【身体的文化:现代性的谱系】The Culture of the Body Genealogies of Modernity
【身体的文化:现代性的谱系】The Culture of the Body Genealogies of Modernity
【身体的文化:现代性的谱系】The Culture of the Body Genealogies of Modernity
Dalia Judovitz
Ann Arbor
Judovitz, Dalia.
The culture of the body: genealogies of modernity / Dalia
Judovitz.
p. cm. - (The body, in theory)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-472-09742-3 (acid-free paper) - ISBN 0-472-06742-7 (pbk. :
acid-free paper)
1. Body, Human (Philosophy)-France-History. 2. Philosophy,
Modern. 3. Body, Human in literature. 4. French literature-
History and criticism. I. Title. II. Series.
B1809.B62 J83 2000
128' .6'0944-dc21 00-009179
ISBN13 978-0-472-09742-5 (cloth) CIP
ISBN13 978-0-472-06742-8 (paper)
ISBN13 978-0-472-02321-9 (electronic)
To Erna Judovits
In Memoriam
What is most surprising is rather the body;
one never ceases to be amazed at the idea that
the human body has become possible.
-FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
Acknowledgments
Introduction
Conclusion 169
Notes 179
Bibliography 211
Index 223
Introduction
The critical literature of the past decades bears witness to a renewed inter-
est in the body, in its literary, philosophical, social, and historical construc-
tion. 1 The confluence of these discourses that shape the destiny of the body
is grounded in specific historical conditions that determine its particular
modes of existence. Rather than treating the body as a given, these studies
compel us to question and explore its conditions of possibility. However,
this effort to inquire into the construction of the body must take into
account the obstacle presented by its conceptual consolidations, which
attain over time a factual authority and stability that are very difficult to
overcome. As Maurice Merleau-Ponty points out regarding the advent of
subjectivity in philosophy: "There are some ideas which make it impossible
for us to return to a time prior to their existence, even and especially if we
have moved beyond them.,,2 The fate of the body as an idea, like that of
subjectivity to whose emergence it is linked, is haunted by the foreclosure of
its past meanings and history. Once consolidated in the modern period, the
idea of the body takes on the character of a given that renders its prior forms
and modalities of existence difficult to perceive and understand. This
dilemma becomes even more pronounced today, since contemporary for-
mulations of the body appear to have done away with the body as we con-
ventionally understand it, by displacing and replacing it with various
artificial and virtual analogues, whose simulationallogic erases the bound-
aries between the human and the machine. The predominance of virtual
bodies and notions of virtual reality today attests to the persistent legacy of
the Cartesian mind-body duality that continues to obscure and even elide
prior formulations of the body. In so doing, this legacy forecloses the con-
ceptual import of earlier paradigms to new ways of thinking about cultural
constructions of the body and notions of embodiment.
What does it mean to speak of the body in terms of culture, understood
both as the medium for the articulation, cultivation, and elaboration of the
body and as a defining tradition? This project is inspired by Michel de Mon-
2 • The Culture of the Body
taigne (1533-1592) and his comment in the testamentary essay "Of Experi-
ence," from the Essays (1588): "I, who operate only close to the ground,
hate that inhuman wisdom that would make us disdainful enemies of the
cultivation of the body (culture du corps)" (III, 13: 849).3 The inhuman wis-
dom that Montaigne decries denies the pivotal role of the body and of expe-
rience and seeks to exceed or even overcome the embodied and mixed
nature of the human condition. His insistence on the cultivation of the body
implies a revalorizing of its culture, along with that of the mind. Montaigne
suggests that it is through physical and mental cultivation that the body
attains worldly being in its various embodiments. 4 And for the reader today,
this notion of cultivation finds its determining horizon in the modern notion
of culture, within whose traditions the body's condition and potential for
transformation are inscribed. 5
Montaigne's essay concludes with a warning against efforts to dissociate
the mind from the body in order to transcend the human predicament as a
hybrid or immixed condition:
They [philosophers] want to get out of themselves and escape from the man.
That is madness: instead of changing themselves into angels, they change into
beasts; instead of raising themselves, they lower themselves. These transcen-
dental humors frighten me, like lofty and inaccessible heights. (III, 13: 856)
tutional abstraction. These cultural shifts reflect a turning point in the West-
ern literary and philosophical traditions, the emergence of a new concept of
the body whose dissociation from both the mind and experiential reality dis-
engages it from the sphere of embodiment. The advent of Cartesian subjec-
tivity leads to the exclusion of the body from the purview of metaphysics,
and to its reduction to a notion of materiality, whose logic is governed by
the regime of the machine.
It is important to note that this study is less historical than "genealogi-
cal," in the Nietzschean sense, to the extent that it seeks to establish the var-
ied and often conflictual traditions and lineages that mark the emergence of
modern notions of the body.? These genealogies of the representations of
the body are neither linear nor progressive, insofar as they reference a his-
tory of struggles, contradictory impulses, and infringements that emerges
out of a series of discontinuous, overlapping, and episodic moments. They
trace the struggles in the assertion of meanings attached to the body, mean-
ings that engage with past traditions in order to rewrite and thus reissue
their future embodiments. Rather than equating modernity with develop-
ments in nineteenth-century industrial culture, this study demonstrates how
these competing early modern cultural discourses inform, suppress, or acti-
vate the meanings attached to the body in the modern period. If the post-
modern functions according to the logic of the future anterior, as Jean-
Fran<;ois Lyotard suggests, then it is precisely that which has become
unpresentable and postponed in the representations of modernity that needs
further consideration, so that we may begin to understand why an early
modern author such as Montaigne may be deemed postmodern, rather than
modern. 8
The book is divided into three parts that roughly coincide with the
baroque, classical, and postclassical periods, each part outlining specific
conceptual frameworks and discursive practices for staging the body and its
horizon of embodiment. 9 The first, "Baroque Embodiments," outlines in the
works of Montaigne and d'Urfe (1567-1625) a way of thinking about the
body that is grounded in a notion of representation understood as shifting
semblance. As examples of early print culture, these works present the
body's engagement in the fabric of the world through reflections on repre-
sentation and its legibility. The presentation of the body occurs in the
modality of a script, as a transitional imprint that bears the traces of social
and cultural practices. The body is staged; its complexion is not given, but
rather constructed like a scenario that derives its meaning from its context
and finds new meanings through its transpositions into other contexts. The
logic of the body thus emerges in the order of translation, understood not as
Introduction. 5
an originary given, but as a script that attains specific meanings through its
transpositions. In both Montaigne and d'Urfe, this scriptorial account of the
body proves to be nonessentialist, to the extent that it defines the body as a
process of embodiment whose provisional instances mark moments in the
history of its becoming. This emphasis on embodiment rather than being
provides insight into the particular freedom and instability of baroque bod-
ies, their capacity to sustain multiple identities that challenge philosophical,
social, and sexual expectations.
Entitled "Cartesian Bodies, Virtual Bodies," the second part examines
the emergence of a new concept of the body whose purely mechanical and
material definition breaks radically with previous philosophical and literary
accounts based on the experiential or lived body. Descartes's elaboration of
a rational subjectivity founded on the primacy of reason entails the
redefinition of the body as a machine whose objective reality is sundered
from its subjective existence. This disembodiment of subjectivity, accompa-
nied by the mechanical reduction of the body, has important consequences,
since embodiment will cease to define the condition of the lived, experiential
body and will refer instead to its submission, manipulation, and incorpora-
tion within the framework of knowledge and disciplines that legislates and
governs its existence. The problems entailed in the Cartesian virtualization
of the body are echoed in the early plays of Corneille (1606-1684). Given
their social, political, and artistic focus, these works provide a worldly, pub-
lic frame to Descartes's scientific and philosophical explorations of the
body. In Corneille's works, the dismemberment of the lived experiential
body coincides with its virtual reconfiguration in terms of political and eco-
nomic paradigms that sublate its organic logic into the organization of the
body politic.
The third part of this study, "Materialist Machines," elaborates the
influence of Cartesian ideas on the development of French materialism in
the eighteenth century. The import and legacy of Cartesianism finds both its
realization and destruction in the works of such thinkers as La Mettrie
(1709-1751) and Sade (1740-1814), the philosophical critic and parodist
of the Enlightenment. Following La Mettrie's mechanization of man, Sade's
works document the reification of the experiential body through social and
cultural practices that displace its materiality onto the codes governing its
philosophical foundation and social administration. Sade's radical philo-
sophical critique coincides with literary experimentation, with a parodic
expenditure of the body that tests the capacity of the human as a sustainable
category. In Sa de the technological destiny implicit in the Cartesian formu-
lation of the body is brought into explicit conflict with the transcendental
6 • The Culture of the Body
ing such works as the Discourse on Method (1637) and Treatise on Man
(1629-33, but not published until 1664). Unlike the Renaissance and
baroque body governed by humors, each of which determines the physical
complexion of an individual, the Cartesian description reifies the corporeal
body in order to resituate its meaning within the mechanical order and the
solidity of the discourse of science. In chapter 4, this initial attempt to
"decorporealize" the body finds its metaphysical expression as all aspects of
the experiential lived body come into question. In Descartes's metaphysical
opus, Meditations on First Philosophy (1641), the denunciation and ulti-
mate exclusion of the body, as a site for error, from the metaphysical elab-
oration of subjectivity leads to its virtualization, its disappearance as body,
and its reappearance as an errant specter haunting the margins of meta-
physical discourse. The triumph of this virtualized image of the body that
negates all experiential and historical reality summarizes Descartes's legacy
to both classicism and modernity, a "history" of the body that has ceased to
be a "culture."
Chapter 5 examines the representation of blood and the body in
Corneille's theater-concomitant with Descartes's description of the
anatomical body in terms of the circulatory system-in order to explore its
symbolic, social, and political connotations. The transfer of notions of
organicity from the physical body to the body of the state is at issue, as evi-
denced in the metaphorical fragmentation of body and the social exchange
and circulation of body parts. As developed explicitly in The Cid (1636),
but also present implicitly in such later plays as Horace (1640) and Cinna
(1641), the body is presented as an object of contention between competing
systems of social exchange and obligation. At issue is the reduction of the
physical body to its social functions, fostering its administrative incorpora-
tion into the body politic of the nascent absolutist state. The expenditure
and economy of the social body challenges the body's identity as physical
organism, thereby marking a shift in the way it is conceived both as private
and as public entity.
In chapters 6 and 7, the Cartesian legacy to the development of eigh-
teenth-century French materialism comes into question, both the apparent
realization of the Cartesian technological dream, La Mettrie's Man-
Machine (1748), and its phantasmagorical, explosive, and perverse destruc-
tion in the marquis de Sade's Misfortunes of Virtue (1787) and Philosophy
in the Bedroom (1795). Working out of Descartes, La Mettrie emphasizes
the body's material and mechanical reality, not in opposition to the mind,
but as a way of usurping through materialism its Cartesian ascendancy.
Sa de carries this materialism to its hyperbolic and parodic limit through a
12 • The Culture of the Body
strategy that violates not only the body, but the philosophical, legal, and
social laws that legislate its existence. The body is presented as a parody of
the Cartesian logic of the machine, since it is saturated with forms of activ-
ity whose violent nature it cannot sustain without destroying the very mean-
ing of sexuality as embodied expression. The Sadean equation of sexuality
with extraordinary violence and violation, where pleasure is purely an
expression of power, parodically restages the violence inherent in the philo-
sophical disembodiment of the body and its social and institutional reem-
bodiment in terms of a dynamics of power.
While this study takes as its focus pivotal literary and philosophical texts
that mark historical shifts and transformations in the way the body is
defined and conceptually understood, the questions that it opens up are by
no means restricted to its past history. Insofar as it is the Cartesian legacy
that has proved decisive to a modernist understanding of the body, the
effort to recover Montaigne's and d'Urfe's positions does not merely enable
an insight into historic change, but opens up new horizons for thinking
about the body. It is precisely their discursive and conceptual incompatibil-
ity with the Cartesian paradigm and its legacy, that can prove to be concep-
tually productive for the contemporary context. For the paradox that con-
fronts modernity is that its historical development has elided previous
world views, such as those of the Renaissance and the baroque, and in that
sense postponed access to their discursive and conceptual frameworks. It is
this very postponement, however, that constitutes the cultural resource of
postmodernism as it redeploys and reappropriates the semblance of the past
in order to reconfigure the promise of a future already nascent in its mar-
gins. Rather than functioning as the insignia of historical archaism, these
earlier conceptual frameworks can be redeployed in contemporary critical
discourse, in order to provide new ways for conceiving and representing the
body as a plural entity whose multiple embodiments attest to its embedded-
ness in the fabric of the world.
Part 1
Baroque Embodiments
Chapter 1
Montaigne's Scriptorial Bodies:
Experience, Sexuality, Style
It is not only dangerous to read Montaigne for diversion, because the plea-
sure we take in him insensibly engages us in his views, it is also dangerous
because this pleasure is more criminal that we might think. For this pleasure
surely arises principally from concupiscence, and supports and strengthens
only our passions, since the author's style is agreeable only because it affects
us (nous touche) and imperceptihly arouses our passions. 4
In his essay "Of Experience" (III, 13), Montaigne explains that he seeks to
portray himself according to experience, that is to say, in a manner com-
mensurate with the exigencies and limits of his body. If traditional self-por-
traits are misleading, this is because Montaigne seeks to present himself as a
being whose life and activity involve movement and change. This valoriza-
tion of movement, of the self as a "being in passage" (III, 2: 611), emerges
from his recognition that our natural thirst for knowledge is delimited by
the diversity of forms of both reason and experience. "Of Experience"
begins with an affirmation of our natural desire for knowledge, echoing
Aristotle's inaugural statement in the Metaphysics. I I However, unlike Aris-
totle, Montaigne emphasizes the diversity of both reason and experience as
embodied forms:
Reason has so many shapes (formes) that we know not which to lay hold of;
experience has no fewer. The inference that we try to draw from the resem-
blance of things is uncertain, because they are always dissimilar: there is no
quality so universal in this aspect of things as diversity and variety. (III, 13:
815)
and contingent character, but rather because it informs and shapes reason
and its laws as diversely embodied representations.
The effort to contain the mutability of experience can be no more suc-
cessful than the effort to contain interpretation. Montaigne represents the
dilemma of the reader as interpreter by referring to an anecdote by Aesop.
In this anecdote, Aesop's dogs discover something like a dead body floating
in the sea. Unable to approach the body, they attempt to drink up the water
in order to dry up the passage, and choke in process. The point of this anec-
dote is that the reader must become a "good swimmer" (III, 13: 817),
which, according to Montaigne, is what Crates said of the writings of Her-
aclitus. 14 Otherwise, as Montaigne warns, the text may stifle the reader
through the density of its suffocating materiality, like silkworms entangled
in their own work. This warning to the reader against sinking or drowning
serves as a reminder both of Heraclitus's depth and weight of learning and
of the threat of the material density of the fabric of the Essays. Thus, the
story of this dead body at sea outlines from the beginning of the essay the
dilemma of the corporeal nature of the text. The threat of its materiality and
physical character is figured through the bias of a double register. The text's
material existence may be perceived to be solid like a dead body, but this
effect of "thinghood" or material existence is mediated through the fluidity
of the sea, which, like the medium of the representational language of the
essay, threatens to overwhelm and thus drown the reader.
Montaigne's analysis of the relation of interpretation to representation
leads him to an examination of language, particularly in its attempts to rep-
resent materiality in the most elementary and brute sense, by tackling the
definition of a stone:
Our disputes are purely verbal. ... A stone is a body. But if you pressed on:
"And what is a body!-'Substance.'-And what is substance?" and so on,
you would finally drive the respondent to the end of his lexicon. We
exchange one word for another word, often more unknown. (III, 13:
818-19)
The detail is often sacrificed for the sake of the greater idea, just as in law or
medicine a particular fact only gains evidentiary status insofar as it fits,
proves useful to, a preordained order. Thus the authority of the law derives
Montaigne's Scriptorial Bodies. 21
less from its encounter with contingent experience than from the experience
of its conventions as a universal given, leading Montaigne to conclude:
"Now laws remain in credit not because they are just, but because they are
laws. This is the mystic foundation of their authority; they have no other"
(III, 13: 821). The justice of laws is based on their statutory nature, not on
their intrinsic or essentially just character. Laws, like currency, are based on
the authority of credit; they are legitimized not by the fact of being just, but
because they are laws. The legitimacy of the law is virtual, based on con-
ventions whose authors, according to Montaigne, are "vain and irresolute
men"-when they are not outright "fools." Thus the script of the law, its
universal and formal character, is tainted by the faulty complexion of its
authors, who seek to perpetuate its authority by drawing upon its virtual
credit.
Following this stinging account of law, medicine fares no better. 16 Mon-
taigne describes the limits of medicine as an institution that legislates in kind
the experiences of the body. While medicine "professes always to have expe-
rience as the touchstone of its workings" (III, 13: 827), its relation to expe-
rience is circumstantial and indirect, since, as Montaigne points out, doctors
have no direct experiences of the diseases they are treating. Rather, their
experience of disease is through its manifest signs, representations that are
often tangential and not always on the mark. 17 Medicine's descriptive and
prescriptive character often fails in the face of the contingent particulars of
disease:
For the others guide us like the man who paints seas, reefs and ports while
sitting at his table, and sails a model of his ship there in complete safety.
Throw him the real thing, and he does not know how to go at it. They make
a description of our diseases like that of the town crier proclaiming a lost
horse and a dog: such-and-such a coat, such-and-such a height, such-and-
such ears; but present it to him, and he does not know it for all that. (III, 13:
827)
very practices that come to define its daily complexion. Rather than
affirming the mastery of reason over the body, Montaigne inscribes the
body within the social fabric that comes to constitute its very texture: "habit
(coustume), imperceptibly, has already so imprinted its character (carac-
teres) upon me in certain things that I call it excess to depart from it" (III,
13: 830).20 The body bears the marks or characters of habits and customs,
inscribing upon it the traces of the social and cultural symbolic. At the very
moment when one attempts to experience the body in its most "proper"
sense, through its personal and private habits and gestures, Montaigne finds
that the body has already been written and marked by its social and cultural
context. Like an inherited illness passed on through genealogical reproduc-
tion, customs and habits reinscribe the self in the domain of social and cul-
tural reproduction. Montaigne's kidney stones, an illness inherited from his
father (Pierre de Montaigne), function like the mark of the alterity of culture
that infuses the proprietary domain of the self, immixing and contextualiz-
ing its nature. Just as death is constantly confusing and mixing with life,
inscribing within the passage of life the decomposition of bodily forms, so
does Montaigne discover within himself the radical infusion of an otherness
that is indissociable from his own representation.
Even when he attempts to experience his own body directly, Montaigne
finds that his desires and appetites are often regulated by external agents.
The discourse of the body is mediated through a system of medical, legal,
and cultural interdictions that devalue its authority. His stoical reiteration
of the authority of desire, his affirmation that the body is governed by prin-
ciples founded on pleasure, rather than discomfort or pain, makes explicit
his effort to rehabilitate the experiential aspects of the lived body:
Both in sickness and in health I have readily let myself follow my urgent
appetites. I give great authority to my desire and inclinations. I do not like to
cure trouble by trouble; I hate remedies that are more nuisance than the dis-
ease .... The disease pinches us on one side, the rule on the other. Since there
is a risk of making a mistake, let us risk it in pursuit of pleasure. (III, 13: 832)
But the body in question here is more expansive than the physical body. For
to speak about desire and pleasure means to speak about the body both as
experienced and as imagined. Desire does not issue simply from the body,
but involves mediation through the intervention of the imagination, a fac-
ulty that though proper to the individual is mediated and constructed
through others.
Montaigne underlines the significance of imagination (fantaisie) and its
relation to desire: "And then how much it is to satisfy the imagination (fan-
24 • The Culture of the Body
Speech belongs half to the speaker, half to the listener. The latter must be pre-
pared to receive it according to the motion it takes. As among tennis players,
the receiver moves and makes ready according to the motion of the striker
and the nature of the stroke. (III, 13: 834)
and parcel of representation. This is why Montaigne can describe his essays
as "consubstantial" with both his written, represented self and his physical
body. For if the body has been scripted by custom, habit, illness and plea-
sure, its legibility emerges in the order of exchange and dialogue, as a
process of a mediated understanding. As the body "speaks," its speech
emerges in the mode of an address whose destination and whose destiny
coincide in the gesture of communication. Thus the body never "speaks"
directly, since it is merely the trace of a communicative exchange, mediated
by both experience and imagination.
The principles of pleasure that govern the body as a physical and as an
imaginary identity are adumbrated by the very limits of its embodiment as a
material and mortal entity. The physical decomposition of the body,
marked through falling teeth and extruded kidney stones, is echoed by a
mental rigidity and the gravity of the aging body. Both become the living
emblems of the reality of death, the anamorphic inscription of the corpse
onto the living body. If the writing of the Essays corresponds to a process of
both incorporation and elimination, this process is one that confirms the
congruence of composition and decomposition in the essay. Commenting
on his kidney stones, Montaigne expresses his interior perception of other-
ness, of an indigestible, inassimilable difference, as a kind of death experi-
enced by the body: "It is some big stone that is crushing and consuming the
substance of my kidneys, and my life that I am letting out little by little
(vuide) or voiding, not without some natural pleasure, as an excrement that
is henceforth superfluous and a nuisance" (III, 13: 840). Underlying the
coincidence of life and excrement, Montaigne stages the drama of his own
existence as an event where he is no longer an active agent. 24 Here the body
is consumed and destroyed by a stone (pierre or gravelle) that, although an
extension of his own body, threatens to empty out and void the substance of
his own life. The kidney stone becomes the inassimilable difference, the
memento mori of the Essays, of an autobiography that takes the form of a
thanatography.
The inscription of death upon the body and the complexion of the self is
made explicit in a passage from "Of Experience" where Montaigne
describes his painful efforts to pass a kidney stone. The kidney stone is both
a product of the body and the mark of an inassimilable difference, which the
self must eliminate in order to protect its bodily integrity. The stone (pierre)
doubly alludes to the author, both to his father's first name (Pierre) and
implicitly to his surname (Montaigne, which also means "mountain" in
French). Thus it would appear that Montaigne's affliction is both physical
and nominal, since as he explains, it bears the mark of the paternal imprint
26 • The Culture of the Body
There is pleasure in hearing people say about you: There indeed is strength,
there indeed is fortitude! They see you sweat in agony, turn pale, turn red,
tremble, vomit your very blood, suffer strange contractions and convulsions,
sometimes shed great tears from your eyes, discharge thick, black and fright-
ful urine, or have it stopped up by some sharp rough stone that cruelly pricks
and flays the neck of your penis; meanwhile keeping up conversation with
your company with a normal countenance, jesting in the intervals with your
servants, holding up your end in a sustained discussion, making excuses for
your pain and minimizing your suffering. (Ill, 13: 836-37)
Even as the individual suffers in the depth of his flesh, meaning can be artic-
ulated only when the experience of suffering makes contact with others: for
us, Montaigne's readers, sweating, turning pale, flushing and trembling are
events that we experience by identifying ourselves first with the man racked
by his stone and then with the spectators that his text gathers around him to
watch his suffering. It is because he shows himself as he is looked upon from
the outside that we have a sense of participating in what he feels within. 25
Unlike the titles of many of Montaigne's essays, which name his topic
explicitly, the title" On Some Verses of Virgil" suggests that this work is but
a literary commentary on Virgil's verses. And yet this is the essay that
addresses the question of sexuality, thereby inviting the reader to ask why
sexuality may be situated in the realm of literary commentary, instead of
being named and discussed directly as a topic. At the beginning of the essay,
Montaigne, burdened by the exigencies of his aged body, revisits retrospec-
tively the sensual pleasures of his youth. 26 A closer look at the opening pas-
sage reveals that the burdens of the aged body, its being "too sedate, too
heavy and too mature," are but the reflections of thoughts, which though
"fuller and more solid, ... are also more absorbing (empechans) and more
burdensome (onereux). "27 He then clarifies the nature of these weighty
thoughts: "Vice, death, poverty, disease, are grave (graves) subjects and
grieve us (grevent)" (III, 5: 638). The French words graves and grevent sug-
gest not only the ponderous materiality of thought, but also the capacity of
thoughts to figuratively engrave and mark the body.28 This incisive engrav-
ing and marking of the body is underlined subsequently by Montaigne's
avowed sensitivity to the slightest pains: those that previously only
"scratched" him, now "pierce him through and through" (III, 5: 640).
Montaigne's text thus introduces itself in terms of its figural force, since it
outlines a process of inscription that scrambles the distinction between body
and thought. 29 Mediating between body and thought, material text and its
formal organization, the issue of style is obliquely scripted into the fabric of
the essay. Style is alluded to figuratively as the capacity to form and inform,
and literally, since the meaning of stylus is that of an instrument for both
28 • The Culture of the Body
tion of the sexual act, he does so by quoting Virgil; hence, the title of the
essay. As Montaigne explains, this representation of Venus in poetry is more
alive than life itself: "Poetry reproduces an indefinable mood that is more
amorous than love itself. Venus is not so beautiful all naked, alive, and pant-
ing as she is here in Virgil" (III, 5: 645). The depictive powers of poetry are
such as to animate things in an imaginative manner that exceeds their ordi-
nary reality.33 A reproduction of life carries greater power than life itself,
thereby displacing the sexual referent with a textual one. 34 The process of
reproduction, of generating copies, enhances as it were the original, sug-
gesting that sexuality itself is indelibly tied to its transposition and displace-
ment into a poetic representation.
However, Montaigne is not content with Virgil's poetic representation of
eroticism between Venus and Vulcan, which takes place in a marital con-
text. He supplements Virgil's erotic scene with Lucretius's description of
Venus's adulterous enjoyments with Mars. 35 He thus substitutes the
description of one erotic scene with another, which he finds more appropri-
ate because of its illicit character. In both of these cited passages, the sexual
act is suspended between speech and silence, as a transition bridging the gap
between the two sexes. 36 Montaigne then proceeds to expand his discussion
of eroticism to a more general reflection on Lucretius's and Virgil's styles
and their capacity for portraying the erotic:
When I ruminate that rejicit (flings), pas cit (devours), inhians (wide-
mouthed), molli (soft), (ovet (fondles), medullas (marrow), labe(acta (trem-
bling), pendet (suspended), percurrit (runs through), and that noble circun-
{usa (blended), the mother of the pretty in{usus (out-poured), I despise those
petty conceits and verbal tricks that have sprung up since. These good people
needed no sharp and subtle play on words; their language is all full and copi-
ous with a natural and constant vigour. They are all epigram, not only the
tail but the head, stomach and feet. There is nothing forced, nothing drag-
ging; the whole thing moves at the same pace. "Their whole contexture is
manly; they are not concerned with pretty little flowers." [Seneca] This is not
a soft and merely inoffensive eloquence; it is sinewy and solid, and does not
as much please as fill and ravish; and it ravishes the strongest minds the most.
(III, 5: 664-65)
Montaigne concludes his essay, "I say that males and females are cast in the
same mold; except for education and custom, the difference is not great"
(III, 5: 685).47 The reversibility that Montaigne ascribes to the two sexes is
not to be understood as a denial of sexual difference. Rather, it indicates dif-
ference's reconceptualization as a transitive, rhetorical gesture whose mean-
ing is derived from its transpositional or translational character. Just as the
referential character of sex is dislodged from physical reality and transposed
into representation, so does the meaning of sexuality emerge here as an
intertextual gesture marked by intersexual overtones.
Montaigne's use of borrowed Latin texts to represent the reality of sex
conflates the horizon of sexuality with that of poetry. The intertextual con-
junction of Latin and French texts opens up the horizon of sexuality transi-
tively, as the space of translation. Just as Montaigne revalues "language by
means of its displacement," so does sexuality gain meaning from its trans-
position. 48 Gender in this context emerges in the mode of quotation, not as
an essential characteristic, but as a rhetorical relation where meaning is gen-
erated through position and juxtaposition. If poetry "reproduces an
indefinable mood that is more amorous than love itself" (III, 5: 645), then
Montaigne's essay conjures up the sexual referent in its dialogical and inter-
textual structure more effectively than any nominal or purely descriptive
efforts. Understood in the register of human commerce or exchange, sexu-
ality derives its meaning from its transitional, intersubjective character. Its
reality is located in the order of the dialogue, the quotation, or the intertext,
that is, as contextually generated meaning.
The facticity of sex does not rely upon the enforced polarity between the
sexes, but on their potential reversibility. This can be seen most clearly in
the descriptions of the two sexes, which are defined less by their specific
anatomical nature than by their virtual status as projections of personal
imagination and cultural myth. Quoting Plato, Montaigne describes the
male sex as "tyrannical member" and a "furious animal," and the female
sex as a "gluttonous and voracious animal." While he ascribes violence to
the male sex in its desire "to subject everything to itself," this violence is also
present in the female sex in its "rage" to satisfy its hunger (III, 5: 654).
However, this initial affirmation of what appear to be conventional sexual
roles (insofar as the male is presented as active and the female as passive or
receptive) is undermined by a series of anecdotes demonstrating the incalcu-
lable nature of female sexual activity and pleasure. 49 Even in the case of
female chastity, this lack of sexuality or inaction is defined as more active
than actual sexual expression: "There is no action more thorny, or more
active than this inaction" (III, 5: 655). Not only is the virginity of women
32 • The Culture of the Body
mark of gender and the mark of genre coincide in the transitional movement
of the essay that offers itself both as text and as intertext. The productive
interplay between text and quotation becomes the shifting terrain for the
deployment of gender and genre as transitive categories.
see these brave forms of expression, so alive, so profound, I do not say 'this
is well said,' I say 'This is well thought.' It is the sprightliness of the imagi-
nation that elevates and swells the words" (III, 5: 665). Breaking down the
oppositions between thought and language and between form and content,
Montaigne brings them together under the aegis of the imagination as the
generative mechanism of embodied meaning. To say or express things well
is not a superficial matter of eloquence, but a matter of combining thought
and imagination. Thought attains its physical impact through its imagina-
tive embodiments, thereby achieving form through expression. At issue is
not style understood in its literal sense of "manual dexterity," as artistic
conceit and ornament, but rather as a manner of impression that materially
influences the soul: "The painting is the result not so much of manual dex-
terity as of having the object more vividly imprinted in the soul" (III, 5:
665).56
Just as the meaning of content may shift in terms of its stylistic disposi-
tion and composition in the essay, so may the use of language and particu-
lar forms of speech be renewed through their transposition into new con-
texts. Reflecting on both the material nature of the French language and the
manner of its usage, Montaigne emphasizes the seminal role of style as it
transposes certain forms of speech:
In our language I find plenty of stuff (etoffe) but a little lack of fashioning
(faffon). For there is nothing that might not be done with our jargon of hunt-
ing and war, which is a generous soil to borrow from. And forms of speech,
like plants, improve and grow stronger by being transplanted. (III, 5: 665)
renewed each time with its new position and disposition. This capacity for
fashioning language as plastic material becomes the imprimatur of style
understood as physical engagement with language in order to renew and
reactivate its representational potential.
Not only does Montaigne transpose forms of speech by revalorizing them
in new contexts, but he also transforms the speech of others when he
embeds their quotations in the fabric of his own text. However, Mon-
taigne's essay is fraught with the anxiety of borrowing from other authors;
he admits that "they may interfere with my style" (III, 5: 666). Admitting to
his own aping and imitative nature, Montaigne is conscious of the imprint
of others upon his own text: "Anyone I regard with attention easily imprints
on me something of himself" (III, 5: 667). While recognizing other authors'
presence in, and influence on, his text, Montaigne's emphasis on style or
fashioning, on his own manner of transposing and disposing the speech of
others, suggests a new way of understanding value and artistic originality.
Just as Montaigne appropriates forms of conventional language by refash-
ioning it as the bearer of "unaccustomed movements," so are his quota-
tiona I borrowings from others renegotiated through their inscription into
the fabric and formal movement of his essay. Functioning in the mode of
appropriation, the style and quota tiona I structure of the essay script an
encounter with alterity in the transpositional logic of the text. Insofar as this
appropriation is strategic and is redeployed in a particular manner, it
becomes the signature of a new way of defining the value of writing as reem-
bodiment, and of authorship as intersubjective embodiment.
Speaking of other forms of writing, such as those encountered in the sci-
ences or philosophy, Montaigne notes their specialized, artificial, and thus
alienating mode of address. He takes as an example his own attendant, his
page: "My page makes love and understands it" (III, 5: 666). However, this
page will be unable to recognize his actions in the philosophical writings
that are read to him. This example is particularly telling, since the word for
page (page) is identical to the word for a page of a book (or "attendant").
Conflating in the same breath his own page and the pages of the Essays,
Montaigne affirms the uniqueness of his own text in terms that refuse its
assimilation to more technical and specialized philosophical writings. The
problem is that such language fails to capture, because of its general char-
acter, the particular and contingent nature of experience. Hence his refusal
to travesty the content of his actions by dressing them up in the philosophi-
cal language of the schools: "I do not recognize in Aristotle most of my ordi-
nary actions: they have been covered up and dressed up in another robe for
the use of the school" (III, 5: 666). The language of the essay does not hide
Montaigne's Scriptorial Bodies. 37
But how does one portray passage? If being is elusive, then its imperceptible
passages are all the more so. In "Of Vanity," Montaigne hints that his desire
for change finds expression in the concurrence of style and thought: "I seek
out change indiscriminately and tumultuously. My style and my mind alike
go roaming" (III, 9: 761). Reflecting on the flux and mobility of nature,
Montaigne's essays locate in the movement of style the conflation of
thought and its changing forms. 59 In the essay "Of Experience," the pursuits
of the mind are described as "boundless and without form": "It is an irreg-
ular, perpetual motion, without model and without aim. Its inventions
excite, pursue, and produce one another (s'entreproduisent)" (III, 13: 818).
The stylistic discontinuities of the material text of the Essays reflect the
changes and rapid movements of the mind, setting both the subject matter
and the reader into motion.
Commenting on his own style, Montaigne in "On Some Verses of Virgil"
stages a kind of internal dialogue with the reader and his own text, docu-
menting the stylistic particularities of his own work:
When I have been told, or have told myself: "You are too thick in figures of
speech. Here is a word of Gascon vintage. Here is a dangerous phrase." (I do
not avoid any of those that are used in the streets of France; those who would
combat usage with grammar make fools of themselves.) "This is ignorant
reasoning. This is paradoxical reasoning. This one is too mad. You are often
playful: people will think you are speaking in earnest when you are making
believe." "Yes," I say, "but I correct the faults of inadvertence, not those of
habit. Isn't this the way I speak everywhere? Don't I represent myself true to
life? Enough, then. I have done what I wanted. Everyone recognizes me in my
book, and my book in me." (III, 5: 667)
Montaigne's dialogue with the reader and with himself, his answers to the
reader's objections concerning his peculiar choice of words and paradoxi-
cal, even maddening, reasoning, constitutes his affirmation of his style of
writing, which bears the authentic signature of the author as he attempts to
represent himself true to life (vivement), as being alive. Quoting itself, the
text of the essay establishes an internal conversation that mimics through its
own address both the presence of the author and that of the reader, thereby
creating the illusion of life. As Richard Regosin notes: "Montaigne claims
his real, physical presence in the work, both by saying he is there and by giv-
ing the reader the sense that he is there. "60 This live representation of the
author thus emerges not merely as a textual conceit of the author, but rather
as a stylistic inscription of presence generated through quotational and
interstitial movements.
This quotational and self-generative aspect of Montaigne's essays allows
Montaigne's Scriptoriai Bodies. 39
the text to reproduce its author with the utmost sincerity and fidelity, sug-
gesting through its physical immediacy its capacity to intercept and directly
address the reader. 61 It is not surprising, therefore, to hear Montaigne say,
"If there are any persons, any good company, in country or city, in France
or elsewhere, residing or traveling, who like my humor and whose humors
I like, they have only to whistle in their palm and I will go furnish them with
essays in flesh and in bone" (III,S: 640). Readers only have to whistle in
their palms to be provided with Montaigne's presence, furnished through
the essay, not merely as writing matter, but as flesh and bone. The illusion
of presence that the Essays foster is provisional upon a performance enacted
by the written text, which effectuates the corporeal incarnation of its
author. Montaigne's embodiment in his encounter with the reader reflects
the movement that the text initiates and then perpetuates as a literary per-
formance. 62 Reaching out its fingers to the reader, the fabric of Montaigne's
essay grabs hold of us, all the while enfolding and unfolding its author
before our very eyes. 63
While borrowing from many other authors and decrying his imitative
nature, Montaigne inscribes through his style the trace of an irretrievable
difference, that of having lived and having represented his experience in the
most original manner possible. Montaigne's stylistic originality demarcates
the Essays from the works of the past and differentiates them from any
common or traditional use of language, allowing the author to rightfully
claim: "In Paris I speak a language somewhat different than at Montaigne"
(III,S: 667).64 The language of the Essays is particular to its author, like a
regional dialect. It reflects the position of an author whose provisional
embodiment is constituted through the particular handling and redeploy-
ment of language as contextualized performance. The incorporation of
other voices and other authors into the fabric of the text defines the alterity
of its complexion. Thus the quotational structure of the Essays attests to
embodiment, not merely as topic, but as the very mechanism that subtends
the production and proliferation of the essays. The manual dexterity of the
author inscribes within the language of the Essays the autograph of style,
which redefines representation in the very process of attempting to repro-
duce itself.
If Montaigne in "Of Experience" speaks about a "culture of the body,"
this is because he seeks a new kind of human wisdom, one that takes into
account the self's "mixed condition" or constitution (III, 13: 850). Operat-
ing "close to the ground," Montaigne chooses not only to speak about expe-
rience and the body, but to rethink the nature of wisdom as a knowledge
that is commensurate to, and reflective of, the exigencies of the body. Mon-
40 • The Culture of the Body
taigne's admission that "transcendental humors" frighten him like lofty and
inaccessible heights represents his rejection of conventional forms of wis-
dom or knowledge, of forms that seek to exceed the human condition.
Whether it involves forms of idealization or devaluation, such wisdom is
prosthetic, to the extent that it relies on the body even as it seeks to over-
come its limits. As Montaigne trenchantly concludes: "Yet there is no use
our mounting on stilts, for on stilts we must still walk on our own legs. And
on the loftiest throne in the world we are still sitting only on our own rump"
(III, 13: 857). The wisdom of the Essays and their legacy to posterity will be
that of a hybrid knowledge that is "intellectually sensual" and "sensually
intellectual" (III, 13: 850). Rather than separating the body from the soul,
and ideas from their representation, this wisdom will take the body both as
a point of departure and as destination, while recognizing embodiment as
the horizon of possibility of its always provisional condition.
Chapter 2
Emblematic Legacies: Regendering the
Hieroglyphs of Desire
Although widely read and broadly disseminated throughout the first half of
the seventeenth century, Honore d'Urft's monumental pastoral novel Astrea
(L'Astree, 1607-27) soon lost its appeal to the general public.! This decline
in interest reflected a shift in taste of the readerly public, who, guided by the
emergent classical aesthetics in the second half of the seventeenth century,
demonstrated a preference for the leaner and more tightly structured novella
(nouvelle), as evidenced by the success of Mme de Lafayette's The Princess
of Cleves (1678).2 Such a development is not altogether surprising, since the
novel's deliberate manipulation of figurative and literal language, as well as
its narrative conventions involving multiplying story lines, no longer corre-
sponded to the highly restrictive aesthetic criteria of verisimilitude and plau-
sibility that define classical norms and mores. 3 The novel's linguistic
excesses and its perceived preciosity are compounded by discontinuities in
time and space that fail to locate subjectivity as a unified agency. The
emphasis on illusion, deception, doubling, metamorphosis, and trans-
vestism further destabilizes the representation of both subjectivity and the
body. A veritable encyclopedia of love, documenting in over five thousand
pages its every possible permutation, Astrea shocks the reader by its unusual
conceit of representing the love interest of the two central characters,
Celadon and Astrea, through the foil of a love story between women. While
appealing to Neoplatonist ideals, the novel audaciously operates through
transvestism the material transformation of a male character into a female
protagonist, only to progressively unhinge gender positions and ultimately
the subjective agency of the protagonists. If this novel became illegible, first
for the classical readers who were no longer able to appreciate its allegori-
cal devices and representational structure, and then later for the modern
42 • The Culture of the Body
readers who were unable to overcome its perceived archaisms, this resis-
tance to legibility began to give way once it was understood that the novel's
representational structure is not merely the insignia of baroque style, but
perhaps a worldview founded on altogether different subjective and repre-
sentational premises. A brief overview of the critical approaches to baroque
style and its epistemological underpinnings will enable us to elaborate the
historical legacy of emblematic traditions that inform the novel's linguistic
and representational strategies.
The analogy of painting to literature, embodied in Horace's phrase ut
pictura poesis ("as in painting, so in poetry"), has been the implicit premise
that informs and guides baroque literary studies. 4 Once we consider the pre-
eminence of visual metaphors in baroque literature, the dominance of illu-
sion, and the trompe l'oeil character of both protagonists and narrative, the
impetus to apply pictorial categories to poetry is not surprising. In France,
the major approaches to baroque literary style are art-historical, based on
Heinrich Wolfflin's concepts of architectural and pictorial style elaborated
in Renaissance and Baroque (1888) and Principles of Art History (1915).5
Wolfflin associates the baroque with the painterly style, as opposed to the
linear style of the Renaissance, and defines it by its focus on open form, on
movement-as the expression of form in function, that is, on the thing in its
relations, rather than the thing in itself. 6 These features are the signatory
conventions of baroque representation: the "apprehension of the world as
shifting semblance."7 The baroque thus represents a new way of conceiving
plastic form, reflecting technical and artistic transformations in the way
vision is conceived and the manner in which it organizes the space of repre-
sentation. 8
Recent attempts to reassess the baroque have been marked by an effort to
move beyond stylistic considerations, in order to come to terms with its
specific historical character. 9 Concomitant to these approaches is the emer-
gence of philosophical studies that examine the baroque, not merely as the
expression of a style, but as a particular manner of apprehending and rep-
resenting the world, a worldview. 1o In this study, Wolfflin's observations
are recontextualized by considering Walter Benjamin's seminal contribution
to baroque aesthetics. In The Origin of German Tragic Drama (1928), Ben-
jamin observes that in baroque works, the "written word tends towards the
visual."!! This appeal to the visual establishes the plastic dimension of
baroque allegory as a "crossing of the borders of a different mode." 12 The
figurative character of the baroque represents for Benjamin the crossover of
poetic and pictorial conventions that baroque allegory enacts as it seeks to
go beyond expression in the self-conscious invocation of convention. 13
Emblematic legacies • 43
novel stages its emblematic heritage through the interplay between word
and image. Baroque allegory thus presents us with a concept of representa-
tion whose ternary structure, as opposed to the modern binary conception
of the sign, enables us to conceive meaning as a convention whose interpre-
tative structure relies upon the mediation of literal and figurative elements.
This study of the legacy of these emblematic traditions in Astrea focuses
on their impact on the representation of subjectivity and the body. The
interplay of word and image informs the peculiar features of the novel's
depiction of the characters' apprehension, perception, and understanding of
the world in relation to landscape, to language, and to representations of
self and other. If the novel's protagonists appear to inhabit a world whose
phenomenological premises are different from our own, this is not simply
because they inhabit the utopic world of the pastoral. Rather, the emblem-
atic nature of the novel's depictions continues to attest to an "apprehension
of the world as shifting semblance," one where representation is not yet
grounded by foundational constraints. Within this representational frame-
work, even sexual difference fails to function as a stable referent or essence,
since difference is undermined by the play of always changing semblances.
This is why presentations of the body, gender, and eroticism in Astrea are
free of conventional oppositions and restraints, since notions of identity are
tied to the logic of appearance. In the pages that follow, the fluidity and free-
dom of the body, setting, speech, and gender will be read as a function of the
novel's implicit reflections on the play of representation.
The opening passage of Astrea describes the physical setting of the novel.
Despite its geographical verisimilitude, the description of this landscape has
been linked to pastoral aspirations. Yet the difficulty of orienting oneself
within this image is due to an excess, rather than a lack, of deictical mark-
ers, and this difficulty suggests that the image is a composite of divergent
points of view:
In the heart of the Country is a most beautiful plain girdled by as with strong
walls, by hills close by, and watered by the River Loire, which originating not
far off, glides gently almost through the midst of it . ... Many other rivulets
in diverse places go about bathing it ... one of the most beautiful of which
is Lignon, which though vagabond in its course, as well as dubious in its
source, runs meander-like through the plain, ... where the Loire receiving it,
Emblematic Legacies • 45
and making it lose its proper name, carries it as tribute unto the Ocean. (1:1,
1:9; emphasis added)21
If you [Lignon] also have good memory of the agreeable occupations you
gave me, since your shores were quite often the faithful secretaries of my
imaginations and of the sweetness of such a desirable life, I am sure that you
will easily recognize that at this time I am neither giving nor offering you any-
thing new which you have not already acquired. (3:5-6; emphasis added)
If the novel is presented as a tribute to the river, this is because the river is
the original secretary of his imaginations, oddly recording ("conserveras
curieusement"), scrupulously preserving, and publicizing them to the vari-
ous river nymphs and gods. Lignon is thus posited both as the source of nar-
ration and as its authorizing agent. The author's indebtedness to the river is
such that the publication of his own work is presented as a repayment to
Lignon, as a tribute to its "authorizing agency."27 Thus the river is desig-
nated as the original site for the production of narrative, which corresponds
to its reproduction as narrative image and as script. The authority of the
author and the landscape become interchangeable, since it is no longer clear
which is the true source of the narration. Thus, from what appears to be
mere geographical description, we stumble upon allegory: the reduction of
the natural world to hieroglyphs whose characters shape the script of the
narrative.
In the third part of Astrea, the opening description of the novel is rein-
voked, not as an element of setting, but as the allegorical embodiment of a
state of mind. At this point, for reasons that will be elucidated later in this
chapter, Celadon, banished from sight by Astrea, returns to live with her
disguised as the druid priestess Alexis. Alexis invites Astrea to look at this
landscape, which is now the only living testimony of his former existence as
Celadon:
And upon this word, opening the window and both leaning over the ledge,
after looking about this and that way, Astrea began thus: Do you see,
Madam, the course of that river ... that is the fatal and defamed river
Lignon, along which you may perceive our hamlet to be seated .... If you
please to cast your eye a little upon the left hand, you may see the temple of
the good Goddess ... under which runs an arm of the detestable Lignon .
. . . Amongst the rest, I observed the picture of the goddess Astrea (for the
temple is dedicated unto her) much different from those by which they used
to represent her unto us: She is portrayed in the habit of a shepherdess. (2:81,
3:223-24)
This "fold" in the material structure of the novel provides insights into how
representation functions; that is, it provides an outlook on what constitutes
"looking" in the novel. In this context, the image of the river Lignon takes
on a new meaning. This time the description appears to follow more con-
ventional spatial rules, yet its rationale is less spatial than affective, for
Lignon is not just a river, it is a despicable one. Although this landscape is
more coherently organized, giving us, in effect, our first true view of the
scene, this view is itself a composite of two different perspectives, those of
Astrea and Alexis. This mediated perspective reflects the physical and psy-
chological distance that now enables the characters to read their lives in the
landscape. This act of reading, which corresponds to visual pointing and
interpreting, transforms the landscape into a text whose legibility relies on
the affective script of the characters.
At the heart of this description of the landscape lies another image, that of
the picture of the goddess Astrea disguised as a shepherdess. Surprisingly,
this portrait, as Astrea tells Alexis, resembles her. In true baroque fashion,
we have a series of receding representations in trompe l'oeil that enables
Astrea to discover and view herself immortalized in the landscape as a god-
dess within a temple. This discovery is not mediated through vision alone.
Rather, Astrea's ability to recognize herself in the image of a goddess is based
on her capacity to assume the script of Celadon's love, insofar as it has trans-
formed the landscape into narrative. This portrait of Astrea thus resembles
her improperly: its verisimilitude cannot be guaranteed either by her own
semblance or by her name. Despite their deictical properties, both image and
name emerge as unstable referents, since neither can define itself without
inscription into the texture of the other. The reflective mirrors generated by
the mise-en-abyme structure of this baroque text produce deictical effects,
but their referential scope is defined by the narrative fabric of the text.
Thus the protagonists of Astrea consider the landscape less a reflective
mirror than a scripted surface whose characters must be deciphered. The
only apparent exception to this rule, in the novel, is the allegorical "Foun-
tain of Love's Truth," a magic mirror of lovers' sentiments. As its title indi-
cates, this fountain provides the beholder with an image of love's truth,
reflecting the lover's innermost thoughts and desires. For Louise Horowitz,
the image of the fountain is the concrete symbol of the novel's "metaphysi-
cal base," of its Platonic presuppositions. Had access to this fountain not
been cut off, there could be no novel, since its absence is equated with the
generation of doubt: "doubt so great that it risks destroying the moral foun-
dation of the novel."28 If the absence of the fountain is to be equated with
the generation of doubt, we must examine how love's truth is revealed. Can
48 • The Culture of the Body
one even speak of love's truth without inquiring into the representation of
love as a source of illusion? In examining the fountain of love's truth, it soon
becomes apparent that the fountain reflects not only the desire of the lover,
but of the beloved:
You know what the property of this water is, and how it necessarily reveals
the most secret thoughts of lovers; for he who looks into it, shall there see his
mistress, and if she loves him he shall see himself by her: but if she loves
another, then the figure of that other shall appear ... as all other waters do
represent the body facing them, this one represents the spirits. Now the spirit,
which is only the will, the memory, and the judgment, when it loves, is trans-
formed into the thing loved; and this is why when you present yourself here,
it receives the figure of your spirit, and not of your body. (1:36, 1:93)
Upon looking into the fountain, the lover perceives the embodiment of
his/her desire: the reflected image of the beloved. The transparency of the
water yields forth the material shape of desire. This objectification of desire
into image, however, depends on the desire of the other, the beloved, whose
own desire mediates the visual reference of the beholder. Unless loved, the
beholder ceases to exist, or worse, the image of the beloved will be accom-
panied by that of the rival. The "truth" of this image of love depends not on
visual accuracy, but speech: the image can only come into existence as an
answer-a response to the image of another desire.
What is peculiar about the "reflective" properties of this fountain is that
the images it generates are the embodiment of thought. They are figures of
thought, rather than mere reflections of an external reality. The fountain of
love's truth is presented as the literal embodiment of Platonism, insofar as it
upholds the superiority of ideas over sensible reality. The fact that this foun-
tain does not reflect the lover, but the beloved, is explained by an appeal to
the Platonic and Neoplatonic beliefs that love involves the transformation
of the soul and its fusion with the love object. 29 This fusion, however, is
exaggerated in this passage to the point of caricature. For the beholder is lit-
erally erased from the image, as if s/he had no apparent physical existence.
Platonic doctrine emphasizes the fact that the sensible merely paves the way
for the intelligible. But in the baroque context, the sensible is no longer a
vehicle for signifying an idea different from itself. Rather, as the very incar-
nation and embodiment of the idea, it seems as if "the concept itself has
descended into our physical world, and we see it itself directly in the
image."3o The image of love's truth is the literal transcription of desire into
visual script. However, this image presents a fundamental problem, to the
extent that the physical embodiment of thought implies the potential disem-
bodiment of the beholder. Thus, the script of desire threatens, by its literal
Emblematic Legacies • 49
sion of the myth thus suggests the loss of the self, to the extent that sight
redefines the self as an improper site. This is why in the novel, the image is
never an object that can exist as a thing in and of itself. Rather, the image is
defined contextually through speech. Thus the gaze can no more objectify
an image than can names, in this novel of endless disguises, truly designate
the protagonists. The referential status of both image and language is in
question.
fluidity of language, the word Aymer constitutes a material base that can
potentially generate different images, some in consonance, and others in
total dissonance with each other. It is not surprising that love (Amour) is
introduced in Astrea, as a flatterer who soon changes his "authority into
tyranny" [son authorite en tyrannie) (1:1, 1:9). This sudden turn in the plot
represents the linguistic ambiguity of love, the fact that its appropriation
through speech inscribes in love a double figure: the authority of love's
script may also correspond to the bitter anagram of tyranny.
In order to understand how d'Urfe explicitly problematizes speech as the
purveyor of figurative meaning in Astrea, we turn to an incident in which
Silvandre, frustrated by the unresponsiveness of Diana, seeks solace in the
echoes of his own voice. While he playfully invokes the mythological nymph
Echo, this gesture is framed by the understanding that the "oracular" pow-
ers of this nymph, her ability to speak, is nothing more than the physical
reflection of the voice as it encounters the obstacle of a material surface. Lis-
tening to his own voice, Silvandre experiences it as the expression of
another:
While recognizing the fact that this "echo" effect was generated by his own
voice, "that he was his own answerer" [que c'estoit luy-mesme qui se
respondait), Silvandre cannot help but be pleased by the response, "feeling
great consolation from the auspicious answers which he received" [ressentir
une grande consolation des bonnes responces qu'il avoit receues] (1:200,
2:11). His pleasure involves hearing his own desire reflected back to him, as
if it were the voice of another. But how does speech generate these echoes,
and how do they become bearers of the script of desire? Similar sounds
resound with different images and may embody different meanings: a frag-
ment of the word for "relieved" (allegements), becomes "I deceived," or lit-
erally, "I lie" (je ments), and "thy voice itself" (ta voix mesme) is echoed
back as a command in the imperative: you must love ("Ayme"). Echo's
responses can be seen as a metareflection on the nature of language. She may
not be lying when slhe says "I lie" because speech itself, rather than the
speaker, is identified as the site of deception. When Silvandre asks whether
52 • The Culture of the Body
the voice he hears is her own (mesme), we witness his experience of the oth-
erness of his own voice, as it literally "speaks" back to him. 36 Echo's
response, "Ayme," playfully suggests that the reflexivity of language itself
may generate effects of desire, in a personally indiscriminate or generic
sense. These echoes are reflections, figurative folds in the material surface of
language suggesting that speech rather than the speaker is the site of illu-
SlOn.
While Silvandre explicitly recognizes the self-reflective character of the
echo, this does not prevent him from purloining this reflection as the
definitive sign of another subjective presence. Flattering his own desire, Sil-
vandre convinces himself that someone else is speaking through him. This
delusion, as the narrator of Astrea tells us, is fostered by the desire of lovers
to find hope, even when there is no apparent reason to justify it: "since it
seemed to him that nothing was governed by chance, but all by an all-wise
providence, he believed that those words which the rock returned to his ear,
were not pronounced by him with purpose, but were put into his mouth by
some good demon, that loved him" (1:200,2:11). In what appears to be an
extraordinary step, Silvandre proceeds to disown his own speech. He is the
speaker, but his speech belongs to someone else. He is merely the mouth-
piece for a demon who embodies his desire better than himself. Who, then,
is this fictitious demon or master ventriloquist who expresses Silvandre's
desire better than he can? This demon is speech itself, the alterity of lan-
guage as a symbolic order that "speaks" before it is spoken. Its arbitrary
appropriation by an individual subject reveals speech to be an improper
vehicle for communication, but a most propitious medium for generating
desire. 3 ?
If speech is shown to be an unstable medium, its written representation
fares no better. Although it would seem that writing stabilizes the inflections
of speech, script is itself vulnerable to misrepresentation. In Astrea,
Celadon's effort to consecrate the laws of love for eternity by engraving
them on a set of tablets is perversely undermined. Having dutifully recorded
the laws of love (on twelve tablets, as compared to Moses' ten), Celadon's
written record is falsified by his novelistic alter ego Hylas, ['inconstant, or
"the inconstant one" (2:194-201, 1:278-81). With a few erasures and sub-
stitutions on the part of Hylas, Celadon's pronouncements begin to express
a meaning that is entirely contrary to their former intent. Hylas's subversion
of meaning can be seen as inscribing in language a new voice, the figure of
another. Silvandre's explanation, that when he read these verses, "they were
other than they are now" [ils estoient autres qu'ils ne Ie sont], marks his
belief that the former verses alone expressed his amorous ideal. Silvandre's
Emblematic Legacies • 53
question regarding this sudden alteration of his verses, "how do you think
such a new picture could be made so promptly" [pourroit-on avoir fait si
promptement un autre tableau] (1:281,2:200-201), reveals the mutability
of language, the fact that small alterations may inscribe images different
from, even contradictory to, an author's intent. Thus it is not surprising that
according to Diana they are both right: "for in one and the same place, you
may find what you both seek; you, Silvandre, may find it written as you did
read, and you, Hylas, as you did correct it" [car en un mesme lieu vous trou-
vez ce que va us cherchez taus deux. Vous, Silvandre, Ie lisant comme il
estoit escrit, et va us Hylas, comme vous l'avez corrigej (1:281, 2:201).
Diana's comment highlights the instability of represented language in
Astrea: the fact that, despite its supposedly univocal character, language's
scriptorial character can be manipulated so as to open up other figurative
interp reta ti ons.
In Astrea, the fragility of communication is most visible in the case of
love. The incessant efforts to communicate love, to ascertain it and assure it,
reveal its instability as a representation. This instability is literally captured
in the novel by the inaugural catastrophic shift in plot: from happiness to
disaster. The disaster that befalls Celadon and Astrea is due to their refusal
to recognize the allegorical character of love. Astrea forces Celadon to feign
love for other women in order to distract attention from their own love.
This ruse, however, quickly turns tragic when Astrea becomes convinced
that her lover is actually deceiving her. She stops believing in the illusory
character of the feint and mistakes it for reality. This error, the mistaking of
the feint for reality, reveals the impossibility of containing the meaning of
representation in the novel. The failure to recognize the allegorical charac-
ter of representation leads to the displacement and anagrammatic restruc-
turing of love (l'amour) into death (Ia mort).
Celadon's attempted suicide following the heroine's injunction, accom-
panied by the near death by drowning of the heroine herself, emblematizes
the dangerous anagrammatic displacement of Astree into desastre and
l'amour into la mort. The novel thus visualizes to the letter the heroine's
injunction. The sudden disappearance of the novel's protagonists into the
river Lignon, and allegorically into the fabric of the text, makes visible the
strategic analogy of the river and the text:
She believed him to be dead, for his feet still did lie in the water, his right arm
slackly stretched above his head, and the left half turned carelessly hanging
behind him and caught under his body. His neck was awry and folded for-
ward by the weight of his head which fell backward, his mouth half open,
and almost full of sand, dribbled on all sides; his face scratched and dirty in
54 • The Culture of the Body
some places, his eyes almost closed; and his hair which he wore very long, so
wet, that water ran like a stream from two springs along his cheeks, whose
effaced countenance was the very picture of death. The middle of his back
was so bent as to seem broken, and that made his belly seem even more
swollen, though filled with so much water as he once was full of himself. (1 :4,
1:16)
Graphically marked by the force of the river, the body becomes grotesque:
it is folded, broken, and discontinuous, to the point that its organic identity
is lost. 38 The contortion and fragmentation of the body is the trace of the
river's figurative force as it reshapes the body. It reconfigures the body's
organic form into a highly artificial shape, one akin to the water-spouting
statues of the baroque. This contorted reorganization of the body is an
expression of the absence of love; that is, a structuring order whose lack
becomes the script of disaster (desastre). To emphasize the lack of closure of
the body, we are repeatedly told that "the water, which he had swallowed,
came out again in such abundance" [l'eau qu'il avoit avalee ressortait en
telle abondance] (1:4, 1:16), indicating the extent to which the materiality
of the body becomes suffused and confused with that of the river.
This consubstantiality of body and landscape, their shared "liquid"
nature, suggests that the materiality of the body is conceived according to a
schema that does not make solid distinctions between matter and form. The
plasticity of water as a medium, its capacity to generate figurative effects
through the movement or "rolling of the wave" [tournoiement de I'onde] is
equated with the plasticity of the body, whose disfigurement (torsion and
irregularity) simply marks another figurative turn in the script. Rather than
presenting the body as an autonomous figure, the baroque text represents it
as a material surface that, like water, is capable of bearing different
reflections, that is, of embodying different figurative effects. In an earlier
passage, the fluidity of the water is also equated with the movement of
thoughts, "sundry thoughts ... which floated like the wave" [divers pensers
... qui flottants com me l'ondeJ (1:3, 1:12). The centrality of water in this
baroque novel thus emerges less as a stylistic conceit than as the expression
of a philosophical and poetic outlook, suggesting a notion of materiality
that encompasses figurative effects. 39 If Plato denounces poetry as a form of
knowledge because he equates it with writing on water, in Astrea it is the
material fluidity of water as a medium that becomes the figure of the poetic
character of representation as it conflates literal and formal effects.
Saturated and rearticulated by the river, Celadon's body appears as a sur-
face upon which the landscape has left its own marks, its own graffiti. His
body is a hieroglyph, inscribed upon and written by nature. In turn,
Emblematic Legacies • 55
throughout the novel Celadon busily inscribes the landscape with signs of
his desire, marking upon nature his own graffiti of love. The landscape thus
becomes an extensive hieroglyphic text: it is a surface that purveys the traces
of his love for Astrea, its "characters" (chiffres) (1:198, 1:486). An emblem
in the landscape of this baroque novel, Celadon transforms the entire land-
scape into allegory: it becomes emblematic. Although he can no longer
speak to Astrea, these signs speak for him of his desire. His brother, point-
ing out Celadon's graffiti on a tree, remarks to Astrea: "You recognize only
too well his characters" [Va us reconnaissez trap bien ses caracteres] (1:5,
1:20). These engraved letters are marks that visibly speak Celadon's desire,
in his absence, since they become literal emblems of his character as a
devoted lover.
The correspondence of Celadon and Astrea is an endless series of
exchanges problematizing the representation of love: how can one be sure
that one is loved, faithful, et cetera, and that one's feelings signify properly?
The doubt expressed in this correspondence, which is also a noncorrespon-
dence of sorts, reflects the impossibility of baroque discourse's guaranteeing
itself as a representation, since the absence of the writer opens up the letter
to unintended interpretations. The letters are relays attempting to frame,
but unable to suture, the absence of the other. The problem is that these let-
ters, like the letters of the alphabet, do not belong to anyone in particular.
They circulate, and to that extent they can become the mirror of anyone and
everyone's desire. Thus, the letters do not merely represent the metonymic
character of desire, by supplementing an absence; they also function as the
site of a figurative excess whose hieroglyphic character emerges as the
insignia of desire.
Celadon and Astrea's love correspondence is intercepted by the nymph
Galathea. Upon reading these letters, Galathea's own affection is awakened
and she proceeds to project into the lovers' exchange her own desire. The
act of reading, of performing the desire of others, leads to her appropriation
of the sentiment expressed by the letters. By adding her own letter to the
pack, Galathea adds the image of her own desire to the correspondence,
thereby appropriating it as a vehicle for her own love. The correspondence
between Astrea and Celadon thus becomes the deceptive mirror of three dif-
ferent desires. Celadon's comment upon getting back his bundle of letters-
"Oh secretary of my former, happier life! how did you fall into strange
hands?" [0 secreta ire de rna vie plus heureuse! comment t'es-tu trouve entre
ces mains estrangeres?] (1:65, 1:73)-summarizes the alterity that marks all
correspondence. As the novel playfully suggests, all letters come from the
hands of strangers, including those one has written oneself. Desire in the
56 • The Culture of the Body
When he would find therein something resembling what he had once thought
(as when different people quite often come across the same conception when
contemplating the same topic), he would pose the tip of his finger on that
place, and when he would find another, he marked it in the same manner.
But, when he found the conclusion of the letter to be thus subscribed, The
most unfortunate, yet, the most faithful of your servants: Oh! cried he, there
is no doubt that it is me who wrote this letter; and it must be, that my good
Demon, who has care of my life, having read the thoughts of my soul, has
written them in this paper, that I might show them unto Diana. (1:230-31,
2:86)
Both Celadon (author) and Silvandre (presumed author) consider the letter
the truest expression of their sentiments, as well as the signatory mark of
their unique identity as suffering lovers. As a figure of speech that expresses
more than the truth, the hyperbole creates the illusion of a unique referent
through poetic exaggeration. 41 To the extent that it invokes something
unique, the hyperbole may be seen as a substitute for the proper name. But
the referential status of the hyperbole implies an impossible summation, one
in excess of represented truth.
Any individual's effort in Astrea to appropriate language exclusively by
attempting to produce an excess of determination or meaning runs the risk
of complete indeterminacy. This risk is reflected by Silvandre's conviction
that he is the true author of the letter. This shift in identity is made possible
by Silvandre's mistaking the hyperbolic signature for the actual gesture of
Emblematic Legacies • 57
respect to the letter Astrea's injunction not to show himself before her eyes.
The solution that is suggested to him, that of disguising himself as a woman,
is offered to him as the only way to prove that he is still a man. As the druid
priest Adamas explains: "But now that time is expired, you must return
unto your self again, and make it appear that you are not only in love, but
a man as well" [il est temps que vous reveniez en vous mesme, et que vous
luy fassiez poroistre que vous n'estes pas seulement amoureux, mais homme
aussi] (1:329, 2:316-17). Transvestism is presented as the solution to
Celadon's failure to recognize that he is not merely a pining lover, but a
man. Thus transvestism becomes a way of observing the dictum of Astrea's
law, while displacing its meaning as interdiction. Adamas's suggestion that
he pass himself off as his daughter, Alexis, demonstrates his literal interpre-
tation of the law: Astrea has not forbidden Celadon to see her, but merely
to be seen by her. Celadon's inability to understand how he will fail to be
recognized by Astrea is answered by Adamas's interpretation of what it
means to be seen:
Do you think that she can see you, when she does not know you? And how
can she know you, when you are in such a habit? -But replied Celadon, let
me be habited as you will, I shall be still Celadon in reality; so that I shall
thereby truly disobey her.-That you are still Celadon, there is no doubt,
answered Adamas, but still you do not by this disobey her command, for she
has not forbidden you to be Celadon, but only to show her this Celadon.
When she sees you, she will not see you, but Alexis. (1:36],2:398)
Rather than considering Adamas's argument as a fine example of casuistry,
his interpretation provides a significant insight into the mediated character
of vision. 44 Adamas points out that the act of seeing is itself codified: sight
is based on recognition, on contextualizing perception on the basis of prior
knowledge. Celadon's fears about disobeying the dictum of the law are
answered by an even more interesting argument. In having assumed the
external signs of Alexis, Celadon is not challenging Astrea's law, because he
alone and not Alexis has been forbidden to show himself. According to
Adamas, Astrea did not command that he cease "being" Celadon, only that
he stop "showing" her this Celadon.
Thus Celadon's persistence in the belief that "a change of clothes does
not change the man," is answered by Adamas's claim that disguise does not
merely dissimulate, but also creates a new persona. Visual disguise provides
a new frame of reference whose referential status is enhanced in turn by lin-
guistic disguise. Adamas's ability first to establish, and then appropriate, the
slippery distinction between Celadon's "being" and his "showing" demon-
Emblematic Legacies • 59
And while saying these words, she [Alexis-Celadon] was kissing her eyes,
sometimes her mouth, and sometimes her breast. And Astrea, thinking her a
woman, did freely permit it; on the contrary, she was so extremely contented
to be thus caressed by one whose face so much resembled Celadon, that she
never remained indebted to Alexis for kisses received, as she immediately
paid back kisses unto Alexis with double interest. None can express the full-
ness of this disguised druid's joy. (2:28, 3:598-99)
Scenes such as this have continued to fascinate readers because they scram-
ble the frames of reference traditionally associated with eroticism. The rep-
resentation of female friendship receives such avid expression as to suggest
lesbianism, yet this lesbianism is also the bearer of heterosexual echoes.
Astrea's pleasure at being caressed by her dear friend Alexis is doubled by
the fact that Alexis is the living portrait of her dead beloved, Celadon. Thus
two different sexual scenarios, homosexual and heterosexual, coincide
within the script of the same situation. Their coincidence reveals the pro-
found affinity of sexuality with other terms, such as disguise and illusion,
that problematize the status of representation in Astrea. Rather than con-
sidering the eroticism of the novel in Horowitz's terms, as an "essential sex-
uality entirely independent of gender," it is more appropriate to regard gen-
der as the figurative expression of sexualityY Considered in these terms, the
inscription of these two gender positions is merely an index of the figurative
character of eroticism in the novel.
Though thrust from the obscurity of desire into the bedazzlement of its
fulfillment, "dazzled with too much light" [ebloui de trop de darte] (1 :334,
2:330), Celadon's daily life with Astrea continues to frustrate his desires.
The apparent advantage that he has over the situation by being transvested
as Alexis is purloined from him by this very disguise. Although he is able to
see and talk to her all day, as well as share the intimate rituals of dressing
and undressing, this visual and discursive access leaves him unsatisfied. To
behold her properly, he wishes that, like Argus, he could have "a body all
covered with eyes" [tout Ie corps couvert d'yeux] (1:334,2:330). Unable to
totally possess Astrea by visually objectifying her into an image, he desires
to hear Astrea confirm her own affection, as object of his love. But
Celadon's desire cannot be satisfied, since when Astrea sees him, she sees
Alexis, and when she expresses her love, her declarations are made to
Alexis, his transvested self and not Celadon:
Oh God, said she, that Alexis would be happy without Celadon and that
Celadon would be happy without Alexis! Were I really Alexis, and not
Celadon, how happy should I be in Astrea's favors, and how much more
happy would I be, if being Celadon, she did not bestow upon me these favors
Emblematic Legacies • 61
as being Alexis! Was there ever a lover more happy and unhappy than I?
(2:30-31,3:604-5)
Despite his erotic fulfillment, Celadon is unable to enjoy his pleasure. This
pleasure divides him by reminding him that its true referent is not himself,
but another: Alexis, his disguised self. If he assumes Astrea's ardent love
declarations literally, then his own identity is in question as a man. Celadon
thus becomes victim of his own feint, insofar as his assumed persona
appears to enjoy pleasures denied to him. Thus the mask attains a "reality"
that objectifies its putative author. Having attempted to disrupt the struc-
ture of allegory by transgressing its limits, Celadon now finds himself
reduced to an object of allegory.
The visual and physical pleasure he derives from being with Astrea only
confirms his lack of self-possession. Celadon's identity is fractured by plea-
sure and purloined from him, thereby reducing his body to an "enigma
about the object of its pleasure."48 Rather than designating Celadon, the
experience of pleasure only reaffirms his allegorical status as an object frag-
mented by love. 49 Although Celadon attempts to sort out whether Astrea's
love really applies to Alexis, the name or the person, his efforts meet with
failure. While Astrea assures him that she loves not the name, but the per-
son-"what it is that I unchangingly love is your person, your spirit, and
your merit" [ce que j'ayme sans changement c'est vostre personne, c'est
vostre esprit, et vostre merite] (2:179, 4:263)-her response further perpet-
uates his confusion. The inability to determine whether he is loved as a man
or as a woman leads Celadon to question his identity. Meditating upon his
condition, Celadon recognizes his dependence on his fictive persona, leading
him to conclude that he is a hybrid: "1 am then both Alexis and Celadon
mingled together" [Je suis done et Celadon et Alexis meslez ensemble]
(2:174, 4:252). This conclusion highlights the extent to which disguise in
the novel leads to the actual transformation of the characters, since by
assuming other personae, they come to embody different gender positions at
the same time. Scripted upon Celadon's body, these gender roles restage his
identity as a composite entity, one whose hybrid essence cannot extricate
itself from allegory.
Sexuality in Astrea thus emerges as the referent not of some intrinsic
essence or reality, but rather as the referent of representation, of one's posi-
tion within it. If transvestism plays such a crucial role in this novel, this is
because it reveals that gender is constructed as the composite of a descrip-
tive image and its frames of reference. As a form of impersonation, trans-
vestism involves the appropriation of someone's image and its fictitious cir-
62 • The Culture of the Body
they decide to banish any action that may establish a difference between
them. Initiated by Alexis, this pact formalizes transvestism as a legitimate
expression of love in the novel: "I do ordain therefore that Astrea shall be
Alexis, and Alexis shall be Astrea, and that we banish from amongst us, not
only all words, but also all manner of actions that may put any difference
between us" (2:86, 4:44; emphasis added). Alexis's command literally
enacts the spiritual union espoused by Neopiatonism, by presenting the
transformation of the lover into the beloved. But this Neoplatonic ideal is
transcribed literally, since the mutual exchange of the lovers' names mimics
their exchange of identities through transvestism. Their mutual loss of selves
in each other, accompanied by the loss of their proper names, can only be
sustained through an impossible fiction, that of abolishing all differences.
Hence, the spiritual ideology that Neoplatonism espoused through the
figurative union of lovers becomes in this passage a travesty of identity.
Neoplatonism is undermined by its literal embodiment, since its figurative
ideal, that of spiritual union, relies on the actual negation of representation
and its material reality.
Consequently, Astrea presents us with what initially appears to be a con-
tradictory representation of sexuality. On the one hand, the novel seems to
reject the notion of sexual difference as a foundational term, as a given
physical and social reality. On the other hand, this work also rejects a spir-
itual ideal that could be seen as an attempt to overcome the notion of dif-
ference. How then is the notion of sexual difference to be thought? The
answer to this question lies in the way Astrea problematizes representation.
As this study has shown, the prevalence of disguise ranging from trans-
vestism to a travesty of the notion of identity demonstrates the power of
representation not only to dissimulate, but also to create new situations and
identities. The freedom that Adamas and later Celadon display in manipu-
lating representation attests to their understanding of its allegorical charac-
ter: the fact that neither vision nor language can function as exclusive pur-
veyors of meaning. In a scene where Alexis and Astrea exchange their
dresses, their discussion about the way they should be retailored in order to
fit properly reveals the plastic nature of the representation of sexual differ-
ence in the novel. Alexis explains: "We shall do to mine the opposite of
what I must do to yours, were I to wear it today, for, said she rising to her
feet, you can well see that yours is too short for me, but as soon as I untuck
these puffs and pleats, it will be to my measure; likewise one must put a tuck
in my hem for it to suit your height" (2:28, 3:597, emphasis added). The
small adjustments to be made in the fabric of these two dresses resituate the
notion of sexual difference as a figure generated by the untucking and tuck-
64 • The Culture of the Body
ing of material folds. 55 The dress emerges as material surface that can be
manipulated to engender different figurative effects. The novel thus suggests
an alternative model for representing sexual difference, one in which it is
conceived as a figurative construct, rather than as a predetermined entity or
essential reality. In a novel where everything partakes in illusion, gender is
no morc real than the reality of fiction. Like the text, or the river into whose
folds the characters appear and disappear, sexual difference emerges as an
emblematic mark, inscribed as script but figuratively fluid. If sexual differ-
ence is otherwise marked in the text, this is because it does not belong to a
fixed symbolic order that would reinforce duality, but to an allegorical
order whose figurative freedom marks the rhetorical nature of representa-
tion. Sexuality thus emerges as a stance within representation, an allegorical
fold produced by the emblematic structure of the text.
The legacy of emblematic traditions in Astrea is perceptible in the fact
that representation is deliberately structured to highlight the allegorical
interplay of word and image, of literal and figurative elements. Despite its
ostensible obsession with visual illusion and voyeurism, images in Astrea
(what is seen and how it is seen) are mediated by the discursive frames of
reference (what is said or written). For this reason, baroque representation
cannot be reduced to a stable frame of reference, thereby liberating the char-
acters and their setting to continued transformations that prevent them
from attaining a fixed or defining semblance. Instead of delimiting and pre-
scribing the protagonists and the settings through an essentializing frame,
baroque representation retains its openness by presenting things in their
relations, rather than the thing itself. As the expression of form in function,
it presents a particular manner for apprehending and representing the
world. Whether representing the body, setting, speech, or gender, the fluid-
ity and the freedom that define Astrea reflect this emblematic legacy to
baroque aesthetics, a mediated apprehension of the world, not as image, but
as changing semblance.
Part 2
Cartesian Bodies, Virtual Bodies
Chapter 3
The Automaton as Virtual Model: Anatomy,
Technology, and the Inhuman
Although less than fifty years separate the publication of Michel de Mon-
taigne's Essays (1588) from Rene Descartes's Discourse on Method (1637;
published anonymously), the representation of the body in these works is
radically different. l Considered from a historical perspective this span of
time appears relatively short, yet it marks one of the most significant turn-
ing points in the conception of the body in the European tradition. For with
Descartes we witness surprising new ways for conceiving the body as an
anatomical, technological, and philosophical entity. These include the
anatomical redefinition of the body in terms of the circulation of blood, its
technological resynthesis as a machine, and its philosophical reduction to a
material thing. Descartes's elaboration of the duality of the mind and body
will relegate the body to an autonomous entity, the objective and mechani-
cal character of which will mark a fundamental departure from previous
traditions. As my analysis of Montaigne demonstrated in part 1, the
baroque body is conceived neither as an autonomous object nor as a mere
instrument. Fully embedded in the fabric of the world, the body functions as
the horizon of subjective being and becoming. Contrary to Montaigne,
Descartes advances a conception of the body that not only decontextualizes
it from its worldly fabric, but, more significantly, replaces it with various
mechanical and virtual analogues. In examining the question of the body in
Descartes, we must ask ourselves whether we are still talking about the
body, as we ordinarily understand it, or about something so altogether dif-
ferent and new as to render obsolete all our previous conceptions. The expe-
riential, lived body in Montaigne's works is replaced in Descartes's works
by an artificial, virtual entity that only summarily mimics certain attributes
linked to the body. It is precisely this rupture and radical redefinition of the
body by Descartes, so radical as to no longer resemble the experiential body,
that will constitute the focus of our discussion. 2
In order to elucidate more precisely the differences in Montaigne's and
68 • The Culture of the Body
As opposed to earlier concepts of blood, which did not involve the notion
of circulation, in De motu cordis et sanguinis (1628) Harvey describes the
circulation of blood as a closed circle, thereby preserving blood against con-
sumption. This self-enclosure of blood within the pathways of the arterial-
venal system establishes it as an autonomous system of exchange within the
body. The continuous and circular movement of blood insures both
the preservation and regeneration of the body. 8 Moreover, as a microcosm
the circulation of blood reflects the movements of the macrocosm, that of
the circular motion of celestial bodies. This analogy of circular motion
inscribes the circulation of blood within the framework of the Renaissance
and baroque worldviews that sought to establish analogical relations
between the microcosm and the macrocosm. 9 Within Harvey's system, the
heart emerges as the true sovereign of the body, the guiding principle of life
whose movements are perceptible throughout the body in the tangible form
of the pulse. 10 Although Harvey compares the heart, in passing, to various
mechanical devices (a pump, fire engine, or hydraulic device), these mechan-
ical analogies still reflect an Aristotelian vitalist view regarding the central-
ity of the heart, rather than a mechanical worldview. 11 It is interesting to
note that despite his mechanist tendencies, Descartes does not appropriate
Harvey's interpretation of the heart as a pump. He explains the motion of
blood as a result of the generation of heat in the heart, a position that he
believes to be different from Aristotle's prior formulation. 12
What may have interested Descartes in Harvey's anatomical model of the
circulation of blood is precisely its autonomous character, a closed and self-
regulating system of exchange, which redefines the physical closure of the
body as material fact. The circulation of blood defines the body as a self-
enclosed system whose network character provides the pathways for its
mechanical functions. The circulation of blood provides a map for the body;
it enables its schematic and figurative representation as a virtual ground-
plan that autonomizes the logic of the body, dislocating, separating, and iso-
lating it from the external world as its frame of reference. The capacity of
the body to mirror and reflect analogically the macrocosm still present in
Harvey's account is disrupted, since Descartes's objectification of the body
reduces its capacity to sustain and generate meaning. The body is no longer
a mirror of the larger cosmos; it is a mere object whose mechanical logic and
material definition reflects his philosophical understanding of nature as
inanimate, defined purely as matter, extension, and motion. 13
The autonomy, centrality, and circuitous nature of the arterial-venal
system enables Descartes to provide a physical analogue to the philosoph-
ical reflections regarding the centrality and autonomy of the cogito in part
The Automaton as Virtual Model • 71
The analogy of the human body to mechanical devices was not new to the
seventeenth century, but dated back to the late Middle Ages. In his treatise
on surgery (1306-20), Henri de Mondeville compares surgery to the
mechanical arts, specifically to architecture. 1? More importantly, he goes on
to define the body as the "instrument of the soul" and dismembers this
instrument, its constituent parts analogous to various mechanical devices
involved in artisanal production: the lungs are compared to the bellows of a
blacksmith, the elbow to a pulley, et cetera. 18 However, Mondeville's
instrumentalization of various body parts preserves the overall organic
character of the body, to the extent that these specific parts function by
analogy to a generalized understanding of artisanal modes of production,
including metaphors that cover the diverse utensils, materials, and products
72 • The Culture of the Body
World, become the theoretical prototypes that will dictate what can be
known about "real men" or the "real world." Commenting on the Treatise,
Canguilhem underlines the deception that Descartes's theory effectuates,
since the analogy of the organism with the machine ignores the concrete
existence of the lived body in order to substitute for it a rational recon-
struction:
The theory of the animal-machine would, therefore, have the same relation
to life that a set of axioms has to geometry, that is, nothing more than a ratio-
nal reconstruction. Thus the theory operates by deception: it pretends to
ignore the concrete existence of what it must represent, and it denies that
what it actually produces comes only after it has been rationally legit-
imized. 25
Briefly alluding to the biblical creation of the body as a statue made of earth
(Gen. 2:7), Descartes rewrites this mythic origin by suggesting that this body
is also a machine deliberately made to resemble the human. His description
74 • The Culture of the Body
of the human body as a statue and then as a machine undermines its bibli-
cal status as a vessel that is animated by the breath of God. Endowed with
the external semblance of the human body, this artificial replica mechani-
cally imitates human functions, such as walking, eating, and breathing. The
fact that Descartes includes breathing among these mechanical functions
alerts us to the secularization of the body, insofar as it is removed from the
sacred purview of the pneuma (breath, or soul).27 This secularization,
implicit in the removal of the body from the realm of the creation, is accom-
panied by its dehumanization. By describing human functions in purely
mechanical terms, as proceeding from matter and depending solely on the
disposition of the organs, Descartes dehumanizes them to the extent that
they cease to refer to the organic reality of the lived body. These mechanical
analogues simulate elements involved in the organization of the lived body
only to sublate them technologically. This conflation of the material and
mechanical aspects of the organization of the body with its overall definition
as an organism will lead to the reassignment of the human to the mind,
instead of the body.
Descartes's subsequent mention of man-made machines, such as clocks,
artificial fountains, and mills that have the power to move of their own
accord, serves to underline human technical ingenuity. This allusion to the
power of machines as artisanal products in turn is a testament to God's
superior productive capacity to fabricate the human body as an infinitely
complex mechanical device. According to Descartes's account, God the cre-
ator becomes God the fabricator, the consummate artisan who disposes of
infinite resources and artistry. The gesture of divine creation that constitutes
the realm of the natural world is now redefined as a form of fabrication that
indelibly conflates technique and art. The natural world is thus sublated by
the artificial logic of the artifact, just as the body is replaced by its mechan-
ical specter-the automaton. As Canguilhem points out: "The intention
behind the construction of an automaton was to copy nature, but in the
Cartesian theory of life the automaton serves as an intelligible equivalent of
nature. There is no room in Cartesian physics for an ontological difference
between nature and art." 28 The Cartesian automaton does not copy nature,
but seeks to gain ascendancy over it by becoming its intelligible equivalent.
In so doing, it conflates organization with fabrication and erases the dis-
tinctions between nature and art. This can be seen in Descartes's claim in
Principles of Philosophy that "it is not less natural for a clock, made of the
requisite number of wheels, to indicate the hours, than for a tree which has
sprung from this or that seed, to produce a particular fruit" (HR, 1:300).
But Descartes is not content merely to secularize divine creation by
The Automaton as Virtual Model • 75
If God created man in the Garden of Eden, Descartes re-creates the body
using the marvelous artifices of the gardens of his time as a paradigm for the
human body.3l Instead of simply describing the body in mechanical terms,
he now stages its workings as the unfolding scenography of a garden land-
scape. The mechanical complexity that underlines Descartes's description of
the human body is represented as a veritable feat of landscape architecture
and engineering, a complex system that weaves in its conceptual fabric var-
ious kinds of machines, the structural and hydraulic principles of which
ensure continuous motion. The human body is represented as a composite
of various technical devices, parts of it operating like springs and others
operating like channels and storage tanks, that is, conduits for the flow,
pressure, and circulation of blood and the animal spirits.
What is notable in Descartes's discussion is the fact that the system for
the circulation of blood also doubles as the carrier of animal spirits. The ani-
mal spirits represent the most rarefied and subtle parts of the blood that are
separated through a process of mechanical filtration (based on the smallness
of pores) into the pineal gland situated in the brain cavity (PWD, 1:100).32
These minute corpuscles "cease to have the form of blood," since they attain
an almost immaterial status. Their subtlety or fineness is such that they take
on the character of a "very fine wind" or rather a "very lively and pure
flame" (PWD, 1:100). Descartes also makes an analogy between the nerves
and the system of pipes underlying a garden. He models the nervous system
on the arterial-venal system, suggesting that neural circulation follows a
hydraulic model involving tiny doors or valves placed in nerves (PWD,
1:107). The nerves are animated by the passage of animal spirits that have
the power to change the shape of muscles (PWD, 1:100). Descartes thus
mechanizes the nervous system by automating its functions, in order to
explain its physiological processes in terms of the activity of the animal spir-
its. What is ingenious about the Cartesian model for the human body is that
its hydraulic circuitry simultaneously accounts both for the circulatory and
the nervous system, at the same time that it serves as a conduit for the ani-
mal spirits, intangible substances that visibly animate the body.
Descartes pursues his analogy of the human body with the gardens of his
time, comparing external objects and their capacity to stimulate sense
organs with garden visitors who unwittingly trigger mechanisms that set an
elaborate spectacle in motion:
External objects, which by their mere presence stimulate its [the body's] sense
organs and thereby cause them to move in many different ways depending on
how the parts of its brain are disposed, are like visitors who enter the grottos
of these fountains and unwittingly cause the movements which take place
The Automaton as Virtual Model • 77
before their eyes. For they cannot enter without stepping on certain tiles
which are so arranged that if, for example they approach a Diana who is
bathing they will cause her to hide in the reeds, and if they move forward to
pursue her they will cause a Neptune to advance and threaten them with his
trident; or if they go in another direction they will cause a sea-monster to
emerge and spew water onto their faces; or other such things according to the
engineers who made the fountains. (PWD, 1:101)
organization of the body, since the rational soul "could not be in any way
derived from the power of matter" (HR, 1:118). While Descartes recognizes
that it is insufficient to think of the rational soul as "lodged in the human
body like a pilot in his ship," and that it is "necessary that it should also be
joined and united more closely to the body" (HR, 1: 118), the Discourse will
provide no further details about how their conjoined nature could even
begin to be thought. Descartes's final conclusion that "our soul is in nature
entirely independent of the body" (HR, 1: 118) will make it all the more
difficult to envisage and mediate their relation. The rational soul's ultimate
autonomy from material and bodily reality implies that it functions in an
entirely different realm of existence. Having radically severed the relation of
the mind to the body, Descartes's subsequent efforts to suture their division
will continue to pose problems throughout his later works. 48
Descartes's insightful and powerful comments regarding the distinctions
between the human and the machine bring out the fundamental paradoxes
that underlie his conception of the body, and that continue to haunt con-
temporary discussions as well. Descartes's first test for identifying the
human with the capacity for representation, understood not merely as
speech but as the ability to communicate and embody ideas through non-
verbal signs, enters into conflict with his second test, which involves the lim-
ited instrumentality of the machine as material artifact. 49 If representation
signifies the capacity for embodiment, for attaining material manifestation
through signs, then the limited or specialized performance of the body as
material artifact could no longer be construed in opposition to the mind.
The material limits of the body would merely reflect a condition to which
reason is subject as well, to the extent that it seeks to define and communi-
cate its own nature. For the capacity of the mind to engage in representation
is not a virtual event, but becomes perceptible and communicable through
material signs, thereby bringing reason within the horizon of the body. Thus
Descartes's insightful and pioneering effort in the Discourse, his test to dis-
tinguish between the human and the machine raises questions that will
remain implicit in his subsequent elaboration of the mind-body dualism in
the Meditations.
As the next chapter will demonstrate, the problem that continues to
haunt the Cartesian system is that of conceptualizing the notion of embodi-
ment, finding a mediation between a disembodied reason and the mecha-
nized body. Descartes's initial anatomical schematization of the body
through the circulation of blood, and his subsequent resynthesis of the nat-
ural body as a machine dismembered from the mind, emerge as instances of
a process of virtualization that document the ascendancy of the automaton
82 • The Culture of the Body
over the experiential body. This virtualization of the body attains its philo-
sophical culmination in the Meditations, where Descartes elaborates a meta-
physical framework that first casts into doubt, only to supersede altogether,
the horizon of the experiential body. Haunted by an errant, disembodied
mind, the triumph of these virtual bodies over the lived body will raise the
specter of the inhuman as one of Descartes's most significant legacies to
the modern age. As the later chapters will demonstrate, this virtualization of
the body as physical entity will entail the aggressive resolidification of the
body as the object of practical discourses that will attend to its administra-
tion. 5o The dehumanization of the lived body, as physical organism, by the
machine will enable its instrumentalization and incorporation into the dis-
cursive and institutional frameworks of newly emergent disciplines in the
sciences, politics, and the arts.
Chapter 4
Spectral Metaphysics:
Errant Bodies and Bodies in Error
error is inalienably linked to the body. The quest for certitude, for the foun-
dations of a discourse of truth counters the evidentiary obstacle presented
by the body and the senses: "All that up to the present time I have accepted
as most true and certain I have learned either from the senses or through the
senses; but it is sometimes proved to me that these senses are deceptive, and
it is wiser not to trust entirely to any thing by which we have once been
deceived" (HR, 1:145). Descartes begins by recognizing the significance of
the body as a conduit for knowledge, insofar as learning proceeds from or
through the senses. This momentary affirmation of sensorial experience is
quickly supplanted by the ghostly traces of possible deception or error. The
fact that the senses are sometimes deceptive leads Descartes to call them into
question altogether and thus remove the body from the purview of knowl-
edge. 6 This initial affirmation of the body and of experience as a source for
knowledge is particularly interesting, since it represents Descartes's unique,
albeit provisional recognition of knowledge as embodied experience. The
removal of the body as an obstacle to true knowledge engenders not merely
its loss to a theory of knowledge, but the corollary loss of embodiment as a
constitutive paradigm.
This disqualification of the body, not merely as instrument but as conduit
for knowledge, reflects the impact of scientific developments in the seven-
teenth century, those of the Copernican revolution, and the research and
production of new scientific instrumentation? The counterintuitive discov-
ery that the earth moves around the sun is supplemented by optical experi-
ments with lenses that prosthetically enhance and expand the horizons of
the senses. The testimony of the senses is undermined by forms of mathe-
matical or technical evidence that supplant experience and the immediacy of
perception. 8 The living body ceases to function as a site both for knowledge
and as a generator of meaning, since the perceptual realm is being replaced
by notions of cognition that function in either purely virtual or technical
realms. The knowledge that the body supplies will be found to be contingent
and partial, and thus irreducible to a universal paradigm or governing
model. This is why perception in the Meditations will be in question both as
external and as internal fact, for its evidentiary nature will be deemed to be
deficient and disruptive, and thus fragmentary and insufficient for any ratio-
nal philosophical synthesis.
The First Meditation is marked by the paradoxical interplay of two
opposing representations of the body. On the one hand, Descartes's
advances the immediacy of his own bodily presence as evidence of the per-
suasive power of the senses; on the other hand, he uses his bodily presence
as a representation intended to cast doubt on the validity of all sense
86 • The Culture of the Body
perception. In this second instance, his bodily presence functions as a site for
deception, ranging from madness to dreams, suggesting that all forms of
sensorial evidence must be cast into doubt:
For example, there is the fact that I am here, seated by the fire, attired in a
dressing gown, having this paper in my hands and other similar matters. And
how could I deny that these hands and this body are mine, were it not per-
haps that I compare myself to certain persons, devoid of sense, whose cere-
bella are so troubled and clouded by the violent vapors of black bile, that
they constantly assure us that they think they are kings when they are really
quite poor, or that they are clothed in purple when they are really without
covering, or who imagine that they have an earthenware head or are nothing
but pumpkins who are made of glass. But they are mad and I should not be
any less insane were I to follow examples so extravagant. (HR, 1:145)
Presented in the first person, this passage reinforces the reader's attention
not merely on the present, but on the bodily presence of the speaking sub-
ject of the Meditations. The fact of Descartes's bodily presence brings into
focus the author of the Meditations as an embodied subject whose evidence
as a material and physical entity is presented as a rhetorically unassailable
fact. I say rhetorically, rather than philosophically, since it is precisely the
evidence of the senses and of the body that have already been in question
and placed under radical erasure through the bias of a totalizing negative
fiction in the Discourse. Descartes asks us rhetorically as to how he could
deny the evidence of his bodily presence. He is quick to reassure the reader
that such a denial is in the order of madness. 9 But the threat of madness that
Descartes conjures up in regard to the denial of the senses is a purely rhetor-
ical gesture, since that precise denial was enacted very simply and categori-
cally in the Discourse, in the hypostatic formulation by which he could feign
that he had no body, that there was no world, "or any place he might be"
(HR, 1:101).10 Thus what is interesting about the Meditations is precisely
the fact that bodily presence is affirmed first as the evidence of the senso-
rium, as an affirmation of the persuasive powers of the perceptual realm,
only to be denounced later as a dangerous lure capable of deluding the per-
spicacity of the mind.
The question that Descartes asks in this passage is, however, crucial to
his philosophy. Let us repeat this question as we read along with the text:
"And how could I deny that these hands and this body are mine?" 11 How in
fact can this denial be operated, for it would imply not merely the threat of
alienation or even madness, but an even more radical gesture of disposses-
sion, that of the loss not merely of our own body as we know it, but of its
facticity as it is experienced by others. However, the evocation of self-decep-
Spectral Metaphysics • 87
tion and madness in this passage takes place in the context of a strangely
reassuring experience; for Descartes relies on the performative evidence of
his own intimate representation, attired in a dressing gown, pen and paper
in hand to suggest the difficulty that he, and by extension the reader, would
encounter in its denial. 12 The madness that Descartes is invoking here has as
its precise object the possibility of the subject's disavowal of its own body,
a maddening contention that Descartes will audaciously pursue, against the
reassuring background of his self-presentation and performance as an
embodied subject. 13
If denying the evidence of the senses risks the threat of madness, their
naive affirmation will be proved to be a matter of illusion or even delusion.
Descartes pursues his argument by reminding himself of his own humanity,
particularly by suggesting that he can conjure up representations of himself
by the fire or even more extravagant ones in his sleep than in a state of mad-
ness. 14 The sensorial evidence of his own presence by the fire is now framed
by the doubt that such a representation does not refer to the external world,
but to the interior world of dreams leading him to conclude that "there are
no certain indications by which we may clearly distinguish wakefulness
from sleep" (HR, 1:147).15 However, the problem is not merely one of dis-
tinguishing the states of sleeping and wakefulness, but of accounting for the
veracity of the sensorial content present both in wakeful and dreaming
states. Whether it is a question of the physically experienced or imagined
body, these representations of embodiment are equally compelling in their
respective realms of wakefulness or sleep, thus casting into doubt the relia-
bility of all sensory data. Descartes's invocation of dreams here is particu-
larly interesting, since during sleep the body becomes in a certain sense "dis-
connected" from the mind. It is precisely the body's physical immobilization
and its shutting down of the external world that coincides with its mental
errancy, its illusionary freedom to embody itself in different guises by defy-
ing the conventions of space and time.
Descartes goes on to hypothesize that he is asleep in order to consider the
nature of the sensorial representations he experiences in dreams, while rec-
ognizing that "possibly neither our hands nor our whole body are such as
they appear to us to be" (HR, 1:146). Having uncovered the doubtful char-
acter of external sense perception, he now proceeds to explore the nature of
doubt as it applies to internal perceptions. While denying any direct refer-
ence between the waking and sleeping world, Descartes suggests that the
"things which are represented to us in sleep are like painted representa-
tions," which could only be formed as "counterparts of something real and
true" (1:146). Pursuing this painterly analogy, Descartes goes on to suggest
88 • The Culture of the Body
that these imaginary representations of eyes, a head, and hands refer less to
actual bodies in the external world, since they may be merely a composite
medley, than to "some other objects yet more simple and more universal
that are real and true" (1:146).16 Thus the imagined body in dreams is dis-
embodied and virtualized, insofar as its referential reality comes to be con-
stituted less by its perceptual semblance than by its abstract generalization
as a corporeal nature. As Descartes explains: "To such a class of things per-
tains corporeal nature in general, and its extension, the figure of extended
things, their quantity, magnitude and number" (1:146). But this notion of
universal corporeality no longer references the reality of the lived body as an
embodied entity, but rather the certitude of a mathematical system that
schematizes the body in the same way that it treats all other objects of
inquiry. Descartes proceeds to reify the lived body, first by undermining its
veracity through association with the errors of sense perception; and sec-
ond, by questioning its reality as the imaginary entity of dreams, only to
suggest its tenuous existence as a virtual entity whose hypothetical charac-
ter is that of a mathematical object, a disembodied thing lacking the very
indices of corporeality.
As Descartes is quick to admit, those sciences that have for consideration
the nature of "composite things are very dubious and uncertain," whereas
arithmetic and geometry treat things so very simple and very general that
without ascertaining whether things are "actually existent" they can attain
some measure of certainty and indubitability. It would seem that the
difficulty of determining the existence of the body, be it the physical or the
imagined one, is a consequence of its composite, embodied character. Only
the disembodiment of the body and its reduction to a hypothetical thing can
guarantee, not necessarily its existence in the world, but its virtual existence
within a system of mathematical certitude. Given this fundamental dismissal
of the body as a phenomenological and psychic entity, due to its consistent
identification as the site of error, the meditating subject must now contem-
plate the ultimate deception, the fact that it may not be the subject, but
rather the object of a deception enacted by someone else. This shift in
agency between being subject, as opposed to object, of doubt is essential
insofar as it reveals the fundamental epistemological impossibility of resolv-
ing the question of doubt within the confines of the embodied subject. It is
only by positing an exteriority that exceeds the limits of the lived body, by
fictionalizing doubt in the guise of the evil genius who acts as supreme
deceiver, that the lived body will be purged of the specters of error attached
to the manifestations of its own agency.
Spectral Metaphysics • 89
Nevertheless 1 have long had fixed in my mind the belief that an all-powerful
God existed by whom I have been created such as I am. But how do I know
that He has not brought it to pass that there is no earth, no heaven, no
extended body, no magnitude, no place and that nevertheless [1 possess per-
ceptions of all these things and that] they seem to me to exist just exactly as
I now see them? (HR, 1:147)
of his own being. 25 He begins with a description of his body that is so clin-
ically remote as to suggest that he is speaking in the third person. The body
is itemized with such complete detachment that its personal attachment to
the speaker comes into doubt: "In the first place, then, I considered myself
as having a face, hands and arms, and all that system of members composed
of flesh and bones as seen in a corpse which I designated by the name of a
body" (HR, 1:151). Thus, when the body is brought back in the Medita-
tions in order to be rejoined to the subject, defined as pure existence, its own
nature has changed, for the body returns not as an animate entity, but an
artificial, mechanical one. Thus another body comes onto the scene, one
whose prosthetic logic organizes mechanically a cadaver. Having been dere-
alized as subjective agency, the body returns as brute physical fact, as a
thing whose purely material and mechanical nature excludes all forms of
agency and memorial imprints, such as we saw in Montaigne's formulation
of the body.
When Descartes goes on to specify the nature of his existence, he focuses
on thought as the sole attribute that belongs inseparably to him. 26 Thought
is now reintroduced into the sum argument, no longer a founding premise
that enables the elaboration of the existence of the subject as in the case of
the cog ito argument, but as an attribute or characteristic that defines the
existence of the subject as a thinking thing (sum res cogitans}.27 In the con-
text of the sum argument thought itself is objectified, since it returns in the
guise of a thing. The reintroduction of thought here serves to preserve it
from contamination by forms of error and deception that the meditating
subject encountered earlier in the Meditations. However, the problem is to
identify the nature of this thinking thing, or as Marin Mersenne argues in
Objections II: "but you do not know what this thinking thing is" (HR,
2:25). This thought that appears in the mode of a thing is one that is difficult
to know precisely because its disembodied character does not reference any
corporeal natures. 28 If Descartes begins to speak about the imagination at
this point, this is precisely because he seeks to identify clearly the disem-
bodied nature of thought. 29 Descartes goes on to specify that the knowledge
and certitude he possesses of his own existence does not depend on the
imagination, nor those things he can feign in imagination:
The piece of wax represents the total gamut of perceptual qualities in all
their immediate eloquence: those of taste, odor, color, figure, size, and
sound. 34 The clarity and distinction of these perceptions is, however,
quickly undermined once Descartes brings this piece of wax into the prox-
imity of fire, since taste is exhaled, color altered, figure destroyed; size
increases and the wax liquefies to the point where it can no longer be held.
While Descartes ascertains the permanence of the wax after this change, he
concludes the impermanence of the senses to provide us with reliable infor-
mation, since what was perceptible in one form is now perceptible under
others. 35 When he proceeds to abstract "all that does not belong to the
wax," he discovers that "nothing remains except a certain extended thing
which is flexible and moveable" (1 :154): that is, an abstract conception that
he will assign to the mind alone, rather than to the senses or the imagina-
tion. 36
Before being altogether swept away by the persuasive elegance and sim-
plicity of this argument, let us backtrack for an instant, for the argument of
the piece of wax proves less the unreliability of the senses than the problem
of thinking the body not as a mathematical abstraction, but as an embodied
natureY The difference in perceptual experiences that qualify the two states
of the wax reflects precisely the fact that the wax is not only matter defined
abstractly as extension, flexibility, and movability, but that it has particular
configurations in its various physical manifestations. The differences in per-
ception involving the particular states of the wax at two different moments
attest less to the deceptive or illusory aspects of perception than to the prob-
lem of universalizing perception across time. The problem posed by the
piece of wax as a hody is its multiplicity in its various physical states and
temporal manifestations. The choice of wax in this context is particularly
telling, since its malleability and flexibility as a substance implies that it can
take on multiple configurations or embodiments. Whereas earlier in his
Spectral Metaphysics • 95
writings Descartes argued for the passivity of the senses by using the anal-
ogy of the imprint of a seal on wax, here in the Meditations he uses the wax
in its multiple embodiments to argue the failure of perception to provide
meaningful information about the world. In so doing, he redefines the wax
as a thing that is no longer a body. Now defined as an "extended thing," this
"same wax" no longer references the phenomenal world, but rather the
immaterial reality of a geometric and mathematical schematism. This geo-
metric description of the wax as an extended thing does not describe it as a
body in the world, since this geometrical notion of thinghood is so general
as to defy embodiment. This reification and disembodiment of the wax,
through the removal of its perceptual qualities as a body, leads to its math-
ematical virtualization. As it recedes from the realm of perception, it
becomes ghostly and spectral, since its reality is no longer defined by the
physical world, but rather by its capacity for being instrumentalized in order
to confirm and find adequation in the virtual realm of mathematical
schematism. Thus the validity of the senses and experiential reality arc rad-
ically undermined through this homology between the mind and the order
of mathematical schematism.
Following the wax argument, which concludes with the affirmation of
the powers of the understanding or the mind, Descartes returns in a last··
ditch effort to consider the power of vision. As the noblest sense, vision is
singled out precisely because its perceptual qualities of clarity and distinc-
tion rival the mind's own ambitions to attain such mental intuitions in its
search for certitude. 38 Since the perceptual clarity of vision stands in com-
petition with the mind's conceptual clarity, Descartes will suggest that the
validity of perceptual vision is based on an ultimate illusion, an elaborate,
artificial chimera engendered by automatic machines pretending to be
human. 39 He concludes the wax argument by positing a highly theatrical
and contrived spectacle:
From this I should conclude that I knew the wax by means of vision and not
simply by an intuition of the mind; unless by chance I remember that, when
looking from the window and saying that I see men who pass in the street, I
really do not see them, but infer that what I see is men, just as I say that I see
the wax. And yet what do I see from the window but hats and coats which
may cover automatic machines? Yet I judge these to be men. (HR, 1:155)40
senses, the body, and what it ultimately means to be human. What is inter-
esting about Descartes's example is precisely the fact that it is paradigmatic
of his general strategy in the Meditations, since the invocation of the virtual
or the machine as fictive entities functions to reveal the deceptive and illu-
sionistic character of visual and other forms of perception. These automatic
machines are in fact embodiments of Descartes's reductionist account of the
body, with the exception that they are here given an agency and the ability
to haunt the human by impersonating it. The simulacrum appears to gain on
the real, not merely by supplanting it, but by mimicking it so successfully as
to destroy reality itself as a frame of reference. Like the evil genius, the
double of God who can perpetuate the ultimate fiction of a total deception,
so do these automatons undermine through their fictional verisimilitude the
human world of perception and the material world that it references.
As Descartes's attempts to strip the automatons of their hats and coats,
in order to denounce the artifices and deceptions perpetuated by vision, the
body has ceased to be in question, having been replaced by a machine.
Descartes's subsequent claim to strip the wax to its bare essentials as a body,
to "distinguish the wax from its external forms" as if he "had taken from it
its vestments" in order to consider it in its "naked" form, reveals that both
the notion of the body and that of embodiment are evacuated in the
process. 41 Ostensibly an argument about the force of perception, insofar as
it engages with the world in the guise of bodies in order to affirm the valid-
ity of the mind alone as the site for true knowledge, the wax argument sun-
ders both the subject's relation to the world, and by extension to its own
body, effectively evacuating it from the world. The world is thus derealized,
transformed into chimeras whose spectral and ghostly nature taunt and
undermine the possibility of any human reality. These automatons and
machines adumbrate the anamorphic, virtual reality of a posthumanist
world whose technological essence defines itself through impossible fictions,
hypotheses of inhuman conceits.
Is It Human?
What then remains of the human, when it has been stripped not only of per-
ception but of its very connection with and embeddedness in the world? The
Spectral Metaphysics • 97
The meditating subject blinds itself to the world by closing its eyes, it can-
cels the intrusion of the world by stopping the ears, and more radically, it
even erases the internal traces of the world in the mind by effacing from
thought all images of corporeal things (as if this were possible) by esteeming
them as vain and false. The attempt to efface all images of corporeal things
is intended to erase the imprint and memory of the bodily traces of the
world that populate the mind of the introspective subject. Thus this self-
mutilatory stripping of the subject through the severance of all connective
ties to the world is enacted both externally and internally. This violent and
forcible removal of the subject from the fabric of the world coincides with
the introspective closure and enfolding-over of the subject onto itself into a
private conversation that the subject undertakes with itself. However, this
radical deracination of all bodily things from the subject and denial of its
embodied character uses a model of introspection, only to deny alterity as
possible content or result of self-reflection. It is important to recall that in
Augustine's Confessions, introspection is a model for faith, rather than self-
understanding, and that it functions as a vehicle for an encounter with the
alterity of the divine. 42 Moreover, as the earlier discussion of Montaigne's
Essays indicated, the introspective examination of the self leads invariably
to the discovery of the other, to the redefinition of the self in an intersubjec-
tive mode. For Montaigne, it is precisely the solitude and isolation of the self
that reveals to the self its embodied character in the writings of others, bear-
ing within itself the estranging script of its worldly and cultural history.43
Breaking with these traditions, the Cartesian model for introspection seeks
to establish through self-reflection the rational essence of the meditating
subject.
Descartes's effort to get to know himself "by holding converse only with
myself," recalls the Platonic definition of thinking as a discourse that the
mind carries on with itself without spoken sound. But as Merleau-Ponty
reminds us, the meditating subject's effort to engage with itself through con-
versation, by seeking an invisible intimacy with itself, implies an impossible
98 • The Culture of the Body
either conceived of itself or perceived through the senses" (HR, 1:186). The
mind's self-reflective inspection of itself excludes the body, which is rele-
gated to the domain of the imagination. 55 For Descartes, the imagination
involves this turn toward the body, in order to confirm something previ-
ously conceived or perceived through the senses. However, as Descartes
subsequently notes, the existence of the body cannot be deduced from the
imagination other than as probability or conjecture (1: 186-87). Hence the
idea of corporeal nature derived through the imagination proves to be
insufficient for the elaboration of a philosophical argument regarding the
existence of the body. While the reintroduction of the imagination into the
subjective content of the meditating subject involves the recognition of its
bodily character, this claim does not modify in any substantive sense
Descartes's previous philosophical position regarding the self-identity of the
mind and its distinction from the body.
Upon their reintroduction by an appeal to commonsense experience, the
senses and the body fare no better than the imagination. While Descartes
admits to having persuaded himself that he "had no idea in his mind that
had not formerly come through the senses" (HR, 1:188), this insight rapidly
leads him to a radical critique of the unreliability of the senses. Similarly, his
admission that his body belongs to him is undermined by the subsequent
affirmation of the separation of the mind from the body. It is through the
senses that Descartes forms the belief that his body belongs to him, and that
he cannot be separated from it, as from other bodies: "Nor was it without
some reason that I believed that this body (which by a certain special right I
call my own) belonged to me more properly and more strictly than any
other; for in fact I could never be separated from it as from other bodies"
(1: 188). This sense of belonging that qualifies the sensorial experience of the
body affirms less the inseparability of the body proper than the sense of sep-
aration experienced in relation to other bodies. Descartes's difficulty in
articulating how the body belongs to him and his inability to describe the
nature of that bond other than by an appeal to a "certain special right"
whose nature is left unelucidated reveal the dilemma posed by embodiment.
It also serves to alert us to the absence of a system of mediation that would
bridge the gap between the senses and the subject's experience of itself.
The reintroduction of the senses in the Sixth Meditation results in their
final dismissal, since Descartes uses his experiences to uncover the errors
and illusionism of sensory perception:
But afterwards many experiences little by little destroyed all the faith which
I had rested in my senses; for I from time to time observed that those towers
Spectral Metaphysics • 101
He attempts to show that the reality of pain does not reference the body
directly, since pain is experienced by the amputee as a reflection of the sub-
ject's prior embodied condition. 61 Despite its immediacy, its intimate and
personal character, the experience of pain appears to designate not merely
the reality of the physical body, but also that of the imagined body.62
102 • The Culture of the Body
of nerves, muscles, veins, blood and skin, that though there were no mind in
it at all, it would not cease to have the same motions as at present, excep-
tion being made of those movements which are due to the direction of the
will, and in consequence depend upon the mind [as opposed to those that
operate at the disposition of its organs] ... " (HR, 1:195). The analogy of
the human body with a machine, where the organic components are reduced
to mechanical counterparts, implies an objectification of the body that
deprives it of any possible agency. Operating purely as a mechanism, such a
body functions by virtue of the disposition of its organs, independently of
the mind. 73 The appeal to the will, and thus by extension to the mind, only
serves to underline the difficulty of locating these forms of human agency
within the logic of the mechanism. These forms of agency appear to haunt
the mechanism, as an afterthought. The disembodiment of the body into a
machine, a purely mechanical analogue of an organism, removes the body
from the surrounding world and undermines its ability to inform and com-
municate with the mind. While the mechanization of the body renders it
available as an object of knowledge, it forecloses the possibility that the
body may function as an agent and site for mediating knowledge. It is pre-
cisely the objective clarity of the mechanized body that elides its capacity to
be reconnected either with the mind or with the world. When Descartes
later specifies that the body is by nature divisible and the mind indivisible
(1:196), this fundamental re-affirmation of their difference makes it even
more difficult to imagine how two such different natures may be intermin-
gled and connected so as to attain a substantial union.
At the end of the Meditations something surprising happens. Descartes
mentions laying aside hyperbolic doubt, not only to recognize that the
senses may indicate more truth than falsehood, but more significantly to
reflect on the role of memory, a term previously devalued in the text?4 But
Descartes is not interested in considering memory itself as a faculty, but
rather in positing memory as an answer to the earlier question that he posed
himself regarding the distinction between waking and sleeping states. Mem-
ory proves to be instrumental to the identity of the rational subject, for it
provides the temporal continuity necessary for the perceived existence of the
meditating subject in time.7 5 According to Descartes, the role of memory is
that it "can never connect our dreams with one another or with the whole
course of our lives, as it unites events which happen to us awake" (HR,
1 :199). It is memory that provides the bridge for the Cartesian subject to
extend and expand its rational dominion, by providing a horizon for both
synthesis and continuity otherwise unavailable to it. It is memory that sup-
plies the temporal horizon of the waking subject:
Spectral Metaphysics • 105
The specter or phantom that haunts Descartes, the sudden apparition and
disappearance of a man that he is unable to contextualize either in terms of
origin or destination, captures the very drama of the Cartesian text. At issue
is less the manifest distinction that he seeks to draw between the states of
wakefulness and sleep than the far more fundamental problem that the very
subject of the Meditations, as it is defined to date, is like the spectral entity
that he conjures up as the effect of his dreams. Without memory, without
the capacity of dwelling in time, the rational subjectivity of the Meditations
remains purely punctual and discontinuous.?6 It is only by contextualizing
perceptions and connecting them with the course of his life through memory
that Descartes can assure the position of the waking, rational subject.
This appeal to and inscription of memory, which appears almost as an
afterthought at the end of the Meditations, alerts us not merely to its
significance, but also to the impossibility of maintaining the rational subject
in its disembodied condition. Although throughout his earlier writings and
his correspondence Descartes has denounced and even rejected the role of
memory, his reintroduction of memory at this point demonstrates precisely
how necessary memory is, both in terms of locating the subject in time, and
in enabling it to connect a variety of experiences. Memory ensures the per-
petuation of the self-identity of the rational subject. As the faculty that
makes it possible for an individual to retain and recall past experiences into
consciousness, memory involves images, impressions or thoughts, embodied
imprints capturing the semblance of the experiential world, which Descartes
up to this point has radically called into question. Along with the imagina-
tion, which Descartes associates with the body, these memorial traces
record the condition of the subject as embodied nature.
By severing the relation of the mind and the body in the Meditations, and
reintroducing only belatedly and as an afterthought the imagination and
memory into the content of subjectivity, Descartes undermines the possibil-
ity of their functioning as a site of mediation for the mind-body duality. It is
precisely the exploration of the sensorial character of the imagination that
could provide insight into the embodied nature of the subject. Considered as
a system of inscription and transcription, memory offers a scriptorial model
that would enable the subject to record and transmit its embodied nature.
106 • The Culture of the Body
necessary and inevitable, will require the overturning of the Cartesian meta-
physical edifice and its subsequent legacies.?? As chapters 6 and 7 will
demonstrate, the development of French materialism in the eighteenth cen-
tury, as elaborated in the writings of La Mettrie and Sade, while appearing
to undermine the Cartesian mind-body dualism through a materialist reduc-
tion, will challenge but not overturn its authority. It is only later, in the writ-
ings Nietzsche and Merleau-Ponty, that the philosophical authority of the
body will be reclaimed as a necessary condition of a subjectivity reembed-
ded into the fabric of the world.
Chapter 5
Incorporations: Royal Power, or the Social
Body in Corneille's The Cid
Taking the logic of the Corneillian text literally, Sorel satirizes its circuitous
representation and transformation of valor, since valor is no longer pre-
sented as being embodied by any particular person:
This valor, firstly, takes on a fantastic body, then it places itself at the open-
ing of this wound, it speaks through this hole and calls to Chimene; then the
author checks himself, and says, however, that this valor does not speak, but
uses the mouth of this wound in order to speak, and finally through this
mouth it [this valor] borrows the voice of Chimene. What detours! This dead
man, no longer able to speak, borrows the voice of his valor, his valor bor-
rows the mouth of his wound, and the wound borrows the voice of
Chimenc. 6
At issue here is more that a question of literary style and the use of figura-
tive language, involving the personification of blood, body parts, and
abstract values. Rather, Sorel's objections focus on Corneille's figurative
Incorporations • 111
governs the play cannot be viewed from a purely structural perspective, but
rather must be specified in order to account for the different kinds of bodily
and social exchange that function in the play.9 Although Doubrovsky
identifies in the play the trace of feudal aristocratic values, based on a sys-
tem of obligation that relies on individual prowess and physical force, this
study will show its paradoxical coexistence with a mercantile and emergent
bourgeois interpretation of value, since value is also presented as payment
and accrued interest from the husbanding of resources. In order to demon-
strate the coexistence of these apparently mutually exclusive systems of
value, this study will examine the circulation of blood, as a figure of social
exchange-that is, the fragmentation of the body and its artificial recupera-
tion in terms of its social function-as a means of explaining the constitu-
tion of royal power. The physical body in the Corneillian text no longer
functions as a microcosm of the state. 10 The prominence of blood, the cir-
culation of which demarcates the closure of the physical body and its reduc-
tion to an artificial mechanism, marks the emergence of a new concept of
statehood in which the law establishes principles of bonding and social
organization that replace blood bonds.
This transformation in the conception of blood is reflected in the Corneil-
lian hero's dilemma regarding the authentic character of his nobility. The
question of the political efficacy of heroic valor and its duration mirrors the
dilemma in the position of the king, whose power is marked by two com-
peting systems of social exchange. The king in The Cid is an absolute sub-
ject, whose position is assured through a process of nomination tied to his
issue from a princely, that is to say "divine," bloodline. But in addition to
being the symbolic guarantor of the collective social body of his subjects
through consanguinity, the king is also an individual who is subject to his-
torical and political pressures. I I Consequently, the king can maintain his
political power only through the economic management and expenditure of
heroic acts that will affirm his symbolic role-that is, to say his valor-as
interest accrued from the wise management of the bodies and blood of his
subjects.
The play opens with the question of how to judge valor within an aristo-
cratic system, where nobility is "naturally" inherited through consanguin-
ity, so that valor can be shared by two people of equal genealogical
descent. 12 The count (Don Gomes) attempts to make a choice between two
Incorporations • 113
For Sorel, the figurative trace of heroism on the body cannot be interpreted
as an absolute sign of heroism, since this engraving on the body outlines the
natural passage of time, rather than individual heroic acts. The universality
of wrinkles among men, be they heroes or ordinary laborers, renders this
figure an inappropriate and even ridiculous embodiment of heroism. Sorel's
critique of Corneille's abuse of figurative language touches on the problem-
atic status of heroism in the play in relation to both language and history.
For Sorel, the legibility of the human body cannot be reduced to the abstrac-
tion of valor by becoming consubstantial with it, for the aging body's phys-
ical traits ill serve the effort to portray the embodiment of a heroic ideal.
The count's effort to interpret the heroic promise of his daughter'S suit-
ors is echoed by the subsequent dispute and duel between the two fathers,
Don Diegue and the count, regarding their own heroism. Paradoxically,
their quarrel takes place in the context of their potential union, that is, the
mixture of their blood through the marriage of their children. While Don
Diegue recognizes their comparable standing as heroes of equal stature, he
attempts to mark their hierarchical difference, since he has been awarded a
higher position in the king's administration. Don Diegue argues: "You are
today as great as once I was. / You see that nonetheless a king has drawn /
A certain difference between us two" (vv. 212-14). Although Don Diegue
recognizes the count's current valor, he understands the king's award of
governorship as a reward for his past valor. The count, on the other hand,
interprets the king's reward as a measure of his political fallibility, observ-
ing that "kings reward not (savellt mal payer) present services" (v. 160).
The count challenges Don Diegue's aristocratic ethos by suggesting that the
king's failure to reward or pay for services performed in the present may
endanger his political viability. For the count, the traditional system of aris-
tocratic exchange based on obligation that defers payments for the past into
the present represents a failure to reward valor in the present. As such, it
does not reward those who presently embody valor and who assure the pro-
tection of the state.
The debate between the two heroes regarding their heroism past and pre-
sent reflects different interpretations of valor as regards history and time.
When Don Diegue suggests that the story of his past life suffices to explain
to his son his present glory ("he / Need only read the story of my life" [v.
186]), the count responds, "Living examples are of much more power. / No
prince can learn his duty in a book" (vv. 191-92). The count's response
indicates that a prince cannot merely rely on recorded past history, since he
needs more than books (livres) to defend his present glory, in order to be
delivered (delivrer) of his enemies. When the recognition of his own valor is
Incorporations. 115
at issue, the count redefines his earlier position, since he views valor as an
objective embodiment in the present, rather than as a nostalgic category.
Although he was willing to "read" and thus infer Don Rodrigue's potential
heroism in the acts of the father, the father's aged body is dismissed as inca-
pable of bearing any longer the inscription of heroic activity.
The count's interpretation announces the emergence of a new system for
measuring valor, one whose terms are based on mercantile, rather than aris-
tocratic, categories. A worthy name and a heroic past do not guarantee
effective intervention in the present. The count underlines his position by
concluding: "If you were valiant, I am valiant still (aujourd'hui)" (v. 195).
The count challenges the king's interpretation of valor and thus his power,
since he feels unjustly excluded by this aristocratic system that favors tradi-
tion and thus past performance over heroic action in the present. In so
doing, the count challenges not merely Don Diegue's position within the
hierarchy, but also the principles of its function and its transmissability. His
insistence that his heroic acts be rewarded through present recognition
marks a reinterpretation of symbolic exchange in mercantile terms as direct
payment, as opposed to deferred reward in a gift-based economy. Thus,
despite its ostensible feudal appearance, the Corneillian ideology of power
also has a mercantile, even bourgeois character. Jean Starobinski observes:
"In the face of such an ideology, typically feudal in structure, Corneillian
psychology seems to define, in contrast, the attitude of the upper bour-
geoisie who make a name for themselves on the strength of their exploits
and of their service to the king and to France" (emphasis added).14 This
mercantile system of social exchange will compete with its earlier feudal
models in order to establish its own ascendancy.
As we have demonstrated, the quarrel that defines the play is hinged upon
two different, but concurrent, interpretations of valor. On the one hand,
valor is defined aristocratically as inherited through nomination and trans-
mitted through genealogy, so that the past symbolically informs the present.
On the other hand, valor is interpreted as a function of an act performed
and recognized in the present, so that past valor no longer serves as a mea-
sure of current worth. This interpretation of valor breaks with aristocratic
traditions, since it is no longer genealogically or nominally coextensive with
the past. The redefinition of heroism in performative terms affirms the coin-
cidence of valor with the exercise of immediate force, so that heroism is
116 • The Culture of the Body
revalued in terms of its pragmatic impact in the present, rather than its
deferred symbolic value. The immortality of heroism as an aristocratic sym-
bol is brought into conflict with pragmatic and utilitarian considerations
that subject it to the demands of history and time. This interpretation of
heroism reflects a new understanding of kingship, understood not merely in
divine terms, but also in worldly and thus political terms.
It is important to note, however, that this equation of heroism with pure
performativity, while mimicking traditional heroism, actually usurps the
traditional aristocratic concepts of genealogy and obligation. The self-
invented character of this new interpretation of valor is summarized in the
count's words, "And all alone ensure the victory" [ne devoir qu'a soi Ie gain
d'une bataille] (v. 183), and his conclusion, "Explain to him your lessons by
your deeds" (v. 184)]. The count sees himself as the executive political arm
of the king, and his own name as the rampart whose symbolic stronghold
preserves Castille. The king's power is represented as being mediated by the
count's actions, or in the count's words, "under my protecting arm" [a
l'ombre de mon bras] (v. 204). The count's demand for direct "payment"
for his services represents a transformation of the traditional aristocratic
structure of obligation, since the obligation of the noble to the king is no
longer conceived in symbolic terms involving retroactive or deferred pay-
ment. Thus, two competing interpretations of the value of heroism are at
work in the service of the king: the first representing traditional aristocratic
values, and the second representing the emergence of mercantile and bour-
geois values. These competing systems of exchange embody the paradox of
the king's symbolic role in the social system, reflecting his dual nature as a
"twinned person." The king's position is double: he is man by nature, sub-
ject to history, mortality, and the possible loss of power; but as the
genealogical inheritor of kingship, he represents divine rights, whose sym-
bolic character make him immortal. As the creator and guarantor of human
laws, kingship places him above those very laws of which he is the supposed
executor. IS
In order to settle the affront to his honor, Don Diegue places his quarrel
with the count in better hands, those of his son. Appealing to his genealog-
icallink with his son, he "borrows" his son's arm in the service of their com-
mon cause as a means of redressing the injustice done to their shared name
and to the heroic purity of their shared blood. Paternity enables the father
to overcome the physical limits of his body by appropriating his son's body,
as an extension of his own being. 16 The conceit upon which this communal
body is based involves the total erasure of the female body that mediates
paternity through its physical intervention. This can be clearly seen in Don
Incorporations • 117
that is, a nominal but powerless agency. IS The only power left to her is a
potential one, that of reinstituting legitimacy through heredity and thus
guaranteeing the reproduction of the monarchy.
The king interprets the duel between Don Diegue and the count as a chal-
lenge to his own absolute power. The independent use of force by the two
nobles threatens the law of the monarchy, since it raises the specter of ille-
gitimate and even tyrannical power. The king reminds the count, through
his spokesman Don Arias, that his legitimacy is above the circuitry of social
exchange, even if his actual power is established through human feats. To
serve the king is a matter of duty and not personal glory: "Whatever glori-
ous deeds a subject does, / These never put the monarch in his debt (Jamais
a son sujet un roi n'est redevable)" (v. 370). The king suggests that his obli-
gation to his subordinates is not reciprocal, since his duty is symbolic and
thus beyond direct measure and recompense. However, the count's perspec-
tive is that the scepter of the king would fall without the intervention of his
own arm, thereby underlining once again the impossibility of separating the
king's symbolic and political power. The conflict of power between the two
nobles, while embodying the paradox of the king's twin nature, also men-
aces its system of law and order.
The king recognizes the challenge posed by the count's interpretation and
redefinition of social exchange in mercantile terms. His vehement response
to the count's persistent desire to engage in a duel underlines the threat pre-
sented by the count's claims about heroism in relation to his own power:
As the giver of the law, the king questions the count's autonomy and his
efforts to impose his own laws, challenging as an individual subject the
king's unique position as absolute subject. The count's act of disobedience
Incorporations • 119
The king's analysis reveals his extraordinary standing in relation to his sub-
jects. His position is defined by prudence, not by force. As king, he is the
steward managing the blood and bodies of his subjects by conserving and
preserving them, even against their own private predilections. As the sym-
bolic head of the social body, the king views himself as its extension, its rea-
son. But his reason is not an ordinary one, since it is the reason of the state,
with him as its figurehead. Thus, the count's challenge to the king's reason
is not an ordinary gesture, as between one subject and another. It is, rather,
an attack on the king as supreme Subject, as the maker and giver of univer-
sal and divinely sanctioned laws to ordinary subjects.
In the play, the king's power is represented as great enough to challenge
and exceed human limits, such as death. When Chimene presents her plea of
vengeance for her dead father, the king appeals to his own immortality
through kingship, in order to suggest that he will take the place of her dead
father: "Your king will be your father in his stead" (v. 672). This symbolic
assurance to Chimene is intended to pacify her desire for vengeance, since
the king as the representative of the social body can substitute himself for
any of the missing parts. By taking on her legal tutelage, he cancels the
demand for Rodrigue's head and thus conserves his arm in his own service.
However, Chimene is not seeking protection from a substitute father, but
120 • The Culture of the Body
the vengeance of her real father. She refuses to accept the king's tutelage
unless its legality can be defined in terms of interpreting the king as both
father and executor of the law.
Chimene's demand for justice is expressed in legal terms that echo the king's
logic, in order to show that Rodrigue's victory against her father menaces
the very structure of the state. 20 Chimene's argument mediates between the
feudal and the mercantile systems of exchange, in order to show that
Rodrigue represents a danger to both. She creates an analogy between her
own vengeance, her demand for payment "blood for hlood"-an allusion to
the feudal system-and the threat that Rodrigue's heroism presents to the
power of the king and to that of the state within a mercantile system:
Chimene argues that by not punishing Rodrigue, the king will lose in terms
of all his interests, whether personal, symbolic, or political. If Rodrigue
must be sacrificed, this is because the Crown and its interests have already
been symbolically immolated. The private aspirations of the hero and his
use of illegitimate force represent a feudal perspective and are here pre-
sented as the challenge of potential tyranny to the order of the state. The
threat of tyranny that haunts Corneille's plays is embodied in this struggle
between nobility sanctioned by force, and the king whose power is assured
through divine rights. 21 Plays such as Horace (1640) and Cinna (1641) rep-
resent in explicit terms the danger that the heroic ethos and its individualis-
tic character present to the legitimate power of the state, since they chal-
lenge privileges of heredity by the use of political force.
Chimene's demands for justice are answered by the plea of Rodrigue's
father, Don Diegue, who claims that his son had merely lent him his hand
and that he, Don Diegue, is the true "head," the one worthy of punishment:
Incorporations. 121
"I am the head; he, Sire, is but the arm" (v. 724). In other words, the father
asks that his son be recognized as a mere instrument, as the extension of
their common incorporated feudal body. The problem is, however, that it is
exactly this feudal body and its principles of incorporation based on force
that present a menace to the modern state understood as a social body,
whose legal and administrative principles of incorporation exceed genealog-
ical bonds.
The scandal of this endless circulation of body parts is put to an end
when Rodrigue confronts Chimene and asks her to kill him in order to
avenge her father. He offends her by presenting his sword to her, which
Chimene perceives to be covered with the blood of her father and thus, fol-
lowing the implicit logic of the scene, to be tainted with her own blood. Don
Rodrigue's solution to Chimene's internal conflict between the competing
demands of filial and erotic love is to insist on the possibility of his own
elimination, in order to efface, as it were, the stains of her own blood on his
sword: "Plunge it in mine, / And thus efface the stain of your own blood"
[Plonge-le dans Ie mien / Et fais-lui perdre ainsi la teinture du tien] (vv.
863-64). This final mixture of the blood of the two protagonists in the act
of death performs a mock marriage that would settle the differences of their
delayed marriage. The erotic subtext of the play indicates the only possible
issue for reconciling social differences: either by shedding blood or by mar-
riage. 22 But the solution that marriage can provide by reconciling the differ-
ences between the demands of genealogy and those of personal history is not
available to the protagonists, since this is not a ceremony that they are free
to authorize and perform by themselves.
Rodrigue's recourse to a heroic ethos, that of a direct encounter and con-
frontation with Chimene, is challenged by Chimene's appeal to the law,
since she recognizes the mediated character of their social encounter. Her
use of legal terminology challenges the critical tradition that has sought to
feminize Chimene by describing her as a victim of passion.23 Chimene pre-
sents her claim as a case would be presented before a judge, thus countering
the illusory freedom of Rodrigue's heroic intervention that assimilates the
judge and the criminal: "1 wish to prosecute, not execute (je suis ta partie, et
non pas ton houreau). / Is it for me to lop your proffered head? (Si tu m'of-
fre ta tete, est-ce II moi de fa prendre?) / I must attack, you must defend
yourself. / I must obtain it from another's hand. I must pursue you but not
punish you" (vv. 940-43}.24 Chimene's reminder to Rodrigue that her quar-
rel is of a juridical, rather than personal, nature defers any immediate solu-
tion. Their quarrel is of a symbolic order, involving the principle of the law
and thus not open to heroic intervention. Chimene's reply to Rodrigue'S
122 • The Culture of the Body
Since the public appreciation of Rodrigue's valor is also the vivid reminder
and living emblem of her father's death, Chimene is not free to forget her
quarrel with her lover. The reality of her father's death is not an abstract
fact, since it is tangibly inscribed upon her own body:
If he's enslaved two kings, he's killed the Count [my father],
And these sad garments which proclaim my woe
Are the first outcome of his gallantry [valor] (valeur).
Elsewhere this lionheart may be extolled;
Everything here speaks to me of his crime.
(Vv. 1130-34)
The objective reality of her father's death, which corresponds to her own
physical appearance marked by mourning, makes it impossible to erase his
death by abstractly incorporating him in a system of exchange that would
trade him for Rodrigue'S valor. Chimene cannot accept Infanta's suggestion
that her father is resuscitated, as it were, through Rodrigue's heroic perfor-
mance: "Your father lives again in him alone" [Que ton pere en lui seul se
voit ressuscite] (v. 1180). Her father cannot be reborn as another person and,
particularly, not in the guise of his assassin. The attempts on the parts of the
king and the infanta to appeal to the welfare of the state in order to console
Chimcne for the loss of her father demonstrate the challenge that the body of
Incorporations • 123
the dead father and its remembrance pose for the well-being of the state.
Chimene's refusal to allow the incorporation of her father's body into the
social body of the state, by recognizing that his heroic traits are now embod-
ied by Rodrigue, indicates her persistence in ensuring his recognition. She
continues to affirm her father's individual existence and rights before the
law. It is interesting to note that the question of the claims of the count's
dead body are echoed by Corneille's own dilemma as author, as he attempts
to justify his elision of extensive references to the funeral and other ceremo-
nial treatments of the dead body in the play. In his "Examen du 'Cid'"
(1660), he elaborates the logistical difficulties of alluding to the count's dead
body, since such references make the possible marriage of Chimene and
Rodrigue at the end of the play seem implausible:
The funeral of the Count was still a very burdensome matter, be it carried out
before the end of the play, or be it that the body remained present in the
palace, awaiting someone to put it in order. The least word that I were to let
fall of it would have broken the heat of attention, and would have filled the
spectator with this cumbersome notion. And I believed it more appropriate
to hide it from the imagination by my silence ... ; I finish with a remark on
what Horace said, that that which one exposes to sight touches much more
than that which one only learns of through a tale. 25
However, the scandal that the dead body poses for Corneille is not merely
one of maintaining, through silence, a plausible ending for the play. Rather,
the residual presence of the body challenges the very logic that seeks to
incorporate the body within the state apparatus and thereby silence its for-
mer existence and legal claims. Corneille's quote from Horace, affirming the
precedence of sight over story, and thus the precedence of present over past
performances, is ironically a reiteration of the count's valorization of per-
formative over narrative representations of heroism. Corneille thus doubly
silences the claims of the physical body. He first excludes it from the stage,
the scene of the representation, and then he elides it again by attempting to
silence its legal claims. This double erasure of the count's dead body enables
Corneille to perform on stage its subsequent incorporation within the inter-
ests of the state, as symbolized by the marriage of Chimene and Rodrigue.
Rodrigue's subsequent victory over the Moors leads to the resolution of the
crisis between the feudal and mercantile interpretations of heroism. By his
124 • The Culture of the Body
victory over two pagan kings, Rodrigue establishes himself in a new relation
to the king and acquires a new identity, a new name, the Cid, a name that
unlike Rodrigue is no longer associated with crime. The king's summation
renders this explicit: "The Moors in flight have carried off his crime" [Les
Mores en fuyant ant emporte son crime] (v. 1414). The king represents
crime in physical, rather than legal terms, so that it can be "objectively"
removed and replaced by valor, as if it were a physical object, rather than a
legal entity. The removal of the count's legal claims through Rodrigue's vic-
tory over the king's enemies indicates the priority of the legal claims of the
state over the rights of any private subject. Moreover, it signals the eco-
nomic reinscription of the body, which, having no intrinsic value in and of
itself, can now be traded for the higher values represented by those of an
incorporated state.
By battling the Moors, Rodrigue/the Cid establishes himself as a new
kind of agent, one whose valor exceeds the domain of the king's compensa-
tion. Through his victory over two pagan kings, the Cid becomes the head
of a new system of merit and exchange. Within this new system, Rodrigue,
alias the Cid, has been named and thus legally recognized by two pagan
kings as their supreme leader. By bringing the pagan kings within the gov-
ernance of his own king, the Cid marks the affirmation of his own subjec-
tion to the order of the state. Rodrigue's submission of his own victory to
the king, which he brings within the dominion of the king proper, is recog-
nized by the king as a gesture that has legal consequences:
By acknowledging the legal claims of the captive kings, the king recognizes
Rodriguelthe Cid's new legal position, which is at once within his own juris-
diction and also outside of it. Whereas Rodrigue has committed a crime, the
victorious Cid is a hero; that is, he has become a "new" person, despite the
fact that he shares the same body with the criminal. Rodrigue'S new name,
the Cid, or "Sire," from the Arabic el Sayyid, no longer designates him
Incorporations • 125
merely as an individual, but also indicates his newly acquired social stand-
ing. Rodriguelthe Cid's divided social and legal status, which echoes the
king's own position as a "twinned person," enables the king to recover the
Cid's victory and his body as interest or surplus value in the economy of his
royal organization and power. The king's recognition of the Cid's heroism is
not merely a sign of generosity, but the sign of the recognition of the politi-
cal and historical contingencies of kingship. Although the Cid's heroism
exceeds the sphere of his social body, the king is able to incorporate and pre-
serve this excess within his own economy of obligation and power. The legal
differences between the king and Rodrigue/the Cid are resolved through this
appeal to a new referential system. As the Cid, Rodrigue can no longer be
held legally accountable to the king, since he is also now a king in his own
right, and thus free to dispose of his power over the bodies of his subjects.
The king's legalistic solution, which upholds the interests of the state,
does not resolve the moral claims of the two protagonists, Chimene and
Rodrigue, since they must continue to argue and uphold their personal
duties and valor. Chimene persists in her demand for justice, since she con-
siders Rodrigue's death to be the only appropriate punishment for murder.
Although she recognizes Rodrigue's value to the state, she insists on the
validity of her own legal position by asking for his death for her father:
"And for my father, not the fatherland" (v. 1365). Rodrigue must be pun-
ished for his crime, so that he may not triumph over crime in the same way
that he triumphed over his enemies. Chimene's call for justice is reinforced
by Rodrigue's own father, who is afraid that the king's refusal to judge
Rodrigue may tarnish his glory (v. 1421). When he insists that the law be
observed, "What! Sire, for him alone you flout (renversez) your laws" (v.
1415), his appeal is based on recourse to heroic, rather than to legal codes.
Rather than attempt to mitigate the crime of his son in court, he would like
him to defend it by force in a duel. Don Diegue's appeal to a heroic solution
marks the shift in his political position. His speech represents his partiality
for his own interests, which he now upholds, like the count before him,
above the interests of state.
Having proven his valor to the state, Rodrigue offers to uphold his duty
to his love by sacrificing himself to it. He once again offers to be sacrificed
by Chimene, even if this sacrifice must be mediated through the hands of his
rival. He tells Chimene, "I shall, in fighting him, lay bare my breast, / Rever-
ing in his hand your instrument (Adorant de sa main La votre qui me perd) "
(vv. 1499-1500). By offering his body to Chimene to be immolated by Don
Sanche's hand, Rodrigue attempts to distinguish between his love for his
country and his love for Chimene. In so doing, he seeks to resolve the imp os-
126 • The Culture of the Body
The king asserts his power in the play by introducing an element not avail-
able to any of its players, that of the symbolic power of duration. The king,
whose position is guaranteed in time, will now invoke temporality to legiti-
mate differences that cannot be resolved in the present. Whereas at the
beginning of the play, the conflict between the count and Don Diegue
showed that heroic acts in the past cannot be effective if they cannot be per-
formed again in the present, the king's invocation of time demonstrates the
transcendence of kingship over the limited duration that defines the bodies
of his subjects. Heroes may live or die, but their existence depends on the
existence of the monarch as guarantor of the state. Even when the king dies,
kingship lives on.
The king's statement at the end the play marks the coincidence between
time, valor, and kingship: "Leave it to time, your valiance and your king"
[Laisse faire Ie temps, ta vaillance et ton roil (v. 1840). The legitimacy of
time mediated through kingship challenges the legality of crime and erases
its performative character. The deferral of the marriage, authorized by the
king, resolves the differences between individual subjects and their tempo-
rality, construed as a pure present. With the passage of time, the crime loses
128 • The Culture of the Body
Nature, the art whereby God hath made and governs the world, is by the art
of man, as in many other things, so in this also imitated, that it can make an
artificial animal. For seeing life is but a motion of limbs, the beginning
whereof is in some principal part within; why may we not say that all
automata ... have an artificial life? ... For by art is created that great
LEVIATHAN called a COMMONWEALTH, or STATE, in Latin CIVITAS, which is but
an artificial man. 28
Does the cogito have a sex? This question might appear to be absurd or at
best irrelevant, given that the discussion of the Cartesian cogito in chapter 3
established the disembodiment of subjectivity and the virtualization of the
body by its reduction to a machine. If the question of sexuality and sexual
difference appears to be moot in regard to Cartesian subjectivity, this is
because the metaphysical definition of the subject as a thinking thing (res
cogitans) and the concomitant reduction of the body to a material and
extended thing (res extensa) radically exclude the question of embodiment.
Although Descartes attempted later in the Meditations to argue the formal
union of these two substances, insofar as they mutually inform human func-
tions, the meaning of their union remained unintelligible. 1 This radical dis-
junction implicit in the Cartesian mind-body dualism, which posits the
autonomy of mind and body as distinct substances, makes it difficult to raise
the question of sexual difference as a subjective, rather than as a purely
material, phenomenon. For the reduction of the body to matter, governed
by mechanical laws, restricts the purview of embodiment and of sexuality,
as one of its signatory manifestations, to purely material and physiological
considerations.
How then are we to think the notion of sexual difference within the
material confines of the Cartesian definition of the body? More troubling
still is the question of the relation of sexual difference to the notion of onto-
logical difference that underlies Cartesian dualism and its elaboration of
subjectivity. In the pages that follow, this troubled and confusing legacy of
the Cartesian conception of the body is at issue, in terms that seek to clarify
both its decisive influence and the difficulties encountered in challenging it.
Starting with an examination of La Mettrie's expansion of the Cartesian
mechanistic account from the body to man as a whole, this study then pro-
ceeds in chapter 7 to inquire into Sade's violent and parodic representations
134 • The Culture of the Body
By the distinction of two substances, res cogitans and res extensa, not only
idealism was provided with a firm foundation: matter was raised to a revolu-
tionary status by comparison to its former position at the rock-bottom of
Aristotle's scheme of entelechy.2
mind. This disengagement of agency from the horizon of the body has
significant consequences, insofar as it suggests its passive submission to a
higher rational order that governs both its construction and functions.
Although Descartes's attempted to defend himself against his contempo-
raries' objections to the materialist implications of his definition of the
body, based on his account of the body as extended matter, his efforts
proved to be unsuccessful. The very fact that he sought to redefine the soul
in purely rational terms (thereby extricating it from Scholastic antecedents
that included, in addition, a sensitive and vegetative soul, that is, embodied
notions of soul) established the effective disembodiment of the subject and
led to the decisive removal of all spiritual aspects from its material sphere.
According to Vartanian, this gesture inadvertently accomplished not only
the decisive substantialization of matter but, more importantly, its elevation
to a new and unprecedented status within an ontological order that had
privileged the mind. Descartes's subsequent elaborations on the mechanical
character of the material body, his analogy between animals and machines
(betes-machines), and the implicit analogy between the human body and a
machine further contributed to materialist appropriations of his philosophy.
Moreover, his insistence on explaining the functions of the body in terms of
mechanical principles implies ascribing to its organization aspects that
define it as an organism as a whole. Given this material and mechanical
definition of the body, the question of embodiment, particularly as it per-
tains to sexual difference, becomes problematic to the extent that it reduces
the horizon of sexuality to purely material concerns. It is this danger that
becomes explicit in La Mettrie's and Sade's materialist interpretations of
Cartesianism, since the substantialization of the body in terms of matter
governed by mechanical laws forecloses an understanding of sexuality out-
side the deterministic sphere of physical phenomena and laws. s
to defy efforts to form either a clear idea of it or to describe it. He then sug-
gests that it is this very complexity that led philosophers to establish the a
priori condition of the mind. La Mettrie, however, insists that the question
of the soul must follow (a posteriori), rather than precede in a foundational
sense an inquiry into the nature of man. Radically undermining previous
theological precedents, he also suggests that the understanding of the soul
must be situated in the same material and mechanical order as the body,
enjoying no greater privilege than any other bodily organ. By observing that
one unravels the soul as one pulls out the guts of the body, La Mettrie chal-
lenges its metaphysical priority as guarantor of certitude and clarity and set-
tles instead for a probable understanding of man's nature.
Aiming pointed barbs at the Cartesian idealization of the mind at the
expense of the body, La Mettrie perversely dismisses Descartes's hypotheti-
cal denial of the body through the rhetorical evocation of madness in the
First Meditation (HR, 1:145), equating this rhetorical position with a state-
ment of belief: "Why should I dwell on those who think their noses or other
members are made of glass?" (MM, 68). His analysis abounds in examples
that seek to relodge the soul within the body, from allusions to hysteria and
hypochondria, to more ordinary instances such as sleep, when the soul and
the body fall asleep together (MM, 68). Using the same examples as
Descartes did in the Meditations to argue the priority and superiority of the
soul, he redeploys their logic so as to claim the interdependence of the body
and the soul within the organism of man defined as a machine: "The blood
circulates too fast? The soul cannot sleep. The soul is agitated? The blood
cannot calm down" (MM, 69). This material co-dependence of the body
and the soul is further emphasized by his insistence on the role of food as the
material substance that fuels and sustains the soul, thus elucidating the
body's nature as a "self-winding machine" (MM, 70).
In order to demonstrate that the states of the soul always correlate to
those of the body, La Mettrie appeals to the evidence provided by compar-
ative anatomy. Noting the structural similarities, except for differences in
size, between man's brain and those of animals, he attempts to bridge the
Cartesian chasm between animal-machines and man-machine by establish-
ing their shared material and mechanical organization. In so doing, La Met-
trie challenges one of the fundamental tenets of the Cartesian philosophical
and theological system. Descartes's definition of animals as machines devoid
of conscious feeling and thought is founded on the privileged uniqueness of
the rational human soul, as well as its purported immortality. It is this meta-
physical interpretation of automatism that La Mettrie usurps by recuperat-
ing a notion of automatism based on mechanical causes that applies to all
138 • The Culture of the Body
animate beings, thereby rendering the differences between man and animals
a matter of degree and not a foundational or a constitutive difference. Given
the great resemblance of man to apes, La Mettrie even raises the question of
their possible education: "Why could not an ape through careful effort com-
municate with sign language just as the deaf?" (MM, 76). This latter ques-
tion directly challenges the Cartesian interpretation of man as an entity that
defines its very humanity through its symbolic capacity of manipulating and
deploying signs. His suggestion that apes may be educated to meaningfully
use signs by training through games or exercise usurps the cognitive prerog-
ative previously reserved solely to designate the human.
La Mettrie emphasizes the material and embodied nature of human
knowledge insofar as it implies the exchange of signs, where "words are the
arbitrary signs" (MM, 79). This definition of knowledge is aimed not only
at redefining cognitive materials, but more importantly at redefining cogni-
tion itself in material, rather than purely conceptual, terms:
All that learning whose wind inflates the balloon-brains of our pedants is
nothing more than a vast accumulation of words and figures which impress
on our brains all those traces by which we distinguish and recall objects ....
Words and figures designated by them [ideas] are so tied together in the brain
that one rarely imagines something without thinking of its name or sign. I
always say imagine because I believe that everything can be imagined, and
that all the parts of the soul can be reduced to imagination alone. Imagina-
tion constitutes them all. (MM, 81)
Rather than denouncing the deceptive and incarnate character of the imag-
ination, as did Descartes, La Mettrie locates both perception and represen-
tation among its functions, along with reason and judgment. Both percep-
tion and representation involve a materially concrete, rather than a purely
abstract, engagement with the world. His privileging of the imagination
thus reflects a recognition of its embodied character, insofar as the knowl-
140 • The Culture of the Body
lofty and rare dignity of genius" (MM, 84), this revalorization fails to
spell out its precise modes of operation. It will be the task of education to
give free reign to or to restrain what La Mettrie calls the "lively springs of
the imagination" (85), in order for individuals to attain either artistic or
scientific (and philosophical) development. His argument regarding imag-
ination as a source of genius is innovative insofar as it attributes a
common source to intellectual development in both arts and sciences.
Moreover, it suggests the shared affinity between poetic and scientific
knowledge. La Mettrie's position is symptomatic of the rise of a new con-
cept of intelligence in the eighteenth century, a concept that no longer
privileges reason, but rather celebrates its powers under the aegis of the
imagination and the multiplicity of forms that it may take, since it "easily
embraces an astonishing host of objects" (MM, 84).1 1 By celebrating the
imagination and the multitude of forms it embodies, La Mettrie redefines
the powers of intellect in terms of its material engagements with the
world. However, this affirmation of imagination as the figure for human
intellect takes place within a rational horizon that excludes considerations
of desire.
Having emphasized the material dimensions of the intellect, La Mettrie
will continue to argue for the material and organizational continuity
between men and animals: "Man is not molded out of more precious clay
than they. Nature employed the same dough for both man and animals,
varying only the leaven" (MM, 90). His refusal to recognize any material
distinctions between the two leads him to reaffirm that "organization is
therefore sufficient to explain everything" (98). Insisting on the organiza-
tion of man as a machine that simply disposes of a few more cogs and
springs than animals, he refuses to explain aspects pertaining to man in
terms that rely on previous philosophical or religious traditions. For
instance, he will argue that the soul is simply an empty word to which no
idea corresponds, and that it should be invoked only to name the part of the
brain that thinks (MM, 98, 103), leading him to conclude: "Thus, the soul
is only a principle of movement or sensible material part of the brain, which
one can regard as the machine's principal spring without fear of being mis-
taken" (MM, 105). The soul is presented here as a principle of movement
lodged in the sensible material part of the brain and thus implicit and inher-
ent in its physical organization. Its former religious and philosophical
autonomy and authority as a purely spiritual and immaterial agent are dis-
missed with no further consideration of the implications of assigning to
material organization properties heretofore reserved to subjectivity and the
definition of the human.
142 • The Culture of the Body
Pursuing the analogy between the human body and the machine, La Mettrie
compares its complexity to an "immense clock," constructed with so much
artifice and skill that if particular parts of the mechanism break down, they
by no means endanger its abilities to function as a whole (MM, 110). How-
ever, La Mettrie is not content to restrict this mechanical analogy to the
body, as Descartes had done, but uses it as a way of describing man as a
whole. This gesture has extremely significant consequences, since it seeks to
reinscribe the entire horizon of the human within the logic of the machine.
La Mettrie elaborates his analogy of man to the machine by introducing into
its mechanical operations conscious feeling, thought, and even moral
reflection:
To be a machine, to feel, think, know good from evil like blue from yellow,
in a word to be born with intelligence and a sure instinct for morality, and
yet to be only an animal, are things no more contradictory than to be an ape
or a parrot and know how to find sexual pleasure. And, since the occasion
presents itself for saying so, who would have ever divined a priori that shoot-
ing off a gob of sperm during copulation would make one feel such divine
pleasure, and that from it would be born a tiny creature who one day, fol-
lowing certain laws, would enjoy similar delights? (MM, 112)
All human functions, ranging from sensation to thought, and including the
capacity to make moral distinctions, are posited as an extension of mechan-
ical principles relocating the human within the realm of automatism and
mechanical determinism. Regardless of their degree of complexity, these
diverse functions that cover the gamut from perceptual to intellectual activ-
ities are assimilated indiscriminately to a mechanical order whose laws
apply to both human and animal behavior.
In the passage ahove, however, La Mettrie is not merely content to state
the mechanical character of perceptual and intellectual functions, but goes
on to suggest that their logic is of the same order as the sexual behavior of
animals. The introduction of sexuality at this point functions as yet another
example of the overlap between human and animal bodily organization and
behavior. However, this appeal to sexuality is particularly surprising, since
it is difficult to understand how sexuality would reference the reality of the
machine. For it is precisely sexuality and procreation that were invoked to
distinguish inanimate machines from animate beings. It is useful in this con-
Men-Machines. 143
text to recall Voltaire's ironic comment that clocks do not make little clocks.
The incapacity of an inanimate machine to create other machines of a com-
plexity and nature equal to itself is answered by La Mettrie through the
mechanization of both sexuality and its procreative functions in all animate
beings. By introducing "sex" into its workings, La Mettrie seeks to embody
the machine as both a gendered and generative device. 12
La Mettrie introduces sexuality within the purview of the machine by
insisting on its purely material and mechanical nature in both men and ani-
mals. Sexuality and its "divine pleasures" are linked reductively to the
mechanics of the animate body, its shooting of a gob of sperm. Sexual plea-
sure is represented as the mere effect of mechanical forces whose expression
is contained within a system of material causality. Thus sexuality ceases to
reflect an encounter between subjects, since their mechanical coupling
attests to the mere performance of a logic inherent in the organizational
blueprint of the machine. Both desire and the potential role played by the
imagination, insofar as they have an impact on both the physical and the
imaginary status of bodies in the context of human sexuality, are entirely
left out of his discussion. Thus La Mettrie's efforts to "sex" the machine
only result in the mechanization of sexuality itself, by reducing it to a purely
organic and physical function that neither reflects nor has any bearing on
the subjective makeup of man as distinguished from animals.
To speak about man, in this context, is no accident, since La Mettrie's
focus is entirely on ejaculation and the male sexual functions and pleasure. 13
Although he does not broach the notion of sexual difference explicitly, his
subsequent discussion regarding the animated nature of the male sperm and
the supposed vegetative nature of female egg into which it plants itself and
which provides its food suggests a very specific gender hierarchy. The
anatomical difference between the sexes is analyzed by emphasizing the
active nature of male sperm, leading La Mettrie to question the actual con-
tribution and participation of the female egg: "For example, so rarely do
male and female seeds make contact in sexual congress that I am tempted to
think that the female seed is unnecessary for generation" (MM, 114).14
Although he recognizes the sometime resemblance of children to the father
or the mother, this physical evidence that attests to the "intercourse between
the parts," does not prevent him from reiterating his prior conviction:
On the other hand, why let the lack of an explanation rule out a fact? It
seems to me that the male does all the work, both in a woman fast asleep as
well as in the most lustful woman. From the beginning, then, the disposition
of body parts comes from the male seed or tiny worm. (MM, 114)
144 • The Culture of the Body
work, sexuality references not the organic body but a mechanical device,
since embodiment merely attests to its material organization and submission
to a rational order. La Mettrie's mechanical reduction of sexuality also
objectifies human behavior, thereby simply expanding Descartes's original
analogy of the body and the machine by generalizing it as universal law.
While neutralizing the differences that separate man from machines, by
assimilating the logic of their behavior to common material and mechanical
laws, this eradication of difference that erodes mind-body dualism does not
ultimately challenge the broader meaning of ontological difference under-
stood as a rational and representational order. Hence it is not surprising
that when La Mettrie evokes the notion of sexual difference in the context
of his embodiment of the machine, its manifestations suggest the reinstate-
ment of power relations and differences proper to the rational and repre-
sentational order that subtends his mechanist account. The logic of sexual
difference thus still remains within the horizon of ontological difference,
thereby revealing the fundamental difficulty of thinking about embodiment
as long as the machine functions as the determining horizon for the being of
humans, animals, and nature as a whole.
The questions and problems raised by La Mettrie's materialist and mech-
anist interpretations of man and nature come to a head in the marquis de
Sade's works, with their violent, perverse, and even criminal interpretations
of sexuality. In the pages that follow, Sade's own engagement with materi-
alism will be at issue. The exaggerated violence that Sade unleashes on the
body of his novelistic protagonists will be examined as a function of both
the mechanical reduction of the body and his efforts to undermine the very
premises that underlie rational thought. Resorting to a strategy of both lit-
erary and philosophical parody, he will radically destabilize the generic and
gender-referential aspects of classical discourse and thus challenge the very
limits of representation. Attempting to destroy both notions of sexual and
ontological difference, Sade will make manifest the violence and relations of
power implicit in the Cartesian legacy-that of the technologization of man
and nature. But this face-to-face encounter of thought with its limits, while
radically challenging the Cartesian metaphysical legacy, will not succeed in
restoring to the body either its corporeality or its capacity for agency.
Chapter 7
Sex at the Limits of Representation
"It is necessary," wrote Baudelaire, "to keep coming back to Sade, again
and again." 1 Baudelaire's injunction has been quite prophetic, since con-
temporary critics continue to return to Sade in order to assess his contribu-
tion to modernity. D. A. F. de Sade's novelistic work has been interpreted by
critics since Bataille as a literature of transgression. 2 However, the limits
that the Sa dean text challenges are not those of sexuality alone. Rather,
through his exhaustive exposition of sexuality, Sade succeeds in expanding
its meaning to include not only perverse and even criminal modes of activ-
ity, but also to challenge all moral referents and thus fundamentally alter the
very definition of the limits of thought.
As Michel Foucault suggests in "A Preface to Transgression," Sade's
transgressive gesture posits through the language of sexuality an ontological
and theological challenge to man's definition of and relation to God:
From the moment that Sade delivered its first words and marked out, in a sin-
gle discourse, the boundaries of what suddenly became its kingdom, the lan-
guage of sexuality has lifted us into the night where God is absent, where all
our actions are addressed to this absence in a profanation which at once
identifies it, dissipates it, exhausts itself in it, and restores it to the empty
purity of its tra nsgression. 3
I state and affirm that I have never written any immoral books,
and that I never shall.
-Sade
to evoke fear and pity, Sade's comments later in his pamphlet indicate that
this statement should be taken "literally." That is to say, that Sade's novels
will deal with adventures so uncommon that their implausibility will
threaten the very definition of the novel. In the Poetics, Aristotle designates
misfortune as an accident inspired by a character flaw or weakness (hamar-
tia), intended to inspire sympathy and catharsis;6 whereas for Sade, misfor-
tune becomes a rule in and of itself-an ultimate challenge to any possible
identification on the part of the reader. Since vice will reap the rewards of
virtue, the process of identification with the character in a cathartic sense is
precluded. The Sadean antinovel thus presents its reader with a paradox.
On the one hand, these works refuse mimesis as a principle of imitation and
identification that guides the reader's relation to the text. On the other
hand, the Sadean antinovel will rely on a new concept of imitation. Rather
than pretending to copy reality, his novels parody the very conventions that
structure novelistic reality.
This strategy for appealing to identification on the part of the reader,
while simultaneously rejecting mimetic conventions, can be seen in Sade's
warning to his readers. Attacking other authors who make "vice seem
attractive," Sade explains in Reflections on the Novel that the violence of his
novelistic representations excludes all possible identification:
I have no wish to make vice seem attractive. Unlike Crebillon and Dorat, I
have not set myself the dangerous goal of enticing women to love characters
who deceive them; on the contrary, I want them to loathe these characters.
'Tis the only way one can avoid being duped by them. And, in order to suc-
ceed in that purpose, I painted that hero who treads the path of vice with fea-
tures so frightful that they will most assuredly not inspire either pity or love.
In so doing, I dare say I am become more moral than those who believe they
have licence to embellish them.?
Sade's works defy the reader's expectations since they refuse claims that rely
on the traditional conception of the novel as a vehicle for imitation and as a
model for truth. While Sade recognizes that the moral referent of classical
novels is merely a subterfuge for presenting images that violate it, his con-
demnation, however, cannot be construed literally as a moral claim.
Although Sade suggests that he is "more moral" than his contemporaries,
his ostensible "moral" intention is immediately put into question by his dis-
claimer at the end of the essay that he is the author of the scandalous Jus-
tine. By challenging his own authenticity as the author of Justine, Sade par-
odies any simplistic inference regarding the authoritative and direct
referential relation of the author and his text. His comment at the end of his
150 • The Culture of the Body
treatise on the novel brackets the question of the identity of the author and
reduces it to a parody of the authorial persona.
Sade's parody of his own authorial persona is made explicit in an attack
on one of the critics of his Crimes of Love, Villeterque. Sade brutally
admonishes his critic by accusing him of falsely identifying the author with
the fictional characters:
Loathsome ignoramus: have you not yet learned that every character in any
dramatic work must employ a language in keeping with his character, and
that, when he does, 'tis the fictional character who is speaking and not the
author? and that, in such an instance, 'tis indeed common that the character
inspired by the role he is playing, says things completely contrary to what the
author may say when he himself is speaking?8
By affirming his explicit complicity with his fictional characters, Sade under-
lines his refusal to be simply assimilated to his work. In so doing, Sade dis-
rupts the mimetic relation between the author and the work, by having his
characters mime him as comical mouthpieces that reiterate his putative
claims. By both disengaging himself from his characters and by enlisting
their support, through a perverse play with the notion of mimesis, Sade suc-
ceeds in distinguishing himself from what he calls Villeterque's "mirror-
authors." 10 Sade's attack on Villeterque and his camp of "mirror" authors
represents his own complex position as a parodist, who uses imitation only
to destroy it as a category that has any referential relation to "reality." His
response does not merely address Villeterque, but functions as a warning to
all future critics who will naively persist in identifying him with his charac-
ters, and who will search for clues of his authorial identity by identifying the
author with the literary work.
In The Misfortunes of Virtue, Sade systematically enacts his critique of
the classical novel through strategies that disrupt identification with both
Sex at the Limits of Representation • 151
mimetic and moral referents. In the preface, Sade forewarns the reader that
the aim of the novel is to depict the misfortunes of virtue, rather than its
rewards. By suspending moral claims, Sade challenges the limits of novelis-
tic verisimilitude and plausibility. The Misfortunes of Virtue presents the
reader with an implausible plot: that of the relentless, exaggerated, and car-
icatural description of the heroine's misfortunes. The heroine, Justine/
Sophie, who can hardly be called such since she is nothing more than a com-
pendium of banal moral maxims, is shown suffering from her unsuccessful
attempts to reconcile her own beliefs and her worldly experiences. Her mis-
fortunes are profoundly literary: they represent a classical discourse, a dis-
course of normative morality and good faith, and its violation through its
explosive encounters and clashes with other types of discourse, representing
various noble, scientific, religious, and mercantile institutions.
The discomfiture of the reader in the face of the erotic victimization of
the heroine takes on a surreal, almost dreamlike character. As Blanchot has
noted, Sade's eroticism paradoxically derives its brutal reality and exagger-
ated freedom from its fictional nature: "Sade's eroticism is a dream eroti-
cism, since it expresses itself exclusively in fiction; but the more this eroti-
cism is imagined, the more it requires a fiction from which dream is
excluded, a fiction wherein debauchery can be enacted and lived." 11 Blan-
chot's observation regarding the deliberate fictional staging of eroticism in
Sade's novels is helpful toward elucidating the reader's complicitous rela-
tion to fiction. The paradox, as Blanchot suggests, is that Sa de uses fiction
in such an exaggerated fashion as to challenge its limits and consequently to
abolish through fiction the reader's sense of novelistic reality.
The reader's effort to identify with the protagonists of the novel is
thwarted from the novel's inception. The Misfortunes of Virtue introduces
two heroines, the sisters Juliette and Justine, who are remarkably different.
Each represents in caricature the obverse of the other. Juliette is the charac-
ter who though virtuous in her beliefs learns that virtue has no real currency
in the social world. She sells the physical equivalent of her virtue many times
over, thereby parodying and debasing it as counterfeit money. She considers
virtue to be a mere sign, a convention that can be traded in the social
domain in order to generate power, pleasure, and security. Her activities
document her remarkable education from victim to master and passage
from pleasure to crime, since her behavior shuns both the notion of social
contract and that of a universal moral referent.
At the other end of the spectrum, Justine represents the epitome of virtue,
a virtue that is so proud of itself that it invites violation. The reader is
trapped, since s/he cannot identify with either character without a sense of
152 • The Culture of the Body
the overt affiliations of this novel to other erotic novels in the eighteenth
century and to the materialist philosophy of La Mettrie, d'Holbach, and
Helvetius, it soon becomes clear that neither eroticism nor philosophy is
treated in traditional ways.16 As this analysis will show, Sa de is not simply
using philosophy as a pretext for the presentation of erotic scenes, or vice
versa. Rather, his exploration of perverse sexuality and crime corresponds
to and reflects his effort to destroy the foundations of rationalist thought.
Perversion, understood in these terms, takes as its point of departure the
sexual referent in order to take to task the premises of rational thought
itself.
The dialogue form of Philosophy in the Bedroom and its theatrical char-
acter present problems for the reader. The narrative level, or what is told, is
enacted and staged for the reader, while providing at the same time theoret-
ical justification. As Sollers has noted, word, gesture, and thought are
brought together within a global theater that constitutes the "writing of the
inadmissible." 17 The problem for the reader is that the identification with
the erotic scene as the stage of desire is constantly interrupted by philo-
sophical disquisitions that threaten to mislead the reader into a criminal
relation to the text. The violation of the traditional norms that govern the
relation between reader and novel and novel and reality corresponds to the
perverse representation of sexuality and reason. As Michel Tort observes:
"We find a correspondence in Sade's work between the theoretical law of
maximizing perverse deviation, and a theory of the evolution of novelistic
forms and their necessary exhaustion." 18 This correspondence in Sade's
work between a theory of perversity and the use of deviant novelistic forms
will be the springboard for our discussion of the status of representation and
its philosophical conditions. A closer reading of the novel will demonstrate
that perversity is not merely an incidental aspect of the novel, but rather that
it reflects Sade's understanding of representation and his critique of classical
reason.
Despite the overt erotic and licentious content of Philosophy in the Bed-
room, the reader quickly becomes aware of the fact that both the erotic
body and the nature of pleasure are being redefined. The problem is that the
incessant couplings and scrambling of body parts defy not only our conven-
tional notion of sexuality, but more importantly, the autonomy of the body
as the bearer and purveyor of pleasure. Eugenie's initiation to sexuality by
her two "teachers," Mme. de Saint-Ange and Dolmance (who are brother
and sister), rapidly progresses into perverse activities. The conventions that
define both the anatomy and the functions of the "natural" body are will-
fully ignored in order to redefine the body and the pleasures traditionally
Sex at the Limits of Representation • 157
much more keenly affected by pain than by pleasure: the reverberations that
result in us when the sensation of pain is produced in others will essentially
be of a more vigorous character" (PB, 252). Pain is described in mechanical
terms as a violent shock, recalling Sade's description in Reflections on the
Novel of why he chose to write about subjects that inspire shock and terror.
Following Sade's perverse logic, the representation of pain mechanically
"reverberates" or mirrors sensation more effectively than pleasure. Cruelty
can also be experienced as a function of mental representations that gener-
ate physical effects: "Look, Madame, do you see it? Do you see this libertine
discharge mentally, without anyone having touched her?" (PB, 288). Sade
supplements the mechanics of the body with virtual images, since the imag-
ination can represent events whose shock value exceeds physical reality.
Thus in addition to investing sexuality in the body in a mechanical sense,
Sade supplements its materiality with virtual images, thereby inscribing sex-
uality in the order of representation. By positing cruelty as a new kind of
pleasure principle, Sade perversely undermines conventional notions of sex-
uality in order to challenge, through representation, the limits of both rea-
son and the natural body.
Undermining the hierarchical separation of the mind and the body by
demonstrating their interchangeability as organs of pleasure, Sa de proceeds
to question further the identity of the body. In Philosophy in the Bedroom,
the body is presented as an undifferentiated entity, whose orifices are indis-
tinguishable by reference to pleasure: "For no one will wish to maintain that
all the parts of the body do not resemble each other, that there are some
which are pure, and others defiled; but, as it is unthinkable that such non-
sense be advanced seriously ... " (PB, 325-26; emphasis added). The tradi-
tional distinctions and hierarchies that describe the body are abolished, in
order to define the body through the principle of resemblance. The cultural
conventions that valorize certain parts of the body in order to exclude oth-
ers are denounced, so that the entire body may become the purveyor of plea-
sure. By affirming the functional resemblance of all the parts of the body,
Sade scrambles its conventional definition in order to constitute the libertine
body through perversion and parody. Not content to question the identity
of the body, Sade goes on to ask what man is, and why he occupies a privi-
leged place in the world:
What is man? and what difference is there between him and other plants,
between him and all the other animals of the world? None, obviously ....
Since the parallels are so exact that the inquiring eye of philosophy is
absolutely unable to perceive any grounds for discrimination (dissemblance),
there is just as much evil in killing animals as men, or just as little, and what-
Sex at the Limits of Representation • 159
ever be the distinctions we make, they will be found to stem from our pride's
prejudices, that which, unhappily, nothing is more absurd. (PB, 330)
one single motor is operative in this universe, and that motor is Nature. The
miracles-rather, the physical effects-of this mother of the human race, dif-
160 • The Culture of the Body
necessary conclusion of his social and philosophical parody. Filial and fra-
ternal love is privileged, since as Sade explains elsewhere, an incestuous
marriage provides "double reason to love."25 His use of this phrase suggests
that the scandal of incest is tied to the duplication and hence deregulation of
heretofore socially incompatible categories. Thus both eroticism and writ-
ing share a similar fate in Sade's work: as discourses of resemblance, their
true referent is the order of representation itself. But representation here no
longer implies either a rational order or the imitation of reality according to
convention, but rather their systematic destruction through the deviant
movement engendered by parody.
The outrage perpetrated by Sade's incestuous discourse undermines the
notion of nature by substituting for it the fictitious space of parody. His
incestuous narratives transform the relation between theory and practice by
valorizing fiction. 26 The originality of Sadean discourse resides less in its
efforts to transgress social norms than in its success at redefining literature
itself as a deviant and even criminal activity. By equating writing with per-
versity and crime, Sade redefines nature as the referent of his writerly proj-
ect. Thus Sade's obsession with incest reflects his effort to rethink nature in
terms of his theory of representation, which is based on resemblance. If
incest is a privileged term, this is because it embodies the very scandal of
representation. Incest is the index of a social and hence a linguistic crisis,
insofar as it suggests the capacity to combine inassimilable social categories
and thus generate fictitious predicates.
This attempt to violate the natural social order by mixing and scrambling
social and linguistic categories can be seen in Juliette, where Noirceuil pre-
sents his ultimate fantasy of perverse marriage. He wants to marry twice the
same day, impersonating both roles of man and woman, while imitated by
Juliette, who transvested as a man would marry another woman:
An extraordinary fantasy torments me since long ago, Juliette .... I want to
get married ... twice the same day: at noon, dressed as a man, marry a bar-
dache as a woman. I want more ... I want a woman to imitate me and what
other woman could better serve this fantasy? Dressed as a man, you must
marry a tribade at the same mass where, as a woman I marry a man! and that
dressed as a man, when I have resumed the vestments of my sex, I marry, as
a man, a bardache dressed as a woman.27
Sade's scenario represents the ultimate perversion of nature, since the false
replication of gender roles generates the ultimate incest fantasy, that of a
marriage of the like, where a trans vested man and woman marries their own
sex. Henaff comments on this scene by noting Sade's desire to permutate
162 • The Culture of the Body
and saturate all possible sexual positions. 28 However, this first type of chi-
asma, of saturation in an encyclopedic sense, is accompanied by an even
more radical gesture. For the desire for totality is accompanied by the pro-
duction of an excess beyond totality. Noirceuil's demand to be imitated by
Juliette, as he imitates himself as a man, creates an excess of signification
that can no longer be accommodated in the order of representation. 29 Mar-
riage as the social union of difference, as an exogamous relation, is doubly
reenacted the same day, each time with the same sexual partners. This fan-
tasy of mimicry becomes the figurative index of incest as a space of pure par-
ody. The free circulation of all the predicates of sexuality, their arbitrary
accumulation and expenditure, de-essentialize both gender and the moral
values attached to it. The sexual referent of the Sadean text thus emerges as
pure simulacrum: a copy without a real referent; that is, as the principle of
parody itself.
Unlike the other materialist thinkers such as La Mettrie, Helvetius, and
d'Holbach, Sa de does not simply revert to a naturalistic ideology.3D He does
not valorize nature as a new idol; on the contrary, he attempts to negate it
and defile it, and yet nature eludes him. 31 Since Sade views even crime and
evil as part of the workings of nature, the efforts to negate nature only
confirm its principles. Nature thus represents a philosophical and moral
scandal, since man can adopt neither an exterior nor a sovereign position in
relation to it. The crisis that nature presents for the Sadean protagonists, as
well as for the author, can only be resolved by subverting the notion of rep-
resentation. Given the perversity that Sade ascribes to nature, Sade's solu-
tion is to copy it and thus infinitely perpetuate it:
yes, I abhor Nature; and I detest her because I know her well. Aware of her
frightful secret, I have fallen back on myself and I have felt .... I have expe-
rienced a kind of pleasure in copying her foul deeds .... Should I love such a
mother? No; but I will imitate her, all the while detesting her, I shall copy
her, as she wishes, but I shall curse her unceasingly.32
as a victim invites and prescribes her final violation: her death by a lightning
bolt at the hands of nature. Justine's grotesque destruction and erasure from
the world of the novel etches upon her body the disfiguring material trace of
nature, which she had always refused to acknowledge: "Lightning had
entered by the right breast, it burned the chest, and came out through her
mouth, disfiguring her face so much that her face inspired horror.,,37 The
final disfiguration of Justine by the lightning bolt, the mark of the arbitrary
character of nature, summarizes Sade's effort to present historical being by
equating it with natural contingency. Passing through the right breast and
coming out through the mouth, writing emerges as a process of figuration
that reproduces the body through disfiguration. Having functioned as a
mere mouthpiece for values that did not come from the heart, Justine's car-
icatural existence is erased by the hand of the author, mimic and lover of
nature. The perverse fidelity of the author, as the incestuous lover of nature,
becomes transfigured in the act of writing presented undecidably as the
hand of both nature and man. This undecidability reveals something funda-
mental about the function of representation in Sade: the refusal to found a
stable principle for representation. Through the expenditure of mimesis, as
an endless play of simulations, the Sadean text represents itself as a copy
with no original, as pure parody. In The Misfortunes of Virtue, this unde-
cidability is put to an end only when all representation stops: when the
author puts down his pen and/or sewing needle.
In conclusion, we are left to ponder Sade's peculiar position in the history
of literature. In so doing we turn to Sollers's provocative question regarding
the paradoxical legacy of the Sa dean text for modernity: "How is it that
Sade is at once prohibited and accepted, prohibited as fiction (as writing)
and accepted as reality; forbidden as general reading and accepted as psy-
chological and physiological reference?,,18 Sollers's question summarizes in
a radical fashion the objections that this study has raised to reading Sade as
a transgressive author. Even if we regard the space of transgression as a pos-
itive space of contestation, the fact remains that such readings uphold sexu-
ality as the ultimate referent of contestation with the real. By maintaining
the distinction between fiction and reality, without understanding how Sade
erodes their mutual boundaries through parody, the transgressive readings
reinforce the paradox of the Sadean text that is banned as fiction while
being upheld as the referent of our psychological and physiological reality.
Can Sade's literary representation of sexuality be banned while sexuality
itself is given an "extraliterary" status? As this study has demonstrated, the
Sadean project, as reflected in both his novelistic practice and philosophical
reflections, can be better understood as a discourse of parody whose strate-
Sex at the Limits of Representation • 167
The genealogies of the modern body outlined in the pages of this volume
present us with a paradoxical legacy. We find ourselves today turning back
to early modern conceptions of the body in order to question and overcome
the predominance of modern conceptions. It is precisely those aspects of the
body that were foreclosed by the foundation of modern notions that enable
us to challenge their conceptual framework and their ostensible factual
authority and solidity. Rather than treating the body as a given, this study
has sought to inquire into its cultural construction, its conceptual and rep-
resentational modes of materialization or consolidation, in order to recover
what had become unpresentable and thus postponed in the modern inter-
pretations of the body. The emphasis on experience and embodiment evi-
denced in these early modern notions of the body, which are grounded in
reflections on the nature of representation, open up the horizon of body
toward postmodern forms of inquiry and thought. Insofar as they stage the
question of the body in terms of communicability, understood as both in an
intersubjective and intercorporeal modality, these works adumbrate con-
ceptual developments central to postmodernity. It is this representational
approach that is supplanted by the emergence of Cartesian and post-Carte-
sian paradigms that have informed and shaped decisively our modern
understandings of the body. However, the consolidation of these modern
conceptual models involves the derealization, even evacuation of the lived
body, in favor of abstract analogues whose material logic is informed by the
regime of the machine. The progressive virtualization of the body, its
schematization, mechanization, and ultimate spectralization, coincides with
the evisceration of corporeality and the contingencies of its multiple embod-
iments. The dematerialization of the body as lived entity implies its para-
doxical return as a material thing, that is to say its "rematerialization" not
as body but as material abstraction defined by epistemological constraints.
It is precisely the idealism inherent in this legacy to modernity, which
bypasses corporeality by recourse to virtual entities and hypothetical
170 • The Culture of the Body
It is decisive for the fortune of nations and of mankind that one should inau-
gurate culture in the right place-not in the "soul" (as has been the fateful
superstition of priests and quasi-priests): the right place is the body,
demeanor, diet, physiology: the rest follows. 1
sub specie aeterni, ascribes to it features of nonbeing that pit the virtual
"reality" of religious, axiomatic, or fictive constructions against the actual
world. Relying on Heraclitus, the philosopher of becoming, and his con-
tention that "being is an empty fiction," Nietzsche denounces the fal-
sification and usurpation of the "apparent world" by the philosophical
fiction of a "real" world emptied of multiplicity and contingency: "The
'apparent' world is the only one: the 'real' world has only been lyingly
added" (36).
At the heart of the distinction between apparent and real, which eviscer-
ates the world from the realm of appearances and the subject from its
embodied condition, lies the philosophical preeminence accorded to reason.
To religious mistrust and dismissal of the world in favor of an otherworldly
reality is now added the deliberate condemnation of the body, no longer
simply a sexual entity, but also a cognitive one. As Nietzsche observes, the
evidence of the senses comes into doubt only by presuming the ascendancy
of reason as the grounding condition: "'Reason' is the cause of our
falsification of the evidence of the senses" (36). This misrepresentation that
transforms the evidence of the senses into a lie eradicates the body from the
purview of both cognition and embodiment. Consequently, this denuncia-
tion and ultimate dismissal of the senses implies the derealization of the
body and the actual world in favor of a virtual being that derives its mean-
ing from the failure to ground being in the actual world. Nietzsche's call for
a return to a notion of culture grounded in the body and its historical
modalities of becoming recovers precisely what philosophy, beginning with
Plato and especially since Descartes, has removed from its purview by posit-
ing the priority of reason. His revalorization of sense perceptions, recovered
from their prior associations with deception and doubt and redeployed as
the insignia of appearance, reinscribes the logic of becoming as the consti-
tutive condition of a reflection on the body in terms that take into account
its historically contingent, contextual, and representational character. His
emphasis on the body and the senses as the insignia of appearance also calls
upon a reflection on language and its representational powers in order to
interrogate the "basic presuppositions of the metaphysics of language" (38).
Such a reflection on language and representation does not reflect simply a
literary bias, but also a philosophical one. For it is within the framework of
language and representation that the metaphysical foreclosure of the body
has already taken place. Nietzsche does not merely urge a reengagement of
the body and its sensorial realm, but also a radical reconsideration of its rep-
resentational status in order to challenge its linguistic presuppositions.
These engagements with the body as sensorial horizon, as representation,
172 • The Culture of the Body
appearance and changing semblance) opens up the body and its identity to
nonessentialist interpretations. Although they appear before the advent of
the modern age, these works locate the question of the body and its culture
within the horizon of language and communication, theoretically elabo-
rated only in the latter part of the twentieth century in the late works of
Merleau-Ponty and in structuralism and poststructuralism. Thus despite the
identification of these works with the late Renaissance and baroque human-
ism, implicit in their emphasis on experience, their explorations of embodi-
ment as a function of representation also suggest postmodernist and posthu-
manist inferences. Their understanding of embodiment as the materializing
effect of representation decenters the embodied subject by inscribing it
within a horizon that exceeds purely phenomenological determinations,
insofar as the subjective presence of the body is scripted within the fabric of
the world. 3
As Nietzsche's comments suggest, and as this study has demonstrated, in
Descartes's writings the experiential body suffers radical redefinition as a
material and mechanical thing, its logic disengaged from the order of ratio-
nal knowledge and the fabric of the world. The preeminence granted to
rational consciousness and the subjection of the body as material thing sever
the objective reality of the body from its subjective existence. As this study
has shown, the emergence of a disembodied subject and the mind-body
dualism will render embodiment moot, since issues of embodiment can no
longer be considered from the purview of the lived body and are transposed
to the institutional frameworks that attend to its administration as a
mechanical object. Moreover, the absence of a temporal horizon that would
ensure the duration of subjectivity in time preempts embodiment by
annulling the possibility of becoming. This failure to temporalize subjectiv-
ity heralds the impossibility of ethics, since the subject's relation to the eth-
ical, according to Emmanuel Levinas, is grounded in the recognition of the
alterity of temporality not as virtual abstraction but as event. 4 The techno-
logical legacy of Descartes's works is most visible in his strategies of virtu-
alization, that of dismissing the reality of the lived, experiential body by
substituting for it mechanical analogues haunted by specters of the inhu-
man. These strategies entail the philosophical derealization and reduction of
the world to deceptive appearances that can only be overcome by positing
hypothetical worlds, whose virtual and axiomatic logic references notions
of an idealized, rather than worldly, reality.
It is interesting to note that despite the impact that Descartes's analogy of
the human organism to the machine has had on philosophical and techno-
logical developments from the eighteenth century into the early part of the
174 • The Culture of the Body
of the world. Already audible in the margins of Montaigne and d'Urf6 writ-
ings, the whispered encounters between the flesh of the body and the flesh of
the world resonate with new urgency as we seek to find new ways of under-
standing the meaning of embodiment as a culture that works through the
past toward an already nascent future.
Notes
Introduction
Chapter 1
1. Nicolas Malebranche, The Search after Truth, trans. Thomas M. Lennon and
Paul Olscamp (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1980), bk. 2, pt. 3, chap. 5,
p.184.
2. As Albert Thibaudet points out, what is lacking in Montaigne's style is lack-
ing in the period as a whole: discipline and order. See Montaigne (Paris: Gallimard,
1963),491.
Notes to Pages 15-17 • 181
3. Guez de Balzac, Entretiens, vol. 18, De Montaigne et de ses ecrits (1657 ed.),
209.
4. Malebranche, The Search after Truth, 184-85.
5. As Merleau-Ponty points out, Montaigne's consciousness is not mind from
the outset, nor does it involve the self-possession implied in the Cartesian under-
standing ("Reading Montaigne," in Signs, 199).
6. For an analysis of classical and baroque style, see Henry Peyre, Qu-est ce que
Ie classicisme? Essai de mise au point (Paris: Droz, 1942); R. A. Sayee, "Renaissance,
Mannerism and Baroque," in The Essays of Montaigne: A Critical Exploration
(Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972), 313-26; and Morris W. Croll,
"Attic" and Baroque Prose Style: The Anti-Ciceronian Movement, ed. J. Max
Patrick, Robert O. Evans, and John M. Wallace (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1969).
7. For general studies on Montaigne's style, see Thibaudet, Montaigne; Floyd
Gray, Le Style de Montaigne (Paris: Nizet, 1958); Sayee, The Essays of Montaigne,
280-312; Gisele Mathieu-Castellani, Montaigne: L 'ecriture de l'essai (Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1988), 115-32. On Montaigne and rhetoric, see Frank
Lestringant, ed., Rhetorique de Montaigne (Paris: Honore Champion, 1985).
8. The question of Montaigne's style is inseparable from broader epistemologi-
cal concerns that mark the distinction between the baroque and classical world-
views. See Walter Benjamin's comments on allegory in The Origin of German Tragic
Drama, trans. John Osborne (London: NLB, 1977), 159-82; and Foucault, Les
Mots et les chases, 32-59.
9. Jules Brody, Lectures de Montaigne (Lexington, Ky.: French Forum, 1982),
55-92, and Nouvelles Lectures de Montaigne (Paris: Honore Champion, 1994),
105-78; Terence Cave, "Montaigne," in The Cornucopian Text: Problems of Writ-
ing in the French Renaissance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979),271-321; Robert D.
Cottrell, Sexualityrrextuality: A Study of the Fabric of Montaigne's Essays (Colum-
bus: Ohio State University Press, 1981); Lawrence D. Kritzman, The Rhetoric of
Sexuality and the Literature of the French Renaissance (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press, 1993), 57-73, 73-92, 133-47; Mathieu-Castellani, Montaigne,
135-253; Jean Starobinski, Montaigne in Motion, trans. Arthur Goldhammer
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), 138-213.
10. On this much-discussed essay see the following related works: Barbara C.
Bowen, "Montaigne's Anti-Phaedrus: 'Sur des vers de Virgile' (Essais, III, V)," Jour-
nal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies 5 (1975): 107-21; Erica Harth, "'Sur des
vers de Virgile': Antinomy and Totality in Montaigne," French Forum 2 (1977):
3-21; Cave, "Montaigne," 271-321; Jean Starobinski, "Speaking Love," in Mon-
taigne in Motion, 185-213; Lawrence D. Kritzman, "My Body, My Text: Mon-
taigne and the Rhetoric of Self-Portraiture," in Rhetoric of Sexuality, 133-47; Floyd
Gray, "Eros et ecriture: 'Sur des vers de Virgil,''' in Les Parcours des "Essais": Mon-
taigne 1588-1988, ed. Marcel Tetel and G. Mallary Masters (Paris: Aux Amateurs
du Livre, 1989),263-72; Geralde Nakam, "Eros et les Muses dans 'Sur des vers de
Virgile,''' in Montaigne: La maniere et la matiere (Paris: Klincksieck, 1992),
182 • Notes to Pages 18-24
133-44; Patricia Parker, "Gender Ideology, Gender Change: The Case of Marie Ger-
main," Critical Inquiry 19 (winter 1993): 337-64.
11. Robert D. Cottrell interprets Montaigne's allusion to Aristotle's Metaphysics
as an effort to emphasize the role of desire ("Representation and the Desiring Sub-
ject in Montaigne's 'De l'experience," in Tetel and Masters, Les Parcours des
"Essais," 97-98). For a comprehensive account of Montaigne's borrowings from
Aristotle, see Edilia Traverso, MOlltaigne e Aristotele (Florence: Felice Le Monnier,
1974).
12. For an analysis of the prevalence of the term forme in this essay, see Brody,
Nouvelles Lectures de Montaigne, 112-17.
13. Commenting implicitly on Montaigne, Michel Foucault recognizes only the
analogical aspects of reason based on resemblance, not on difference (Les Mots et les
chases, 63-67). While it is true that difference is not posited in Montaigne as a foun-
dational term constitutive of the ontology of being, difference nonetheless functions
as one of the constitutive paradigms of the operations of reason.
14. Cottrell understands this anecdote as an allegory of desire, as the effort to
seek and possess the object of desire ("Representation and Desiring Subject," 101-3,
105-6).
15. For a general account of law in Montaigne, see Carol Clark, "Montaigne
and Law," in Montaigne and His Age, ed. Keith Cameron (Exeter: University of
Exeter Press, 1981),49-68.
16. For a general analysis of medicine in Montaigne, see Margaret Brunyate,
"Montaigne and Medicine," in Cameron, Montaigne and His Age, 27-38; for a
broader account of Renaissance medicine, see Vivian Nutton, "Medicine in the Age
of Montaigne," in Montaigne and His Age, 15-25.
17. As Geralde Nakam points out, illness in Montaigne can be as much the effect
of physical developments as of the imagination, and it may be treated in kind
("Corps physique, corps social: La maladie et la sante," chap. 4 in Montaigne,
61-65).
18. Examining Montaigne's earlier pronouncements on medicine in "Of the
Resemblance of Children to Their Fathers," Starobinski claims that Montaigne crit-
icizes traditional empiricism without proposing anything to take its place. He inter-
prets the essay "Of Experience" as a gloss on this earlier essay (Montaigne in
Motion, 150-56).
19. For Montaigne's earlier exploration of the notion of custom, see "Of Cus-
tom, and Not Easily Changing an Accepted Law" (I, 23). Also see Tzvetan
Todorov's discussion of custom and natural law, "L'Etre et I'autre: Montaigne," in
"Montaigne: Essays in Reading," an issue of Yale French Studies 64 (1983): 113-21.
20. While noting that personal customs or habits may be subject to change, Ull-
rich Langer focuses on the relation of custom to the law. See "Montaigne's Cus-
toms," Montaigne Studies: An Interdisciplinary Forum 4, nos. 1-2 (1992): 82,
83-95.
21. For an analysis of the role of the imagination in Montaigne, see Dora Pol-
Notes to Pages 24-29 • 183
36. According to McKinley, these portraits of Venus by the Latin authors depict
Venus as a metaphor of sexual passion as experienced by the male (Words ill a Cor-
ner, 87). The question is whether the choice of these passages by Montaigne is moti-
vated by the fact that they describe sexual pleasure as a kind of dialogue or interval
between speech and silence.
37. Gray notes Montaigne's systematic mixing of Virgil's and Lucretius's lan-
guage ("Eros et ecriture," 2 72). Mathieu-Castellani comments on the implications of
Montaigne's gesture, observing that "words make love" and "have a sex" (Mon-
taigne, 129-30).
38. As McKinley points out, even before their existence in the Essays, the Virgil
and Lucretius passages were closely linked, signaling Montaigne's recognition of
Virgil's borrowing from Lucretius (Words in a Corner, 90-91). For an analysis of
Virgil's borrowing from Lucretius, see Michael C. J. Putnam, The Poetry of the
Aeneid: Four Studies in Imaginative Unity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1965),137.
39. Starobinski interprets Montaigne's act of borrowing as a gesture of both
dependence and rivalry, one that mediates Montaigne's own self-possession (Mon-
taigne in Motion, 112-14).
40. For a philosophical and psychoanalytic analysis of performativity as cita-
tionality, see Butler, Bodies That Matter, 12-16.
41. Kritzman interprets this symbolic image of an "idealized masculine lan-
guage" as an inverse image of the essayist, in Rhetoric of Sexuality, 67.
42. Kritzman notes the indeterminacy of the interplay between rhetoric and sex-
uality: "The text sets up an indeterminate play between rhetoric and sexuality at the
same time that it expresses the wish for a rhetorical potency that would capture and
authentically represent the energies figured in the self-portrait" (Rhetoric of Sexual-
ity, 137).
43. Parker interprets Montaigne's pronouncements on the virile style as the con-
tinuation of a long-standing Latin tradition that opposes "manly style" to feminized
laxness. However, she also notes that when Montaigne actually deploys these terms
in their sexual sense in his essay, they are associated not with the affirmation of viril-
ity, but with its failure ("Gender Ideology, Gender Change," 252-54). Carol Clark
observes that this opposition is not consistently sustained in Montaigne's writings,
since feminized laxness and softness are also treated in an approbatory fashion. See
The Web of Metaphor: Studies in the Imagery of Montaigne's "Essais" (Lexington,
Ky.: French Forum, 1978),91-96,161-62.
44. Kritzman notes Montaigne's tendency to "bitextuality," to the traces of the
feminine in a masculine mode, as a sign of ambivalence within the textual subject
(Rhetoric of Sexuality, 68-71).
45. For Montaigne's comments on impotence, see Essays, I, 2; I, 21; I, 54; and
Ill, 5. See also Lee R. Entin-Bates, "Montaigne's Remarks on Impotence," Modern
Language Notes 91 (May 1976): 640-54; and Lawrence D. Kritzman, "Montaigne's
Fantastic Monsters and the Construction of Gender," in Writing the Renaissance:
Essays on Sixteenth-Century French Literature in Honor of Floyd Gray, ed. Ray-
Notes to Pages 30-37 • 185
mond C. La Charite (Lexington, Ky.: French Forum, 1992), 191-94; d. Parker's dis-
cussion in "Gender Ideology, Gender Change," 345-46,348-53.
46. According to Hugo Friedrich, the insufficiency of French compared to Latin
reflects a common humanist bias against the so-called vulgar languages. However,
this supposed imperfection of the French language is but an invitation for Montaigne
to use it (Hugo Friedrich, Montaigne, trans. Robert Rovini [Paris: Gallimard, 19681,
377).
47. Montaigne's conclusion is hard to reconcile with Bowen's claim that he is
antifeminist ("Montaigne's Anti-Phaedrus, " 107).
48. For Cave's comment regarding Montaigne's revalorization of language, see
Cornucopian Text, 288.
49. Parker comments that Montaigne's sometime reliance on the Aristotelian
orthodoxy of women's greater passivity is undermined by an overwhelming number
of anecdotes documenting activity ("Gender Ideology, Gender Change," 351-52,
354-56).
50. Cf. Marc E. Blanchard's discussion of the representation of female sexuality
in Trois portraits de Montaigne: Essai sur la representation a la Renaissance (Paris:
Nizet, 1990),209-11.
51. Although the number six appears to be arbitrary, it is in excess of the roman
numeral V of the essay "On Some Verses of Virgil" (III, 5). At the inception of this
essay, Montaigne puns exhaustively on the coincidence of the letter V, in verses and
Virgil, etc., and the roman numeral V.
52. Montaigne adds that sexual pleasure becomes vicious either by immodera-
tion or by indiscretion (III, 5: 668). Kritzman interprets Montaigne's description of
pleasure in a Freudian sense, as a lowering of tension through a process of emptying
out (Rhetoric of Sexuality, 146).
53. For a general analysis of "mutual obligations" as they pertain to both mar-
riage and love, see Starobinski, Montaigne in Motion, 198-207. While Starobinski
distinguishes between the contractual nature of marriage and the love "bargain,"
which he defines as an exchange in desire (202), my own analysis focuses on sexual
pleasure in both contexts as a transactional and transitive category.
54. McKinley observes that "the subject of text focuses the problem of quota-
tion" as a productive principle, both enabling and restraining (Words in a Corner,
102).
55. See Richard Regosin, The Matter of My Book: Montaigne's "Essais" as the
Book of the Self (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977), 199. However, in
this passage he privileges exclusively the self-reflexive aspects of language as the
essential entity and medium of incarnation of the essay.
56. John O'Neill notes Montaigne's reliance on Stoic criteria, particularly in his
preference for a "palpable" or energetic style. See Essaying Montaigne: A Study of
the Renaissance Institution of Writing and Reading (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1982),93-95.
57. Cf. Starobinski, Montaigne in Motion, 208.
58. As Starobinski comments: "Doubling does not secure replication of identity
186 • Notes to Pages 38-41
but introduces difference, inaugurating the whole infinite series of the countable"
(Montaigne in Motion, 20).
59. Fran~ois Rigolot powerfully argues for the fluidity and metamorphic charac-
ter of Montaigne's self-presentation. See Les Metamorphoses de Montaigne (Paris:
Presses Universitaires de France, 1988),227-29.
60. Regosin, Matter of My Book, 203.
61. For the dynamism of the text as a generative, living body, see Lawrence D.
Kritzman, Destructionldecouverte: Le fonctionnement de la rhetorique dans les
"Essais" de Montaigne (Lexington, Ky.: French Forum, 1980), 102-5, 107. Rigolot
suggests that Montaigne's theory of textual generation is based on Ovid's Metamor-
phoses (Les Metamorphoses de Montaigne, 126).
62. For an analysis of the body forged in the text as a transcription of the move-
ment of desire, see Kritzman, "Montaigne's Family Romance," in Rhetoric of Sexu-
ality, 77.
63. Cave suggests that Montaigne is a fold in his own text (Cornucopian Text,
282).
64. For an analysis of Montaigne's name both as a proper name and as a geo-
graphical location, see Fran~ois Rigolot, "Semiotique et onomastique: Le nom pro-
pre de Montaigne," in Tetel and Masters, Les Parcours des "Essais," 147-49.
Chapter 2
1. Astrea was published in five parts, the first part in 1607, the second in 1610,
the third in 1619, and an incomplete fourth part (comprising the first four books) in
1625. After d'Urfe's death in 1625, his secretary, Balthazar Baro, to whom the book
had originally been dictated, completed the fourth part and published this version in
1627, followed by a fifth part that he claimed was based on the author's notes, also
in 1627. This chapter is an expanded and revised version of "Emblematic Legacies:
Hieroglyphs of Desire in L'Astree," in EMF: Studies in Early Modern France, ed.
David L. Rubin (Charlottesville, Va.: Rockwood Press, 1995),31-54.
2. The Princess of Cleves is considered to formally inaugurate the birth of the
novel in the French tradition, though the early part of the century is replete with sev-
eral other novelistic traditions, such as the pastoral, the precious, and the comic nov-
els. It is important to note that this genealogy of the origins of the French novel con-
veniently overlooks Charles Sorel's parody of Astrea entitled The Extravagant
Shepherd, which was republished in the 1633 edition with the subtitle The Anti-
Novel. Thus it would seem that the emergence of the antinovel in France precedes
the emergence of the novel.
3. The insistence on normative and idealist aesthetic criteria such as verisimili-
tude (vraisemblance) and plausibility (bienseance) and the concomitant effort to cen-
sure and purify both theatrical and novelistic discourse relegated previous novelistic
efforts to obsolescence. Such developments also suggest the potential impact of the
classical rule of the three unities elaborated in the dramatic context of the novel,
Notes to Pages 42-43 • 187
abstract personification, but as a figurative device that "uncovers nature and history
according to the order of time" (The Fold, 12).
15. See Albrecht Schone, Emhlematik und Drama im Zeitalter des Barock
(Munich: Beck, 1964); Dietrich jons, Das "Sinnen-bild": Studien zur allegorischen
Bildlichkeit bei Andreas Gryphius (Stuttgart: Metzder, 1966); and Peter M. Daly's
discussion of their contribution in Emblematic Theory: Recent German Contribu-
tions to the Characterization of the Emblem Genre (Nendeln: KTO Press, 1979),
21-77. For an analysis of emblems and their impact on literature see Daly's Litera-
ture in Light of the Emblem (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1979); and
Daniel S. Russell's groundbreaking The Emblem and Device in France (Lexington,
Ky.: French Forum, 1985).
16. In order to get a better idea of the scope and variety of emblem books, see
Mario Praz's bibliography of over six hundred authors in Studies in Seventeenth-
Century Imagery (London: Warburg Institute, 1939-47), vols. 1-2. See in particular
his discussion of Andrea Alciati, Emblematum fiber, considered the seminal source
of the emblematic genre, particularly as regards his reliance on the Greek epigram-
matic tradition (1:22-31).
17. See Daniel S. Russell's persuasive argument in "Du Bellay's Emblematic
Vision of Rome," Yale French Studies 47 (1972): 100.
18. Schone, Emblematik und Drama, 21; also quoted in Daly, Literature in
Light, 38.
19. See Angus Fletcher, Allegory: The Theory of a Symbolic Mode (Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1964),3.
20. This statement, attributed by Plutarch to Simonedes of Ceos, has a major
resurgence during the Renaissance and baroque periods, as demonstrated by the
writings of Pompeo Garigliano, Marino and others. See Giulio Marzot, L'ingegno e
il genio del Seicento (Florence: La Nuova Italia, 1944).
21. Except as noted, translations are based on Astrea: A Romance, 3 vols. (Lon-
don: Printed by W. W. for H. Moseley, T. Dring, and H. Herringman, 1657-58), as
emended by Leonard Hinds and the author to reflect more closely the text's literal
and figurative language and to update spelling. Quotations of the original French are
from L'Astree, ed. Hugues Vaganay, 5 vols. (Lyon: Pierre Masson, 1925). Both
French and English versions are cited by volume and page, the translation listed first,
then the original French.
22. Gerard Genette, "Le Serpent dans la Bergerie," introduction to L'Astree, ed.
Gerard Genette (Paris: Union genera Ie d'Editions, 1964), 10. For Louise Horowitz,
on the contrary, in Honore d'Ur(e (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1984), 16, L'Astree
is geographically accurate to the extent that it represents an idealized Forez.
23. I am referring here to such details as the yellow and fly-spotted wallpaper in
Balzac's Eugenie Grandet, where the most minute details in the environment reflect
the psychological and social instincts of the characters, as well as to Zola's novels,
where environmental influences are translated into congenital disorders.
24. For an analysis of the significance of the river, see M. Gerhardt, "Un Person-
Notes to Pages 45-51 • 189
36. This is exactly the pleasure that Narcissus is unable to enjoy, since he is
unable to recognize the echoes of his own speech (Nouvet, "An Impossible
Response," 122-23).
37. For an analysis of how subjective effects are arbitrarily generated through the
use of the first person, see Emile Benveniste, "De la subjectivite dans Ie language," in
Probtemes de tinguistique generate (Paris: Gallimard, 1966).
38. For a preliminary analysis of this passage in relation to the graphic and styl-
istic dimension of the text, see my "The Graphic Text: The Nude in L'Astree,"
Papers in French Seventeenth Century Literature 15, no. 29 (1988): 532-33.
39. It is only with Descartes and the advent of classicism that the mind-body dis-
tinction will become firmly established.
40. The philosophical implications of this incident are elaborated in the context
of Descartes's hyperbolic doubt argument in my Subjectivity and Representation in
Descartes, 22-23, 155-59.
41. See the definition of hyperbole in The Winston Dictionary: Encyclopedic
Edition (Philadelphia: John C. Winston Co., 1957),475.
42. In his reading of L 'Astree, Gerard Genette emphasizes the transgressive
dimension of the novel, the fact that the code of love only exists to engender fraud.
His interpretation reflects a dialectical conception of desire, where desire is defined
in terms of its own negation ("Le Serpent dans la Bergerie," 19-21).
43. Despite its structuralist character, Jacques Ehrmann's analysis is heavily
indebted to Sartre, to a dialectical and humanist essentialism. See Un Paradis des-
espere: L'amour et l'illusion dans "L'Astree" (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1963),4.
44. Horowitz, Honore d'Ur(e, 111-12.
45. Horowitz perceptively examines the thematic dimensions of disguise, with-
out inquiring, however, into how they express the status of representation in the
novel (Honore d'Ur(e, 96-125).
46. As Horowitz suggests, "Celadon becomes a woman, through our reading of
a female name" (Honore d'Ur(e, 114).
47. Horowitz, Honore d'Ur(e, 98.
48. Jean-Louis Schefer, "On the Object of Figuration," trans. T. Corrigan and
D. Judovitz, Sub-Stance 39 (1983): 30.
49. As the narrator tells us from the beginning, love involves the appropriate loss
of oneself: "The truth is, if one must acquire some happiness in the loss of oneself,
(Celadon) could consider himself lost so well unto the purpose" (1:1) [II est vray que
Notes to Pages 62-67 • 191
si en la perte de soy mesme on peut faire quelque acquisition, dont on se doive con-
tenter, il se peut dire heureux de s'estre perdu si a propos] (1:10).
50. It is interesting to note that the English translation has Alexis pressing
Astrea's body against her bosom, while the original version uses the word estomach,
which loosely refers not to the stomach, but the middle of the body, considered at
the time as the true repository of affection.
51. For Sigmund Freud, the fetish is substitute for the maternal phallus; see
"Fetishism" (1927), in Sexuality and the Psychology of Love, ed. Philip Rieff (New
York: Collier Books, 1974),215.
52. For instance, Celadon's hat is not just a hat, to the extent that within the
folds of its lining are hidden the couple's letters. This item of clothing is tossed back
and forth with the couple's correspondence.
53. In the closing moments of d'Urfe's novel, Astrea competes with Alexis,
claiming to be Astrea, in order to save Alexis's life. Her argument to Polemas regard-
ing the truth of her identity is based on an appeal to her clothes: "consult these
clothes which I wear" (3:185) [demandez-Ie a ces habits que je porte] (4:752).
Clothes in this context function in the manner of speech: they provide the visual
response to a query regarding the competing claims of two individuals for the same
name. However, Polemas is not persuaded, and he sentences them both to death:
"Since you are both the daughters of that villain, I order that you both be treated
accordingly" (3:185) [Puis donc, que vous estes toutes deux filles de ce meschant
homme, j'ordonne que vous soyez toutes deux traitees comme telles] (4:752). Unable
to tolerate resemblance, Polemas settles the danger posed by these competing dou-
bles hy suppressing both of the terms.
54. As if to verify the perfection of this new disguise, we are told that the sight of
Astrea, alias CeladonlAlexis, invites the amorous advances of Hylas.
55. Deleuze also notes in reference to baroque sculpture that folds are not simply
decorative effects, but convey the "intensity of a spiritual force exerted on the body"
(The Fold, 122).
Chapter 3
assimilation of their positions. See The Body Emblazoned: Dissection and the
Human Body in Renaissance Culture (London: Routledge, 1995),23-32.
14. See The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. E. S. Haldane and G. R. T.
Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 1:101 (hereafter cited as HR).
15. Canguilhem also notes the dependence of Descartes's theory of the animal
machine on the cogito (A Vital Rationalist, 227).
16. George Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon critiques the interpretation of the cir-
culation of blood in mechanical terms. In Histoire naturelle des animaux (1748), he
comments: "It is obvious that neither the circulation of blood nor the movement of
the muscles nor the animal functions can be explained in terms of impulse or any of
the laws of ordinary mechanics" (chap. 10, as quoted by Canguilhem, A Vital
Rationalist, 165). For a general account of Descartes's mechanical interpretation of
nature, see E. J. Dijksterhuis, The Mechanization of the World Picture (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1961),403-18.
17. Marie-Christine Pouchelle, Corps et chirurgie Ii I'apogee du Moyen Age
(Paris: Flammarion, 1983), 170-73. Mondeville privileges the architect, who is
defined by the capacity to design a plan of action. This privilege, accorded to archi-
tects as a guiding paradigm for surgeons, also occurs in Descartes's analogies in part
2 of the Discourse, which compares the philosopher with the architect who operates
according to an overall blueprint.
18. For these analogies, see Pouchelle, Corps et chirurgie, 176-83. Aristotle also
makes an analogy between animal movements and automatic mechanical move-
ments like those in war machines such as the catapult. See Alfred Espinas, "L'Or-
ganisation ou la machine vivante en Grece au IVe siecle avant J.-c.," Revue de Mha-
physique et de Morale (1903): 702-17.
19. Pouchelle elaborates this cohesion between anatomical and social categories
in Mondeville in Corps et chirurgie, 189-92.
20. Sec Aquinas's Summa Theologiae (I, II, 13, 2) and Antoniana-Margarita
Gomez-Pereira, Opus nempe physicis medicis ac thelogicis non minus utile quam
necessarium (Medina del Campo, 1555-58). In his letter to Mersenne, June 23,
1641, Descartes denies knowledge of Gomez's work and dismisses it offhand, but
the similarity of their positions is striking. Sec G. A. Lindebom's discussion in
Descartes and Medicine (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1979), 61-62.
21. A possible literary source may include Jean Froissart's "L'Horioge
amoureus" (ca. 1368), in which an analogy is elaborated between the mechanisms of
a clock and those of love. I want to thank Patrick Wheeler for bringing this text to
my attention.
22. For an analysis of the meaning of this term as presented in late-seventeenth-
century dictionaries, see Claude Reichler, "Machine et machinations: La ruse des
signes," Revue des Sciences Humaines 58, nos. 186-87 (1982): 33-39. Also see
Gerard Simon's analysis of this term in "Les Machines au XVIIe siecle: Usage,
typologie, resonances symboliques," in Revue des Sciences Humaines 58, nos.
186-87 (1982): 10-13.
23. See Georges Canguilhem's comments in A Vital Rationalist, 206-7; see also
194 • Notes to Pages 72-77
his general discussion of the relation of the Cartesian machine to the notion of the
organism, in "Machine and Organism," in "Incorporations," ed. Jonathan Crary
and Sanford Kwinter, special issue of Zone 6 (winter 1992): 45-69.
24. John Cottingham notes that Descartes is referring here to "fictional men,"
introduced in an earlier and (lost) part of the Treatise on Man, analogously to his use
of the "new world" in the World (PWD, 1:99). For a detailed analysis of the role of
the fictional and the axiomatic in the World, see my Subjectivity and Representation
in Descartes, 87-97.
25. Canguilhem, "Machine and Organism," 53-54.
26. For an analysis of the mathematical and epistemological underpinnings of
Descartes's philosophy, see my Subjectivity and Representation in Descartes, 39-85.
27. In his letter to Reneri for Poll at, Descartes argues that the statement "I am
breathing, therefore I exist," is insufficient as an argument for existence, since the
thought of breathing implies existence in the mode of "I am thinking, therefore I
exist" (April or May 1638; PWD, 3:98).
28. Canguilhem, A Vital Rationalist, 207.
29. Carolyn Merchant, The Death of Nature: Womell, Ecology, and the Sci-
entific Revolution (San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1980),194-205.
30. Descartes's descriptions of gardens and hydraulic statues are possihly based
on the royal gardens of Saint-Germain-en-Laye. See Ferdinand Alquie's annotation
in Rene Descartes, Oeuvres Philosophiques de Descartes, 3 vols., ed Ferdinand
Alquie (Paris: Garnier, 1973), 1:390. A possible scholarly source for the analysis of
the mechanical forces at stake may include Salomon de Caus, Les Raisons des forces
mouvantes avec diverses machines tant utiles que plaisantes auxquelles sont jointes
plusieurs desseings de grottes et de fantaines (Frankfurt, 1615).
31. Descartes's description of gardens echoes Montaigne's own astonishment
hefore the hydraulic marvels of his own time, in Journal de voyage en Italie par la
Suisse et l"Allemagne en 1550-1581 (Paris: Cluh Fran"ais du Livre, 1954), 109. For
a general analysis of French seventeenth-century gardens and their relations to carte-
sian metaphysics, see Allen S. Weiss, Mirrors of Infinity: The French Formal Garden
and 17th-Century Metaphysics (New York: Princeton Architectural Press, 1995).
32. In the medieval and renaissance traditions, the animal spirits are invoked to
mediate the relation of body and soul. See David P. Walker's discussion in "Medical
Spirits in Philosophy and Theology from Ficino to Newton," in Arts du spectacles et
histoire des idees: Recueil offert en hommage Ii Jean Jacquot (Tours: Centre d'etudes
superieures de la Renaissance, 1984),287-300.
33. Descartes's dramatic representation of the human body through the unfold-
ing scenography of garden displays recalls the staging devices of dissection in the
anatomy theater. See Sawday's analysis of the theatricality of dissection in The Body
Emblazoned, 146-58.
34. For an analysis of dissection as a spectacle of display that renders visible the
scientific gaze and the perspective of natural philosophy, see Francis Barker, The
Tremulous Private Body: Essays on Subjection (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press, 1995), 65-76.
Notes to Pages 77-81 • 195
of the mind and the body attains its fullest elaboration in The Passions of the Soul
(completed 1645-46 and published in 1649).
49. My reading differs with Keith Gunderson's efforts to distinguish these two
tests as (1) the language test and (2) the action test. See his Mentality and Machines,
2d ed. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985), 8-17.
50. Cf. Barker, The Tremulous Private Body, 93-94.
Chapter 4
1. Harry Frankfurt has drawn our attention to the figures of demons, madmen,
and dreamers and their crucial function in Descartes's justification of reason, with-
out focusing specifically on the question of the body. See Demons, Madmen, and
Dreamers: The Defense of Reason in Descartes's Meditations (Indianapolis: Bobbs-
Merrill, 1970).
2. Gary Hatfield argues that Descartes relies not only on Loyola'S exercises,
which define the attainment of spirituality through sensory materials constructed by
the imagination, but also on the Augustinian tradition that relies on a skeptical
approach and the contemplation of thought. See "The Senses and the Fleshless Eye:
The Meditations as Cognitive Exercises," in Essays on Descartes's Meditations, ed.
Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986),48-54.
3. As I have suggested in an earlier study (Subjectivity and Representation in
Descartes, 173-81) that the theological arguments for the existence of God serve to
buttress Descartes's ontological arguments, in terms that concede the finitude of
human understanding only to emphasize the infinite perfectibility of human will as a
counterpart of the divine.
4. Drawing upon the writings Edmund Husser! and Maurice Mer!eau-Ponty,
Drew Leder has noted the role of the body as epistemological obstruction. See The
Absent Body (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 128-34.
5. These arguments and the critical debates that accompany them are elabo-
rated in detail in my analysis of the Meditations in Subjectivity and Representation
in Descartes, 137-83.
6. In his reply to the Seventh Objection, Descartes uses the metaphor of a bas-
ket from which he removes all apples in order to determine which ones are rotten
(HR, 2:282); d. Anthony Kenny, Descartes: A Study of His Philosophy (New York:
Random House, 1968), 18-19. The prohlem with this analogy is less the fact of call-
ing into question our beliefs (as Kenny suggests) than that in attempting to escape
deception engendered by the senses the Cartesian subject is willing to dispose of its
own embodied nature and give up its natural condition as a body.
7. Descartes's decisions not to publish The World and to publish the Discourse
on Method anonymously reflect his reaction to Galileo's condemnation by the
church for his expressed support of the Copernican hypothesis. At the beginning of
his Optics, Descartes discusses the discovery of lenses and their impact on the expan-
sion of our knowledge of nature (PWD, 1:152).
8. See Descartes's example in the Meditations of our two different ideas of the
Notes to Pages 86-90 • 197
sun. The first, derived through the senses (adventitious ideas) presents the sun as
extremely small, whereas the second, based on astronomical reasoning and instru-
mentation, presents the sun as several times larger than the earth (HR, 1:161).
9. For Michel Foucault, madness is inadmissible for the doubting subject, since
its exclusion and internment founds the advent of rational discourse (Folie et derai-
son: Histoire de la folie a /'age classique [Paris: Gallimard, 1972], 56-59).
10. These claims in the Discourse are far more radical, since they do away with
the body altogether rather than attempt to consider and enumerate the various forms
of deception entailed in madness and dreams.
11. Michel Foucault, in "My Body, This Paper, This Fire," Oxford Literary
Review 4, no. 1 (1979): 16, returns to this passage in his response to Derrida to
emphasize the centrality of madness for the Cartesian project.
12. The immediacy in question here is not merely that of sensory evidence, but of
the simulation of sensation, the illusion of immediacy staged by the performative
aspects of the text.
13. Descartes's examples of madness preponderantly involve instances of bodily
misperception or denial, suggesting that the issue is less madness per se (as Foucault
contends) than the body as its privileged object. For a critique of Foucault's position
in his debate with Derrida, see my "Derrida and Descartes: Economizing Thought,"
in Derrida and Deconstruction n, ed. Hugh J. Silverman (New York: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1989),40-58.
14. It is in this context that the radicality of dreams, as opposed to madness,
comes into view. Based on Martial Gueroult's position, Derrida will argue that it is
in the case of sleep and not that of madness that the absolute totality of ideas of sen-
sory origin becomes suspect. See his "Cogito and the History of Madness," in Writ-
ing and Difference, trans. Allan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978),
51.
15. For Norman Malcolm the question of whether one is awake or dreaming is
quite senseless to the extent that it would imply making judgments during dreams.
See Dreaming (London: Routledge, 1959), 109.
16. Descartes's search for simples, as opposed to composites, here echoes the
principles of the method announced in the Discourse. His discussion is patterned on
his positing of color as the universal substrate of both dreams and painted represen-
tations. Cf. Caton, The Origin of Subjectivity, 115.
17. For a discussion of the passage from a deceptive God to the evil genius, see
Caton, The Origin of Subjectivity, 118-21.
18. Martial Gueroult observes that hyperbolic doubt differs from skeptical
doubt insofar as it proceeds not from the reality of things, but from the resolution to
doubt everything. See Descartes' Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of
Reasons, trans. Roger Ariew, 2 vols. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1984-85),1:20-21.
19. According to Gueroult, this metaphysical doubt attacks not merely natural
doubt, but also the intrinsic objective validity of clear and distinct ideas, and as such
is even contrary to the "nature of our mind" (Descartes' Philosophy, 1:21).
198 • Notes to Pages 90-94
34. It is important to note that the wax shows up earlier in Descartes's writings,
specifically in the Rules, where the wax-and-seal analogy is a metaphor for the pas-
sive and receptive character of the senses (HR, 1:38).
35. In his reply to Hobbes, Descartes explains that he does not consider the per-
ceptual qualities of the wax to belong to the formal nature of the wax itself (HR,
2:63).
36. This becomes the abiding sameness or essence of the wax that is independent
of its experiential qualities. Caton observes that this argument will lead to the con-
clusion that both the body and the mind can only be known "supersensibly" (The
Origin of Subjectivity, 153-55).
37. Descartes's critique of the reliability of the senses and the imagination was
the focus of my earlier essay, "Vision, Representation, and Technology in
Descartes," in Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision, ed. David Michael Levin
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 74-80.
38. For a comprehensive historical and analytical account of vision and its elab-
oration in Descartes, see Martin Jay, "The Noblest of the Senses: Vision from Plato
to Descartes," in Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century
French Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993),21-82. For a philo-
sophical critique of Cartesian vision, see Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "Eye and Mind,"
in The Primacy of Perception, ed. James M. Edie, trans. Carleton Dallery (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1964), 159-90.
39. For a detailed analysis of Descartes's critique of vision and the transposition
of its properties to the mental domain, see my "Vision, Representation, and Tech-
nology in Descartes," 63-84.
40. Alain Vizier mentions this digressive passage as an instance of Descartes's
dismissal of the exterior and exteriority as a form of sensorial knowledge. See
"Descartes et les automates," Modern Language Notes 3 (1996): 693-94.
41. Gassendi observes, in his Reply to the Fourth Objection, that to strip a sub-
stance of those attributes by which we apprehend it is to destroy our knowledge of
it (HR, 2:98-99). Descartes acknowledges Gassendi's objection in his letter to
Clerselier (HR, 2:134).
42. See Augustine's comments on Ambrose's introspective reading of the Bible
(book 6) and on memory and the mind (book 10), in Confessions, trans. R. S. Coffin
(London: Penguin, 1961).
43. See Montaigne's essay "Of Experience" and the analysis of it in chapter l.
44. Merleau-Ponty, Visible and Invisible, 234.
45. Cf. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "The Body as Expression and Speech," in The
Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1995), 174-99; see also Leder's discussion of language, thought, and the body
in The Absent Body, 121-25.
46. For an eloquent critique of this position, see Jean-Fran~ois Lyotard, "Can
Thought Go On without a Body?" in The Inhuman: Reflections on Time, trans.
Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
1991),8-23.
200 • Notes to Pages 99-101
47. Garber notes that in the Sixth Meditation, the commonsense, sensual bodies
that appear earlier in the Meditations have been replaced by the lean, spare objects
of geometry (Descartes's Metaphysical Physics, 75-76).
48. In reference to the Fifth Meditation, Garber observes that Descartes's focus
on the geometrical features of the body is the capacity to perform proofs about them
(Descartes's Metaphysical Physics, 81).
49. For a general examination of the role of imagination in Descartes's works,
see Jean H. Roy, L'Imagination selon Descartes (Paris: Gallimard, 1944).
50. Given that the first example of a body provided by Descartes is that of a chil-
iagon, a mathematical object, there is a question as to the precise meaning of
"body." Caton also notes that the "body" to which imagination turns remains a
mystery (The Origin of Subjectivity, 162).
51. Commenting on the Sixth Meditation, Gassendi reproaches Descartes for
attempting to distinguish imagination from intellection, because for him these two
are the actions of one and the same faculty, rather than types of internal cognition
(HR, 2:190-91). Descartes replies by reaffirming their distinctness as "wholly
diverse modes of operation," for in thinking the mind employs itself alone, whereas
in imagining it contemplates a corporeal form (HR, 2:229).
52. It is important to note that Descartes deliberately chose not an ordinary
object, but a virtual one, in order to demonstrate the capacity of the mind to hypoth-
esize in the context of mathematical schematism, as a way of underlining the imagi-
nation's figurative failure to attain such schematization.
53. Caton presents the imagination and the understanding as equal modes of
applying the same power of knowledge or mind (The Origin of Subjectivity,
161-62). However, this modal interpretation overlooks Descartes's explicit privileg-
ing of the understanding over the imagination, which is necessary in order to main-
tain the virtual nature of Cartesian rationality.
54. Dennis L. Sepper examines the relation between the imagination and inge-
nium in order to argue for the centrality of the imagination in Descartes's early writ-
ings and its subsequent abandonment. See" Ingenium, Memory Art, and the Unity
of Imaginative Knowing," in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Rene
Descartes, ed. Stephen Voss (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 142-57.
55. We must keep in mind Gassendi's query to Descartes, regarding the fact that
the mind may be unable to turn toward itself or toward any idea, without turning
toward something corporeal or represented by corporeal ideas (HR, 2:192).
56. In the Fifth Objection Gassendi recognizes that the senses may lead some-
times to error, but he wonders whether such error is sufficient to renounce all sen-
sory perception (HR, 2: 193). Also compare Leder's analysis of the body as a site of
error and dysfunction (The Absent Body, 131-32).
57. Merleau-Ponty argues that perceptual "synthesis" has to be incomplete,
since it cannot present a "reality" other than by running the risk of error (The Phe-
nomenology of Perception, 377).
58. For Montaigne, it is precisely the diversity and multiplicity of experience that
constitute its universality ("Of Experience," Essays, III, 13: 815).
Notes to Pages 101-3 • 201
beth: Conceiving Both the Union and Distinction of the Mind and Body," in
Descartes: Critical and Interpretative Essays, ed. Michael Hooker (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1978), 217-19.
70. In his reply to the Fifth Objection, Descartes affirms the union, but not the
coextensive nature, of the mind with the body: "though the mind is united with the
whole body, it does not follow that it itself is extended throughout the body" (HR,
2:232).
71. As Descartes himself admits in his letter to Elizabeth (June 28, 1643), it is
difficult for the human mind to conceive at the same time the distinction between the
mind and the body and their union (PWD, 3:227).
72. In the Fourth Objection, Arnauld observes that Descartes's distinction and
separation of the mind and the body is so radical as to make it difficult to rejoin them
(HR, 2:84-85). Rather than addressing directly Arnauld's objection, Descartes
replies by noting that his proof for substantial union does not preclude having a
clear and distinct idea of the mind on its own (HR, 2:102-3).
73. Cf. Genevieve Rodis-Lewis's critique, "Limitations of the Mechanical Model
in the Cartesian Conception of the Organism," in Hooker, Descartes, 152-65;
reprinted and revised in L'Anthropologie cartesienne (Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France, 1990), 149-67.
74. Descartes's invocation of memory is all the more surprising given his earlier
critiques in his correspondence, the Rules, and the Discourse, critiques of both the
tradition of the arts of memory, and memory as a faculty (Judovitz, Subjectivity and
Representation in Descartes, 26-32, 59-60, 68-73).
75. For a critique of Descartes's notion of temporality and its instantaneous
character, see Jean Wahl, Du role de I'idee de I'instant dans la philosophie de
Descartes (Paris: Alcan, 1920).
76. Martin Heidegger noted Descartes's exclusion of temporality, other than
that defined by the present of the presence-at-hand, in Being and Time, trans.
John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: Harper and Row, 1962),
129.
77. Tom Conley notes that Gilles Deleuze's interpretation of Leibnizian mon-
adology suggests that Leibniz resolves Cartesian mind-body dualism through physi-
cal means grasped as foldings, without recourse to occasionalism or parallelism. See
his remarks introductory to The Fold, xii. For Deleuze's detailed analysis, see 5-26,
85-99, 126-37.
Chapter 5
1. A preliminary version of some of the ideas elaborated in this chapter was pre-
sented as a paper to the North American Association for Seventeenth Century
French Literature Conference, at Wake Forest University, March 1987, and pub-
lished as "Royal Power or The Social Body in Corneille," in Actes de Wake Forest,
ed. Milorad R. Margitic and Byron R. Wells, ColI. Biblio 17, no. 37 (Tiibingen:
Papers on Seventeenth Century Literature, 1987), 59-73.
Notes to Pages 110-16 • 203
Chapter 6
Chapter 7
Conclusion
Adam, Antoine. "La Theorie Mystique de l'Amour dans L'Astree et ses sources Ital-
iennes." Revue d'Histoire de la Philosophie (1937).
Anton, Charles. Classical Dictionary. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1873.
Apostolides, Jean-Marie. Le Prince sacrifie: Theatre et politique au temps de Louis
XIV. Paris: Minuit, 1985.
Aquinas, Saint Thomas. Summa Theologica. London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1964.
Aristotle. "The Poetics." On Poetry and Style. Trans. G. M. A. Grube. New York:
Bobbs-Merrill, 1979.
Augustine, Saint, Bishop of Hippo. Confessions. Trans. R. S. Coffin. London: Pen-
guin, 1961.
Baltrusaitis, Jurgis. Anamorphic Art. Trans. W. J. Strachan. New York: Harry J.
Abrams, 1977.
Balzac, Guez de. Entretiens. Vol. 18, De Montaigne et de ses ecrits. Paris, 1657.
Barker, Francis. The Tremulous Private Body: Essays on Subjection. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press, 1995.
Barkin, Leonard. Nature's Work of Art: The Human Body as Image of the World.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1975.
Barthes, Roland. Sade, Fourier, Loyola. Paris: Seuil, 1971.
Bataille, Georges. L'Erotisme. Paris: Minuit, 1957.
- - - . La Litterature et Ie mal. Paris: Gallimard, 1957.
Baudelaire, Charles. "Projcts et notes diverses." Oeuvres Completes. Paris: Seuil,
1968.
Beaune, Jean-Claude. L'Automate et ses mobiles. Paris: Flammarion, 1980.
Beauvoir, Simone de. "Must We Burn Sade?" The Marquis de Sade: The 120 Days
of Sodom, and Other Writings. Compiled and trans. Austryn Wainhouse and
Richard Seaver. New York: Grove Press, 1966.
Beck, L. J. The Metaphysics of Descartes: A Study of the Meditations. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1965.
Benjamin, Walter. The Origin of German Tragic Drama. Trans. John Osborne. Lon-
don: NLB, 1977.
Benveniste, Emile. "De la subjectivite dans Ie language." Problemes de linguistique
generale. Paris: Gallimard, 1966.
Bitbol-Hesperies, Anne. Le Principe de la vie chez Descartes. Paris: J. Vrin, 1990.
212 • Bibliography
Gallagher, Catherine, and Thomas Laqueur, eds. The Making of the Modern Body:
Sexuality and Society in the Nineteenth Century. Berkeley: University of Califor-
nia Press, 1987.
Gallop, Jane. Intersections: A Reading of Sade with Bataille, Blanchot, and Klos-
sowski. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1981.
Garber, Daniel. Descartes's Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1992.
Gaste, Armand. La Querelle du Cid. Paris: H. Welter, 1899.
Gaukroger, Stephen. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1995.
Genette, Gerard. "Lc Serpent dans la Bergerie." Introduction to rAstnie. By Hon-
ore d'Urfe. Ed. Gerard Genette. Paris: Union genera Ie d'Editions, 1964.
Gerhardt, M. "Un Personnage principal de L'Astree: Le Lignon." Colloque comme-
moratif du quatrieme centenaire de la naissance d'Honore d'Ur(e, 47-56. Mont-
brison: La Diana, 1970.
Gilson, Etienne. Etudes sur Ie rule de la pensee medievale dans la formation du sys-
teme cartesien. 5th ed. Paris: J. Vrin, 1984.
Gomez-Pereira, Antoniana-Margarita. Opus nempe physicis medicis ac thelogicis
non minus utile quam necessarium. Medina del Campo, 1555-58.
Gray, Floyd. Le Style de Montaigne. Paris: Nizet, 1958.
- - - . "Eros et ecriture: 'Sur des vers de VirgiL'" Les Parcours des "Essais"; Mon-
taigne 1588-1988. Ed. Marcel Tetel and G. Mallary Masters. Paris: Aux Ama-
teurs du Livre, 1989.
Greenberg, Mitchell. "Stage Whispers: Corneille's Absolutism." Les Contes de Per-
rault: La contestation et ses limites; Furetiere, Actes de Banff. Ed. M. Bareau,
J. Barchillon, D. Stanton, and J. Alter. Paris: Biblio 17/30, ] 987.
Grene, Marjorie. "The Heart and Blood: Descartes, Plemp, and Harvey." Essays in
the Philosophy of Science of Rene Descartes. Ed. Stephen Voss. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1993.
Gueroult, Martial. Descartes' Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of
Reasons. 2 vols. Trans. Roger Ariew. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1984-85.
Gunderson, Keith. Mentality and Machines. 2d cd. Minneapolis: University of Min-
nesota Press, 1985.
Harari, Josue V. Scenarios of the Imaginary. Ithaca, N. Y.: Cornell University Press,
1987.
Harth, Erica. "'Sur des vers de Virgile': Antinomy and Totality in Montaigne."
French Forum 2 (1977): 3-21.
Hatfield, Gary. "Descartes' Physiology and Its Relation to His Psychology." The
Cambridge Companion to Descartes. Ed. John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1992.
- - - . "The Senses and the fleshless Eye: The Meditations as Cognitive Exercises."
Essays on Descartes's Meditations. Ed. Amelie Oksenberg Rorty. Berkeley: Uni-
versity of California Press, 1986.
Bibliography. 217
Kritzman, Lawrence D. The Rhetoric of Sexuality and the Literature of the French
Renaissance. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
- - - . "Montaigne's Fantastic Monsters and the Construction of Gender." Writing
the Renaissance: Essays on Sixteenth-Century French Literature in Honor of
Floyd Gray. Ed. Raymond C. La Charite, 191-94. Lexington, Ky.: French
Forum, 1992.
- - - . Destruction/decouverte: Le fonctionnement de la rhhorique dans les
"Essais" de Montaigne. Lexington, Ky.: French Forum, 1980.
Lacan, Jacques. "Le Stade du mirair." Ecrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966.
Lafayette, Marie-Madeleine de. La Princesse de Cleves. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion,
1966.
- - - . The Princesse of Cleves. Ed. and trans. John d. Lyons. New York: W. W.
Norton, 1994.
La Mettrie, Julien Offray de. L'Homme machine. Oeuvres philosophiques de M. de
La Mettrie. Berlin, 1774.
- - - . Man a Machine and Man a Plant. Trans. Richard A. Watson and Maya
Rybalka. Intra. Justin Leiber. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994.
Lange, Frederick Albert. The History of Materialism. Trans. Ernest Chester Thomas.
New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1925.
Langer, Ullrich. "Montaigne's Customs." Montaigne Studies: An Interdisciplinary
Forum 4, nos. 1-2 (1992): 83-95.
Laqueur, Thomas. "Orgasm, Generation, and the Politics of Reproductive Biology."
The Making of the Modern Body: Sexuality and Society in the Nineteenth Cen-
tury. Ed. Catherine Gallagher and Thomas Laqueur. Berkeley: University of Cal-
ifornia Press, 1987.
Leder, Drew. The Absent Body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990.
Lestringant, Frank, ed. Rhhorique de Montaigne. Paris: Honore Champion, 1985.
Levinas, Emmanuel. "Time and the Other." The Levinas Reader. Ed. and Intra.
Sean Hand. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989.
Lindebom, G. A. Descartes and Medicine. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1979.
Lyotard, Jean-Fran"ois. "Can Thought Go On without a Body?" The Inhuman:
Reflections on Time. Trans. Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1991.
- - - . The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Intra. Frederic Jame-
son. Trans. Geoffrey Bennington and Brian Massoumi. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1984.
Malcolm, Norman. Dreaming. London: Routledge, 1959.
- - - . "Descartes's Proof That His Essence is Thinking." Descartes: A Collection
of Critical Essays. Ed. Willis Doney. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press,
1968.
Malebranche, Nicolas. The Search after Truth. Trans. Thomas M. Lennon and Paul
Olscamp. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1980.
Mandrau, Robert. Introduction a fa France moderne, 1500-1640: Essai de psy-
chofogie historique. Paris: Albin Michel, 1974.
218 • Bibliography
Maravall, Jose Antonio. The Culture of the Baroque: Analysis of a Historical Struc-
ture. Trans. Terry Cochran. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986.
Margitic, Milorad R. Essai sur fa mythologie du Cid. Romance Monographs.
Oxford: University of Mississippi, 1976.
Marzot, Giulio. L'ingegno e il genio del Seicento. Florence: La Nouva Italia, 1944.
Mathieu-Castellani, Gisele. Montaigne: L 'ecriture de l'essai. Paris: Presses Universi-
taires de France, 1988.
Mattern, Ruth. "Descartes's Correspondence with Elizaheth: Conceiving Both the
Union and Distinction of the Mind and Body." Descartes: Critical and Interpre-
tative Essays. Ed. Michael Hooker. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1978.
Mazlish, Bruce. The Fourth Dimension: The Co-Evolution of Humans and
Machines. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993.
McKinley, Mary B. Words in a Corner: Studies in Montaigne's Latin Quotations.
Lexington, Ky.: French Forum, 1981.
Merchant, Carolyn. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology and the Scientific Rev-
olution. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1980.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. "The Body as Expression and Speech." The Phenomenol-
ogy of Perception. Trans. Colin Smith. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1995.
- - - . "Eye and Mind." The Primacy of Perception. Ed. James M. Edie. Trans.
Carleton Dallery. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964.
- - - . "Everywhere and Nowhere." Signs. Trans. Richard C. Cleary. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1964.
- - - . The Prose of the World. Ed. Claude Lefort. Trans. John O'Neill. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1973.
- - - . "Reading Montaigne." Signs. Trans. Richard C. Cleary. Evanston: North-
western University Press, 1964.
- - - . The Visible and the Invisible. Trans. Alphonso Lingis. Evanston: North-
western University Press, 1968.
Montaigne, Michel de. The Complete Essays of Montaigne. Trans. Donald Frame.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1985.
- - - . Essais de Montaigne. Ed. Maurice Rat. 2 vols. Paris: Garnier Frcres, 1962.
- - - . Journal de voyage en Ita lie par la Suisse et I'Aliemagne en 1550-1581. Paris:
Club Franc;ais du Livre, 1954.
Mornet, Daniel. La Pensee franr;aise au XVlIle siecle. Paris: Colin, 1965.
Mumford, Lewis. Technics and Civilization. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1963.
Nakam, Geralde. "Eros et les Muses dans 'Sur des vers de Virgil.' " Mcmtaigne: La
Maniere et la matiere. Paris: Klincksieck, 1992.
- - - . "Corps physique, corps social: La maladie et la sante." Montaigne: La
Maniere et la matiere.
Naville, Pierre. "Sade et la philosophie." Oeuvres completes du Marquis de Sade.
Ed. Gilbert Lely. Vol. 11. Paris: Au Cercle du Livre Precieux, 1962-64.
Bibliography. 219
Weiss, Allen S. Mirrors of Infinity: The French Formal Garden and 17th-Century
Metaphysics. New York: Princeton Architectural Press, 1995.
Wellman, Kathleen. La Mettrie: Medicine, Philosophy, and the Enlightenment.
Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1992.
Wolflin, Heinrich. Renaissance and Baroque. Trans. Kathrin Simon. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1967.
- - - . Principles of Art History: The Problem of the Development of Style in Later
Art. Trans. M. D. Hottinger. New York: Dover, 1950.
Yoiton, John W. Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1984.
Index
heroism/valor in, 109, 110, 111, Deleuze, Gilles, 187-88n. 14, 191n. 55,
112-16,120,121-25 202n. 77
kingship in, 112, 116, 117, 118-20, Derrida, Jacques, 197n. 14
122, 125, 127-28, 130 Descartes, Rene
law in, 118-20, 121-22, 124-25, on body as machine, 4, 5,9-11,174,
126 175
legibility of bodies in, 112-15 on certitude, 7, 16-17
legitimacy in, 118, 122, 127-28 cogito of, and power relations,
love vs. honor in, 109, 125-26 144-45
marriage in, 121, 123, 126-27, 204n. and Gassendi, 199n. 41
22 influence of, 169, 173-74, 175-76,
metaphorical figures in, 109-11, 114 205n. 7 (see also materialism,
on physical body and the body French)
politic, 109, 111, 117, 120-21, Optics, 196n. 7
122-23, 128-29, 130 The Passions of the Soul, 201n. 63
reception of, 109-11, 130 Principles of Philosophy, 74,201 n.
Rodriguelthe Cid, 123-25 69
social body in, 11 on priority of thought, 8
style of, 110-11 rationalism of, 144
time in, 127-28 rational subjectivity of, 4, 5, 16
Cinna (Corneille), 11, 111, 120 on reason/speech, 195n. 46
Ciorenescu, Alexandru, 189n. 26 Rules, 199n. 34
Clark, Carol, 184n. 43 on souls/thoughts of animals, 78,
classicism, 190n. 39, 191-92n. 2 195n. 37, 195nn.41-42
Coleridge, Samuel, Biographia Liter- The World, 72-73, 194n. 24, 196n.
aria, 205n. 11 7
Confessions (Augustine), 97 See also Discourse on Method; Medi-
Conley, Tom, 202n. 77 tations on the First Philosophy;
consciousness, 6, 181n. 5. See also Treatise on Man
thought desire
Copernican revolution, 85, 196n. 7 and imagination, 23-24
Corneille, Pierre, 5, 11 and individual expression, 204n. 27
Cinna, 11, 111, 120 for knowledge, 18, 182n. 11
Heraciius, 117 La Mettrie on, 140, 143
Horace, 11, 120 Diderot, Denis, 206n. 20
Nicomede, 117 Discourse on Method (Descartes)
Rodogune, 117 on architect as model, 193n. 17
Sertorius, 117-18 body's elimination in, 86, 197n. 10
See also The Cid on circulation of blood, 67, 68-71,
Cottingham, John, 194n. 24, 201n. 65 192n. 12, 193n. 16
Cottrell, Robert D., 182n. 11, 182n. 14 cogito, centrality/autonomy of,
Crates, 19 70-71, 193n. 15, 198n.22
Crimes of Love (Sade), 150 vs. Corneille's Cid, 109,130
critical literature on the body, 1, 179n. human vs. machine, 81, 196n. 49
1 influences on, 72, 193nn. 20-21
Cysarz, Herbert, 189n. 27 mechanistic model of body in, 67,
68-71, 72-73, 79-81, 192-93n.
death, 25, 26-27, 183n. 24 13, 193nn. 15-16, 195n.47
226 • Index