Corporate - Social - Responsibility - Article
Corporate - Social - Responsibility - Article
Corporate - Social - Responsibility - Article
222
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 223
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
224 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
8 E. Dodd, ‘For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees’ (1931) Harvard Law Review
1049; A. Berle, ‘For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees’ (1932) Harvard Law
Review 1365.
9 C. Riley, ‘Understanding and Regulating the Corporation’ (1995) 58 Modern Law Review
595. See also Deakin and Hughes, Enterprise and Community.
10 See discussion in Dine, Governance of Corporate Groups, pp. 33–4.
11 Parkinson seeks to minimise the impact of these difficulties by calling for an ‘ethical’ fidu-
ciary duty but this may be simply another way of attempting to change the culture from
‘outside’, it says nothing as to how to formulate and weight the ethical considerations:
J. Parkinson, ‘The Socially Responsible Company’ in Addo, Human Rights Standards.
12 J.-J. Du Plessis, ‘Corporate Governance: Reflections on the German Two-Tier System’
(1996) Journal of South African Law 315.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 225
13 The discussion of John Parkinson’s views in this chapter do not imply that I disagreed
with many of his views. I was a friend and admirer of John and was deeply distressed by
his untimely death in 2004.
14 Parkinson, ‘Socially Responsible Company’. 15 Ibid., p. 59.
16 Parke v. Daily News [1962] 2 All ER 929.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
226 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Human rights
r Principle 1: support and respect the protection of international human
rights within their sphere of influence; and
r Principle 2: make sure their own corporations are not complicit in
human rights abuses.
Labour
The Secretary-General asked world business to uphold:
r Principle 3: freedom of association and the effective recognition of the
right to collective bargaining;
r Principle 4: the elimination of all forms of forced and compulsory
labour;
r Principle 5: the effective abolition of child labour; and
r Principle 6: the elimination of discrimination in respect of employment
and occupation.
Environment
The Secretary-General asked world business to:
r Principle 7: support a precautionary approach to environmental
challenges;
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 227
r Principle 8: undertake initiatives to promote greater environmental
responsibility; and
r Principle 9: encourage the development and diffusion of environmen-
tally friendly technologies.
Why should business participate in this initiative? Because as markets have gone
global, so, too, must the principle and practice of corporate citizenship. In this
new global economy, it makes good business sense for firms to internalize these
principles as integral elements of corporate strategies and practice.17
Note that the ‘benefit’ accrues to ‘it’, the corporation since, ‘CSR can
help to build brand value, foster customer loyalty, motivate their staff, and
contribute to a good reputation among a wide range of stakeholders.’22
It has been claimed that CSR is ‘outreach’ which provides education for
the disadvantaged.23 For Hopkins, it means ‘ethical behaviour of busi-
ness towards its constituencies or stakeholders. I define stakeholders as
consisting of seven azimuths or major groups’ which are:
17 www.un.org
18 http://europa.eu.int/eur-lex/en/com/gpr/2001/com2001 0366en01.pdf
19 Commission Green Paper, Promoting a European Framework for Corporate Social Respon-
sibility (COM (2001) 366 final, Brussels, 18 July 2001).
20 Ibid.
21 Business and Society: Corporate Social Responsibility Report (Department of Trade and
Industry, 2002).
22 Ibid., ‘Foreword’ by Douglas Alexander.
23 Corporate Citizenship (The Smith Institute, 2000).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
228 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
r owners/investors (share or stockholders);
r management;
r employees;
r customers;
r natural environment;
r the wider community;
r contractors/suppliers.24
The UK Corporate and Social Responsibility Report25 states that ‘[t]he
fundamentals of equal opportunities are a central plank of CSR’.26 It
should be noted, however, that the whole concept of CSR is not with-
out its opponents. A comprehensive attack on ‘global salvationism’ and
CSR in particular can be found in Misguided Virtue,27 where it is argued
that:
CSR embodies the notion that progress in relation to environmental and social
issues lies in making norms and standards more stringent and more uniform,
in part by corporations acting on their own initiative. This approach takes too
little account of costs and benefits of extending regulation in ways that would
reduce welfare. The effects of enforced uniformity are especially damaging in
labour markets. The greatest potential for harm of this kind arises from attempts,
whether by government or businesses in the name of CSR and ‘Global Corporate
Citizenship’ to regulate the world as a whole. Imposing common international
standards, despite the fact that circumstances may be widely different across
countries, restricts the scope for mutually beneficial trade and investment flows.
It is liable to hold back the development of poor countries through the suppression
of employment opportunities within them.28
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 229
PR capture
The first and most obvious danger of the vagueness of these concepts and
the focus on the benefit to the corporations is that the voluntary nature of
codes and the imprecision of CSR provides an unparalleled opportunity
for ‘spin’ for companies.
Corporations have . . . set out to persuade the public that the very raison d’etre of
commerce has changed, and to co-opt the environmental debate. Companies are
no longer insidious faceless corporations interested in profit at any cost, they were
now caring corporations concerned about communities, consumers, children.
They were committed to pollution prevention, to people, to the planet. There
was only one problem with this strategy – on the whole, they were lying.32
Rowell alerts us to the huge effort put in by corporations and their
‘white hat’ networks and NGOs in order to present themselves as
environmentally friendly from ‘Paraquat and nature working in perfect
harmony’33 to ‘The Japanese Power Reactor and Nuclear Development
Corporation has created a green cartoon called “Mr Pluto” whose job it
is to teach children that nuclear power is safe. “If everybody treats me
with a peaceful and warm heart, I’ll never be scary or dangerous” says
the Smurf-like creature.’34
It is instructive that many CSR programmes are run by the public
relations departments of companies. It was argued in chapter 2 that CSR
can act as a moral deflection device. Those putting energy into such
programmes can feel good about it while failing to address underlying
issues. CSR as moral deflection also works by blaming companies for
their actions while retaining the structure which pushes them to behave
badly. The CSR movement thus adopts the ‘blame the company’ as a
primary moral deflection device.
So far as monitoring CSR performance, many auditing firms have
lucrative contracts to perform this function. However, as we have seen
31 Hertz, Silent Takeover, p. 172.
32 A. Rowell, Green Backlash (Routledge, London, 1996).
33 Advert in Malay Mail, April 1993, depicting a scene of palm trees, birds and flowering
plants in a rural idyll: Rowell, Green Backlash, p. 104.
34 Rowell, Green Backlash, p. 105.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
230 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 231
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
232 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
those values in one part of the organisation (even if that part is at the top
of the hierarchy)’.45 Neither of these views are acceptable to the ‘nexus
of contracts’ theorists who argue that the conception of a company as an
institution is seriously misleading since ‘companies, being merely a set of
contractual relationships, are not different in kind from markets. It is held
to follow that it is meaningless to suppose that companies can be under
any obligation to operate in a socially or ethically responsible manner’.46
Addo and Wood identify a number of ‘principles’ underlying the impo-
sition of responsibility,47 whose first principle is essentially the concept of
the corporation as existing by virtue of a concession by society: ‘society
grants legitimacy and power to business’.48 As a consequence, companies
must act responsibly. Again this is challenged by the ‘nexus of contracts’
theorists who argue that the risk undertaken by the shareholders means
that they contract for an indefinite return. All other ‘contractors’ agree
to a definite return on their contract. After these are paid, the sharehold-
ers are entitled to any surplus that remains.49 This theory rests on several
misconceptions, the first being that shareholders are entitled to a ‘residue’
when, in UK law at least, they have no entitlement to a dividend. The
only residue that shareholders are entitled to is a division of a surplus in
a solvent winding-up, not a proportion of profits. The second is equat-
ing a shareholder’s right to return with ‘maximisation’ of that return.
As Parkinson points out, even if the ‘contracting shareholders’ could be
considered to be owners, that does not mean that they may insist that
directors attempt to maximise profits in any way at all.50
Wood’s second principle is an:
organisational principle which requires businesses to be responsible for the out-
comes relating to the primary and secondary areas of their involvement with
society. A car manufacturer for example, can be expected under this principle
to share responsibility for environmental pollution, vehicle safety and initiatives
addressing drivers’ education . . . Corporate responsibility under this principle . . .
demonstrates a credible relationship between the effects of corporate activities and
the responsibilities sought to be imposed.51
45 K. Goodpaster, ‘The Concept of Corporate Responsibility’ (1983), Journal of Business
Ethics 1, at 10, cited in Addo, ‘Human Rights and TNCs: Introduction’, p. 16.
46 Parkinson, ‘Socially Responsible Company’, p. 53 (citation of explanation does not imply
agreement with the theory). See F. Easterbrook and D. Fischel, The Economic Structure
of Corporate Law (Cambridge, Mass., 1991); Henderson, Misguided Virtue.
47 D. Wood, ‘Corporate Social Performance Revisited’ (1991) 16 Academy of Management
Journal 312.
48 Ibid., p. 314.
49 Parkinson, ‘Socially Responsible Company’, p. 53. For an extensive analysis and critique
of the economic theories underpinning these theories see Dine, Governance of Corporate
Groups.
50 Wood, ‘Corporate Social Performance’, p. 51. The concept of ownership in relation to
companies is addressed in chapter 6.
51 Addo, ‘Human Rights and TNCs: Introduction’, p. 18.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 233
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
234 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 235
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
236 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 237
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
238 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 239
77 See, e.g., Regulation Without the State (Institute of Economic Affairs, London, 2000).
78 D. Pearce, A. Markandya and E. Barbier, Blueprint for a Green Economy (Earthscan,
1989).
79 Ibid., p. 2. 80 Ibid., p. 30.
81 M. Jacobs, ‘The Limits to Neoclassicism’ in M. Redclift and T. Benron (eds), Social
Theory and the Global Environment (Routledge, London, 1994).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
240 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
what matters, the results of wellbeing surveys will provide the answer
to the ‘correct’ level of environmental protection. As Jacobs points out,82
the neo-classical approach is founded on methodological individualism,
based ‘on the currently existing preferences of consumers’. At the same
time, it is presented as morally neutral, seeking to discover an ‘optimal’
outcome which is nevertheless not presented as morally best.83 Given a
moral framework which derives from ‘the greatest good of the greatest
number’, the ‘optimal’ elides with the normative ‘morally best’, absent
some mystical dimension which can conveniently be derided by oppo-
nents (see below, discussion of ‘green backlash’). Indeed, ‘on the premise
that satisfying consumer preferences is what matters, most neo-classicists
would argue that [the optimal level of protection] is the level of protection
which society therefore should choose’.84
The foundation of this economic approach is the desire to avoid the
problem of externalities by turning ‘the environment into a commodity
which can be analysed just like other commodities’.85 The motive may
be to retain the economists’ role as governmental advisers86 or to seek
genuine protection for the environment: because it has hitherto been free
it has been significantly overused.
In valuing the environment it is argued that all aspects of the
environment87 can be valued with a money yardstick.88 This is supported
by the view that human life is valued by the amount of resources which
a society will use to save life. This (unsupported) argument is unsound,
confusing as it does the resources available to achieve a certain aim and
the value of that which will be lost if the aim is not achieved. Jacobs89 com-
ments ‘[m]any environmentalists and Greens object to this treatment on
82 Jacobs, ‘Limits to Neoclassicism’, p. 75.
83 Ibid., p. 70. 84 Ibid., p. 72. 85 Ibid. 86 Ibid., p. 69.
87 The apparently simplistic attribution of value to environmental commodities is mitigated
by an attempt to factor into the equation not just ‘use’ value but ‘option’ value (the
value of preserving something in case the consumer wishes to use it), ‘Bequest’ value,
which is the value of options for future generations, and ‘existence’ value, which is
the ‘sentimental’ value placed on the existence of whales etc. The poorer nations are
mentioned as providing a rationale for natural capital conservation (which, to be fair,
is the approach later adopted instead of a substitutability approach) and the process
of exporting an unsustainable quantity of hardwood from poor nations is described as
a policy choice on that basis: ‘If we take the broader view [why broader?], based on
total rather than natural capital only, the hardwood exporting countries may simply be
converting their export revenue into investments which will sustain their future’: ibid.,
p. 70. The ‘choice’ exercised by these countries is then castigated: ‘export proceeds
are often turned into consumption’. The solution to this is foreign aid for sustainable
development, a patronising solution which disguises the lack of choice that plagues these
nations.
88 Pearce, Markandya and Barbier, Blueprint, p. 53.
89 Arguing along lines not dissimilar to R.M. Dworkin, ‘Is Wealth a Value’ (1980) 9 Journal
of Legal Studies 191, discussed in chapter 2.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 241
essentially moral grounds, namely that it devalues the cultural and spiri-
tual meaning which the environment has for human society and ignores
altogether the rights of other species’.90 This confusion translates into an
attempt to measure the degree of concern, i.e. the willingness of individuals
to pay for the environment.91 A further confusion arises in the assertion
that ‘preserving and improving the environment is never a free option; it
costs money and uses up real resources’.92 Again, the hidden assumption
is that ‘growth is good’ since the cost of preservation may be ‘in terms
of some benefit foregone’. The inexpensive option of not developing is
discounted. Jacobs,93 in investigating the claim of this school of thought
to moral neutrality, points out that in their analysis of the environment
they depart completely from their analysis of ‘public goods’ the value of
which cannot be derived from individual market preference. In departing
from this tenet so far as environmental issues are concerned, they cease to
analyse the real world: ‘They are analysing what might happen if the envi-
ronment were a set of commodities . . . Why should economists analyse a
thing as if it were something else?’ Two answers are given by Jacobs to this
question: the first, that the creation of a pseudo-market creates protection
from the overuse of ‘free’ environmental goods, the second, that individ-
uals do in fact treat the environment as if it were a purchased commodity.
Jacobs advances criticisms of both of these answers. On the issue of pro-
tecting the environment by use of market mechanisms, Jacobs argues that
optimality may not be the sole criteria for allocating resources. We might,
he argues ‘tolerate some inefficiency in total allocation to ensure a more
egalitarian sharing-out – for example, insisting that everyone should have
access to the same quantity of drinking water.’ The construction of hypo-
thetical markets, especially on the basis of ‘willingness to pay’, ‘cannot
be divorced from ability to pay which leads inevitably to inegalitarian
outcomes’.94 The hypothetical market also leads to insufficient weight
being placed on rights over the environment, particularly where destruc-
tion may lead to destruction of a culture. Further, it gives insufficient
weight to the desires and wishes of future inhabitants, based as it is on the
preferences of the present generation. These may ‘express the interests of
the present generation in [future] people’. They do not ‘express the inter-
ests of future people’.95 These alternative bases for social choice expose
the hollowness of optimality as the foundation for action concerning the
environment. Optimality is derived from individually expressed choices.
Even supposing that this works with commodities where a market exists,
90 Jacobs, ‘Limits to Neoclassicism’, p. 74.
91 Pearce, Markandya and Barbier, Blueprint, p. 55.
92 Ibid., p. 56. 93 Jacobs, ‘Limits to Neoclassicism’. 94 Ibid., p. 76.
95 And ignores the interests of other species: ibid. The extinction of species may be ‘optimal’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
242 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
Jacobs points out that the individual preferences surrounding the hypo-
thetical market are just that – hypothetical. Thus, ‘in the case of the
environment there are no individually expressed preferences . . . it is no use
invoking the primacy of individual preferences to prove the primacy of
individual preferences. The importance of optimality is simply a value
judgment.’96 The claim to ethical neutrality is a sham and the real issue is
whether, because of the ‘public goods’ nature of the environment, a public
forum should take account of moral criteria rather than individual self-
interest. The second answer is met by evidence from contingent valuation
exercises which tend to show that it is not the case that the environment is
viewed as if it were merely another commodity, and explaining the signif-
icant failure to reach ‘a priced environment’ by the concept of ‘category
mistake’: ‘The environment belongs in the sphere not of monetary but of
moral valuation: people choose what they believe to be right as “citizens”,
rather than what is in their interests, as “consumers”.’97 Jacobs suggests
an alternative approach termed ‘institutional environmental economics’
which would research the way in which people actually value the envi-
ronment, as consumers or citizens, or a complex mixture of them both,
and would therefore address the ethical and moral effects of choices to be
made and the political process through which choices must be processed,
whether public or market-based.98
The sociologists
In order for sociologists to analyse environmental problems ‘some deep-
seated (and in important respects, well-founded) inhibitions need to be
overcome’.99 These include the recent experience of biological deter-
minism, including the holocaust, racism and sexism, as well as the foun-
dations of sociology which deliberately sought to create a human identity
separate from nature. The ‘dualist strategy of thinking about “nature”
and “society” (or “culture”) as qualitatively different realms offers one
obvious and unambiguous way of resisting biological determinism’.100
However, as Benton shows, dualist conceptions spawn a range of
approaches from naturalistic reductionism, through technological deter-
minism to sociological reductionism:
96 Ibid., p. 77.
97 Ibid., p. 81 and see M. Sagoff, The Economy of the Earth (Cambridge University Press,
1988).
98 Jacobs, ‘Limits to Neoclassicism’, pp. 86–7.
99 T. Benton and M. Redclift, ‘Introduction’ in Social Theory and the Global Environment
(Routledge, 1994).
100 T. Benton, ‘Biology and Social Theory’ in Benton and Redclift, Social Theory.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 243
In each case ‘nature’ is counterpoised to ‘society’, but at the polar extremes one of
these opposed terms tends to swallow up the other. In naturalistic reductionism
human society is seen as part of the wider totality of nature, whereas in the
more extreme forms of sociological (or discourse) reductionism, ‘nature’ becomes
transmuted into its symbolic representations.101
That this tradition is alive and well appears from Contested Natures102
in which Macnaughten and Urry argue against the claim that the envi-
ronment is ‘essentially a “real entity”, which, in and of itself and substan-
tially separate from social practices and human experience has the power
to produce unambiguous, observable and rectifiable outcomes’.103
Benton and Redclift argue that a further difficulty arises from the
parameters which have traditionally bounded sociological studies. The
nation state has been seen as of considerable significance and the gener-
alised, abstract nature of many theories ignores or minimises the impact
of space and time.104 The importance of breaking out of this way of
thought is of vital importance given the power imbalance between nation
states and TNCs. Sklair105 introduces the concept of transnational prac-
tices to add to analyses which concern relations between states and state
actors.106 Taking the analysis of O’Riordan107 that environmentalists can
be classified as ‘dry’, ‘shallow’ and ‘deep’, Sklair postulates that the global
environmental elite belonging to the two former categories are able to
understand and work with the global capitalist elite who are active in the
world’s trading systems. This is because that cumulative elite believe in a
‘technical fix’ of problems (dry greens) or in neo-classical ‘shallow green’
economic analysis:
Clearly, the dominant forces in the global capitalist system have no option but
to believe and act as if [the contradiction between capitalist development and
global survival] can be resolved by a combination of economic-technological,
political and culture ideology means. Part of this must involve the ways in which
the capitalist system uses the Third World to resolve the contradiction.108
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
244 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
109 P. Hirst and G. Thompson, Globalisation in Question (2nd edn, Blackwell, Oxford,
1996).
110 See ibid., esp. chs 6 and 7.
111 Will Hutton, ‘Anthony Giddens and Will Hutton in Conversation’ in W. Hutton and
A. Giddens (eds), On the Edge: Living with Global Capitalism (Cape, London, 2000).
112 Benton and Redclift, Social Theory, p. 7. 113 Ibid., p. 9.
114 Benton, ‘Biology and Social Theory’, p. 32. 115 Ibid., p. 32.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 245
116 D.H. Meadows, D.L. Meadows, J. Randers and W. Behrens, The Limits to Growth
(Universe Books, New York, 1972).
117 Benton, ‘Biology and Social Theory’, p. 33. 118 Ibid.
119 Ibid., p. 37. 120 Ibid.
121 A. Clayton, G. Spinardi and R. Williams, Policies for Cleaner Technology (Earthscan,
1999).
122 Ibid., p. 6. 123 U. Beck, Risk Society (translation published by Sage, London, 1992).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
246 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
124 Agreed 29 January 2000 in Montreal, see A. Quereshi, ‘The Cartagena Protocol on
Biosafety and the WTO: Co-existence or Incoherence?’ (2000) ICLQ 835.
125 P. Bernstein, Against the Gods: The Remarkable Story of Risk (Wiley, London, 1996).
126 B. Adams, ‘Running Out of Time’ in Benton and Redclift’ Social Theory, pp. 92, 93.
127 S. Lash, B. Szersynski and B. Wynne, Risk, Environment and Modernity: Towards a New
Ecology (Sage, 1996), p. 2.
128 Ibid., p. 3.
129 Beck, Risk Society, and ‘Risk Society and the Provident State’ in Lash, Szersynski and
Wynne, Risk, Environment.
130 Lash, Szersynski and Wynne, Risk, Environment, p. 13. 131 Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 247
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
248 Companies, International Trade and Human Rights
redistributive justice that has been buried by fear of the necessity for self-
denial and the complexity of the interrelations between the world trading
system and ecological concerns. It is this central importance of risk and
its assessment that may give us a clue to formulating new methods of
thought which can overcome the difficulties of the polarised and distant
modes of thought considered above and begin to develop an approach to
industrial processes which combines scientific and ethical thought. Some
small steps have been taken in the field of corporate governance which
may provide clues to a framework of thought.
Social ecologists argue that the ecological crisis is the outcome not of a
generalised anthropocentrism but of distorted social relations at work in
hierarchical systems where an elite subjugates others while ‘pillaging the
natural world for prestige, profit and control’.137 The solution suggested
is small societies ‘which recognise that human wellbeing is inextricably
bound up with the wellbeing of the natural world on which human life
depends’.138 Zimmerman’s study of radical ecology shows how deeply
diverse, even confused, its roots can be seen to be. Exposing the risk that
tendencies to enthrone the ‘natural’ can lead to the rise of authoritar-
ianism – ‘[i]n stressful times, people are all too willing to surrender to
leaders promising to end humanity’s alienation from nature’139 – Zim-
merman explores the roots of deep ecology through the 1960s counter-
culture, complete with psychotropic drugs, to religious and specifically
christian roots of the ecological crisis in the ‘domination of man’ over
nature.140 The rejection of modernity’s ‘dark side: its control obsession,
its logic of identity, its anthropocentric humanism’ by the mainstream
postmodernist theorists such as Derrida, Foucault, Lyotard and Deleuse
have cross-fertilised with deep ecology despite some initial mutual
suspicions.141 Adding to this the feminist perspective that androcentrism
is significantly to blame for the ecological crisis142 (however justified),
lays a fine foundation for a ‘green backlash’ which emphasises elitism,
obscurity, anti-christianity, an out-of-touch attitude, anti-male attitudes
and impossible and illogical solutions. ‘Deep-green perspectives often
rely on some version of an arcadian “golden age” in which humans lived
in harmony with one another and with nature.’143 The suggested solu-
tions ‘are remarkably consistent in their versions of the “cure”: a return
to a materially more simple, egalitarian and convivial, decentralized
communal existence’.144
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006
Corporate social responsibility 249
Conclusion
This study of one of the issues which lies at the heart of many of the codes
of conduct, whether they are globally proposed or adopted by compa-
nies, shows how one small element of corporate social responsibility can
become a matter of hot dispute and runs the risk of being subverted by
market fundamentalists or become meaningless by an appeal to ‘golden
age’ values. Much work remains to be done to identify a sound basis for
responsibility, to identify the values that should be espoused by an inter-
national concession theory and to feed them into systems of corporate
governance.145 Some suggestions are made in chapter 6.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Institute of Advanced Legal Studies, University of London, on 30 Mar 2020 at 12:44:16,
subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511660139.006