Plumbing The Depths: Marxism and The Holocaust: Callinicos, Alex
Plumbing The Depths: Marxism and The Holocaust: Callinicos, Alex
Callinicos, Alex.
Alex Callinicos
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 386
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 387
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 388
Facing Evil
The lacuna whose presence Mason retrospectively acknowledged in
his own major writings—“[t]he absence of biological politics and
genocide”—has certainly been removed in the contemporary histori-
ography of National Socialism.18 Raul Hilberg’s great pioneering
work The Destruction of the European Jews no longer stands alone: a host
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 389
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 390
sequently be in the Shoah, including the element of an irreducible choice. The pre-
conditions and the surrounding context of this kind of choice can and always must
be explored and described. But it remains in the end what it is: underdetermined, a
choice.22
Though this was the insight of what he calls a “powerful and cre-
ative Marxist intellect,” for Geras it goes beyond the limits of a con-
ventional Marxism, preoccupied as that is with precisely the “precon-
ditions and surrounding context” to which the will to destroy revealed
in both the Tsarist pogroms and the Holocaust itself cannot be re-
duced. It highlights that aspect of the Holocaust that he believes tends
to get neglected in interpretations such as Baumann’s that stress the
role played characteristic structures of modernity—for example, the
bureaucratic division of labour and the large-scale use of technol-
ogy—in allowing many perpetrators to distance themselves emotion-
ally as well as physically from the crimes they were helping to com-
mit. Geras argues that such analyses fail to give proper weight to “the
cruel desires and sense of an unusual elation, . . . the emotional charge
produced—and maybe required—by the assault upon the innocent”
evident in many descriptions of Nazi atrocities. “There is something
here that is not about modernity; something that is not about capital-
ism. It is about humanity.”23
As this last sentence implies, Geras’s argument rests ultimately on a
certain view of human nature. Elsewhere he makes this assumption
explicit, contending that a capacity for evil is an intrinsic feature of
human nature co-existing with more benign traits, and that socialist
theory and practice must take proper account of this potential.24 The
intuition expressed in the passage from Trotsky that Geras cites is in-
deed one that any proper understanding of mass murder must accom-
modate. A remarkably similar analysis of the psychological mechanism
described here by Trotsky was recently offered from the perspective of
an idiosyncratically Lacanian Marxism by Slavoj Žižek:
although, on the surface, the totalitarian Master . . . imposes severe orders, compelling
us to renounce our pleasures and to sacrifice ourselves to some higher Duty, his ac-
tual injunction, discernible beneath the lines of his explicit words, is exactly the op-
posite—the call to unconstrained and unrestrained transgression. Far from imposing on
us a firm set of standards to be obeyed unconditionally, the totalitarian Master that
suspends (moral) punishment—that is to say, his secret injunction is You may!: the pro-
hibitions that seem to regulate social life and guarantee a minimum of decency are
ultimately worthless, just a device to keep the common people at bay, while you are
allowed to kill, rape and plunder the Enemy, let yourself go and excessively enjoy, vi-
olate ordinary moral prohibitions . . . in so far as you follow Me!25
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 391
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 392
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 393
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 394
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 395
nity where German capital and labour were reconciled and the small
producer finally in the saddle. Here we see the centrality of racism to
National Socialism. Their supposedly common biological “race”
united Germans of all classes against the alien Jews and against other
inferior races, especially the Slavs, with whom, according Hitler’s So-
cial Darwinism, Germans were in competition for territory and re-
sources in the East.47
This racist, pseudo-revolutionary ideology provided the cement of
National Socialism as a mass movement. Trotsky noted that the ple-
beian, anti-capitalist character of Nazi ideology made using Hitler
risky for the German ruling class:“this method has its dangers. While
it makes use of fascism, the bourgeoisie nevertheless fears it.” Else-
where he wrote: “The political mobilization of the petty bourgeoisie
against the proletariat . . . is inconceivable without that social dema-
gogy which means playing with fire for the big bourgeoisie.” But,
though thus sensitive to the conflicts between the Nazis and the rul-
ing class, Trotsky assumed these would tend to be overcome once the
former took power, when the specificity of fascism as a distinctive
type of mass movement would progressively disappear: “as the Italian
example shows, fascism leads in the end to a military-bureaucratic dic-
tatorship of the Bonapartist type.” This implies a significant difference
between Nazism out of and in power:
German fascism, like Italian fascism, raised itself to power on the backs of the petty
bourgeoisie, which it turned into a battering ram against the organizations of the
working class and the institutions of democracy. But fascism in power is least of all the
rule of the petty bourgeoisie. On the contrary, it is the most ruthless dictatorship of
monopoly capital.48
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 396
The relationship between big business and the Nazis after Hitler’s ac-
cession to the Chancellorship was riddled with tensions. The conser-
vatives’ hopes of incorporating the Nazis as junior partners were soon
dashed. Hitler and his followers used the reign of terror they launched
against the organized working class both to demonstrate their useful-
ness to those who had brought them to power and also to conquer
exclusive control of the state (with the exception of the Reichswehr).
To quote Kershaw once again:
Only Hitler, and the huge—if potentially unstable—mass movement he headed, could
ensure control of the streets and bring about the “destruction of Marxism,” the basis
of the desired counter-revolution. Yet precisely this dependence on Hitler and eager-
ness to back the most ruthless measures adopted in the early weeks and months of the
new regime guaranteed that the weakness of the traditional elite groups would be laid
bare in the years to come as the intended counter-revolution gave way to the Nazi racial
revolution in Europe and opened the path to world conflagration and genocide.54
The Night of Long Knives ( June ) assuaged elite fears of
Nazi plebeian radicalism by eliminating Ernst Röhm and other lead-
ers of the SA (storm-troopers) who advocated a “Second Revolu-
tion,” but at the price of entrenching the Nazis in power and, in par-
ticular, allowing the SS (who carried out the massacre with the help
of the army), to extend their control of the security apparatus. The
months of – saw a further radicalization of the regime made
possible by the removal of the chiefs of the military (Blomberg and
Fritsch) and of Hjalmar Schacht, who had previously dominated the
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 397
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 398
then popular among the Communist Parties would predict. This in-
volved a pretty crude form of instrumentalism in which the state be-
comes the tool of a handful of big monopolists.59 Here rather the
Nazis (or, given the fragmentation of the Führerstaat, a section of the
National Socialist regime) used their control of the state to gain direct
access to the accumulation process. This helps to explain why the
Nazis did not simply, as Trotsky predicted, collapse into a conventional
military dictatorship: they converted political into economic power.
This achievement puts Mason’s “primacy of politics” into a different
light. The Hitler regime’s success in setting the parameters for private
capital was no mere act of ideological levitation, but was rather closely
associated with its success into entrenching itself in control of a large
and expanding state capital.60
This way of putting it also helps to place the evolution of National
Socialism in a wider context. For the s were marked by the dis-
integration of the world market, the contraction of foreign trade, and
a general drive by the state to supplant private enterprise that was
widely seen by left and right alike as having failed. The most extreme
case of this tendency towards state capitalism was, of course, the So-
viet Union during the so-called “Stalin revolution” of the late s
and the s, but the New Deal in the United States and the na-
tionalizations carried out even by the Tory-dominated National Gov-
ernment in Britain are other examples. The Nazis’ drive to autarky
and to war must be seen against this background: the increasing diffi-
culties faced by a largely closed German economy in obtaining scarce
raw materials through foreign trade undoubtedly played a part in
pushing the regime towards seizing them through territorial expan-
sion and military conquest.61 But the Nazis leaders’ judgement that
long-term survival depended on an imperial drive into eastern and
central Europe was an assessment they shared with key sections of
both big capital (particularly in heavy industry) and the military.62
Above all, Nazi radicalism respected certain limits: most importantly,
the basic structure of economy remained untouched. Germany under
Hitler remained an industrial capitalist society, with economic power
concentrated in the hands of big capital. From the perspective of the
basic structure of class relations, whether that capital took the form of
private enterprise or state concerns was a secondary matter. The
Utopia of a racially pure, socially homogeneous Volksgemeinschaft re-
mained just that. As Detlev Peukert puts it, “National Socialism
adapted readily to long-term trends towards modernization. In terms
of long-range socio-economic statistical data, the years of the Third
Reich (or at least the years of peace up to ) show no divergence,
either positive or negative.”63 The working class, though atomized and
subject to the end to the surveillance and terror of the Security Po-
lice, were able to use the conditions of full employment produced by
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 399
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 400
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 401
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 402
The conflicts of interest between the various power centres of the Third Reich,
which were constantly losing or gaining importance and influence, arose out of the
tension between differing and generally hypetrophied goals (of conquest), sanitized
social utopias, and the notorious scarcity of the materials necessary for these. Even
when the representatives of the various institutions pursued conflicting, mutually ex-
clusive interests, they were willing to work together to resolve the conflicts necessarily
produced by their divergent strategies—especially the intended speed of their imple-
mentation—with the help of theft, slave labour, and extermination.76
Critical to this process was the often only implicit role played by
biological racism in providing the framework of debate and the basis
on which decisions could be legitimized. The following remark of
Hitler’s to Himmler in comes as close as he ever did to
acknowledging the Holocaust, but it is also highly revealing of the
character of this ideology:“The discovery of the Jewish virus is one of
the greatest revolutions that have taken place in the world. The battle
in which we are engaged is of the same sort as the battle waged, dur-
ing the last century, by Pasteur and Koch. How many diseases have
their origin in the Jewish virus! . . . We shall regain our health only be
eliminating the Jew.”77
This medical language (also present in the common Nazi use of the
word “cleansing” as a euphemism for mass murder) is symptomatic of
a pseudo-scientific ideology that posited a hierarchical world of races
from which the “unfit” should be eliminated. It was in virtue of this
ideology that Hitler authorized the secret T- “euthanasia program”
under which between , and , mentally ill patients were
murdered in –: the personnel used and expertise acquired in
this operation were later transferred to the Operation Reinhard camps
(Belzec, Sobibor, and Treblinka).78 The same biological racism—a
modern ideology, not traditional anti-Semitism—motivated the murder
of the Roma and Sinti, largely through the initiative of the Criminal
Police (a separate wing of the RSHA from the Security Police) and
despite Hitler’s lack of personal interest in the “Gypsy Question.”79
But it was the Jewish “virus,” as Hitler called it, that represented the
most deadly danger to the health of the German Volk. As Paul Karl
Schmidt, press chief of the German Foreign Office, put it in :
“The Jewish question is no question of humanity and no question of
religion, but a question of political hygiene. Jewry is to be combated
wherever it is found, because it is a political infectant, the ferment of
disintegration and death of every national organism.”80 Thus when it
came to devising actual policies for the “final solution of the Jewish
question,” murder was the Nazis’ default position, set by an ideology
that identified the Jews as a deadly threat. The Holocaust was the out-
come of a bureaucratic problem-solving process over-determined by
the biological racism that constituted the ideological cement of Na-
tional Socialism.
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 403
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 404
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 405
This passage brings into focus the feeling that gradually develops
about the metaphor of “working towards the Führer ” while reading
Kershaw’s fine biography of Hitler—namely that a concept that
within certain narrow limits may be quite useful is being stretched to
the point of meaninglessness. There would often have been a discrep-
ancy between the actual motivations of the actors listed above and the
reasons that they gave in order to legitimize their actions within the
“public sphere” of the Third Reich. Kershaw covers himself against
this kind of objection by treating these cases as ones “where ideolog-
ical motivation was secondary, or perhaps even absent altogether, but
where the objective function of the actions was nevertheless to fur-
ther the potential for implementation of the goals which Hitler em-
bodied.”91 But what criterion is one to use in order to determine
whether particular actions had this “objective function”?
Kershaw talks of Hitler “representing” or “embodying” certain “ide-
ological imperatives,” but this simply pushes the problem back: how
are we establish what these imperatives were? To refer to Hitler’s per-
sonal goals would collapse into the kind of intentionalism that the
metaphor of “working towards the Führer” is presumably meant to
avoid. In a manner familiar to any student of Hegel, objectivism risks
sliding into its polar opposite, subjectivism. The only way to avoid this
trap is, in my view, to place at the basis of one’s interpretation of Na-
tional Socialism, not Hitler’s personal role as charismatic leader, but
rather the specific nature of Nazism as a distinctive kind of mass
movement.92
Here we return to Trotsky’s analysis of fascism. National Socialism
represented a particular response to the intense social and economic
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 406
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 407
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 408
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 409
each year because “they lack the food and minimal medical facilities
that would keep them alive,” a cause that it is well within human
power to remove.103
The point of these comparisons is not to relativize the Holocaust
out of existence, or to deny the historical specificity of the extermi-
nation of the Jews. Much of this essay has, after all, been devoted to
addressing this specificity. The point is rather that avoidable, socially
caused mass death is a chronic feature of the modern world. The mix
of causes of these mass deaths—economic structures, bureaucratic
callousness, collective ideologies, deliberate policy, and emotions as
diverse as hatred, greed, fear, indifference, and the enjoyment of a
perverted liberation—varies from case to case. If the Holocaust repre-
sents one extreme—that of deliberate, industrialized mass murder,
contemporary child mortality represents another—that of impersonal
structural causation.104 But both are avoidable, and both arose within
modern capitalism. Studying the extermination of the Jews is impor-
tant. We need to remember the victims and to remain alert against
movements reviving the obscene ideology of National Socialism. But
understanding the Holocaust can also help to prevent the mass mur-
ders that are happening now, and stop us from being mere bystanders.
Notes
1 This text provided the basis of my inaugural lecture at the University of York on March
. The interpretation it offers was originally given in a talk at Marxism (organized
by the Socialist Workers Party in London in July ). I am grateful to Tom Baldwin,
Norman Geras, Donny Gluckstein, and Julie Waterson for their comments. I should also
acknowledge two debts that date back to the s, to the late Tim Mason, for his per-
sonal kindness and the intellectual inspiration he offered, and to Colin Sparks for the
informal tutorials he gave me (amidst much friendly raillery) in the Marxist theory of
fascism.
2 K. Marx, Early Writings (Harmondsworth: Penguin, ), .
N. Finkelstein, The Holocaust Industry (London: Verso, ), .
P. Novick, The Holocaust and Collective Memory (London: Bloomsbury, ), –, n. .
The problem of comparison was effectively dealt with by some of the saner contributions
to the German Historikerstreit of the s: see especially H. Mommsen, “The New His-
torical Consciousness and the Relativizing of National Socialism,” in Forever in the Shadow
of Hitler? (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, ).
Novick., Holocaust and Collective Memory, .
W. G. Runciman, A Treatise on Social Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
), I. .
See, for example, S. Friedlander, ed., Probing the Limits of Representation (Cambridge: Har-
vard University Press, ), and N. Geras, “Life Was Beautiful Even There,” Imprints
().
N. Geras, “Marxists before the Holocaust,” in id., The Contract of Mutual Indifference (Lon-
don: Verso, ), –. On Mandel’s wartime brush with death see “The Luck of a
Crazy Youth,” in G. Achcar, ed., The Legacy of Ernest Mandel (London: Verso, ), where
Geras’s piece also appears.
E. Mandel, The Meaning of the Second World War (London: Verso, ), –. See also id.,
“Material, Social and Ideological Preconditions for the Nazi Genocide,” in Achcar, ed.,
Legacy of Ernest Mandel.
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 410
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 411
). See, for an alternative account of late th century Europe, E. J. Hobsbawm, The Age
of Empire 1875–1914 (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, ).
Id., Why Did the Heavens Not Darken? (New York: Pantheon, ), , , , . Mayer’s
detailed account of the Holocaust will be found in ibid., Part Three.
See, for example, C.R. Browning, “The Holocaust as By-product?” in id., The Path to
Genocide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ).
I. Kershaw, Hitler (London: Allen Lane, –), II. –.
W. Manoschek, “The Extermination of the Jews in Serbia,” in Herbert, ed., National So-
cialist Extermination Policies. See more generally O. Bartov, Hitler’s Army (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, ).
See, for example, A.J. Mayer, The Furies:Violence and Terror in the French and Russian Revo-
lutions (Princeton: Princeton University Press, ).
The aristocratic monde involved in the plot to kill Hitler is well evoked in some of the
memoir literature: see, for example, C. Bielenberg, The Past is Myself (London: Corgi, )
and The Berlin Diaries 1940–1945 of Marie ‘Missie’Vassiltichikov (London: Methuen, ).
J. Fest, Plotting Hitler’s Death (New York: Henry Holt, ), .
See, for example, D. Peukert, Inside Nazi Germany (Harmondsworth: Penguin, ) and,
for a general survey of the literature, M. Nolan, “Work, Gender, and Everyday Life: Re-
flections on Continuity, Normality and Agency in Twentieth-Century Germany,” in I.
Kershaw and M. Lewin, eds., Stalinism and Nazism (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, ).
Mayer, Why Did the Heavens Not Darken?, .
Ironically enough in the light of his later evolution, this characterization of National So-
cialism is very close to Ernst Nolte’s definition of fascism as “revolutionary reaction”: see
Three Faces of Fascism (New York: Mentor, ).
L. D. Trotsky, The Struggle against Fascism in Germany (New York; Pathfinder, ), .
Poulantzas, Fascisme et dictature, –.
Trotsky, Struggle against Fascism, .
Ibid., .
See the careful analysis of the evidence in D. Gluckstein, The Nazis, Capitalism and the
Working Class (London: Bookmarks, ), ch. , and Ian Kershaw’s summary of the state
of popular opinion on the eve of the Nazi seizure of power: Hitler, I. –.
D. Guerin, Fascism and Big Business (New York: Monad, ), .
Despite the immense value of Ian Kershaw’s Hitler as a compellingly written and scholarly
synthesis of a vast literature, Fest’s older biography (perhaps because his conservatism at-
tunes him more to the nuances of German cultural life) paints a more convincing portrait
of Hitler as a racial revolutionary who, when his Machiavellian engagement with the re-
alities of power finally failed at Stalingrad, relapsed into the Utopianism of the pre-
period, embracing what Fest calls “the strategy of a flamboyant downfall,” Hitler (Har-
mondsworth: Penguin, ), . See also, for example, ibid., –.
Trotsky, Struggle against Fascism, , , , . When Donny Gluckstein approvingly
cites the last two sentences quoted he is, I think, mistaken, even though I agree with the
argument that surrounds this quotation: Gluckstein, Nazis, Capitalism, and the Working
Class, .
Poulantzas, Fascisme et dictature, Pt. , ch. IV.
Fest, Plotting Hitler’s Death, .
In my view this is also the best way of conceptualizing the relationship between the state
and capital as such: see R. Miliband,“State Power and Class Interests,” New Left Review
() and C. Harman,“The State and Capitalism Today,” International Socialism . ().
The analysis put forward by Henry Ashby Turner in German Big Business and the Rise of
Hitler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ), though offered as a refutation of Marxist
accounts of Nazism, therefore actually provides detailed support for the interpretation de-
veloped here.
D. Peukert, The Weimar Republic (Harmondsworth: Penguin, ), –, –.
Kershaw, Hitler, I..
Ibid., I.; see generally ibid., I, chs. and .
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 412
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 413
a l e x ca l l i n i c o s
03.callinicos.384-414 8/28/01 11:13 AM Page 414
t h e ya l e j o u r n a l o f c r i t i c i s m