entirely for
its own sake. No one would ever speak of wanting happiness for the
sake of obtaining some further or other good. The happy person is
one who wants for nothing more. Hence it is clear that happiness is
not a good; it is not even accurate to speak of it as “the highest
good” if such words signify that happiness is one good among oth-
ers, albeit the greatest. Happiness is the same as what we have
called the good, the supreme good; but it is summum bonum only in
the sense of being the totality or sum of every kind of good [totum
bonum]. Furthermore, we can identify happiness with living well, or
with a good human life, since the formula is the same in both cases.
The relation between happiness and pleasure is also clear: surely
happiness is not the same as sensual pleasure, which is merely one
kind of good; nor is happiness, considered objectively, the same as
pleasure in the sense of satisfaction; but when we consider happi-
ness, or the end, subjectively, it can be understood in terms of
pleasure, for in possessing all good things the happy person enjoys
every sort of satisfaction and in this sense has maximized pleasure.
“Yes”, says the student, “your language says what I mean. But I
don’t see how this is going to show the natural law of human behav-
ior to be a moral rule—a rule (about the end) which is violable.”
We are now prepared to show the student that. Only one new
point needs to be added. Considered materially, there are many dif-
ferent conceptions of happiness. The differences are, for the most
part, with respect to the order of goods—one person emphasizing
wealth, let us say, another friendship, another knowledge, and so
forth. There may be differences in the listing of the goods; though
this is less frequently the case, some people have omitted sensual
pleasure as a good, others have omitted the social goods, and some
have even omitted knowledge and what has been called “moral vir-
tue.” Now the new point we must add (and prove) is simply this:
that among all the different conceptions of happiness which people
have recorded, there is only one right conception, in material detail,
of the variety and order of goods. If a person seeks anything other
than happiness as rightly constituted, the person is not really seeking
happiness at all, but a false or illusory version of it, even though the
wrong thing is sought as the person’s ultimate end because the per-
son conceives it under the same formula.
Let us call the end as rightly conceived the real good; let us call
the end as wrongly conceived the apparent good. Using words this
way, we can see that if the rule about the end is expressed by “Seek
the good, real or apparent,” then it cannot be violated, for it is simp-
ly a natural law, a description of how human beings must in fact
behave—and being a description it is incorrectly expressed as a pre-
scription, in the imperative mood rather than the declarative. But if
the rule is expressed by “Seek the real good,” then it is violated by
every human being who wrongly conceives his or her end, and we
have a moral law, truly prescriptive, saying what human beings
should seek. The same thing can be said in terms of happiness:
“Seek happiness properly constituted by a correct enumeration and a
right ordering of goods” can be violated in many ways; but “Seek
happiness as any collection of goods in any order” cannot be violat-
64
ed at all. In short, if materially there is one right, and many wrong,
conceptions of happiness, the fact that all people seek the same end
formally does not mean there is no violable rule about the end. On
the contrary, there is a rule the violation of which leads away from
rather than toward real happiness.
Now, in the first place, let us remember that all good things
does not mean every particular good, but only some of every kind of
good. If this were not so, it would take an infinitely long life to get
all good things, and, furthermore, the pursuit of happiness would be
competitive—as is the attempt to corner the market and possess eve-
ry piece of a certain commodity. But this is not the case; however
much in fact they do, people need not interfere with one another in
the pursuit of happiness.
First, the order of these goods, like the enumeration of their va-
riety, depends upon our understanding of the various capacities of
human nature in their relation to one another.
“I am sorry that you insist upon this last point”, the student says,
“because it is a stumbling block in the way of my agreement with
you. You simply haven’t proved the point in any way, and, without
obstinacy, I must stand on what I know—which is contrary to what
you say is the case. I can see, however, that, assuming what you say
to be true, the rest follows. And even though you have not given me
the analysis which shows the precise order of the partial goods, I
can surmise how that might be done. But I am still worried about
the possibility of happiness, as you have defined it. I still don’t see
how it is possible for a person to be happy if he or she has to pos-
sess every sort of good thing altogether and at once.”
The very language the student has used in raising this question
is crucial to the answer. Strictly speaking, a person cannot ever be
happy. He or she can only become happy. A human life is some-
thing in the process of becoming. It is a temporal whole, the parts of
which cannot coexist. A life is a whole only in the way in which a
day or a game is a whole—as an orderly succession of moments.
The becoming of the whole is not completed until the process is ac-
tually finished. That is why Solon, a wise man of ancient Greece,
made what at first seems to be a paradoxical point, namely, that you
cannot tell whether a person is happy until the person is dead. Stated
less paradoxically, the point is that happiness is the quality of a
whole life, not of its parts. Another ancient, the Roman Boethius,
defined happiness as the state of those made perfect by the posses-
sion in aggregate of all good things. The student may think that this
is the definition of happiness we have been employing. His attention
must be called, therefore, to two important differences.
It has been said that the means are the end in the process of be-
coming. This is the sum of moral knowledge. In the building of a
life, as in the building of a house, it is true that as the parts are
properly chosen and properly put together, the perfection of the
whole gradually becomes. In every particular case, the ultimate cri-
terion of choice is the end: the choice is right or wrong according as
the realization of the end is furthered or hindered. At the beginning
of life all good things is a possibility; when life is over, the possibil-
ity either has been realized or not, and that will depend upon the
choices which have been made.
70
“I think I see”, the student says, “how what you have called a
true conception of the end of life is a first principle from which all
the rest can be derived. I know I don’t see the detailed steps here,
but that would be too much to expect. I do understand how, in a
general way, the problem of preference is solved—at least in so far
as the value to be placed on different things in relation to one anoth-
er follows from what you have called the order and proportion of
goods, which in turn follows from the way in which we conceive
happiness to be constituted as a whole of parts. I am sure I don’t
understand any of this well enough to know how to think correctly
in a particular case, facing particular alternatives—assuming, of
course, that I had previously thought correctly about the end, and
through it about the means in general. But what bothers me most of
all is still the point about the violability of moral rules. Am I right in
supposing, from what you have said, that people fail to do what they
should do simply because of bad thinking—wrongly conceiving
happiness, which means making errors about the order or variety of
goods, and consequently misjudging the relative worth of objects in
particular cases of preference?”
No, the student must be told at once, to suppose that all miscon-
duct—bad choices leading to bad acts—follows from bad thinking
is itself a great error in thinking; as a matter of fact, a famous one in
the history of moral theory. The quickest way to show the student
that bad thinking is only one of the sources of misconduct is to re-
71
mind him of something we saw toward the close of the first part of
our discussion—when we still supposed pleasure to be the only cri-
terion of preference. Remember the rule of conduct we had then
formulated: “In any case in which a choice can be made, a person
should prefer the alternative which, in the long run or viewing life
as a whole, maximizes pleasure and minimizes displeasure.” The
student should now be able to see how that rule contains in germ
almost all the truth we have subsequently discovered, for the maxim
could be thus rephrased: in any case in which a choice can be made,
a person should prefer the alternative which, considering the possi-
bility of living a whole life well, tends to realize the possibility of
happiness. Now we saw, in our earlier discussion, that the rule is
violable in two ways. We distinguished between two sorts of mis-
takes we can make—mistakes of calculation and mistakes of acting
contrary to our calculations. Even though a person has thought cor-
rectly about the end and the means in general, and in this sense
knows what is really good for him or her, the person may in a par-
ticular case be seduced by what is apparently better at that time,
even though it is really worse in the long run.
Human beings are not simply rational beings. They are rational
animals. They are creatures of passion, of animal appetites, but they
are also capable of abstract thought, by which they can form a con-
ception of happiness and of the goods in general which constitute it.
All the goods we have been talking about—happiness itself, or the
various kinds of partial goods—are rational or intelligible objects.
They certainly cannot be perceived by the senses, although particu-
lar instances of the partial goods may somehow present themselves
in that way. But precisely because human beings are creatures of
sense as well as of reason, and because their desires can be deter-
mined by what they sense as well as by their abstract thinking, the
alternatives which they face in particular cases of preference are, as
objects, both sensible and intelligible, and make their appeal both to
their animal appetites and to their wills—the latter being the desire
for objects rationally judged to be good, the former being the desire
for what is sensed as good.
We have previously said that the means are the end in the pro-
cess of becoming. The end is rightly understood only so far as we
rightly apprehend the means which constitute it. It is also true that
the end is possessed at any moment only to the extent that we pos-
sess the means which generate it—the habits from which our con-
duct flows. At any given moment in his life a person is more or less
on the way to becoming happy according to the state of his or her
habits, especially the moral habits—the virtues or vices—which
make his or her character what it is. Aristotle thus summarized the
whole of his Ethics when he said. “According as a man’s character
is, so does the end appear to him.” Until a life is over, you cannot
judge whether it is a happy one; but so far as you can see into a per-
son’s character, you can tell, even while life is going on, whether a
person is becoming happy.
75
14. It should be recognized that brevity is the real reason for this change in
style. Although the full development of argument with respect to each of
80
the three points mentioned would depend upon psychological propositions
already questioned by the student, there is no reason why the student
should not proceed hypothetically—to discover whether other moral truths
(other than the one about happiness) can be established, once it is granted
that man is a rational animal, that man has a nature and powers essentially
distinct from the nature and powers of brute animals, that man has free
will, etc. If the student had been told, at the very beginning of the discus-
sion, that these psychological propositions were indispensable to the argu-
ment, he would either have refused to begin until these propositions had
been proved, or rightly have insisted that any conclusions reached by an
argument thus undertaken must be regarded as hypothetical. That is the
way he now views the conclusion about happiness (as constituted in the
same way for all men). There is no reason, therefore, why he would be
unwilling similarly to entertain further conclusions about the order of
goods or about virtue, if they could be reached. But to deal argumentative-
ly with each of the three points, now to be considered, would require much
more time and patience than can be expected of the reader. That is why I
shall present an analytical summary of the argument instead of letting it
expand in response to the demands of an inquiring mind.
WHEN THE word “good” was first introduced to name “any object
of desire,”15 the student might have stopped the discussion, or
turned it into other channels, by asking whether this was not a mere
tautology, a mere rule of verbal substitution (i.e., the word “good”
being substitutable for “object of desire” and conversely). For such
a question would have raised a crucial issue concerning the relation
of these two basic terms: either whatever is called “good” is so
81
called because it is in fact desired by someone; or whatever anyone
desires is desired because it is good. In the first alternative, there
could be no distinction between the real and the apparent good,
since the fact of desire itself is regarded as conferring goodness up-
on its object. In the second alternative, goodness would be a proper-
ty of things apart from their being actually desired, for as good they
would be desirable whether or not desired , in which case no object
would be really good unless it were desirable according to its being,
whereas any object whose goodness derived simply from its being
desired might be an apparent good. It is plain that the alternative
which destroys the distinction between real and apparent goods re-
sults in complete subjectivism (and the denial of moral knowledge).
Only the alternative which maintains this distinction can uphold the
objectivity of good. Only if it is possible to desire things because
they are good (and, as such, desired), can desires themselves be ob-
jectively judged as right or wrong (i.e., according to the goodness or
badness of their objects).16
After the student had begun to see the relation between happi-
ness, as a whole of goods, and the various partial goods which con-
stitute it, he might have inquired concerning the relation of these
partial goods to one another. He might have asked whether all the
partial goods are equally good, or good in the same way; whether
one type of partial good may be a means to another, and if so,
whether this means-end relationship is the same as the means-end
relationship between the partial goods and happiness. These ques-
tions would have started another line of analysis. Let me briefly
summarize what is involved in answering them.
In the order of theory and intention, the end precedes the means,
for it is by knowledge of the end that we know and can intend the
means productive of it. But, in the order of practice and execution,
the means precede the end, for in order to become happy we must
first acquire the productive means. Whereas the constitutive means
are the end so far as it is realized at any time, the productive means
are the end in process of becoming realized. Because the end deter-
mines the productive means (in the order of intention) and the pro-
ductive means determine the end (in the order of execution), it is
equally true to say that as man conceives the end, so will his or her
character be; and to say that as a man’s character is, so is the end for
him.42 As reciprocally determinative of each other, the end and the
99
productive means are correlative: the order of goods or desirables is
correlative with the ordering of desires. If the end at which a man
aims is only the apparent, and not the real good (because of some
inadequacy or falsity in his conception of the variety or order of par-
tial goods), then his habits of desire may appear to be virtuous, but
they will really be vices; and conversely, if a man be habitually vi-
cious in any respect, that disorder of his desires will be productive
of apparent, but not real, happiness. The man of really good charac-
ter is not one who possesses some virtues and some vices, for no
real virtue can be conjoined with any vice. Only the cardinal virtues
in their integrity can constitute a really good character, just as only
an adequate and true ordering of all partial goods can constitute real
happiness. Thus we see the two ways in which happiness exists
practically . Theoretically, happiness may exist in the mind as a
conception of the end, whether true or false. But practically, it exists
either (a) objectively in a human life in so far as it is perfected by
the possession of all good things, or (b) subjectively in a human
character in so far as it is perfected by real virtue. This is just anoth-
er way of saying that the productive means are the end in the pro-
cess of becoming. But saying it this way enables us to see that
though the complete actuality of happiness is attained only in a
complete life, it is virtually present, as in its causes , in a good char-
acter. Objectively, happiness exists only as a process of becoming
exists, which means that it cannot exist at any moment; whereas
subjectively, happiness exists at any moment to whatever extent its
efficient causes exist. In the first sense, therefore, we cannot say that
a man was happy until he is dead; in the second, we can say that he
is happy while he is alive, if we know that he has a virtuous charac-
ter.
The man of virtue has practical knowledge of the means and end
of life. Through his moral virtues he has a connatural knowledge of
the good at which these virtues aim; and through his prudence, he
has a living habit of regulating each particular act in accordance
with the demands of virtue. But if having virtue is indispensable for
knowing practically how to live well—if virtue itself mediates be-
tween true theory and sound practice—then how can virtue be ac-
quired? Since theoretical knowledge of principles is insufficient,
since practical knowledge of some sort seems to be both prerequi-
site for the formation of virtue and also consequent thereupon, there
appears to be a vicious circle here, or at least a mystery about how
anyone becomes virtuous. So far as I know, there is only one solu-
tion to this problem, in the domain of purely natural causality. One
man of virtue, thereby having practical knowledge, not only for the
guidance of his own life, but for the direction of others, must be the
efficient cause of the formation of virtue in another man, so that the
latter gradually becomes able, through the practical knowledge
which virtue gives, to regulate his own life. It remains true, of
course, that the principal efficient cause of virtue must be a man’s
own acts, performed voluntarily and directed with prudence by his
own reason. The moral preceptor is, therefore, like any other teach-
er, at best an accessory or cooperative cause: moral training, like
intellectual teaching, is an art of cooperating with nature, aiding the
primary cause which is reason’s own activity. So far as habituation
is concerned, the efficiency of moral training can go no further than
the formation of what Aristotle called “inchoate virtue”—moral
habits formed in one person as the result of the regulation of his acts
103
by another. The growing person may thus come to possess inchoate
virtue before he knows the principles of moral theory and before he
has practical knowledge whereby to regulate his own conduct. Such
inchoate virtues, nevertheless, operate as the seed of genuine virtue,
for they are a source of good conduct; and as the result of good acts,
though these be initially performed under external regulation, con-
natural knowledge of the good accrues, practical knowledge of how
to act well grows, and prudence itself develops.48a By this route, it
is possible for a man to become virtuous without ever being learned
in moral theory. No one ever becomes virtuous simply by learning
moral theory, though moral theory may confirm a man in virtue, or
remotely facilitate his practice of good acts.
NOTES TO CHAPTER VI
16. This issue was briefly considered at one point in the dialectic.
See Chapter III, pp. 43-44: If “the objects we have called goods are
good only because they are desired”; if “there is always a relativity
of the good to actual desire.’’ then “we shall never be able to say
104
what men should desire, which is central to moral knowledge as
normative or prescriptive. In order to get beyond a mere description
of what men do desire, we must somehow show the student that the
objects men desire, they desire because they judge them to be
good.” But in the discussion itself, this problem was inadequately
solved by proposing an ultimate end, which in fact all men do de-
sire, namely, to live well; and in terms of this end, we argued that
men should desire whatever is necessary for the attainment of this
end. This is a partial solution, since it is true that the goodness of
means may be derived from the goodness of the end they serve; but
it leaves two major questions unanswered: (1) is the end good simp-
ly because all men do desire it, or because it is the ultimate good
which all men should desire? and (2) are any of the means good in
their own right, and apart from being means to the end, so that they,
too, should be desired because they are intrinsically good (i.e., de-
sirable)? The student permitted the discussion to go on at this point,
although he could have stopped it by insisting upon a deeper exami-
nation into the meaning of the good as an object of desire.
22. It does not follow that a man who, judging aright, desires what
is really good, will necessarily act accordingly; for in the conflict
between his sensitive and his rational appetites, an apparent good
may dominate his conduct at the moment of action. See Aristotle’s
account of incontinence in the Ethics, Bk. VII, 3. All that is here
being said is that the basic truths which constitute ethical theory—
truths about the variety and order of objects which are really good
for man—rest on metaphysical and psychological knowledge, the
former concerning the foundation of goodness in being, the latter
concerning the foundation of the real human good in the nature of
man. The real human good is the natural human good as apprehend-
ed and thus become an object of conscious desire; the human good,
taken without qualification, is not identical with the natural human
107
good, for it includes all the apparent goods which are the objects of
mistaken judgments. If the word “good” be restricted in its signifi-
cation to mean “real good,” then the metaphysical statement that the
good is what all desire is true only for the objects of natural desire,
human or otherwise; it certainly is not true for the objects of con-
scious human desire, since what all men desire, consciously, may be
either really or apparently good.
23. This distinction between the object of desire and the object of
knowledge accounts for the radical difference between theoretical
and practical truth: only when the object is an already determinate
nature can truth be in the intellect by conformity to what is; since
the object of desire is also the object of our practical judgments, and
since this object is always a future contingent event, i.e., a change to
be accomplished, the truth of practical judgments cannot be by con-
formity to what is, but must be by conformity of the judgment to
right desire, i.e., desire for a real good, an object of natural desire.
24. I shall return to this distinction between goods of man and goods
for man in a later discussion of means and ends. This distinction,
made in terms of the axiom that everything seeks its own perfection,
raises profound ethical problems which cannot be discussed here:
for example, the whole problem of altruism and selfishness. Is man
ever obligated to work for the good of any other thing, inanimate or
animate, animal or human, and if so, how is this a real good, i.e., an
object of natural desire, if it is not a good for man as well as a good
of the other thing? This problem becomes particularly acute with
respect to the relation of men in economic and political associations.
In theology, this distinction is exemplified by the consideration of
the Divine being and goodness as the ultimate good for man, where-
as the vision of God is the ultimate good of man’s soul. The theo-
logical case indicates furthermore, that what is good for man may be
superior to him in being, and its efficient causality in bringing about
human perfection may be without human aid, except in the order of
108
dispositive causality; whereas the material things which are good for
man are not only inferior in being, but usually, if not always, require
efficient causality on the part of man (the work of his art) to render
them useful.
29. Strictly speaking, they are not goods of the “body” in the sense
in which this might be opposed to goods of a living thing, goods it
can possess because it has a soul and is alive. The distinction be-
tween “goods of the body” and “goods of the soul” must be under-
stood, rather, in terms of the distinction between man’s specifically
human powers and those powers which man has because the ration-
al soul virtually includes the sensitive and vegetative souls.
31. This is not inconsistent with the truth that sensual pleasure, like
every other partial good, is a constitutive means of happiness.
But the object of love, unlike the beautiful, is not an object of com-
pletely disinterested enjoyment, apart from desire and action. There-
fore, the object of love must be defined as the good of another per-
son; as such it may also be an object of desire comparable to the
desire for one’s own perfection. The truth that everything naturally
desires its own perfection must be understood in such a way that the
desire for the perfection of an alterego, i. e., a loved object, is in-
cluded. Just as we can never possess other things without making
them parts of ourselves, so the perfection of a loved object is a per-
fection we vicariously enjoy as if it were the perfection of our own
personality. Cf. The Theory of Democracy, Part II, Section 2, in The
Thomist, III, 4. Although the object of love is strictly the good and
not the beautiful, there remains a sense in which the loved object is,
apart from desire and as simply apprehended, beautiful. To under-
stand the object of love, either as good or as beautiful, it is neces-
sary to distinguish the “love” which names a passion and the “love”
which names a motion of the will; for in the sphere of sensitive ap-
petite love is strictly selfish, being the origin of desire for posses-
sion, for incorporation of another into one’s own being, whereas in
the sphere of will, love is entirely altruistic, being correlative with
desire for the good of another as other and reaching fruition in the
apprehension of that other’s perfection as beautiful.
34. See Chapter VII. One indication that social goods should be
classified primarily as intrinsic and enjoyable goods is that friends
are objects of love—having a goodness to be loved as we love the
goodness of ourselves. Cf. note 32. Another indication is that the
goodness of a community, domestic or political, is a common good
in the sense that it is shared by the members: it is not only a com-
mon object of desire, but also a fruition commonly enjoyed. See The
Theory of Democracy, Part II, Section 2
111
34a. Cf. St. Thomas’s discussion of the meaning of “good” in the
case of good habits: Summa Theologica, I-II, 55, 4 ad 2.
35. See Chapter IV, p. 48. The second sort were not then called
“functional means.”
36. These last two points are of great importance, for they apply to
the analysis of functional means the deeper principles whereby
goods are distinguished as utile and honestum, and as human and
animal. In one sense, of course, every functional means is useful,
but a good may be useful functionally (in relation to some other
good it serves) without being essentially useful in its own type( i.e.,
not being a good for man, but a good of man). Furthermore, since
happiness is specifically human, only those goods are essentially
constitutive of it, which, as partial goods, are bonum honestum hom-
inis; extrinsic goods, or intrinsically animal goods, are only acci-
dentally constitutive of happiness.
These two points convey Aristotle’s insights about means and ends.
He distinguished between goods which are mere means, goods
which are both means and ends, and the good which is absolutely
and simply the end. A mere means is any bonum utile, whether or
not it also functions as an end; a means which is essentially an end
is any bonum honestum: with the exception of pleasure in the sensi-
ble order, and contemplative activity in the order of intelligible
goods, happiness is the only good which never functions as a means,
and it is the only end simply and absolutely, because even pleasure
and contemplation are constitutive means of human happiness. Aris-
totle also distinguished between antecedent and constitutive means,
and this is the distinction we have made among partial goods (all of
them constitutive in a broad sense) according as they are accidental-
ly or essentially constitutive of happiness. In other words, a mere
means is, as constitutive, accidental to human happiness, whereas a
means which is also genuinely an end is essential to the constitution
of human happiness. These two basic points go much deeper than
the distinction among partial goods as functional means and ends.
See Aristotle, Ethics, I, 7. Cf. John Dewey’s attempt to regard every
good equally as an end, in Reconstruction in Philosophy, New York,
1919: Ch. VII.
37. All the objects of choice are means of this type. We always
choose and act in particular situations, and the good which is the
112
object of choice is always, therefore, a singular instance of a type of
good—hence always a constitutive means-in-particular. (This classi-
fication of all objects of choice as constitutive means-in-particular
does not prevent the cross-classification of them as functional
means or ends.) This fact about the objects of choice is indispensa-
ble to an understanding of freedom of choice. Only means-in-
particular are contingently constitutive of happiness; means-in-
general, being necessarily constitutive, cannot be objects of free
choice. In willing happiness necessarily, we must will whatever is
necessary to its constitution, as we conceive it; but we need not will
this or that particular instance of a type of good, for such means are
only contingently constitutive of happiness. Failure explicitly to
observe this distinction between constitutive means-in-general and
means-in-particular accounts for some ambiguity in passages in
which St. Thomas discusses the necessitation of the will with re-
spect to means. Vd.
40. The two theoretical problems of ethics concern, first, the end,
and second, its generative means. The first problem is solved when
happiness is adequately and truly defined; the solution is here
equivalent to knowledge about the order and variety of partial
goods, and their functional relationships to one another. The second
problem is solved when we are able to deduce from the nature of
happiness what must be the nature of its generative means.
Knowledge of the constitutive means is explicitly equivalent to
knowledge of the end; but knowledge of the generative means is
only implicitly contained in knowledge of happiness, and must be
deductively explicated. When we know what the generative means
are, we can proceed to the practical problem of how to possess them
and, through them, how to become happy.
46. See St. Thomas, Summa Contra Gentiles, III, 37; cf. Summa
Theologica, I-II, 66, 5 ad 1.
47. Thus the apparent conflict between Book I and Book X of Aris-
totle’s Ethics is resolved. If it was due to any fault on Aristotle’s
part, it can be attributed to his failure to distinguish between two
senses of “the highest good”—(a) the sum of goods, which is happi-
ness as the end, constituted by every type of partial good, and gen-
erated only by cardinal virtue; and (b) the supreme type of partial
good, which is contemplation as the end served by all the other par-
tial goods, though generated directly only by intellectual virtue.
There can be no question that it is the goodness of a whole life, not
speculative activity, which is the ultimate object of natural desire,
and hence is happiness or the last end. Speculative activity is merely
the best aspect of a good life, its most enjoyable phase. This is con-
firmed by Boethius’ definition of happiness as the state of those
who possess in aggregate all good things. Thus conceived, happi-
ness cannot be identified with any single type of good, not even
with speculative activity in this life. I say “in this life’’ because Boe-
thius’ definition reveals the analogy of temporal and eternal happi-
ness (the one constituted by a simultaneous, the other by a succes-
sive, possession of “all good things”), and thereby helps us to un-
derstand how the contemplation of God in the Beatific Vision may
be identified with eternal happiness, whereas no sort of speculative
activity can be rightly identified with temporal happiness. In this
life, the contemplation of God, whether it be the activity of wisdom
as a purely natural virtue or the activity of faith and supernatural
116
intellectual gifts, is not happiness, but only the highest part thereof.
Hence two things must be said about St. Thomas’ definition of im-
perfect, or temporal, happiness as consisting in contemplative ac-
tivity: first, that this is not an accurate definition of temporal happi-
ness, any more than Aristotle’s definition in Book X is; second, that
it is a better definition of the highest part of temporal happiness,
than could have been given by Aristotle, because St. Thomas con-
ceives contemplation in terms of God as the object, and as supernat-
urally generated by faith and the gift of wisdom, whereas Aristotle’s
meaning for “contemplation” lacks any objective specification, and
even if the Divine be implied as object, merely natural wisdom is
obviously insufficient. Cf. Summa Theologica, I-II pp. 3-5.
(1) The nature of the state. If man were not by nature a social, and
also, through being rational, a political, animal, the state or political
community would not itself be natural. It originates, or comes into
being, in answer to a human need. If man, like other non-gregarious
animals, could subsist in a solitary mode of life, not even the family
would be a natural community, for it would answer to no natural
need. And if man could live well (i.e., live humanly, rather than
merely subsist), apart from a larger community than the family, the
domestic society would suffice, and there would be no natural need
119
for the state. That which comes into being as indispensable to the
fulfillment of a natural need is itself natural and necessary. This type
of naturalness and necessity is in the order of final causality. To say
that the state is natural in this sense is, therefore, to deny that it is
artificial—i.e., an accidental contrivance which is totally dispensa-
ble, as, for example, any work of useful art that is a mere luxury. At
one extreme, then, there is the error of the social contract which
conceives the state as if it were a mere luxury—not natural at all in
the order of final causality. At the other extreme, there is the errone-
ous notion that the state is entirely natural in the order of efficient
causality—that it flows from instinctive determinations, rather than
is a free work of reason. This latter error confuses human associa-
tion with the instinctively determined communities of the social
brutes. The nature of the state is rightly conceived only when it is
understood both as originating in natural needs, and also as being a
mode of association which is determined by reason rather than in-
stinct.
Although the goodness of the state, or common good, is not the end
in the temporal order, it may, nevertheless, be an end, in the strict
sense in which every partial good which is a bonum honestum is an
end. Moreover, within the sphere of specifically political activity,
the common good, the welfare of the political community, is the last
end toward which all political institutions, agencies, and acts, are
ordered as means. In the domain of political life, the common good
occupies a place analogous to that of contemplation in the order of
partial goods constitutive of happiness. Furthermore, the common
good is a complex whole of many social goods, whose variety and
order constitute it, as happiness is constituted by the variety and or-
der of all good things. And just as moral virtue is both a constitutive
part of happiness and also its productive means, so good govern-
ment is, as a social good, constitutive of the common good, and also
the one means which is directly productive of the state’s well-being.
(By “government” here I understand all the institutions and agencies
through which both rulers and ruled can act for the common good.)
Just governmental activity not only maintains the common good,
but also facilitates the formation of virtue in the citizens and thus
the state is, indirectly, productive of happiness, or the life of virtue.
Thus we have learned that the nature of the state, its mode of being,
and its essential goodness, cannot be understood except in terms of
the nature of man, the perfection of his nature by virtue, and the per-
fection of his life by happiness. Unless, therefore, the principles of
ethics can be ascertained, as objective theoretical truths comprising
wisdom in the practical order, the principles of politics cannot be
established. Unless, as a branch of practical philosophy, it be found-
ed upon moral wisdom, political theory cannot be defended against
the skepticism of realpolitik, or protected against the doctrinal er-
rors of totalitarianism. But no part of practical philosophy (ethics or
politics) can be validated as knowledge of absolute and universal
principles without the prior acknowledgment of ultimate theoretic
truths—about being, goodness, and the nature of man. To overcome
moral skepticism, and realpolitik as its consequence, it is necessary,
first, to eradicate its root in the prevailing positivism which denies
philosophical knowledge—metaphysics, and especially the philoso-
phy of man. This has been illustrated in the very motion of our in-
quiry; the dialectic of morals uncovered the need for a prior dialec-
tic of substance, essence, and man. Until that prior work is done,
most of the truths we seemed to reach, both dialectically and by de-
ductive elaboration, will not convince the student. Lacking convic-
tion with respect to these, the student remains susceptible to all the
“political religions” which rush in to fill the vacuum created by his
doubts and denials. In the world as it is today, a good work the phi-
losopher can do is to labor inductively in the fields of metaphysics
and psychology, for the sake of moral wisdom and, ultimately, for
the foundation of a true political philosophy.
NOTES