Chapter 1 - Constructivism in Mathematics Education PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 29

Chapter 1: Constructivism in Mathematics Education

Author(s): Nel Noddings


Source: Journal for Research in Mathematics Education. Monograph, Vol. 4, Constructivist
Views on the Teaching and Learning of Mathematics (1990), pp. 7-18+195-210
Published by: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/749909
Accessed: 23-08-2018 15:35 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/749909?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

National Council of Teachers of Mathematics is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,


preserve and extend access to Journal for Research in Mathematics Education.
Monograph

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Chapter 1: Constructivism in Mathematics Education

Nel Noddings
Stanford University

Constructivism is a popular position today not only in mathematics education (von Glasers-
feld, 1987a) but in developmental psychology, theories of the family, human sexuality,
psychology of gender (Hare-Mustin & Marecek, 1988), and even computer technology
(Forman & Pufall, 1988). It is also the center of considerable controversy in mathematics
education (Brophy, 1986a; Confrey, 1986). In a spirit of support for what constructivists are
trying to accomplish, I want to discuss some strengths and weaknesses in the position. In
particular, I will suggest that constructivism is not a strong epistemological position despite
its adherents' claims. Indeed it might best be offered as a post-epistemological perspective.
I will begin by providing some background on constructivism; next I will discuss its
epistemological weaknesses and, finally, its great strengths as a pedagogical view.

Background
Constructivism may be characterized as both a cognitive position and a methodological
perspective (Noddings, 1973). As a methodological perspective in the social sciences,
constructivism assumes that human beings are knowing subjects, that human behavior is
mainly purposive, and that present-day human organisms have a highly developed capacity
for organizing knowledge (Magoon, 1977). These assumptions suggest methods-
ethnography, clinical interviews, overt thinking, and the like-specially designed to study
complex semi-autonomous systems.
As a cognitive position, constructivism holds that all knowledge is constructed and
that the instruments of construction include cognitive structures that are either innate
(Chomsky, 1968; 1971) or are themselves products of developmental construction (Piaget,
1953; 1970a; 1971a). The latter interpretation is more characteristic of constructivism as a
cognitive position, and it is the one held by most constructivists in mathematics education.
A philosophical shift in the 1960's and 70's from behaviorism to various forms of
structuralism and cognitivism induced exciting changes in psychology, sociology, linguistics,
and anthropology. It also revived and invigorated a whole field of study-psycholinguistics
(Slobin, 1971). Cognitive psychology renewed its interest in concept formation, complex

I want to thank Jim Greeno and Denis Phillips for helpful suggestions on a first draft.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
8

problem solving, and the connection between cognitive structures and behavior. One form of
cognitivism became known as constructivism. Ulric Neisser describes it as follows:

The present approach is more closely related to that of Bartlett (1932, 1958) than to
any other contemporary psychologist, while its roots are at least as old as the "act
psychology" of the nineteenth century. The central assertion is that seeing, hearing,
and remembering are all acts of construction, which may make more or less use of
stimulus information depending on circumstances. (1967, p. 10)

Here we note something that will be important in the later discussion. According to
Neisser, all mental processes are constructive, and the line between perception and cognition
is blurred. Even the processes often regarded as passive, such as seeing and hearing, are
described as constructive. If Neisser is correct, then learners are necessarily performing acts
of construction even in situations of so-called rote learning. I will return to the problems this
raises for constructivist teaching when I discuss the connection between activity and learning,
but for now it is enough to note that constructivists in mathematics education do not disagree
with Neisser's description of cognitive activity. Von Glasersfeld (1987b), for example, says,
"perceiving, from a constructivist point of view, is always an active making rather than a
passive receiving..." (p. 217).
While Neisser traced his constructivism to act psychology, Piaget traced his more
directly to Kantian philosophy. In Insights and Illusions of Philosophy (1971b), he credited
Kant with the first description of an epistemological subject. Kant, that is, described the
structures by which any competent subject acquires or generates knowledge. Piaget followed
Kant in distinguishing between empirical knowledge (knowledge of the contingent world)
and logico-mathematical knowledge (knowledge of necessary truths). But he broke with
Kant in describing cognitive structures as products of development rather than innate
structures. This is a matter on which he also differed from Chomsky. Whereas Chomsky
holds that the linguistic structures of mind are innate, Piaget insisted that certain logical
structures, developed through the coordination of actions, precede linguistic development and
make the construction of linguistic structures possible (1971a). Although both Chomsky and
Piaget call for the development of competence theories that describe the structures of mind
(Noddings, 1974), Chomsky's view is anchored in the philosophical tradition of rationalism,
while Piaget's is much closer to the dynamic perspective of pragmatism.
In accepting the Kantian distinction between empirical and logico-mathematical
knowledge, Piaget accepted the difficult task of explaining the development of cognitive
mathematical structures. Here Piaget relied on the concept of reflective abstraction.
Reflective abstraction is different from classical abstraction in that it does not proceed from a
series of observations of contingent events or objects. Rather, it is a process of interiorizing

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
9

our physical operations on objects. As we move sets of objects about (put them together,
rearrange them, separate them), we interiorize properties of mathematical operations rather
than objects; we acquire implicit understanding of commutativity, associativity, and
reversibility. Here the claim is that there is an essential connection between purposive
activity and the development of cognitive structure. There is also a recognition (sometimes
overlooked by contemporary radical constructivists) that the objects play a role in reflective
abstraction; that is, epistemological subjects and objects are indissociably linked in
operational events. We cannot force certain results onto the objects we operate on. Our
operations are somehow constrained. There is an inevitability about the outcomes and
characteristics of operations. That is why the resulting structures are logico-mathematical
and why their workings are marked by necessity. This conclusion suggests a challenge to
those constructivists who emphasize the uniqueness of individual constructions, and I will
discuss the problems of conflating individual subject and epistemological subject a bit later.
Piaget's theories are, in the important sense just described, thoroughly constructivist.
Not only are intellectual processes themselves constructive-a point on which both Neisser
and Chomsky would agree-but cognitive structures themselves are products of continued
construction. Constructivism is rooted in the idea of an epistemological subject, an active
knowing mechanism that knows through continued construction. This active construction
implies both a base structure from which to begin construction (a structure of assimilation)
and a process of transformation or creation which is the construction. It implies, also, a
process of continual revision of structure (a process of accommodation). Finally, Piaget's
cognitive constructivism leads logically to methodological constructivism. The need to
identify and describe various cognitive structures in all phases of construction suggests
methods such as the clinical interview and prolonged observation that permit us to make
inferences about the structures that underlie behavior.

So far I have concentrated on constructivist writings and debates two decades old. A
search of current literature shows that the concept pops up everywhere. For example,
Thoresen (1988) has raised questions about the rigor and clarity of "constructivism" in
counseling psychology. But, although mathematics educators also cite some recent thinkers
on constructivism (see other chapters in this volume), there seem to be few epistemological
advances beyond Piaget. This is not to say that there have been no advances in the
psychological aspects of constructivism. Cognitive scientists and mathematics educators who
favor the cognitive science approach have moved well beyond Piaget in describing the way
"minds" operate to build representations, retrieve "frames," copy items from long term
memory, and match initial frames with the demands of a current problem. (See, for example,
Davis, 1984; Kintsch & Greeno, 1985; Papert, 1980; Simon, 1979). However, most of these

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
10

researchers are interested in the way our minds work, not in the epistemological status of the
mind's products. Further, their language-"copying," "non-destructive read outs," "frames,"
"retrieval"-is highly colored by work with computers. There is a shift from the organic
language of Piaget to machine language. Many such writers do not even use the word
constructivism, although they embrace the central idea that the operations of mind are
constructed. I intend no criticism in these remarks about cognitive science advances, but I
want to emphasize the psychological and pedagogical aspects of these advances; they are not
epistemological.
Constructivists in mathematics education contend that cognitive constructivism
implies pedagogical constructivism; that is, acceptance of constructivist premises about
knowledge and knowers implies a way of teaching that acknowledges learners as active
knowers. As Gerald Goldin notes in his chapter in this volume, it is clear that one can
embrace the pedagogical methods suggested by constructivists without accepting
constructivist premises. It may also be the case that a convinced philosophical constructivist
need not, logically, employ only so-called constructivist methods. That will be an important
issue when we discuss the connection between activity and learning.
Although there are conceptual differences in current constructivist views (and some of
these will be important in the coming analysis), constructivists generally agree on the
following:

1. All knowledge is constructed. Mathematical knowledge is constructed, at least in


part, through a process of reflective abstraction.

2. There exist cognitive structures that are activated in the processes of construction.
These structures account for the construction; that is, they explain the result of
cognitive activity in roughly the way a computer program accounts for the output of a
computer.

3. Cognitive structures are under continual development. Purposive activity induces


transformation of existing structures. The environment presses the organism to adapt.

4. Acknowledgment of constructivism as a cognitive position leads to the adoption of


methodological constructivism.

a. Methodological constructivism in research develops methods of study consonant


with the assumption of cognitive constructivism.

b. Pedagogical constructivism suggests methods of teaching consonant with


cognitive constructivism.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
11

Constructivism as Epistemology
All knowledge is constructed (von Glasersfeld, 1987a). Is this an epistemological or a
psychological claim? Constructivists, following Piaget, usually reject this question as a form
of philosophical error. In this view epistemology and psychology are so intricately bound up
in each other that it makes no sense to try to separate them. Constructivists have an
important insight here-one shared in part by earlier pragmatists and contemporary
philosophers whose views of knowledge tend toward pragmatism. Wittgenstein, even in his
positivist days, dismissed epistemology as "the philosophy of psychology" (1961), and more
recently W. V. O. Quine has argued for the "naturalization of epistemology" (1969). Richard
Rorty (1979) goes even further and suggests that both traditional epistemology and the
various structuralisms of Piaget, Chomsky, Levi-Strauss, Marx, and Freud are on a similar
wrong track (p. 249)-the quest for a description of nature through the workings of mind.
I think Rorty is right when he says that the attempt to construct or discover a
foundation for science (and all knowledge) is hopeless whether one depends on the structures
of perception (observation), self-evident truths, or cognition. But even if foundational
epistemology is rejected (and this is what constructivists should do), some epistemological
questions remain, and, of course, constructivists have not rejected epistemology. Thus our
initial question retains its point: What sort of assumption (epistemological, psychological, or
both) is being made when one says, "All knowledge is constructed"?
The question can be logically broken into two parts. First, what has the assumption to
do with judging the status of general knowledge claims? Given a statement offered as a bit of
knowledge, how does the claim about construction help us to decide what becomes part of
the bona fide body of knowledge and what does not? Second, if we focus on knowers, how
do we judge when they know and when they do not? These are two basic questions of
epistemology.
Let's consider, first, knowledge as a set of statements in the public domain. Here we
are not asking what it means to say: Joe knows p. We are asking, rather, what it means to
claim p as a bit of knowledge. One of the first questions we ask when we are faced with an
alleged knowledge claim is, "Who said that?" Ifp is a mathematical statement, we are more
likely to accept it if George Polya or John von Neumann is its source than if, say, Ronald
Reagan or a local high school student came up with it. The mathematicians have an authority
that the other two do not have.

But our judgment is not based on raw authority. The mathematicians' authority is not
like that of the pope (or, at least, it shouldn't be). We do not accept their word simply
because their office confers unassailable authority. Rather we accept p, tentatively, because

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
12

we know that mathematicians belong to a community that subjects all knowledge claims to
careful scrutiny, and the criteria for such scrutiny are laid out for all the community to see.
The fact (if it is one) that p was constructed is irrelevant as a criterion for its status as

knowledge. Constructivists are right when they suggest that the genesis ofp is not irrelevant
to the growth of mathematical knowledge, nor is it irrelevant to someone's learning about p .
Studying the construction ofp can lead to a host of objections, revisions, and new hypotheses
(Lakatos, 1976), and it can provide insight for learners. What the construction cannot do,
however, unless it is part of the proof itself, is to establish p's status as knowledge.
The fact thatp was constructed tells us nothing about truth, knowledge, the
justification of belief, or the nature of evidence-all traditional interests in epistemology.
Rather, the constructivist assumption should be followed by a break with epistemology.
Having accepted the basic constructivist premise, there is no point in looking for foundations
or using the language of absolute truth. The constructivist position is really post-
epistemological, and that is why it can be so powerful in inducing new methods of research
and teaching. It recognizes the power of the environment to press for adaptation, the
temporality of knowledge, and the existence of multiple selves behaving in consonance with
the rules of various subcultures. What is left of epistemological questions may be divided
among mathematics (its canons and methods), the sociology of knowledge (what groups have
the power to label p knowledge), and the psychology of learning and teaching.
Many of the traditional questions of epistemology would be shifted to mathematics
itself. Here, clearly, a body of knowledge is continually under construction, and some
nucleus of it is firmly established. Mathematicians need not answer the question what
knowledge is generally; they need only describe mathematical knowledge and the tests a
proposition must pass to be admitted to that body of knowledge. In an important sense, at
any given time, there is a world of mathematics already established to be discovered by
individual students. If a student picks up a bit of this pre-established material, does he or she
have knowledge? Under what circumstances?
These questions lead us to the second part of our question: How does the
constructivist assumption help us to decide whether a knower knows? All knowledge is
constructed. If Neisser's premise-that all mental acts are constructive-is accepted, then
this basic claim-as an epistemological claim-is trivial. We cannot distinguish between
knowledge and other mental products, or even errors, by virtue of their construction. A
difficulty that arises in constructivist talk is this: On the one hand, if students memorize p,
we often deny that the students have knowledge of p, even ifp is well established in the
public domain; if, on the other hand, students come up with q as a result of construction, we
sometimes accept q as knowledge even if it is demonstrably false.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
13

Consider, first, constructions that are somehow faulty or lead to results that are

wrong. The most notorious is Erlwanger's Benny (1973). Benny had a system for converting
his answers to the ones on the answer sheet provided by the curriculum. His method was
systematic, and he could explain it. Converting 3/2 to .5, for example, involved adding 2 and
3 and prefixing a decimal point. That this rule also made it possible to convert 2/3 to .5 did
not seem to bother Benny.
Constructivists often point to the case of Benny because it illustrates how badly
mathematics can be learned when a curriculum does not encourage mathematical thinking.
But the problem here is not that Benny fails to construct (he could hardly avoid doing so) but,
rather, that the environment fails to press Benny to correct his misconceptions. The
constructivist teacher would prefer to help Benny by having him explore whether the result
3/2 = 2/3 is satisfactory. If it is not, then some change in his procedural rules is clearly
necessary. But old-fashioned behaviorists might simply put Benny on a schedule of practice
that includes very careful evaluation of his responses and immediate feedback. Benny, by
definition, would still be constructing, but constructivists consider constructions performed in
such situations to be less powerful than the sort generated by personal puzzlement, goal-
setting, testing hypotheses, etc.

In rejecting Benny's claims to knowledge, constructivists should abandon traditional


epistemological talk. Here is a construction. In a domain other than mathematics-with

some other, nonmathematical, objects-this construction of Benny's might make sense.


Indeed Benny's response to the curriculum that isolated him so completely was an adaptive
response. He succeeded at whatever game he was playing, but he was not playing the game
of mathematics. This suggests-and here is the great strength of pedagogical
constructivism-that the teacher's main function is to establish a mathematical environment.

A second, obverse, difficulty arises when constructivists want to deny that rote
responses represent knowledge. If a student recites a bit of arithmetical information, for
example, but does not understand where this information came from or how it can be used,

we often say the student does not "really know." We reject his statement as a knowledge
claim.

Now, traditional epistemology can do this because it has a criterion of justified true
belief that must be applied to every case of claiming to know. This assumes that things can
be true quite independently of any knower's activity. For A to know x x must be true, A
must believe x and A must have good reasons for believing x. The student who simply
parrots something may indeed be denied a claim to knowledge. (Even this is not a simple
matter, however, because we can find substantial philosophical reasons for accepting "the
teacher said so" as a good enough reason to support a student's claim! For more on

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
14

"epistemic dependence," see Siegel, 1988.) To reject as knowledge a claim that the
community accepts as true is a tricky business.
How can constructivists reject such a knowledge claim? They might begin by saying
that the student cannot give an adequate account of x. For example, how is x derived? But
we do not expect students to be able to give this sort of account of most x 's. "How did you
get it?" is the question we usually ask. The answers we accept to this question are based
inevitably on the already established body of mathematical knowledge and the canons of
thinking laid down by the mathematical community.
The constructivist suggests that we can make a decision on the basis of whether or not
x was constructed. But does this make sense? As a cognitive position, constructivism asserts
that all mental activity is constructive. Even when students are in what look to be rote
learning situations, they must perforce construct, because that is the way the mind operates.
So it seems to me that constructivists should talk about weak and strong acts of construction
rather than acts involving or not involving construction. In mathematical environments,
strong acts of construction would no doubt be those recognized by mathematicians as
mathematical; weak constructions would be those evaluated as limited in mathematical use.

(I have already discussed those-like Benny's-that might be judged faulty because they do
not belong at all to the applicable mathematical domain.)
Some genuine and very tough questions about teaching follow. Might it not be the
case, for example, that some students perform strong acts of construction no matter how the
material is presented? And might it not also be the case that, while the teacher is encouraging
exploration and genuine (strong) acts of construction, some students perform weak acts such
as quietly waiting for group consensus and then noting the answer?
Both aspects of the question about a knower's status need further analysis,
elaboration, and clarification. It is by no means clear that the current use of epistemological
language will be particularly helpful in this task. What is clear is that the emphasis on
construction forces us to probe deeply into students' activity. How firm a grasp do they have
on the material? What can they do with it? What misconceptions do they entertain? Even if
they are producing wrong answers, are they constructing in a way that is mathematically
recognizable? These are among the questions we need to ask in order to teach effectively,
and they are not epistemological.

Methodological Constructivism
Acceptance of the premise that knowledge and (many constructivists would say) reality itself
are constructed leads to methodological constructivism. In research this means that we have
to investigate our subjects' perceptions, purposes, premises, and ways of working things out if

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
15

we are to understand their behavior. Even at the contextual level, as we try to understand the
effects of physical and cultural environments on people, we have to look at their purposive
interaction with those environments. We no longer believe that people are simply caused to
behave in certain ways by an environment that is entirely external to and independent of their
cognitive processes.
For teachers, methodological constructivism becomes pedagogical constructivism. In
order to teach well, we need to know what our students are thinking, how they produce the
chain of little marks we see on their papers, and what they can do (or want to do) with the
material we present to them. But the cognitive premises of constructivism can dictate only
guidelines for good teaching. We cannot derive from them, any more than we can from any
other cognitive position, specific teaching methods.
Pedagogical constructivism suggests more sophisticated diagnostic tools-tools that
will uncover patterns of thinking, systematic errors, persistent misconceptions (see Confrey,
this volume). Further, the elaboration required in, say, thinking aloud in the presence of a
teacher encourages students to concentrate on the question or problem at hand. Conducted
well, such a session gives the teacher many opportunities to reassure students that they are
doing some things right, that their thinking has some power, that their errors are
correctable. Above all such a method can be used to create a mathematical environment-

one that will press for mathematical adaptation rather than a form suitable for another
environment.

Overt thinking is, or can be, a powerful teaching method as well as a diagnostic tool,
but teachers need not be confined to it by their constructivism. For example, if a teacher
learns through such a diagnostic session that Betsy is making a certain kind of error over and
over, it seems perfectly reasonable to show her how to do the procedure correctly and give
her a batch of practice exercises. It may indeed be reasonable to provide whole classes with
drill and practice at appropriate times. In particular if it is clear that performance errors (e.g.,
wrongly combining or simplifying radicals) are getting in the way of concentrating on more
significant problems, straightforward practice may actually facilitate genuine problem
solving.
I am not recommending that students be kept at drill and practice for days or years on
end (until, as some say, they've mastered the basics). Rather, I'm suggesting that teachers
anticipate some of the skills that students will likely need to construct important concepts and
principles. Students need building materials, tools, patterns, and sound work habits if they
are to construct mathematical objects and relationships. Some of these materials, tools, and
patterns can and should be created through strong acts of construction by the students
themselves; others might simply be accepted and tried out on trust (weak acts, but not faulty).

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
16

Constructivist premises imply that there will be many roads to most solutions or
instructional endpoints. We cannot, therefore, be sure that all students will find the
anticipated skills necessary or even useful in their constructions. But there is a high
probability that some particular skills will be needed in any given task. Any teacher who has
conducted an overt thinking session sympathizes with students who must agonize over every
step of a solution-often forgetting in the process why they are dividing, or solving a
proportion, or factoring an unwieldy expression. My point here is that we need not discard
all of the strategies recommended by theorists who espouse direct instruction (Brophy,
1986a; Good, Grouws, & Ebmeier, 1983) even if we disagree with them on fundamental
cognitive premises (Noddings, 1986).
Many mathematics educators recognize the power of "constructivist methods" in one-
to-one situations, but they also see that schoolteachers cannot work continuously in such
situations (Cobb, Wood, & Yackel, this volume). Classroom conditions force us to think
about instructional economies. Constructivist teachers have to keep their basic premises in
mind, but they should feel free to adapt a wide variety of methods for their own purposes.
Given our premises, we need to get thinking out into the open, to encourage students to
conceive their own mathematical purposes and execute their own plans, and to provide
situations and objects that may trigger conflict (disequilibrium) and reflective abstraction.
How can we do all this with a classroom full of students, and what pitfalls lie in our way?
Consider, first, the common constructivist recommendation that teachers make heavy
use of manipulatives. This recommendation was an early and plausible attempt to apply
Piagetian theory directly to teaching. If reflective abstraction proceeds from the operations
we perform on objects, then it makes sense to have our students work with objects. The
difficulty, of course, is that students must have a purpose for engaging in the manipulation of
objects. Otherwise, objects can be as mysterious as numerals; even Cuisenaire rods can
become "symbols made of colored wood" (Holt, 1964).
Understanding this possibility, we need, perhaps, to provide some direct instruction
on the use of various manipulatives and then simply make them available. In actual problem
solving situations, we probably should not guide students in their use. If we do, we are likely
to detach students from their own purposes and set them blindly to work on our own.
Caveats of this sort spring up everywhere in constructivist teaching. Students will construct,
but we want their constructions to be guided by mathematical purposes, not by the need to
figure out what teachers want or where they are headed.
Next, because teachers have to work with many children, it makes sense to ask
whether there is a way to approximate the one-to-one situation with a whole class. Can we
elicit genuine student thinking in the whole class situation? Several promising models have

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
17

appeared (see the essays in this volume and also Davis, 1984; Lampert, 1988; Schoenfeld,
1985; Steffe, Cobb, & von Glasersfeld, 1988). All of these methods share a common
characteristic: They are all highly interactive. Teachers both model and elicit, but they
model by asking questions, following leads, and conjecturing rather than presenting faultless
products. Teaching this way requires considerable mathematical knowledge as well as
pedagogical skill. How can teachers follow students' suggestions if they do not know enough
mathematics to perceive where the suggestions may lead? This is a problem for teacher
education.

But a caveat again arises directly out of the constructivist framework. While a lesson
of the sort advocated above is conducted, students will be "constructing." Some will be
performing strong (mathematical) acts of construction. Hearing evidence of such thinking,
teachers (and observers) may be delighted with the lesson. But other students (how many?)
may be performing weak acts on the problem at hand, and some may be "chasing deer in the
wildwood" as Virgil Mallory used to say. It would, therefore, seem unwise to rely on such
lessons day in and day out.
How else can we induce the engagement that is essential if students are to perform
powerful constructions? One possibility is to increase the amount of time students spend
working together (see Cobb, Wood, & Yackel; Maher & Alston, this volume). The use of
small groups in cooperative learning is becoming a popular strategy, and there are sound
cognitive reasons for allowing students to work together. Vygotsky (1978) posited group
interaction as one source in the development of mental operations; that is, he suggested that
children gradually internalize the talk that occurs in groups. They begin to challenge
themselves, ask for reasons, and in general monitor their own mental work as others do their
public speech. Cobb, Wood, and Yackel follow a line of thinking called "social
constructivism" that puts great emphasis on the processes of communicating and negotiating
in communities. A difficulty here is that, once again, we must somehow ensure that the
community is a mathematical community. To assume that the deliberations of any
community-conducted by some general plan of right action-will lead to acceptable
mathematical results suggests a traditional epistemology. In a post-epistemological
perspective, we recognize the canons and ways authorized by this particular community. (On
the possibility of construing epistemology as itself the study of human understanding, see
Toulmin, 1972.)
But group work is not a pedagogical panacea in any case (see Noddings, 1989). Some
students may participate eagerly while others sit out the session waiting for answers to
develop. Assigning rigid roles so that everyone has to participate can distract students'
attention from mathematics to the group process itself. Further, students can be rude and cruel

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
18

to one another, and teachers have to watch group operations to be sure that students are
learning to help and care for each other-not just to solve problems in expeditious ways.
Here, too, there is a large part for teacher education to play. The literature on small
groups and cooperative learning is growing rapidly. What kind of small group scheme should
teachers use? How should groups be constituted? For what kinds of task? Should there be
inter-group competition? Should teachers use individual or group evaluation? Will the end-
product be a group one or set of individual ones (Noddings, 1989)? Teachers need to be well-
informed in order to use these methods effectively. Further, constructivist teachers need
practice in selecting and justifying the forms that are compatible with constructivist premises.
The great strength of constructivism is that it leads us to think critically and

imaginatively about the teaching-learning process. Believing the premises of constructivism,


we no longer look for simple solutions, and we have a powerful set of criteria by which to
judge our possible choices of teaching method.
I will close by giving a simple example of a teacher's constructivist thinking. Suppose
I am concentrating on the central problem of getting my students' thinking out into the open.
As I mark a set of tests, I realize that, alas, students are not showing their work as I have
instructed them to do. Then I look at what I'm doing-taking off points here and there for
small or large errors. Aha! Suppose I switch to a positive scheme of grading? The next day,
and before every written exercise thereafter, I remind students that I'll be searching for

thoughts to reward. They will get points for useful pictures, charts, formulas, statements that
suggest either hypotheses or doubts, challenges to the question itself. And then I do this. No
more -2s and -10s. Their papers will, rather, be peppered with +2s and +10s together with
remarks encouraging attempts or explaining why an attempt failed. The result should be lots
more student talk on paper. (It worked for me, by the way.) This is just one example of
constructivist thinking applied to an everyday problem of schoolteaching, but it illustrates the

power of constructivism as a cognitive and methodological position.

Conclusion

Constructivism is, logically, a post-epistemological position. The standard questions of


epistemology cannot be answered-or even reasonably asked-from this perspective. Its
premises suggest, rather, abandonment of traditional epistemological language. This move
leads us to concentrate on constructivism as a cognitive position and methodological
perspective. As such, it can be powerful in helping us to study mathematical learning, to
develop appropriate teaching strategies, and to reflect on the everyday problems of
schoolteaching. But it requires considerably more analysis and elaboration in the community
of mathematics educators if it is to meet the kinds of legitimate objections I have noted here.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
References

Anonymous
Anonymous(1711).
(1711).Osservazioni,
Osservazioni,Giornale
Giornale
de'Letterati
de'Letterati
d'ltalia,
d'ltalia,
5(6), 5(6),
137-140.
137-140.
(Reprinted
(Reprinted
in i
Vico,
Vico, 1858).
1858).

Baird,
Baird, J.,
J.,&&White,
White,R.R.(1984).
(1984).
Improving
Improving learning
learning
through
through
enhanced
enhanced
metacognition:
metacognition:
A A
classroom
classroomstudy.
study.Paper
Paper presented
presentedthethe
annual
annual
meeting
meeting
of the
of American
the American
Educational
Educational
Research
Research Association.
Association.New
New Orleans,
Orleans,
LA.LA.

Baroody,
Baroody, A.A.J.
J.(1985).
(1985).Mastery
Masteryof of
thethe
basic
basic
number
number
combinations:
combinations:
Interalization
Interalization
of of
relationships
relationshipsor orfacts?
facts?Journalfor
Journalfor Research
Research
in Mathematics
in Mathematics
Education,
Education,
16(2), 16(2),
83-98.83-98.

Baroody,
Baroody, A.
A.J.J.(1987a).
(1987a).
Children's
Children's
mathematical
mathematicalthinking:
thinking:
A developmentalframeworkfor
A developmentalframeworkfo
preschool,
preschool,primary,
primary,and andspecial
special
education
education
teachers.
teachers.
NewNew
York:
York:
Teachers
Teachers
College
College
Press. Press

Baroody,
Baroody, A.
A.J.
J.(1987b).
(1987b).
The
The
development
development
of counting
of counting
strategies
strategies
for single-digit
for single-digit
addition.
addition.
Journalfor
JournalforResearch
ResearchininMathematics
Mathematics
Education,
Education,
18(2),
18(2),
141-157.
141-157.

Baroody,
Baroody, A.
A.J.,
J.,&&Gannon,
Gannon,K.K.
E. E.
(1984).
(1984).
TheThe
development
development
of the
of commutativity
the commutativityprinciple
principl
and
and economical
economicaladdition
addition
strategies.
strategies.Cognition
Cognition
andand
Instruction,
Instruction,
1(3), 1(3),
321-329.
321-329.

Baroody,
Baroody, A.
A.J.,
J.,&&Ginsburg,
Ginsburg, H. H.
P. P.
(1986).
(1986).
TheTherelationship
relationship
between
between
initial
initial
meaningful
meaningful
and an
mechanical
mechanicalknowledge
knowledgeofofarithmetic.
arithmetic. In J.
In Hiebert
J. Hiebert
(Ed.),
(Ed.),
Conceptual
Conceptual
and procedural
and procedural
knowledge:
knowledge:The
Thecase
caseofof
mathematics
mathematics (pp.(pp.
75-112).
75-112).
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence
NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum
Erlbaum
Associates.

Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

Bartlett, F. C. (1958). Thinking. New York: Basic Books.

Bauersfeld, H. (1988). Interaction, construction, and knowledge: Alternative perspectives for


mathematics education. In T. Cooney & D. Grouws (Eds.), Effective mathematics
teaching (pp. 27-46). Reston, VA: NCTM.

Biggs, E. (1987). Understanding area. Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 6 (3), 197-199.

Bishop, A. (1985). The social construction of meaning-a significant development for


mathematics education? For the Learning of Mathematics, 5 (1), 24-28.

Blumer, H. (1969). Symbolic interactionism. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Bogdanov, A. (1909). Science and philosophy. In (anonymous editor), Essays on the


philosophy of collectivism (Vol.1). St. Petersburg.

Bridgman, P. (1934). A physicist's second reaction to Mengenlehre. Scripta Mathematica, 2,


101-117; 224-234.

Brophy, J. (1986a). Teaching and learning mathematics: Where research should be going.
Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 17, 323-346.

Brophy, J. (1986b). What are the data?-A reply to Confrey. Journalfor Research in
Mathematics Education, 17, 361-368.

195

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
196

Brown,
Brown,J.J.
S.,S.,
& Burton,
& Burton,R. R. R.
(1978).
R. (1978).
Diagnostic
Diagnostic
models formodels
procedural
forbugs
procedural
in basic bugs in basic
mathematical
mathematical skills.
skills.
Cognitive
Cognitive
Science,
Science,
2, 155-192.
2, 155-192.

Brown,
Brown,J.J.
S.,S.,
Collins,
Collins,
A., &A.,
Duguid,
& Duguid,
P. (1989).
P.Situated
(1989). cognition
Situatedand
cognition
the culture
andof the culture of
learning.
learning. Educational
Educational
Researcher,
Researcher,
18 (1), 32-42.
18 (1), 32-42.

Brown,
Brown,S. S.
I., I.,
& Walter,
& Walter,
M. I. M.
(1983).
I. (1983).
The art The
of problem
art of posing.
problemPhiladelphia:
posing. The
Philadelphia:
Franklin The Franklin
Institute
Institute Press.
Press.

Brownell,
Brownell, W.W.
A. (1935).
A. (1935).
Psychological
Psychological
considerations
considerations
in the learning
in the
andlearning
the teaching
andofthe teaching of
mathematics.
mathematics. In D.
InW.D. Reeve
W. Reeve
(Ed.), The
(Ed.),
teaching
The teaching
of arithmetic
of arithmetic
(Tenth Yearbook
(Tenth
of the
Yearbook of the
National
NationalCouncil
Councilof Teachers
of Teachers
of Mathematics,
of Mathematics,
pp. 1-31). pp.
New1-31).
York: Bureau
New York:
of Bureau of
Publications,
Publications, Teachers
Teachers
College,
College,
Columbia
Columbia
University.
University.

Brownell,
Brownell, W.A.
W.A.(1945).
(1945).
WhenWhen
is arithmetic
is arithmetic
meaningful?
meaningful?
Journal of Educational
Journal of Research,
Educational Research,
38(7),
38(7),481-498.
481-498.

Bruner,
Bruner,J.J.
(1986).
(1986).
Actual
Actual
minds,
minds,
possiblepossible
worlds. Cambridge,
worlds. Cambridge,
MA: HarvardMA:
University
Harvard University
Press.

Bruni, J.V. (1977). Experiencing geometry. Belmont: Wadsworth Publishing Company,


Inc.

Burton, L. (1984). Mathematical thinking: The struggle for meaning. Journalfor Research in
Mathematics Education, 15, 321-329.

Bush, W. S. (1986). Preservice teachers' sources of decisions in teaching secondary


mathematics. Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 17, 21-30.

Buswell, G. T., & Judd, C. H. (1925). Summary of educational investigations relating to


arithmetic. Supplementary Educational Monographs, No. 27. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.

Byers, B. (1983). Beyond structure: Some thoughts on the nature of mathematics. In J. C.


Bergeron & N. Herscovics (Eds.), The Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Meeting of PME-
NA, Montreal.

Carpenter, T. P. (1986). Conceptual knowledge as a foundation for procedural knowledge:


Implications from research on the initial learning of arithmetic. In J. Hiebert (Ed.),
Conceptual and procedural knowledge: The case of mathematics (pp. 113-132). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Carpenter, T. P., & Fennema, E. (1988). Research and cognitively guided instruction. In E.
Fennema, T. P. Carpenter, & S. J. Lamon (Eds.), Integrating research on teaching and
learning mathematics (pp. 2-19). Madison, WI: Wisconsin Center for Educational
Research, University of Wisconsin-Madison.

Carpenter, T. P., Hiebert, J., & Moser, J. M.(1983). The effect of instruction on children's
solutions of addition and subtraction word problems. Educational Studies in Mathematics,
14, 55-72.

Carpenter, T. P., & Moser, J. M. (1982). The development of addition and subtraction
problem-solving skills. In T. P. Carpenter, J. M. Moser, & T. A. Romberg (Eds.),

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
197

Addition and
and subtraction:
subtraction: AA cognitive
cognitiveperspective
perspective(pp.
(pp.9-24).
9-24).Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,NJ:
NJ:Lawrence
Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.

Carpenter, T. P., & Moser, J. M. (1984). The acquisition of addition and subtraction concepts
in grades one through three. Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 15, 179-202.

Carpenter, T. P., Moser, J. M., & Romberg, T. A. (Eds.). (1982). Addition and subtraction:
A cognitive perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Chomsky, N. (1968). Language and mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

Chomsky, N. (1971). Syntactic structures. The Hague and Paris: Mouton.

Clement, John (1982). Algebra word problem solutions: analysis of a common


misconception. Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 13, 16-30.

Cobb, P. (1981). Constructivism, the teaching experiment, and modeling. In C. Comiti and
G. Vergnaud (Eds.), Proceedings of the International Conference of the International
Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 1, pp. 50-55). Grenoble,
France.

Cobb, P. (1985). A reaction to three early number papers. Journalfor Research in


Mathematics Education, 16, 141-145.

Cobb, P. (1988). The tension between theories of learning and theories of instruction in
mathematics education. Educational Psychologist, 23, 87-104.

Cobb, P. (in press). Multiple perspectives. In L. A. Steffe & T. Wood (Eds.), Transforming
Early Childhood Mathematics Education. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Cobb, P., & Steffe , L. (1983). The constructivist researcher as teacher and model builder.
Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 14 (2), 83-94.

Cobb, P., & Wheatley, G. (1988). Children's initial understandings of ten. Focus on
Learning Problems in Mathematics, 10 (3), 1-28.

Cobb, P., Wood, T., & Yackel, E. (in press). A constructivist approach to second grade
mathematics. In E. von Glasersfeld (Ed.), Constructivism in mathematics education.
Holland: Reidel.

Cobb, P., Yackel, E., & Wood, T. (1988). Curriculum and teacher development:
Psychological and anthropological perspectives. In E. Fennema, T. P. Carpenter, & S. J.
Lamon (Eds.), Integrating research on teaching and learning mathematics (pp. 92-131).
Madison, WI: Wisconsin Center for Educational Research, University of Wisconsin-
Madison.

Cobb, P., Yackel, E., & Wood, T. (1989). Young children's emotional acts while doing
mathematical problem solving. In D. B. McLeod & V. M. Adams (Eds.), Affect and
mathematical problem solving: A new perspective (pp. 117-148). New York: Springer-
Verlag.

Confrey, J. (1983). Young women, constructivism and the learning of mathematics. Paper
presented at the annual meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group
for the Psychology of Mathematics Education. Montreal.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
198

Confrey, J. (1985). A constructivist view of mathematics instruction: A theoretical


perspective. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research
Association. Chicago.

Confrey, J. (1986). A critique of teacher effectiveness research in mathematics education.


Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 17, 347-360.

Confrey, J. (1987). "Misconceptions" across subject matters: Science, mathematics and


programming. Proceedings of the Second International Seminar on Misconceptions and
Educational Strategies in Science and Mathematics, 1, 81-106. Ithaca, NY: Comell
University.

Cooney, T. (1985). A beginning teacher's view of problem solving. Journalfor Research in


Mathematics Education, 16(5), 324-336.

Cooper, D., & Clancy, M. (1982). Oh! Pascal! New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

Crowley, M. L. (1987). The van Hiele model of the development of geometric thought. In M.
M. Lindquist & A. P. Shulte (Eds.), Learning and teaching geometry, K-12 (1987 NCTM
Yearbook, pp. 1-16). Reston, VA: National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.

Davis, R. B. (1984). Learning mathematics: The cognitive approach to mathematics education.


Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Company.

Davis, R. B. (1985a). The role of representations in problem solving: Case studies. The
Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 4(3), 281-291.

Davis, R. B. (1985b). Solving the "three switch" problem: A case study. The Journal of
Mathematical Behavior, 4(3), 281-291.

Davis, R. B. (1987). Theory and practice. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 6,97-126.

Davis, R. B. (1988a). The world according to McNeill. Journal of Mathematical Behavior,


7(1), 51-78.

Davis, R. B. (1988b). The interplay of algebra, geometry, and logic. Journal of Mathematical
Behavior, 7(1), 9-28

Davis, R. B. (1989). The culture of mathematics and the culture of schools. The Journal of
Mathematical Behavior, 8(2), 143-160.

Davis, R. B., & McKnight, C. (1980). The influence of semantic content on algorithmic
behavior, Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 3(1), 39-87.

De Millo, R., Lipton, R., & Perlis, A. (1986). Social processes and proofs of theorems and
programs. In T. Tymoczko (Ed.), New directions in the philosophy of mathematics (pp.
267-285). Boston: Birkhauser.

Dewey, J. (1938). Experience and education. New York: MacMillan.

Dewey, J. (1963). Experience and education. New York: Collier.

Diels, H. (1957). Die Vorsokratiker. Hamburg: Rowohlt.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
199

Dienes,
Dienes, Z.
Z.P.P.(1963).
(1963).An
Anexperimental
experimental
study
study
of mathematics
of mathematics
learning.
learning.
London:
London:
Hutchinson.
Hutchinson.

Dienes,
Dienes, Z.
Z.P.P.&&Jeeves,
Jeeves,M.M.
(1965).
(1965).
Thinking
Thinking
in structures.
in structures.
London:
London:
Hutchinson
Hutchinson
Educational.
Educational.

Dilworth,
Dilworth,R. R.P.P.(1973).
(1973).The
Thechanging
changing
face
face
of mathematics
of mathematics
education
education
(Final(Final
reportreport
of theof the
Specialized
SpecializedTeacher
TeacherProject,
Project,
1971-72).
1971-72).
Sacramento,
Sacramento,
California:
California:
California
California
State State
Department
Departmentof ofEducation.
Education.

Dossey,
Dossey, J.
J.A.,
A.,Mullis,
Mullis,I.V.S.,
I.V.S.,
Lindquist,
Lindquist,
M. M.
M.,M.,
& Chambers,
& Chambers,
D. L.D.
(1988).
L. (1988).
The The
mathematics
mathematicsreport
reportcard:
card:
Are
Are
wewe
measuring
measuring
up?up?
(National
(National
Assessment
Assessment
of Educational
of Educational
Progress
Progress report).
report).Princeton:
Princeton:Educational
Educational
Testing
Testing
Service.
Service.

Doyle,
Doyle, W.,
W.,Sanford,
Sanford,J.J.& &
Emmer,
Emmer,E. (1983).
E. (1983).
Managing
Managing
academic
academic
taskstasks
in junior
in junior
high school:
high school:
Background,
Background,design
designand
andmethodology
methodology (Report
(Report
No. No.
6185).
6185).
Austin:
Austin:
University
University
of Texas,
of Texas,
Research
Research and
andDevelopment
Development Center
Centerforfor
Teacher
Teacher
Education.
Education.

Erlwanger,
Erlwanger,S.S.H.H.(1973).
(1973).Benny's
Benny's
conception
conception
of rules
of rules
and and
answers
answers
in IPIinmathematics.
IPI mathematics.
Journal
Journal of
ofChildren's
Children'sMathematical
MathematicalBehavior,
Behavior,
1(2),1(2),
7-26.7-26.

Erlwanger,
Erlwanger,S.S.H.H.(1975).
(1975).Case
Case
studies
studies
of of
children's
children's
conceptions
conceptions
of mathematics,
of mathematics,
part I.part I.
Journal
Journal of
ofChildren's
Children'sMathematical
Mathematical Behavior,
Behavior,
1(3),1(3),
157-283.
157-283.

Fabricus,
Fabricus, W.
W.(1979).
(1979).Piaget's
Piaget'stheory
theory
of of
knowledge;
knowledge;
Its philosophical
Its philosophical
context.
context.
High/Scope
High/Scope
Report,
Report, 4(7),
4(7),4-13.
4-13.

Fennema,
Fennema,E.,
E.,Carpenter,
Carpenter, T.T.
P, P,
& Peterson,
& Peterson,
P. (1986).
P. (1986).
Teachers'
Teachers'
decision
decision
making
making
and and
cognitively
cognitivelyguided
guidedinstruction:
instruction:A new
A newparadigm
paradigmfor for
curriculum
curriculum
development.
development.
Paper Paper
presented
presentedat
atthe
theseventh
seventhannual
annual
meeting
meeting
of the
of the
International
International
Group
Group
for the
forPsychology
the Psychology
of of
Mathematics
MathematicsEducation.
Education.London,
London,
England.
England.

Feyerabend,
Feyerabend,P.P.(1987).
(1987).Farewell
Farewell
to to
reason.
reason.
London/New
London/New
York:
York:
Verso.
Verso.

Forman,
Forman, G.,
G.,&&Pufall,
Pufall,P.P.
B.B.
(Eds.)
(Eds.)
(1988).
(1988).
Constructivism
Constructivism
in the
in computer
the computer
age. Hillsdale,
age. Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Fuson, K. C. (1988). Children's counting and concepts of number. New York: Springer-
Verlag.

Fuson, K. C., & Hall, J. W. (1983). The acquisition of early number word meanings: A
conceptual analysis and review. In H. P. Ginsburg (Ed.), The development of
mathematical thinking (pp. 49-107). New York: Academic Press.

Gelman, R., & Gallistel, C. (1978). Young children's understanding of numbers.


Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Ginsburg, H. P. (1977). Children's arithmetic: The learning process. New York, NY: Van
Nostrand.

Ginsburg, H. P. (1982). Children's arithmetic: How they learn it and how you teach it.
Austin, TX: Pro-Ed.

Ginsburg,
Ginsburg, H.
H. P.
P. (1983).
(1983).The
Thedevelopment
developmentofof
mathematical
mathematical
thinking.
thinking.
New
New
York:
York:
Academic
Academic
Press.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
200

Ginsburg,
Ginsburg,H.
H.P.P.(1989).
(1989).
Children's
Children's
arithmetic
arithmetic
(2nd(2nd
ed.). ed.).
Austin,
Austin,
TX: Pro-Ed.
TX: Pro-Ed.

Ginsburg,
Ginsburg,H.H.P.,
P.,& &Oper,
Oper,S. S.
(Eds.).
(Eds.).
(1969)
(1969)
Piaget's
Piaget's
theory
theory
of intellectual
of intellectual
development.
development.
Englewood
EnglewoodCliffs,
Cliffs,N.J.:
N.J.:Prentice-Hall.
Prentice-Hall.

Ginsburg,
Ginsburg,H.H.P.,
P.,Posner,
Posner,J. J.
K.,K.,
& Russell,
& Russell,
R. L.R.(1981).
L. (1981).
The development
The development
of mental
of mental
addition
additionasasa afunction
functionofofschooling.
schooling.
Journal
Journal of Cross-Cultural
of Cross-Cultural
Psychology,
Psychology,
12, 163-178.
12, 163-178.

Ginsburg,
Ginsburg,H.
H.P.,
P.,& &Russell,
Russell,R. R.
L. (1981).
L. (1981).
Social
Social
classclass
and racial
and racial
influences
influences
on early
on early
mathematical
mathematicalthinking.
thinking. Monographs
Monographs of the
of the
Society
Society
for Research
for Research
in Child
in Development,
Child Development,
46:(16)
46:(16) (Serial
(SerialNo.
No.193).
193).

Goldin,
Goldin, G.
G.A.
A.(1984).
(1984).
Structure
Structurevariables
variables
in problem
in problem
solving.
solving.
In G. In
A. G.
Goldin
A. Goldin
and C. E.
and C. E.
McClintock
McClintock(Eds.),
(Eds.),Task
Task
variables
variables
in mathematical
in mathematicalproblem
problem
solving
solving
(pp 103-169).
(pp 103-169).
Philadelphia:
Philadelphia:Franklin
Franklin Institute
Institute
Press
Press
(presently
(presently
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,
New Jersey:
New Jersey:
Lawrence
Lawrence
ErlbaumErlbaum
Associates).
Associates).

Goldin,
Goldin, G.
G.A.
A.(1987).
(1987).
Cognitive
Cognitiverepresentational
representational
systems
systems
for mathematical
for mathematical
problemproblem
solving.solving.
In
In C.
C. Janvier
Janvier(Ed.),
(Ed.),Problems
Problemsof of
representation
representation
in the
in teaching
the teaching
and learning
and learning
of of
mathematics
mathematics(pp. (pp.125-145).
125-145).
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,
NewNew
Jersey:
Jersey:
Lawrence
Lawrence
Erlbaum
Erlbaum
Associates.
Associates.

Goldin,
Goldin, G.
G.A.
A.(1989).
(1989).
Constructivist
Constructivist
epistemology
epistemology and discovery
and discovery
learning
learning
in mathematics.
in mathematics.
In In
G.
G. Vergnaud,
Vergnaud,J.J.Rogalski,
Rogalski,
& M.
& M.Artigue
Artigue(Eds.),
(Eds.),
Actes
Actes
de la de
13elaConference
13e Conference
Internationale
Internationale
de
de PME
PME (International
(International Group
Groupforfor
thethe
Psychology
Psychologyof Mathematics
of Mathematics
Education)
Education)
(Vol. 2,(Vol.
pp 2, pp
15-22). Paris.

Good, T. L., & Grouws, D. A. (1978). Missouri mathematics effectiveness project: A


program of naturalistic and experimental research (Tech. Report No. 142). Columbia:
University of Missouri, Center for Research in Social Behavior.

Good, T. L., Grouws, D. A., & Ebmeier, H. (1983). Active mathematics teaching. New
York: Longman.

Groen, G. J., & Resnick, L. B. (1977). Can preschool children invent addition algorithms?
Journal of Educational Psychology, 69, 645-652.

Gunstone, R., & Northfield, J. (1988, April). Inservice education: Some constructivist
perspectives and examples. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American
Educational Research Association. New Orleans.

Guskey, T. R. (1986). Staff development and the process of teacher change. Educational
Researcher, 15(5), 5-12.

Hadamard, J. (1945). The psychology of invention in the mathematical field. New York:
Dover Publications, Inc.

Hare-Mustin, R. T., & Marecek, J. (1988). The meaning of difference. American


Psychologist, 43, 455-464.

Harlen, W., & Osborne, R. (1985). A model for learning and teaching applied to primary
science. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 17(2), 133-146.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
201

Hiebert,
Hiebert, J.
J.(1984).
(1984).Children's
Children'smathematics
mathematics
learning:
learning:
The The
struggle
struggle
to link
toform
link form
and and
understanding.
understanding.Elementary
Elementary School
School
Journal,
Journal,
84, 84,
497-513.
497-513.

Hiebert,
Hiebert, J.
J.(Ed.).
(Ed.).(1986).
(1986).
Conceptual
Conceptual
andand
procedural
procedural
knowledge:
knowledge:
The case
Theof
case
mathematics.
of mathematics.
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,NJ:
NJ:Lawrence
Lawrence Erlbaum
ErlbaumAssociates.
Associates.

Holt,
Holt, J.
J. (1964).
(1964).How
Howchildren
children
fail.
fail.
NewNew
York:
York:
Delta
Delta
Books.
Books.

Howson,
Howson,G.
G.C.C.J.,
J.,Keitel,
Keitel,C.,C.,
& Kilpatrick,
& Kilpatrick,
J. (1981).
J. (1981).
Curriculum
Curriculum
development
development
in in
mathematics.
mathematics.Cambridge,
Cambridge,England:
England:
Cambridge
Cambridge
University
University
Press.Press.

Inhelder,
Inhelder,B.,
B.,Garcia,
Garcia,R.,R.,
&& Voneche,
Voneche,
J. (1977).
J. (1977).
Epistemologie
Epistemologie
genetique
genetique
et equilibration.
et equilibration.
Neuchatel/Paris:
Neuchatel/Paris:Delachauz
Delachauzet et
Niestle.
Niestle.

James,
James, W.
W.(1880).
(1880).Great
Greatmen,
men,great
great
thoughts,
thoughts,
and and
the environment.
the environment.
Atlantic
Atlantic
Monthly,
Monthly,
46, 46,
441-459.

Kamii, C. K. (1985). Young children reinvent arithmetic. New York: Teachers College
Press.

Kelly, G. A. (1955). A theory of personality: The psychology of personal constructs. New


York: Norton.

Kidder, T. (1989). Among schoolchildren. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Kilpatrick, J. (1986). Reflection and recursion. In Carss, M. (Ed.), Proceedings of the Fifth
International Congress on Mathematical Education. Boston: Birkhauser.

Kilpatrick, J. (1987). What constructivism might be in mathematics education. In J. C.


Bergeron, N. Herscovics & C. Kieran (Eds.), Proceedings of the Eleventh Conference of
the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (pp. 2-27).
Montreal: University of Montreal.

Kintsch, W. & Greeno, J. G. (1985). Understanding and solving arithmetic word problems.
Psychological Review, 92, 109-129.

Kitchener, R. (1989). Genetic epistemology and the prospects for a cognitive sociology of
science: A critical synthesis. Social Epistemology, 3(2), 153-169.

Kline, M. (1980). Mathematics: The loss of certainty. New York: Oxford University Press.

Koretz, D. (1988). Arriving in Lake Wobegon: Are standardized tests exaggerating


achievement and distorting instruction? American Educator, 12(2), 8-52.

Kouba, V. (1986, April). How young children solve multiplication and division word
problems. Paper presented at the National Council of Teachers of Mathematics research
presession, Washington, D.C.

Labinowicz, E. (1985). Learning from children: New beginnings for teaching numerical
thinking. Menlo Park, CA: Addison-Wesley.

Labinowicz, E. (1987). Children's right to be wrong. Arithmetic Teacher, 35(4), 2 & 20.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
202

Lakatos,
Lakatos,I.I.(1976).
(1976).Proofs
Proofs
andand
refutations
refutations
(J. Worral
(J. Worral
& E. Zahar,
& E. Zahar,
Eds.). Cambridge:
Eds.). Cambridge:
Cambridge
CambridgeUniversity
University Press.
Press.

Lampert,
Lampert,M.M.(1988).
(1988).
TheThe
teacher's
teacher's
rolerole
in reinventing
in reinventing
the meaning
the meaning
of mathematical
of mathematical
knowingknowing
in
in the
the classroom.
classroom.Proceedings
Proceedingsof the
of the
NorthNorth
America
America
Chapter
Chapter
of theofPsychology
the Psychology
of of
Mathematics
MathematicsEducation
Education Group
Group(pp.(pp.
433-480).
433-480).
Northern
Northern
Illinois
Illinois
University.
University.

Landis,
Landis,J.
J.H.H.(1990).
(1990).
Teachers'prediction
Teachers'prediction
and and
identification
identification
of children's
of children's
mathematical
mathematical
behavior:
behavior:Two Twocase
case
studies.
studies.
Unpublished
Unpublished
doctoral
doctoral
dissertation.
dissertation.
Rutgers
Rutgers
University.
University.

Landis,
Landis,J.
J.H.H.and
andMaher,
Maher,C. C.
A. A.
(1989).
(1989).
Observations
Observations
of Carrie,
of Carrie,
a fourth
a fourth
grade student,
grade student,
doing doing
mathematics.
mathematics.The The
Journal
Journal of of
Mathematical
Mathematical
Behavior,
Behavior,
8(1), 3-12.
8(1), 3-12.

Lave,
Lave, J.
J.(1988).
(1988).Cognition
Cognitionin in
practice:
practice:
Mind,
Mind,
mathematics
mathematics
and culture
and culture
in everyday
in everyday
life. life.
Cambridge:
Cambridge:Cambridge
Cambridge University
University
Press.
Press.

Lawler,
Lawler,R.
R.W.
W.(in
(inpress).
press).
Constructing
Constructing
knowledge
knowledge
fromfrom
interactions.
interactions.
JournalJournal
of Mathematical
of Mathematical
Behavior.

Lerman, S. (1989). Constructivism, mathematics, and mathematics education. Educational


Studies in Mathematics, 20, 211-223.

Lesh, R., & Landau, M. (Eds.). (1983). Acquisition of mathematical concepts and processes.
New York: Academic Press.

Lesh, R., & Zawojewski, J. (1987). Problem solving. In T. Post (Ed.), Teaching
mathematics in grades K-8: Research-based methods. Boston: Allyn & Bacon.

Lochhead, J. (1983a). Beyond Emile. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American
Educational Research Association. Montreal.

Lochhead, J. (1983b). Constructivist approach to teaching mathematics. In J. C. Bergeron


& N. Herscovics (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Meeting: PME/NA.

Lortie, D. C. (1975). School teacher. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Lunkenbein, D. (1985, April). Cognitive structures underlying processes and conceptions in


geometry. Paper presented at the research presession of the annual meeting of the National
Council of Teachers of Mathematics. San Antonio, TX.

Mager, R. (1962). Preparing instructional objectives. Palo Alto, California: Fearon.

Magoon, A. J. (1977). Constructivist approaches in educational research. Review of


Educational Research, 47(4), 651-693.

Maher, C. A. (1986, June). Teacher development in mathematics: A model. Paper presented at


the working conference on Models for Teacher Development. Rutgers University.

Maher, C. A., & Alston, A. (1988, July). Implementing a modelfor teacher development in
mathematics. Paper presented to the Sixth International Congress on Mathematical
Education. Budapest, Hungary.

Maher, C. A., and Alston, A. (1989). Is meaning connected to symbols? An interview with
Ling Chen. The Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 8(3), 241-248.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
203

Maturana,
Maturana,H.H.(1980a).
(1980a).
Biology
Biology
andand
cognition.
cognition.
In H.In
Maturana
H. Maturana
& F. Varela
& F. Varela
(Eds.), (Eds.),
Autopoiesis:
Autopoiesis:The
Theorganization
organization
of the
of the
living.
living.
Dordrecht:
Dordrecht:
Reidel.Reidel.

Maturana,
Maturana,H.H.R.R.(1980b).
(1980b).
Man
Man
andand
society.
society.
In F.In
Benseler,
F. Benseler,
P. M. P.
Hejl,
M.&Hejl,
W. K.&Kock
W. K. Kock
(Eds.),
(Eds.), Antopoiesis,
Antopoiesis, communication,
communication,
and and
society
society
(pp. 11-32).
(pp. 11-32).
Frankfurt,
Frankfurt,
West Germany:
West Germany:
Campus
CampusVerlag.
Verlag.

McKnight,
McKnight,C.C.(1987).
(1987).
The
The
underachieving
underachieving
curriculum.
curriculum.
Champaign:
Champaign:
Stipes Publishing
Stipes Publishing
Company.

McKnight, C. C., Crosswhite, F. J., Dossey, J. A., Kifer, E., Swafford, S. D. Travers, K.
J., Cooney, T. J. (1987). The underachieving curriculum: Assessing U.S. school
mathematics from an international perspective. Champaign, IL: Stipes.

McNeill, R. (1988). A reflection on when I loved math, and how I stopped. Journal of
Mathematical Behavior, 7(1), 45-50.

Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Montaigne, Michel de (1972). Essais (Vol.2). Paris: Librairie Generale Francaise.

Moyer, M. B., & Moyer, J. C. (1985). Ensuring that practice makes perfect: Implications for
children with learning difficulties. Arithmetic Teacher, 33(1), 40-42.

NACOME. (1975). Overview and analysis of school mathematics, Grades K-12.


Washington, DC: Conference Board of the Mathematical Sciences.

National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. (1989). Curriculum and evaluation standards


for school mathematics. Reston, VA: NCTM, Inc.

National Research Council. (1989). Everybody counts: A report to the nation on thefuture of
mathematics education. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

Nicholls, J. G. (1983). Conceptions of ability and achievement motivation: A theory and its
implications for education. In S. G. Paris, G. M. Olson, & W. H. Stevenson (Eds.),
Learning and motivation in the classroom (pp. 211-237). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.

Nicholls, J. G. (1989). The competitive ethos and democratic education. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.

Noddings, N. (1973). Constructivism as a base for a theory of teaching. Unpublished


doctoral dissertation, Stanford University.

Noddings, N. (1974). Competence theories and the science of education. Educational


Theory, 24, 356-364.

Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics and moral education. Berkeley:
University of California Press.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
204

Noddings,
Noddings,N.N.
(1986).
(1986).
Teaching
Teaching
as a heuristic
as a heuristic
enterprise.
enterprise.
Paper presented
Paper at
presented
the annualat the annual
meeting
meetingofofthe
the
Psychology
Psychology
of Mathematics
of Mathematics
Education
Education
Group. East
Group.
Lansing,
East
Michigan.
Lansing, Michigan.

Noddings,
Noddings,N.N.
(1988).
(1988).
An An
ethicethic
of caring
of caring
and its and
implications
its implications
for instructional
for instructional
arrangements.arrangements.
American
AmericanJournal
Journalof Education,
of Education,
96(2), 96(2),
215-230.
215-230.

Noddings,
Noddings,N.N.
(1989).
(1989).
Theoretical
Theoretical
and practical
and practical
concernsconcerns
about small
about
groups
small
in mathematics.
groups in mathematics.
The
TheElementary
Elementary School
School
Journal,
Journal,
89(5), 89(5),
607-623.
607-623.

Novak,
Novak,J.,
J.,&&
Gowin,
Gowin,
D. B.D.(1984).
B. (1984).
Learning
Learning
how to how
learn.to
New
learn.
York:New
Cambridge
York: Cambridge
University
University Press.
Press.

Nussbaum,
Nussbaum, J.J.
(1982).
(1982).
Alternative
Alternative
frameworks,
frameworks,
conceptual
conceptual
conflict and
conflict
accommodation:
and accommodation:
Toward
Towarda aprincipled
principledteaching
teaching
strategy.
strategy.
Instructional
Instructional
Science, 11,
Science,
183-200.
11, 183-200.

Osborne,
Osborne,R.,R.,
Bell,
Bell,
B., B.,
& Gilbert,
& Gilbert,
J. (1982).
J. (1982).
Science Science
teaching teaching
and children's
and view
children's
of the view of the
world.
world.Hamilton,
Hamilton,New
New
Zealand:
Zealand:
S.E.R.U.,
S.E.R.U.,
University
University
of Waikato.
of Waikato.

Papert,
Papert,S.S.(1980).
(1980).
Mindstorms:
Mindstorms:
Children,
Children,
computers,
computers,
andpowerful
andpowerful
ideas. New York:
ideas.Basic
New York: Basi
Books.

Perret-Clermont, A. N. (1980). Social interaction and cognitive development in children.


New York: Academic Press.

Perry, M., Church, R., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (1988, April). Learning a principle versus
learning a procedure: Looking beyond what is taught. Paper presented at the annual
meeting of the American Educational Research Association, New Orleans.

Peterson, P., & Clark C. (1978). Teachers' reports of their cognitive processes during
teaching. American Educational Research Journal, 14(4), 555-565.

Peterson, P., Swing, S., Stark, K., & Waas, C. (1984). Students' cognitions and time on
task during mathematics instruction. American Educational Research Journal, 21(3), 487-
515.

Piaget, J. (1937). La construction du reel chez l'enfant. Neuchatel: Delachaux et Niestle.

Piaget, J. (1948). To understand is to invent. New York: Viking.

Piaget, J. (1953). Logic andpsychology. Manchester, England: Manchester University


Press.

Piaget, J. (1964). Learning and development. In R. E. Ripple, & V. N. Rockcastle (Eds.),


Piaget rediscovered (Report of the Conference on Cognitive Studies and Curriculum
Development). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.

Piaget, J. (1965). The child's conception of number. New York: Norton.

Piaget, J. (1969). Mechanisms of perception (G. N. Seagrim, Trans.). New York: Basic
Books.

Piaget, J. (1970a). Genetic epistemology. New York: Columbia University Press.

Piaget, J. (1970b). Le structuralisme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
205

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1970c).
(1970c).Science
Science
of of
education
education
and and
the psychology
the psychology
of theofchild.
the child.
New York:
NewOrion.
York: Orion.

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1970d).
(1970d).Structuralism.
Structuralism.
New
New
York:
York:
BasicBasic
Books.
Books.

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1971a).
(1971a).Biology
Biology
andand
knowledge.
knowledge.
Chicago:
Chicago:
University
University
of Chicago
of Chicago
Press. Press.

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1971b).
(1971b).Insights
Insights
andand
illusions
illusions
of philosophy.
of philosophy.
New York:
New York:
World.World.

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1980a).
(1980a).Adaptation
Adaptationandand
intelligence:
intelligence:
Organic
Organic
selection
selection
and phenocopy.
and phenocopy.
Chicago:Chicago:
University
Universityof ofChicago
ChicagoPress.
Press.

Piaget,
Piaget, J.
J.(1980b).
(1980b).Afterthoughts.
Afterthoughts. In M.
In Piattelli-Palmarine
M. Piattelli-Palmarine
(Ed.), (Ed.),
Language
Language
and learning:
and learning:
The
The debate
debatebetween
between Jean
Jean
Piaget
Piaget
andand
NoamNoam
Chomsky.
Chomsky.
Cambridge:
Cambridge:
Harvard
Harvard
University
University
Press.

Piaget, J. (1980c). The psychogenesis of knowledge and its epistemological significance. In


M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.), Language and learning: The debate between Jean Piaget and
Noam Chomsky. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Piattelli-Palmarini, M. (1980). How hard is the "hard core" of a scientific program? In M.


Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.), Language and Learning: The debate between Jean Piaget and
Noam Chomsky. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Pierce, C. S. (1935). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Pierce (Vol. 5, C. Hartshome & P.
Weiss, Eds.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Pittendrigh, C. S. (1958). Adaptation, natural selection, and behavior. In A. Roe & G. G.


Simpson (Eds.), Behavior and evolution. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Plato. (1956). Great dialogues of Plato. New York: New American Library.

Polya, G. (1962). Mathematical discovery: On understanding, learning, and teaching problem


solving. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

Popkin, R. (1979). The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley/Los


Angeles: University of California Press.

Quine, W. V. 0. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Ontological


relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

Resnick, L. B. (1983). A developmental theory of number understanding. In H. P. Ginsburg


(Ed.), The development of mathematical thinking (pp. 109-151). New York: Academic
Press.

Resnick, L. B., & Ford, W. W. (1981). The psychology of mathematics for instruction.
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Reyes, L. H. (1984). Affective variables and mathematics education. Elementary School


Journal, 84, 558-581.

Riley, M. S., Greeno, J. G., & Heller, J. I. (1983). Development of children's problem-
solving ability in arithmetic. In H. P. Ginsburg (Ed.), The development of mathematical
thinking (pp. 153-200). New York: Academic Press.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
206

Rogoff,
Rogoff,B.,
B.,& &Lave,
Lave,
J. J.
(Eds.)
(Eds.)
(1984).
(1984).
Everyday
Everyday
cognition:
cognition:
Its development
Its development
in social context.
in social context.
Cambridge:
Cambridge:Harvard
HarvardUniversity
University Press.
Press.

Rorty,
Rorty,R.R.(1979).
(1979).
Philosophy
Philosophy
and and
the mirror
the mirror
of nature.
of nature.
Princeton:
Princeton:
Princeton
Princeton
UniversityUniversity
Press.

Rosenshine, B. (1976). Classroom instruction. In N. Gage (Ed.), The psychology of


teaching methods (Seventy-seventh Yearbook, pp. 335-371). Chicago: National Society
for the Study of Education.

Ross, S. (1986, April). The development of children's place-value numeration concepts in


grades two throughfive. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American
Educational Research Association. San Francisco, CA.

Rowell, J.A. (1989). Equilibration and the teaching of science. Synthese, 80(1), 141-162.

Scheman, N. (1989). Commentary on Sandra Harding's "The method question." Newsletter


on Feminism and Philosophy, 88(3), 40-44.

Schoenfeld, A. H. (1985). Mathematical problem solving. New York: Academic Press.

Schoenfeld, A. H. (1987). What's all the fuss about metacognition? In A. H. Schoenfeld


(Ed.), Cognitive science and mathematics education (pp. 189-216). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Schoenfeld, A. H., Smith, J. P., & Arcavi, A. (in press). Learning: The microgenetic analysis
of one student's evolving understanding of complex subject matter domain. In R. Glaser
(Ed.), Advances in instructional psychology (Vol. 4). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.

Schon, D. A. (1983). The reflective practitioner. New York: Basic Books.

Schutz, A. (1962). The problem of social reality. The Hague, Holland: Martinus Nijhoff.

Siegel, H. (1988). Rationality and epistemic dependence. Educational Philosophy and


Theory, 20(1), 1-6.

Siegler, R. S. (1987). Strategy choices in subtraction. In J. Slobada & D. Rogers (Eds.),


Cognitive process in mathematics (pp. 81-106). Oxford, England; Oxford University
Press.

Siegler, R. S., & Shrager, J. (1984). Strategy choices in addition: How do children know
what to do? In C. Sophian (Ed.), Origins of cognitive skills (pp. 229-293). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Simmel, G. (1885). Ueber eine Beziehung der Selectionslehre zur Erkenntnistheorie. Archiv
fur systematische Philosophie, 1, 34-45.

Simon, H. (1979). Models of thought. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and Human Behavior. New York: The Free Press.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
207

Slobin,
Slobin, D.D.I.I.(1971).
(1971).Psycholinguistics.
Psycholinguistics.
Glenview,
Glenview,
IL: Scott,
IL: Scott,
Foresman.
Foresman.

Smedslund,
Smedslund,J.J.(1977).
(1977).
Piaget's
Piaget's
psychology
psychology
in practice.
in practice.
British
British
Journal
Journal
of Educational
of Educational
Psychology,
Psychology,47,
47,1-6.
1-6.

Snow,
Snow, R.
R.(1972).
(1972).A Amodel
model teacher
teacher
training
training
system:
system:
An overview
An overview
(Research
(Research
and Development
and Development
Memorandum
Memorandum92, 92,Ed.
Ed.
066066
437).
437).
Stanford:
Stanford:
Center
Center
for the
forResearch
the Research
and Development
and Development
in in
Teaching.
Teaching.

Starkey,
Starkey,P., P.,&&Gelman,
Gelman,
R. R.
(1982).
(1982).
TheThe
development
development of addition
of addition
and subtraction
and subtraction
abilitiesabilities
prior prior
to
to formal
formalschooling
schooling
inin
arithmetic.
arithmetic.
In T.
InP.T.Carpenter,
P. Carpenter,
J. M. J.
Moser,
M. Moser,
& T. A.&Romberg
T. A. Romberg
(Eds.),
(Eds.), Addition
Additionand
andsubtraction:
subtraction:
A cognitive
A cognitiveperspective
perspective
(pp. 99-116).
(pp. 99-116).
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,
NJ: NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Steffe, L. P.(1983). The teaching experiment methodology in a constructivist research


program. In M. Zweng, T. Green, J. Kilpatrick, H. Pollak, & M. Suydam (Eds.),
Proceedings of the Fourth International Congress on Mathematical Education (pp. 469-
471). Boston: Birkhauser.

Steffe, L. P. (1986, April). Mathematical teacher education in a constructivistframework.


Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association,
San Francisco.

Steffe, L. P. (1987, April). Principles of mathematical curriculum design in early childhood


teacher education. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational
Research Association. Washington, DC.

Steffe, L. P. (1988, April). Mathematics learning and teaching for today's schools. Paper
presented at the annual meeting of the National Council for the Teachers of Mathematics.
Chicago.

Steffe, L. P., & Cobb, P. (1983). The constructivist researcher as teacher and model builder.
Journalfor Research in Mathematics Education, 14, 83-94.

Steffe, L. P., Cobb, P., & von Glasersfeld, E. (1988). Construction of arithmetical meanings
and strategies. New York: Springer-Verlag.

Steffe, L. P., von Glasersfeld, E., Richards, J., & Cobb, P. (1983). Children's counting
types: Philosophy, theory, and applications. New York: Praeger Scientific.

Steffe, L. P., Shrum, J. W., Clifton, P. D. Hart, N., & Ireland, E. K. (1985). Final report:
Secretary's discretionary program, planning grant to develop the Georgia Teacher Fellow
Program in Science and Mathematics. In A. Buccino & C. Purvis (Eds.). Designing and
implementing a teacher career ladder. Athens: The Clarke County (Georgia) Schools and
The College of Education of the University of Georgia.

Stephens, W., & Romberg T. (1985). Reconceptualizing the role of the mathematics teacher.
Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Educational Research Association.
Chicago.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
208

Stevens,
Stevens,A. A.L.,
L.,& &Collins,
Collins,A. A.
(1980).
(1980).
Multiple
Multiple
conceptual
conceptual
modelsmodels
of a complex
of a complex
system.system.
In In
R.
R. E.
E. Snow,
Snow,P.P.Federica,
Federica, & W.
& W.E. Montague
E. Montague(Eds.),
(Eds.),
Aptitude,
Aptitude,
learning
learning
and instruction:
and instruction:
Cognitive
Cognitiveprocess
processanalyses
analysesof of
learning
learning
and and
problem
problem
solving
solving
(Vol. 2,
(Vol.
pp. 177-188).
2, pp. 177-188).
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,NJ: NJ:Lawrence
Lawrence Erlbaum
Erlbaum Associates.
Associates.

Sund,
Sund, R.,
R.,&&Picard,
Picard,A.A.
(1972).
(1972).
Behavioral
Behavioral
objectives
objectives
and evaluational
and evaluational
measures:
measures:
Science Science
and and
mathematics.
mathematics.Columbus,
Columbus, Ohio:
Ohio:
Merrill.
Merrill.

Thom,
Thom, R.
R.(1973).
(1973).Modern
Modernmathematics:
mathematics:
DoesDoes
it exist?
it exist?
In Howson,
In Howson,
A.G. (Ed.),
A.G. (Ed.),
Developments
Developmentsininmathematical
mathematicaleducation:
education:
Proceedings
Proceedings
of theofSecond
the Second
International
International
Congress
CongressononMathematical
MathematicalEducation
Education
(pp. (pp.
194-209).
194-209).
Cambridge:
Cambridge:
Cambridge
Cambridge
University
University
Press.

Thompson, P. (1985). Experience, problem solving, and learning mathematics:


Considerations in developing mathematical curricula. In E. A. Silver (Ed.), Teaching and
learning mathematical problem solving: Multiple research perspectives (pp. 189-236).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Thoresen, C. (1988). The constructivist concept: Primacy of the obscure. The Counseling
Psychologist, 16(2), 249-255.

Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding (Vol. 1). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Turner, M. (1967). Philosophy and the science of behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-
Crofts.

Vaihinger, H. (1913). Die Philosophie des Als Ob. Berlin: Reuther & Reichard.

Van Engen, H. (1949). Analysis of meaning in arithmetic. Elementary School Journal. 49,
321-329; 335-400.

Vico, G. B. (1858). De antiquissima Italorum sapientia (1710). Naples: Stamperia de'Classici


Latini.

Vinner, S. (1983). Concept definition, concept image, and the notion of function.
International Journalfor Mathematics Education, Science and Technology, 14(3), 293-305.

Voigt, J. (1985). Patterns and routines in classroom interaction. Researches en didactique des
mathematiques, 6, 69-118.

von Glasersfeld, E. (1974). Piaget and the radical constructivist epistemology. Paper
presented at the Third Southeastern Conference of the Society for Research on Child
Development. Chapel Hill, NC.

von Glasersfeld, E. (1980). Adaptation and viability. American Psychologist, 35(11), 970-
974.

von Glasersfeld, E. (1981). The "truth" about Pythagoras. Problem Solving. 3(5 & 6).

von Glasersfeld, E. (1982). Subitizing: The role of figural patterns in the development of
numerical concepts. Archives de Psychologie. 50, 191-218.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
209

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1983).
(1983).On
Onthe
the
concept
concept
of of
interpretation.
interpretation.
Poetics,
Poetics,
12, 207-218.
12, 207-218.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1984).
(1984).An
Anintroduction
introduction to to
radical
radical
constructivism.
constructivism.
In P.InWatzlawick
P. Watzlawick
(Ed.),
(Ed.), The
The invented
inventedreality
reality(pp.
(pp.17-40).
17-40).
New
New York:
York:
Norton.
Norton.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1985).
(1985).Reconstructing
Reconstructingthethe
concept
concept
of of
knowledge.
knowledge.
Archives
Archives
de de
Psychologie,
Psychologie, 53,
53,91-101.
91-101.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1987a).
(1987a).Learning
Learning as as
a constructive
a constructiveactivity.
activity.
In C.
InJanvier
C. Janvier
(Ed.),(Ed.),
Problems
Problems ofof representation
representationininthe
theteaching
teachingand
and
learning
learning
of mathematics
of mathematics
(pp. (pp.
3-17).
3-17).
Hillsdale,
Hillsdale, NJ:
NJ:Lawrence
LawrenceErlbaum
ErlbaumAssociates.
Associates.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1987b).
(1987b).Preliminaries
Preliminariesto to
any
any
theory
theory
of representation.
of representation.
In C.InJanvier
C. Janvier
(Ed.),
(Ed.), Problems
Problemsof ofrepresentation
representationinin
the
the
teaching
teaching
andand
learning
learning
of mathematics
of mathematics (pp. (pp.
215- 215-
225).
225). Hillsdale,
Hillsdale,New
NewJersey:
Jersey:Lawrence
LawrenceErlbaum
ErlbaumAssociates.
Associates.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(1988,
(1988,July).
July).Environment
Environment andand
communication.
communication.
Paper
Paper
presented
presented
at the
at the
Sixth
Sixth International
InternationalCongress
CongressononMathematical
MathematicalEducation.
Education.
Budapest,
Budapest,
Hungary.
Hungary.

von
von Glasersfeld,
Glasersfeld,E.E.(in
(inpress).
press).Abstraction,
Abstraction,re-presentation,
re-presentation,
andand
reflection.
reflection.
In L.InP.L.Steffe
P. Steffe
(Ed.),
(Ed.), Epistemologicalfoundations
Epistemologicalfoundationsofof mathematical
mathematicalexperience.
experience.
NewNewYork:
York:
Springer-
Springer-
Verlag.

von Uexkiill, J. (1970). Streifziige durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen (with
Georg Kriszat). Frankfurt am Main: Fischer. (Originally published in 1933).

Vuyk, R. (1981). Overview and critique of Piaget's genetic epistemology (Vols. 1 & 2). New
York: Academic Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA.: M.I.T. Press.

Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes.


Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Weber, R. (1986, April). The constraints of questioning routines in reading instruction. Paper
presented at the meeting of American Educational Research Association. San Francisco,
CA.

Wertheimer, M. (1959). Productive thinking (Enlarged edition). New York: Harper & Row.

Wertsch, J. V. (1985). Vygotsky and the socialformation of mind. Cambridge: Harvard


University Press.

Whimbey, A., & Lochhead J. (1980). Problem solving and comprehension. Philadelphia:
Franklin Institute Press.

Whitney, H. (1985). Taking responsibility in school mathematics education, The Journal of


Mathematical Behavior, 4(3), 219-235.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
210

Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Wittgenstein, L. (1964). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. Oxford: Blackwell.

Wood, T. (in press). Whole class interactions as the negotiation of social contexts within
which to construct mathematical knowledge. In C. Keitel (Ed.), Mathematics, education
and society. Berlin: UNESCO.

Wood, T., Cobb, P., & Yackel, E. (in press). The contextual nature of teaching: Mathematics
and reading instruction in one second-grade classroom. Elementary School Journal.

Woods, S. S., Resnick, L. B., & Groen, G. J. (1975). An experimental test of five process
models for subtraction. Journal of Educational Psychology, 67, 17-21.

This content downloaded from 163.245.138.250 on Thu, 23 Aug 2018 15:35:34 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like