What Makes A Concept Good A Criterial Framework For Understanding
What Makes A Concept Good A Criterial Framework For Understanding
What Makes A Concept Good A Criterial Framework For Understanding
J ohn Gerring
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0032-3497%28199921%2931%3A3%3C357%3AWMACGA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-9
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR' s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions ofUse provides, in part, that unless you
have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of ajoumal or multiple copies of articles, and
you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.j stor.org/joumals/pal.html.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or
printed page of such transmission.
JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to creating and preserving a digital archive of
scholarly joumals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
http://www.j stor.org/
Thu Jun 1 10:25:23 2006
What Makes a Concept Good?
A Criterial Framework for Understanding
Concept Formation in the Social Sciences*
John Gerring
Boston University
Nowhere in the broad and heterogeneous work on concept formation has the
question of conceptual utility been satisfactorily addressed. Goodness in
conceptformation, 1 argue, cannot be reduced to 'clarity,' to empiricalor
theoretical relevance, to a set ofrules, or to the methodology particular to a
given study. Rather, 1 argue that conceptual adequacy should be perceived
as an attempt to respond to a standard set of criteria, whose demands are
felt in the formation and use ofall social science concepts: (1) familiarity,
(2) resonance, (3) parsimony, (4) coherence, (5) differentiation, (6) depth,
(7) theoretical utility, and (8) field utility. The significance ofthis study is to
be found not simply in answering this important question, but also in pro-
viding a complete and reasonably concise framework for explaining the
process of concept formation within the social sciences. Rather than con-
ceiving of concept formation as a method (with a fixed set ofrules and a
definite outcome), 1 view it as a highly variable process involving trade-offs
among these eight demands.
*1 thank Andrew Gould, Hanna Pitldn, Amn Swamy and Craig Thomas for their helpful
comments and suggestions. 1 am particularly grateful to David Collier and David Waldner for
their work, their support, and their ongoing input to debate on matters methodological.
1. Giovanni Sartori, "Guidelines for Concept Analysis," Social Science Concepts: A Sys-
tematic Analysis, ed. Giovanni Sartori (Beverly Hills: Sage, 1984), 60.
dum), (b) the properties or attributes that define them (the intension, connota-
tion, definiens, or definition), and (c) a label covering both a and b (the term).
Concept formation is thus a triangular operation; good concepts attain a
proper alignment between a, b, and c. 2
If this notion seems unfamiliar to readers it is doubtless because so little
attention has been devoted to the subject of concept formation within the
social sciences. To be sure, concepts are a central concero for philosophers,
political theorists, sociological theorists, intellectual historians, linguists, and
cognitive psychologists.3 However, these scholars are primarily interested in
concepts as they function in ordinary or philosophical contexts, not in the spe-
cialized realm of social science. I take as my point of departure the assump-
All authors make lexical and semantic choices as they write and thus partici-
pate, wittingly or unwittingly, in lO ongoing interpretive battle. This is so
because language is the toolkit with which we conduct our work, as well as
the substance upon which we work. Indeed, concept formation lies at the heart
of all social science endeavor. It is impossible to conduct work without using
concepts. It is impossible even to conceptualize a topic, as the term suggests,
without putting a label on it. Any significant work 00 a subject will involve a
reconceptualization of that subject. Any work on the nation-state, for example
-if at all persuasive-alters our understanding ofthe nation-state. No use of
language is semantically neutral.
The importance of concept formation to the conduct of social science may
be glimpsed by the familiar observation that one 's results are heavily colored
by one 's definition of key terms. If I say "Somoza was a fascist," the hearer
is apt to respond, "Define 'fascist. '" It is commonly said that one can prove
practically anything simply by defining terms in a convenient way. This is no
doubt what prompts certain commentators to say tbat we ought to pay less
attention to the terms we use, and more to the things out there (in the world)
4. Max Weber, The Methodology ofthe Social Sciences (New York: Free Press, 1949), 105-
06. Weber's rernarks on social science are usefully contrasted with Wittgenstein's comments on
the practice of philosophy. "Philosophy may in no way interfere with the actual use of language;
it can in the end only describe it ... it leaves everything as it is" (Logicallnvestigations 41: para
124); quoted in Gordon Graham, Historical Explanation Reconsidered (Aberdeen: Aberdeen
University Press, 1983), 2. Sorne approaches to ordinarily language philosophy approach this
neutral ideal. Most, however, do not even pretend too
360 What Makes a Concept Good?
that we are talking about. 5 Yet, it will become clear in the course of this dis-
cussion that we cannot dispense with high-order concepts like fascism, ideol-
ogy, democracy, justice, and so forth. If we conducted social science business
only with directly-observable or countable concepts (deaths, votes, and the
like) we would have very little of importance to say, and we would have no
way of putting these small-order concepts together into a coherent whole.
Knowledge would no longer cumulate. Indeed, social science would be
stopped in its tracks. If we canoot, then, get language out of the way, we had
best learn to deal more effectively with words. We had best learn, in other
words, what differentiates a good concept from one that is less good, or less
usefu!.
This brings us to a consideration of what, precisely, is the matter with the
way we use language (and in particular, key concepts) in social science. For
many years it has been a standard complaint that the tenninology of social sci-
ence lacks the clarity and constancy of the natural science lexicon. 'Ideology,'
for example-a concept we shall employ repeatedly in the following discus-
sion-has been found to contain at least thirty-five possible attributes, form-
ing a conceptual apparatus with 235 definitional possibilities.6 Other concepts,
like justice, democracy, the state, and power, are similarly (though perhaps not
so extremely) fraught. Truly, it might be said, we do not know what it is we
are talking about when we use these terms: for when A says 'ideology' she
may mean something quite different than B. Concepts are employed differ-
ently in different fields and sub-fields, and within different intellectual tradi-
tions (e.g., marxist, weberian, behavioral, rational choice).
But the confusion does not end there, for even within single subfields or
intellectual traditions there is a good deal of ambiguity surrounding such
terms. Concepts are routinely stretched to cover instances that lie quite a bit
outside their normal range of use.7 Or they are scrunched to cover only a few
instances (ignoring others). Older concepts are redeployed, leaving etymo-
5. Popper, for example, writes "Never let yourself be goaded into taking seriously prob-
lems about words and their meanings. What must be taken seriously are questions of fact, and
assertions about facts, theories and hypotheses; the problems they solve; and the problems they
raise." Karl Popper, Unended Quest: An lntellectual Autobiography (LaSalle, IL: Open Court,
1976), 19; quoted in David Collier, "Putting Concepts to Work: Toward a Framework for Ana-
lyzing Conceptual Innovation in Comparative Research," presented at the annual meetings of the
American Political Scíence Association, Boston, MA (September 1998).
6. See John Gerring, "Ideology: A Definitional Analysis," Political Research Quarterly 50
(December 1997): 957-94.
7. On conceptual stretehing, see David Collier and James E. Mahon, Jr., "Conceptual
'Stretehing' Revisited: Adapting Categories in Comparative Analysis," American Political Sci-
ence Review 87 (December 1993), 845-55; Giovanni Sartori, "Concept Misformation in Com-
parative Politics," American Political Science Review 64:4 (December 1970), 1033-46; Sartori,
"Guidelines."
John Gerring 361
logical trails that confuse the unwitting reader. New words are created to refer
to things that were perhaps poorly articulated through existing concepts, leav-
ing a highly complex lexical terrain (for the old concepts continue to circu-
late). Words with similar meanings crowd around each other, vying for atten-
tion and stealing each others' attributes (e.g., ideology, political culture,
belief-system, value-system). Thus we play "musical chairs with words," in
Sartori's memorable phrase. 8
This sort of semantic confusion throws a wrench into the work of social
science. Arguments employing such terms have a tendency to fly past each
other; work on these subjects does not cumulate. Concepts seem to "get in the
way" of a clear understanding of things. Our conceptual apparatus seems
defective.
8. Giovanni Sartori, "The Tower of Babble," in Tower 01 Babel: On the Definition and
Analysis 01 Concepts in the Social Sciences, ed. Giovanni Sartori, Fred W. Riggs, and Henry
Teune (International Studies, occasional paper no. 6),9. See a1so Sarton, "Guidelines," 38, 52-53.
9. Galileo is paraphrased in Richard Robinson, Definition (Qxford: Clarendon Press,
1954), 63. Robinson discusses the problems caused for Locke by his arbitrary redefinition of
'idea.' "In common use in Locke's century the word 'idea' meant, as it does in ours, something
essentially part of the thinker or perceiver and not of the objects he surveys. To redefine it, there-
fore, as any object of thinking was either to make a most violent departure from usage or to imply
that no man can ever think about anything that is not a part of himself. The latter is what hap-
pened to Locke, without his intending it" (74).
362 What Makes a Concept Good?
It is not our aim simply to discover a method for identifying with suff-
icent accuracy the facts to which the words of ordinary language refer
and the ideas they convey. We need, rather, to formulate entirely new
eoncepts, appropriate to the requirements of science and expressed in an
appropriate terminology.11
10. For work in the ordinary-Ianguage tradition (1 employ the terro loosely), see John L.
Austin, Philosophical Papers; Philosophy and Ordinary Language, ed. Charles E. Caton
(Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1963); Ordinary Language, ed. V.C. Chappell (Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1964); Pitkin, Wittgenstein; Gilbert Ryle, The Concept 01 Mind (New
York: Bames & Noble, 1949); Paul Ziff, Semantic Analysis (Ithaca: Comell University Press,
1960). See also work by G.E.M. Anscombe, Stanley Cavell, Jerry Fodor, Jerrold Katz,
Norman Malcolm, and John Wisdom-allloosely inspired by Wittgenstein's later work.
11. Emile Durkheim, The Rules 01Sociological Method [1895] (New York: The Free Press,
1964), 36-7.
John Gerring 363
indisputable that such departures must, and should, be taken on sorne occa-
sions. 12 Social science cannot accept words simply as they present themselves
in ordinary speech, or a natural-Ianguage dictionary. Sorne fiddling with
words and definitions is incumbent upon the researcher.
A second tradition in concept formation equates successful definition with
the identification of attributes that provide necessary and sufficient conditions
for locating examples of the term (Le., the phenomenon itselt). "In defining a
name," writes MilI, "it is not usual to specify its entire connotation, but so
much only as is sufficient to mark out the objects usualIy denoted by it from
alI other known objects. And sometimes a merely accidental property, not
involved in the meaning of the name, answers this purpose equally we11."13
FolIowing this general tack, a later logician writes: "A class must be defined
by the invariable presence of certain common properties. If we include an
individual in which one of these properties does not appear, we either fall into
a logical contradiction, or else we form a new class with a new definition.
Even a single exception constitutes a new class by itself."14 To define human
as an animal that is (a) featherless and (b) bipedal, for example, is to offer a
definition that successfulIy picks out one species from other species. This
approach privileges one desideratum (which 1 calI 'differentiation') over aH
others. Like the approach of ordinary language, this approach is not so much
wrong as insufficient. Humans are indeed featherless and bipedal, but this is
not what we usualIy mean when we use the word 'human.' (Consider the qual-
ities that we consider distinctively 'human'; featherlessness and bipedality
would probably rank low on such lists.) Although definitions in social science
are ca11ed upon to perform a referential function, their purpose is not merely
referential (see below).
Moreover, even if we were to privilege differentiation over a11 other con-
ceptual desiderata, achieving the goal of the 'classical' concept (whose attrib-
12. Richardson, Definition (73) and Sartori, "Guidelines," offer further ref1ections on this
point.
13. Jobo Stuart Mili, System olLogic [1843] 8th ed. (London: Longrnans, Green, 1872), 73.
14. W. Stanley Jevons, The Principies 01 Science (London: 1892), 723; quoted in Abraharn
Kaplan, The Conduct ollnquiry: Methodology lor Behavioral Science (San Francisco: Chandler
Publishing, 1964),68. See also Pau) F. Lazarsfeld, "Concept Formation and Measurernent in the
Behavioral Sciences: Sorne Historical Observations," in Concepts, Theory, and Explanation in
the Behavioral Sciences, ed. Gordon J. DiRenzo (New York: Randorn House, 1966), 144-204;
Felix E. Oppenheirn, Political Concepts: A Reconstruction (Chicago: University of Chicago,
1981). Although Sartori's work is too wide-ranging to fit into any single rnodel, his repeated
injunction to "seize the object" ("Guidelines," 26), to "identify the referent and establish its
boundaries" (33) puts hirn closer to the classical camp than to any other. "Tbe defining proper-
ties are those that bound the concept extensionally. . . . Confine your defining to the necessary
properties," writes Sartori (55). For further discussion of the classical concept, see Adcock,
"What is a 'Concept, '" and Taylor, Linguistic Categorization.
364 What Makes a Concept Good?
utes always identify its referents, and no others) might not be possible in
many instances. Consider the concept 'mother.' If defined as the person who
gives birth to a child we would appear to satisfy the always-and-only crite-
rion. But how are we to refer to foster mothers and adoptive mothers, or sur-
rogate mothers (who do not provide genetic material for the child)? Are these
not also, in some basic sense, 'mothers'? Even the "featherless and biped"
definition breaks down in the face of accident victims and birth defects. Prob-
lems multiply when one begins to consider social science concepts. Which
attributes of 'democracy,' for example, should be considered necessary and
sufficient to identify instances of democracy--eontestation, participation,
accountability, protection of basic rights, or some combination thereof? The
classical notion of a concept is an ideal rarely satisfied in social science, as
many writers have pointed OU1. I5
A third tradition argues that concept formation is rightfully subservient to
theory formation. Concepts are the hand-maidens of theories, and conse-
quently may be judged only so good as the theories they serve. 16 Indeed, con-
cepts are the building-blocks of all inferences, and the formation of many
concepts is clearly, and legitimately, theory-driven. "Theory formation and
concept formation go hand in hand," Hempel stresses; "neither can be carried
on successfully in isolation from the other."17
My only dissent from this line of reasoning-and it is one with which
most scholars would probably concur-is to point out that concept formation
is not merely a matter of theory formation. This will become abundantIy clear
as we progress. For the moment one might consider the fact that a concept's
utility in facilitating theory-formation is influenced by the degree to which it
can be differentiated from neighboring concepts. If, let us say, 'ideology' is
defined in such a way as to encroach upon what we normally think of as polit-
ical culture, then the theory within which this concept takes its place is seri-
ously impaired. A rose by another name-say, 'political culture'-may smell
15. See Collier and Mahon, "Conceptual 'Stretehing' "; Kaplan, Logic o/lnquiry (68);
Lakoff, Women, Fire.
16. See, e.g., Russcll Faeges, "Theory-Driven Concept Definition and Classificatory Per-
versity," unpublished manuscript, n.d.; Carl G. Hempel, Aspects o/ Scientific Explanation: And
Other Essays in the Philosophy o/Science (New York: The Free Press, 1965), 139. A slight1y dif-
ferent version of the theoretical approach is offered by Murray G. Murphey, Philosophical Foun-
dations o/Historical Knowledge (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994). Rather than seeing concepts per-
forming functions within theories, Murphey proposes that "theories that explain the behavior and
properties of instances of the concept are the meanings of concepts" (23-24; emphasis added).
Thus, the best definition of gold is "the element whose atomic number is 79."
17. Hempel, Aspects, 113 (see also 139). Kaplan calls this the paradox of conceptualization:
"The proper concepts are needed lo formulate a good theory, but we need a good theory to arrive
at the proper concepts" (Logic o/lnquiry, 53).
John Gening 365
more sweet. A great theory, with poorly crafted concepts is at best a great idea,
poorly implemented. Concept formation and theory formation are intimately
conjoined; the former is not reducible to the latter.
Other work on the subject of concept formation is more difficult to sum-
marize (mainly because the field of concept formation is so poorly defined).
A fourth approach suggests that concept formation is particular to the concept-
type--e.g., circular, classical, classificatory, comparative, connotative, con-
textual, core, deductive, denotative, disposition, empirical, essential, essen-
tially-contested, experiential, family-resemblance, functional, genus el
differentia, ideal-type, inductive, lexical, metrical, minimal, nominal, object,
observable, operational, ostensive, persuasive, polar, precising, property,
radial, real, residual, stipulative, technical, theoretical, and so forth. 18 Accord-
ing to this line of reasoning, different concept-types impose different defini-
tional demands on the conceptualizer. Each is appropriate for different
(largely context-driven) tasks.
Finally, as 1 have suggested, a good deal of work on concept formation in
the social sciences (including sorne of the work just cited) does not fall neatly
18. See, e.g., Kazimierz Adjdukiewicz, "Three Concepts of Definition," in Problems in the
Philosophy of Language, ed. Thomas M. Olshewsky (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
1969); Peter A. Angeles, Dictionary ofPhilosophy (New York: Bames and Noble, 1981),56-58;
Robert Bierstedt, "Nominal and Real Definitions in Sociological Theory," in Symposium on Soci-
ological Theory, ed. Llewellyn Gross (Evanston, IL: Row, Peterson, 1959); Thomas Borger, Max
Weber's Theory ofConcept Formation: History, Laws, and Ideal Tjpes (Durham: Duke Univer-
sity, 1976); E Stuart Chapin, "Definition of Definitions of Concepts" Social Forces 18 (Decem-
ber 1939), 153- 60; Bemard P. Cohen, Developing Sociological Knowledge, 2nd ed. (Chicago:
Nelson-Hall, Inc, 1989); Collier and Mahon, "Conceptual 'Stretching"'; Gordon J. DiRenzo,
"Conceptual Definition in the Behavioral Sciences," in Concepts, Theory, and Explanation in the
Behavioral Sciences, ed. Gordon J. DiRenzo (New York: Random House, 1966),6-18; Richard
G. Dumont and William J. Wilson,"Aspects of Concept Formation, Explication, and Theory Con-
struction in Sociology," American Sociological Review 32 (December 1967), 985-95; George J.
Graham, Jr. , Methodological Foundations for Political Analysis (Waltham, MA: Xerox College
Publishing, 1971); Carl G. Hempel, "Fundamentals ofConcept Formation in Empirical Science,"
Foundations of the Unity of Science 2 (1952); Kaplan, Logic of lnquiry; Lakoff, Women, Fire;
Leonard Linsky, "Reference and Referents," in Problems in the Philosophy of Language, ed.
Thomas M. Olshewsky (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1969); John William Miller, The
Definition of a Thing, with Some Notes on Language (New York: W.W. Norton, 1980); Arthur
Pap, "Theory of Definition," in Problems in the Philosophy o/ Language, ed. Thomas M.
Olshewsky (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1969); Hilary Putnam, "The Meaning of
'Meaning'," in Mind, LAnguage and Reality, Philosophical Papers, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1975), 215-71; Robinson, Definition; Bertrand Russell,"On Denoting,"
in Olshewsky, Problems in the Philosophy ofLanguage; Sartori, "Tower of Babble," 28-30; Sar-
tori, "Guidelines," 72-85; Arthor L. Stinchcombe, Constructing Social Theories (New York: Har-
court, Brace, 1968); P.E Strawson, "On Referring," in Olshewsky, Problems in the Philosophy o/
Language.
366 What Makes a Concept Good?
into any of the foregoing schools. 19 Indeed, social science is replete with folk
wisdom on the matter of concept formation. We applaud the virtues of clarity,
making sense, seizing the object, relevance, rigor, standardization, systemati-
cization, theoretical yield, utility, and parsimony, and decry the evils of ambi-
guity, vagueness, indefiniteness, triviality, and idiosyncrasy. Yet, these famil-
iar admonitions are themselves rather vague, and perhaps contradictory,
suggesting the need for further research. 20 We should like very much to follow
Locke's advice to "strip all ... terms of ambiguity and obscurity."21 The ques-
tion is, how shall we do so?
The Argument
19. See, e.g., Martin Bulmer and Robert G. Burgess, "Do Concepts,Variables and Indicators
Interrelate?" in Key Variables in Social Investigation, ed. Robert G. Burgess (London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul, 1986); David Collier and Steven Levitsky, "Democracy with Adjectives: Con-
ceptual Innovation in Comparative Research," World Politics 49 (AprilI997): 430-51; Carl G.
Hempel, "Typological Methods in the Social Sciences," in Philosophy olthe Social Sciences: A
Reader, ed. Maurice Natanson (New York; Random House, 1963); Hempel, Philosophy 01Nat-
ural Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1966); Kaplan, Logic olInquiry; John C.
McKinney, Constructive Typology and Social Theory (Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1966); Eugene
J. Meehan, The Foundations 01 Political Analysis: Empirical and Normative (Homewood, IL:
Dorsey Press, 1971); Mili, System of Logic; Tadeusz Pawlowski, Concept Formation in the
Humanities and the Social Sciences (Boston: D. Reidel, 1980). See also the extensive bibliogra-
phy in David Collier and Henry Brady, "Studies of Major Concepts in Political Analysis: An
IlIustrative Inventory," unpublished manuscript (Berkeley: Department of Political Science, Uni-
versity of California at Berkeley).
20. Consider, for example, Sartori's ("Guidelines," 63) Rule 1: "Of any empirical concept
always, and separately, check 1) whether it is ambiguous, that is how the meaning relates to the
term; and 2) whether it is vague, that is how the meaning relates to the referenl."
21. Quoted in Richardson, Definition, 70.
22. "Words," wrote Virginia Woolf, "are the wildest, freest, most irresponsible, most
unteachable of all things. Of course, you can catch them and sort them and place them in alpha-
betical order in dictionaries. But words do not live in dictionaries; they live in the mind.... Thus
to lay down any laws for such irreclaimable vagabonds is worse than useless. A few trifling rules
of grammar and spelling are a11 the constraint we can put on them. A11 we can say about them, as
we peer at them over the edge of that deep, dark and only fitfu11y i11uminated cavern in which
they live - the mind - a11 we can say about them is that they seem to like people to think and
to feel before they use them, but to think and to feel not about them, but about something differ-
enl. They are highly sensitive, easily made self-conscious. They do not like to have their purity
or their impurity discussed.... Nor do they like being lifted out on the point of a pen and exam-
ined separately. They hang together, in sentences, in paragraphs, sometimes for whole pages at a
John Gerring 367
further questions: which contexts matter (or should matter), and under what
circumstances? Despite the complexities these questions introduce, 1 believe
that it is possible to arrive at a single account of concept formation within the
social sciences that is at once comprehensive and reasonably concise. Good-
ness in concept formation is most fruitfully understood as an attempt to medi-
ate among eight criteria: familiarity, resonance, parsimony, coherence, differ-
entiation, depth, theoretical utility, and field utility (see Table 1).
The common-sense conclusion from this eight-part list is to say that con-
cepts may be formed with a wide variety of purposes and may fulfill a wide
variety of attendant functions in social science research. 1 wish to carry the argu-
ment one step further. 01 course differently constructed concepts will empha-
size and deemphasize different demands. In this sense, they each "do their own
thing" (as work on concept-types implies). But the suppression of one or more
demands does not go unnoticed by other social scientists. A concept with high
theoretical utility that offends norms of established usage (or vice-versa) is less
serviceable for this fact. Thus, although particular criterial demands are often
ignored, they are ignored at a costo This points to the notion of concept forma-
tion as a set of tradeoffs-a tug of war among these eight desiderata. Concept
formation is a fraught exercise-a set of choices which may have no single
'best' solution, but rather a range of more-or-less acceptable altematives. This
eight-part criterial framework provides a quick and ready schema by which the
time. They hate being useful; they hate making money; they hate being lectured about in public.
In short, they hate anything that stamps them with one meaning or confines them to one attitude,
for it is their nature to change" (The Death o/the Moth, quoted in Richardson, Definition, 65).
368 What Makes a Concept Good?
l. Criteria
Familiarity
ing lexicon whicb, as currentIy understood, most accurately describes the phe-
nomenon under definition. Where several existing terms capture the phenom-
ena in question with equal facility-as, for example, the near-synonyms
worldview and weltanschauung-achieving familiarity becomes a matter of
finding the term with the greatest common currency. Simple, everyday terms
of a researcher's native language are, by definition, more familiar than terms
drawn from languages which are dead, foreign, or highly specialized. Where
no terms within the existing general or social-science lexicon adequately
describe the phenomena in question the writer is pressed to invent a new term.
Yet, neologism is the greatest violation of the familiarity criterion, for it
involves the creation of an entirely new term with no meaning at aH in normal
usage. AH other things being equal, a writer should tum to this expedient only
when no other semantic options present themselves. "Let us not stipulate until
we have good reason to believe that there is no name for the thing we wish to
name," notes Robinson emphaticaHy.24 Durkheim's comments on the matter
are also pertinent.
In actual practice, one always starts with the lay concept and the lay
term. One inquires whether, among the things which this word confus-
edly connotes, there are sorne which present common external charac-
teristics. If this is the case, and if the concept formed by the grouping of
the facts thus brought together coincides, if not totaHy (which is rare), at
least to a large extent, with the lay concept, it wiH be possible to continue
to designate the former by the same term as the latter, that is, to retain in
science the expression used in everyday language. But if the gap is too
considerable, if the common notion confuses a plurality of distinct ideas,
the creation of new and distinctive terms becomes necessary.25
At the same time, we ought not visualize the invention of new terms as
qualitatively removed from the redefinition of old terms. Neologisms, while
rejecting ordinary language, strive at the same time to re-enter the universe of
inteHigibility. They are never simply nonsense words; they are, instead, new
combinations of existing words (e.g., bureaucratic-authoritarianism) or roots
(e.g., polyarchy, heresthetic), or terms borrowed from other time-periods (e.g.,
corporatism), other language communities (e.g., equilibrium), or other lan-
guages (e.g., laissezfaire). By far the most fertile grounds for neologism have
Resonance
Why do some terms stick while others, with virtuaHy identical meanings, dis-
appear? Why are some efforts successful at reformulating a field or a prob-
lem, and others (with the same general argument) often overlooked? One
factor in the knowledge game which relates directIy to concept formation is
the "cognitive click" of a given term, which I shaH caH resonance.
"Makers, breakers, and takers," "exit, voice, and loyalty," and "civic cul-
ture" are aH examples of resonance at work. 28 As is apparent, the demand for
resonance is often fulfiHed by reference to nearby terms, which may form part
of a larger typology. If two of three terms in a typology end in the same suffix
(-tion, -ity, ...) it may be desirable to find a third with the same suffix.
Rhyming schemes are wonderful mnemonic devices.
To be sure, the search for resonance is often at odds with the satisfaction
of other criteria. The search for a catchy label tempts writers to violate the
familiarity criterion, making up new words to replace existing words or
choosing exotic options over plain ones. There are enough cases of abuse that
within social science circles snazzy labels are often regarded as terminologi-
26. On polyarchy, see Robert A. Dahl, Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition (New
Haven, Yale University Press, 1971). On heresthetic, see William H. Riker, The Art of Political
Manipulation (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986). On corporatism, see David Collier,
"Trajectory of a Concept: 'Corporatism' in the Study of Latin American Politics," in Latin Amer-
ica in Comparative Perspective, ed. Peter Smith (Boulder: Westview Press, 1995), 135-62;
PhilipPe Schmitter C., "Still the Century of Corporatism?" in The New Corporatism, ed. Freder-
ick B. Pike and Thomas Stritch (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974).
27. Robinson (Definition, 55) notes: "Men will always be finding themselves with a new
thing to express and no word for it, and usually they will meet the problem by applying whichever
old word seems nearest, and thus the old word will acquire another meaning or a stretched mean-
ing. Very rarely will they do what A. E. Housman bade them do, invent a new noise to mean the
new thing."
28. See Stephen D. Krasner, Defending the Nationallnterest: Raw Materials lnvestments
and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978); Albert O. Hirschman,
Exit, Voice, Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States (Cambridge: Har-
vard University Press, 1970); Gabriel A. Almond and Sidney Yerba, Civic Culture: Political Atti-
tudes and Democracy in Five Nations (Princeton: Princeton University, 1963). See also discus-
sion in Collier and Levitsky, "Democracy with Adjectives," 450.
John Gerring 371
cal tinsel-rhetorical covers for poor research. Yet, before we dismiss the cri-
terion of resonance as frivolously aesthetic and obfuscatory, we should con-
sider the reasons why scholars continue to search for words which are not
only clear, but also captivating.
Effective phrase-making can no more be separated from the task of con-
cept formation than good writing can be separated from the task of research.
It seems fairly obvious that 'ideology' resonates in a way that 'belief-system'
does not, which may explain something about the persistence of the former in
the face of a fairly concerted academic onslaught over the past severa!
decades. One might also consider Marx's choice of proletariat over 'working
classes.' Would his work have had the same impact had he stayed with the ter-
minological status quo?
If resonance is important in reconceptualizing old ideas, as well as in coin-
ing new terms, how does one achieve this quality? This is a very difficult ques-
tion to answer, or to predict, since there are so many nonsemantic (auditory,
visual, and perhaps even olfactory) cues to which readers commonly respondo
Resonance, for example, might be derived from a word's metaphoric, synech-
dotic, alliterative, or onomatopoetic value, its rhyming scheme or rhythm
(number of syllables, stress, ...). These are matters that we need not pursue
here. The point is, concepts aspire not simply to clarity but also to power, and
power is carried by a term's resonance as well as its meaning.
Parsimony
29. See, e.g., Sarton, "Guidelines," 40, 54-55; Fred W. Riggs, "The Definition of Concepts"
in Sartori et al., Tower ofBabel, 39-76.
372 What Makes a Concept Good?
What can now be said could also have been said previously, without
using the new rule or the new name; but it can now be said in fewer
words, because the thing can now be indicated by a single name,
whereas formerly a descriptive phrase was required. The value of such
timesaving does not lie merely or mainly in leaving more time for other
activities. Abbreviation not merely shortens discourse; it also increases
understanding. We grasp better what we can hold in one span of atten-
tion, and how much we can thus hold depends on the length of the sym-
bols we have to use in order to state it. Abbreviations often immensely
increase our ability to understand and deal with a subject.31
The Chinese language takes this quest for abbreviation to what we in the west-
em world would consider to be an extreme, substituting single characters for
whole English sentences. Logical and mathematical languages also prize
brevity. The point is, natural languages (of any sort) also seek to reduce
human experience. Reduction, of course, is not the only task of language, just
as it is not the only task of concepts in social science. But consider: key con-
cepts are likely to be employed repeatedly and insistentIy in a given work. To
say 'political belief-system' once in a paragraph is enough; to say it thrice in
a paragraph is awkward and tendentious. Single-word concepts, particularly
those that trip easily off the tongue, can be used unobtrusively. A11 other
30. Proposed substitutes violate the parsimony criterion (e.g., 'political belief-system'), or
the intelligibility/familiarity criterion (e.g., 'weltanschaaung'). See Gerring, "Ideology."
31. Robinson, Definition, 68.
Jobn Gerring 373
How much better they serve than those authoritative masses of words
called titles, by which so large a proportion of sound and so small a pro-
portion of instruction are at so large an expense of attention granted to
us, such as-'An Act to explain and amend an act entitled An Act to
explain and amend ... ' Coinages of commodious titles are thus issued
day by day throughout the session from an invisible though not unli-
censed mint. But no sooner has. the last newspaper of the last day of the
session made its way to the most distant of its readers, than aH this
leaming, aH this circulating medium, is as completely buried in obliv-
ion as a French assignat. So many yearly strings of words, not one of
which is to be found in the works of Dryden, with whom the art of coin-
ing words fit to be used became numbered among the lost arts, and the
art of giving birth to new ideas among the prohibited ones!33
Coherence
Arguably, the most important criterion of a good concept is its internal coher-
ence-the sense in which the attributes that define the concept, as well as the
characteristics that actually characterize the phenomena in question, "belong"
to one another. There must be sorne sense of coherence to the grouping, rather
32. It may be observed that parsimony in a tenn occasionally conflicts with parsimony in a
definition. 'Ideology,' for example, scores well on the first and poorIy on the second. 'Belief-
system' scores poorIy on the first, but well on the second.
33. Jeremy Bentham, Bentham's Handbook o/ Political Fallacies [1834] ed. Harold A.
Larrabee (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1952), 10-11.
374 What Makes a Concept Good?
34. AH these examples are drawn from Malcolm B. Hamilton, "The Elements of the Con-
cept of Ideology" Political Studies 35 (1987): 20-21.
35. An 'essential' or 'real' definition is defined as: "Giving the essence of a thing. From
among the characteristics passessed by a thing, one is unique and hierarchically superior in that
it states (a) the mast important characteristic of the thing, andlor (b) that characteristic upon
which the others depend for their existence" (Angeles, Dictionary 01 Philosophy, 57). See also
Mil1, System olLogic, 71.
36. Robert A. Dahl, "The Concept of Power," [1957] in Political Power: A Reader in Theory
and Research, ed. Roderick BeH, David V. Edwards, and R. Harrison Wagner (New York: Free
Press, 1969), 79-80.
John Gerring 375
that is, that a single principie is able to subsume various uses and instances of
the concept-the highest possible level of coherence has been achieved in that
concept. (It will be noted that 'core' conceptualizations are also, conveniently,
parsimonious ones.)
Each of the proposed core definitions for ideology is an attempt to restore
coherence to the tangled set of attributes associated with this concept by
pointing to a fundamental attribute that successfully explains, or resolves con-
tradictions among, other attributes. 37 It should be obvious that coherence in a
term is usually fairly easy to achieve if one or more of the term's traditional
meanings are overlooked. Thus, one may specify a core attribute for ideology
and include in the concept only those peripheral characteristics that mesh
nicely with the chosen core meaning (ignoring all other attributes evoked by
ordinary usage of the term). Again, we have a situation in which concept for-
mation involves trade-offs between different criteria.
Differentiation
froro the clarity of its borders within a field of similar terms. A poorly bounded
concept has defmitional borders which overlap neighboring concepts.
The importance of differentiation is brought out nicely in the OED's def-
inition of 'definition,' which (among other things) asserts that defining an
object is "the act or product of marking out, or delimiting, the outlines or char-
acteristics of any conception or thing."40 The two terms (definition and differ-
entiation) are very close in meaning. As Pitkin explains, "the meaning of an
expression is delimited by what might have been said instead, but wasn't.
Green leaves off where yellow and blue begin, so the meaning of 'green' is
delimited by the meanings of 'yellow' and 'blue."'41
Ideology is an excellent example of a concept without clear borders. It is
difficult, one finds, to use the concept of ideology without tripping over the
neighboring concepts of belief-system, worldview, value-system, symbol-
system, myth, public philosophy, political philosophy, political culture, public
opinion, policy agenda, political rhetoric, and political discourse. If, however,
we can clarify, by adjusting the attributes of the intension, how ideology dif-
fers from these other terms then we have increased the differentiation of the
concept. For purposes of maximum differentiation (ignoring the demands of
other conceptual criteria), one might define ideology as: (a) composed of
values, beliefs, and attitudes, but not issue-positions and policy results (dif-
ferentiating it from programs, policies, agendas, and actions); (b) coherent,
but not rigorously and systematically so (differentiating it from philosophical
systems); (c) directly concemed with politics, and acting as a guide to politi-
cal action (in contrast with those many near-synonyms which imply only a
minimal connection to the real world of politics); (d) 'partisan' (oppositional,
engaged); (e) persistent through time (as distinguished from public opinion
and policy agendas); and (f) manifested in speech or in written form but not
reducible to language (as distinguished from forms of discourse). With these
defining characteristics, the concept of ideology comes about as close as one
can come, given the sheer number of its near-synonyms, to fulfilling the cri-
terion of differentiation. Without such differentiating characteristics, readers
are likely to wonder how-or whether-ideology differs from related con-
cepts, and wby none of these other terms were chosen to label the concept
under definition.
Sorne years ago, Hannah Arendt bemoaned the general lack of attention
paid by political scientists to distinctions between 'power,' 'force,' 'authority,,
and 'violence. '42 In the interirn, this lack of attention has been followed by
what some might call a surfeit of attention. 43 But Arendt's point is still good:
useful definitions define a term against related terms, telling us not only what
a concept is, but also what it is not. 44 Internal coherence is inseparable from
external differentiation.
It should be clear from the foregoing discussion that differentiation refers
not only to semantic space (the degree to which a concept's definitional bor-
ders are clear) but also to physical space (the degree to which a concept's bor-
ders in time and space are clearly demarcated).45 What we wish to know about
a social science concept is not merely what it is, but also where it is-which
is to say, where it isn't. In order to perform this task effectively a concept must
be sufficiently bounded.
Differentiation, like aH criterial demands, is a matter of degrees. Contrary
to the classical view of concepts-where defining attributes are to be found
always-and-only in the extension-most social science concepts must take a
pragmatic approach to the goal of establishing differentiation (for the simple
reason that there are no always- and-only attributes). Table 2lays out the pos-
sibilities. Where unique properties are present (category 1), all others are
superfluous (for purposes of establishing differentiation). It hardly matters
whether the property in question is invariably present, or invariably absent,
although in the latter case the definitional attribute will be residual. Where
unique properties do not exist, we are forced to rely on the less perfect expe-
dient of sometimes-differentiating attributes in order to establish tlle bound-
aries of a concept. In such cases-including the vast majority of abstract con-
cepts-the "minimal definition strategy" that Sartori advises simply makes no
sense. 46 One is compelled in the case of ideology, for example, to place quite
47. W. Stanley Jevons, The Principies 01 Science [1877] (New York: Dover, 1958), 708.
John Gening 379
useful. Barbara Geddes notes that state autonomy is generally "inferred from
its effects rather than directly observed.
No one, it seems, is quite sure what 'it' actualIy consists of. State auton-
omy seems at times to refer to the independence of the state itself, the
regime, a particular government, some segments or agencies of the gov-
ernment, or even specific leaders. It seems the phrase can refer to any
independent force based in the central government.48
Depth
The larger purpose of concept formation is not simply to enhance the clarity
of communication (by showing where, precisely, the borders between con-
cepts are located), but also the efficiency of communication. We are looking
for a way to group instances/characteristics that are commonly found together
48. Barbara Geddes, Politicians' Dilemma: Building State Capacity in Latin America
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996), 5.
49. Robert Dahl, "Power," in lnternational Encyclopedia 01the Social Science 12, ed. David
L. Si11s (New York: Macmi11an, 1968),414. Quoted in Geoffrey Debnam, The Analysis olPower:
Core Elements and Structure (New York: SI. Martin's Press, 1984),2.
50. Genera11y, the quest for bounded concepts leads one to concrete, 'observational' con-
cepts. This, it might be said, is the virtue of small concepts (their sPecificity, and hence clear bor-
ders). Indeed, it is difficult to imagine a larger concept being more bounded than the sma11er con-
cepts within its purview. 'State' is unlikely to be more bounded than 'executive,' 'parliament,' and
'bureaucracy.' However, this does not mean that a11 observational concepts are bounded, and a11
'abstract' terms fuzzy. Consider the various terms used to describe parts of river-e.g., 'delta,'
'source,' 'beach,' and so forth. These, too, are shifty.
380 What Makes a Concept Good?
so that we can use the concept's label as shorthand for those instances/char-
acteristics. The utility of a concept is enhanced by its ability to 'bundle' char-
acteristics. The greater the number of properties shared by the phenomena in
the extension, the greater the depth of a concept. 51
Within the U.S., the geographic concept of the West is vulnerable to the
charge that these states do not share many features in common; the concept,
in other words, is not meaning-full. Meaning, in this case, refers to the number
of shared attributes that the term calls forth. The deeper or richer a concept,
the more convincing the claim that it defines a class of common entities,
which are therefore deserving of being called by a single name. The term, in
this sense, carries more of a punch-it is, descriptively speaking, more pow-
erful, allowing us to infer many things-the common characteristics of the
concept-from one thing, the concept's label. The concept of the South, fol-
lowing the opinion of most historians, would have to be considered deeper
than the West, since a much longer list of accompanying attributes can be
constructed.
One of the rationales behind the familiar injunction not to define concepts
residually (by what they aren't) is rooted in the problem that in doing so we
violate the criterion of depth. Not-X attributes may be useful for establishing
differentiation, but they are not productive of depth. Residual concepts merit
the appellation 'shallow'; indeed, in the case of a purely residual concept
there is no water at all in the bathtub. Ceteris paribus, deep concepts are supe-
rior to shallow ones. While for the task of bounding a phenomenon a single
reliable trait may be sufficient, the task of describing it demands plenitude.
Good concepts identify fecund categories.
This is not to say, however, that parsimony and depth are directly at odds
with one another. Depth refers to properties that may be defining or accom-
panying (non-definitional). To define 'human' as a rational animal in no way
compromises the depth of this category. Indeed, if one considers the sheer
number of things that can be said to differentiate humans from other animals,
this must be considered an extraordinarily deep concept.
51. Although rarely acknowledged as a desideratum of concepts at-Iarge (but see Arthur L.
Stinchcombe, Theoretical Methods in Social History, [New York: Academic Press, 1978],21,29),
the notion of depth is implicit in virtually all descriptions of classificatory methods of definition.
Mill (System 01Logic, 460) defines a Kind, for example, as a class of things "distinguished from
all others not by one or a few definite proPerties, but by an unknown multitude of them; the com-
bination of proPerties on which the class is grounded being a mere index to an indefmite number
of other distinctive attributes." The argument here put forth may be viewed, therefore, as an
attempt to generalize from classificatory methods of concept formation to concept formation at
large. What is true for one, 1 would argue, is true for the other.
JoOO Gerring 381
Theoretical Utility
The classic scientific goal of a social science concept is to aid in the formula-
tion of theories, as discussed above. 52 Concepts are the building-blocks of aH
theoretical structures and the formation of many concepts is legitimately
theory-driven. Anomie, libido, mode 01 production, and charisma owe their
endurance, at least in part, to the theories of Durkheim, Freud, Marx, and
Weber. Indeed, these terms have little meaning in the social sciences without
these broader theoretical frameworks.
Classificatory frameworks (which 1 shaH consider a species of 'theory')
are particularly important since their effort is more explicitIy conceptual than
other sorts of inferences. A classification aims to carve up the universe into
comprehensive, mutually exclusive, and hierarchical categories. Within such
a schema, a given concept derives much of its utility from its position within
this broader array of terms. Ideology, for example, within a general cognitivist
framework, has often been used to refer to the highest (Le., most sophisti-
cated) level of political understanding. 53 This brings with it an emphasis on
certain traits like abstraction, sophistication, and knowledge. Other commonly
understood features of the concept must be excluded or else the classificatory
schema wiH be violated. Although this involves sorne sacrifice of familiarlty,
it may make more sense to appropriate the general term 'ideology,' with aH its
complications, than to resort to neologism (which of course has its own con-
ceptual costs, as we have discussed). One can think of concepts whose exis-
tence is almost wholly dependent upon their classificatory utility. Thompson
et al. 's latalism and Luebbert's traditional-authoritarianism have few exter-
nal referents. 54 Indeed, they are virtuaHy empty categories, failing the depth
criterion miserably. However, these concepts are redeemed to sorne degree by
their utility within broader typologies, which they help to define and delimite
These are extreme cases but they iHustrate the more general point that con-
cepts often categorize. 55
But theoretical utility need not be so (shall we say) 'theoretical.' Consider,
once again, the concept of ideology. 1 have argued that we ought to define ide-
ology broadly-to refer to all minimally coherent political belief-systems-
rather than to adopt a more narrow definition (including, perhaps, only those
values and beliefs that are dogmatic) because we need a way to talk about
these things, and 'political belief-system' is too long and awkward a term to
adequately perform this function. Ideology, broadly defined, has a theoretical
utility that ideology, narrowly defined, does no1. Colloquially stated, "we
should possess a name wherever one is needed; wherever there is anything to
be designated by it, which it is of importance to express. "56
Field Utility
common sense and moral honesty...," writes Bentham (Bentham's Handbook, 11). "Not only,"
writes his intellectual godchild, "should every word perfectly express its meaning, but there
should be no important meaning without its word" (Mili, System ofLogic, 456).
58. Patrick Gardiner, from whom 1 steal this phrase, has a somewhat different point in mind.
See Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation [1952] (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1961),55.
59. See Sartori, "Guidelines."
384 What Makes a Concept Good?
matter other than those which state the classification itself. Tradition-
ally, such a concept was said to identify a 'natural' class rather than an
'artificial' one. Its naturalness consists in this, that the attributes it
chooses as the basis of classification are significantly related to the
attributes conceptualized elsewhere in our thinking. Things are grouped
together because they resemble one another. A natural grouping is one
which allows the discovery of many more, and more important, resem-
blances than those originally recognized. Every classification serves
sorne purpose or other...: it is artificial when we cannot do more with
it than we first intended. 60
60. Kaplan, Logic ollnquiry, 50-51. Hempel's observations are similar: "the familiar vague
distinction between 'natural' and 'artificial' c1assifications may well be explicated as referring to
the difference between classifications that are scientifically fruitful and those that are not: in a
classification of the fonner kind, those characteristics of the elements which serve as criteria of
membership in a given class are associated ... with ... extensive clusters of other characteris-
tics. For example, the two sets of primary sex characteristics which determine the division of
humans into male and female are each associated ... with a large variety of concomitant physi-
cal, physiological, and psychological traits. It is understandable that a classification of this sort
should be viewed as somehow having objective existence in nature, as 'carving nature at the
joints,' in contradistinction to 'artificial' classifications, in which the defining characteristics have
few explanatory or predictive connections with other traits; as is the case, for example, in the divi-
sion of humans into those weighing less than one hundred pounds, and all others" (Aspects 01Sci-
entific Explanation, 147) See also Jevons, Principies 01 Science, 679.
61. Angeles, Dictionary olPhilosophy, 56.
62. 1 have therefore used these last two tenns to refer to goodness in concept formation at-
large.
John Gerring 385
63. See Connolly, Terms 01 Political Discourse; Lakoff, Women, Fire; Pitldn, Wittgenstein;
Charles Taylor, "Neutrality in Political Science," in Readings in the Philosophy 01Social Science,
ed. Michael Martin and Lee C. McIntyre (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994); Peter Winch, The Idea
01 a Social Science, and its Relation to Philosophy (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1958).
Finley's discussion of the word 'slave' is particularly apt (M. l. Finley, "Generalizations in
Ancient History," in Generalizatíon in the Writing 01 History, ed. Louis Gottschalk [Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1963] 22-3).
64. See Sartori, "Concept Misfonnation."
65. This would apPear to be the implication of Sartori's work on the tradeoffs between
extension and intension (see "Concept Misfonnation," and "Guidelines").
386 What Makes a Concept Good?
Another objection to the criterial framework might be that concepts are not
really, as claimed, part of a single enterprise. Rather, what we may have is a
set of widely-varying conceptual exercises, each responding to different cri-
teria of adequacy. Indeed, considering the number and diversity of concept-
types listed on page 365-ideal-typical, radial, classical, and so forth-my
claims for uniformity in concept formation within the social sciences may
appear to readers as an exemplary case of conceptual stretching (in the
derogatory sense of that term).
To be sure, concepts differ from one another. Yet I would argue that these
differences are better understood as differences of degree, rather than of kind.
Moreover, and more significantly, those differences that matter (to social sci-
ence work, that is) can be readily mapped across the eight dimensions of our
framework. Work on concept-types is subsumable within the criterial frame-
work. 'Classical' concepts, for example, privilege differentiation; 'ideal-type'
concepts emphasize coherence (generalIy at the expense of differentiation);
'radial' and 'family-resemblance' concepts emphasize coherence, depth, and
familiarity; 'polar' concepts emphasize coherence and theoretical utility; and
so forth. Each concept-type emphasizes a different conceptual task or tasks-
but not to the total exclusion %ther tasks. Ideal-type concepts have not
renounced all claims to differentiation; classical concepts do not eschew all
ties to coherence, depth, or standard usage. 66
66. Interestingly, the notion of an ideal-type is pre-figured in early work by Jevons (Princi-
pies of Science, 722-24). "Perplexed by the difficulties arising in natural history from the dis-
covery of intermediate forms, naturalists have resorted to what they caH classification by types.
Instead of forming one distinct class defined by the invariable possession of certain assigned
properties, and rigidly including or excluding objects according as they do or do not possess aH
these properties, naturalists select a typical specimen, and they group around it aH other speci-
mens which resemble this type more than any other selected type. 'The type of each genus,' we
are told, 'should be that species in which the characters of its group are best exhibted and most
evenly balanced.' " Yet Jevons promptly dismisses this pragmatic effort as "a certain laxity of log-
ical method."
Of the connection between ideal-types and empirical reality, Weber (Methodology of the
Social Sciences, 97) writes: "AH expositions for example of the 'essence' of Christianity are ideal
John Gerring 387
types enjoying only a necessarily very relative and problematic validity when they are intended
to be regarded as the historical portrayal of empirically existing facts." However tenuous the con-
nection to reality, it seems clear from Weber's exposition that ideal-type concepts must bear some
relationship to empirically existing phenomena in order to be of use to social science. The rela-
tive nature of conceptual adequacy is also recognized (at least implicitly) in the following com-
ments by Hempel. "Cognitive significance in a system is a matter of degree: significant systems
range from those whose entire extralogical vocabulary consists of observation terms, through the-
ories whose formulation relies heavily on theoretical constructs, on to systems with hardly any
bearing on potential empirical findings." Carl Hempel, "Empiricist Criteria of Cognitive Signif-
icance: Problems and Changes," in The Philosophy o/ Science, ed. Richard Boyd, Philip Gasper,
and J.D. Trout (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1991),81.
67. See Ronald M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1977); Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopía (New York: Basic Books, 1974); JoOO
Rawls, A Theory o/ Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971); Michael Walzer,
Spheres o/ Justice: A De/ense o/ Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books, 1983). For
explicitly empirical work on justice, see Justice: Views from the Social Sciences, ed. Ronald
Cohen (New York: Plenum Press, 1986); Norma Frohlich and Joe A. Oppenheimer, Choosing
Justice (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Karol Edward Soltan,"Empirical Stud-
ies of Distributive Justice." Ethics 92 (1982): 673-91; Soltan, The Causal Theory o/ Justice
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987).
388 What Makes a Concept Good?
Sartori and co11eagues offer the most impressive synthesis to date on the
vexed question of concept formation. 68 The primary effort of their research has
been to uncover a set of rules-a method-by which to guide the process of
concept formation in the social sciences.69 Rules one and two in Sartori's
handbook, for example, read as fo11ows:
This list extends to ten, and offers a convenient summary of what might be
ca11ed the "rulebook" approach to concept formation, an approach that
extends back to J. S. MilI. 7 I
The most obvious difficulty with this set of rules is that they are at pains
to rise above the commonsensical. (What a110ws us to determine whether
'ambiguity' or 'vagueness' is present in a definition?) More troubling is the
frequency of Sartori 's caveats-"awaiting contrary proof," "a11 other things
being equal," and so forth. 72 These difficulties suggest that concept formation
is a more dynamic and unpredictable process than can be managed within a
recipe-like approach. (As one wag has noted, when is ceteris ever rea11y
paribus?)
73. See Jevons, Principies 01 Science, 26. This point was amplified by Sartori, "Concept
Misformation," 1041. For other work highlighting the role oftradeoffs and intemal contradictions
in concept formation, see Cohen, Developing Sociological Knowledge, 131-45; Collier, "Putting
Concepts to Work," Collier and Mahon, "Conceptual 'Stretehing,'" Collier and Levitsky,
"Democracy with Adjectives," and Andrew C. Gould, "Conflicting ImPeratives and Concept For-
mation," unpublished manuscript (Notre Dame, IN: Department of Govemment, University of
Notre Dame, 1998).
390 What Makes a Concept Good?
would not mistake it for some other concept). It is familiar, and it seems suf-
ficiently parsimonious. Most important, Geddes manages to attain a high
degree of differentiation. She has some doubts, however, about its theoretical
utility (it "may not be the most important aspect of administrative reform").
No definitional choice, one imagines, would be perfect.
It would be easy to conclude from this example, and from the general discus-
sion that preceded, that concept formation is mostly a 'contextual' affaire Con-
texts differ, to be sure, and the task of concept formation will vary consider-
ably according to the specific real-world situation that one is attempting to
describe, specific semantic fields (fields ofneighboring concepts), specific ety-
mological histories (the traditional social-scientific or ordinary-Ianguage
understandings of the term), and specific analytic tasks. At the same time, it
should be noted that in all contexts the conceptualizer will have to wrestle with
the same eight demands. Concept formation thus retains a certain uniformity
across the disciplines and subject matters that compose the social sciences.
Nor do we lack standards in differentiating good concepts from bad ones.
I would argue, instead, that standards are assessable in terms of the goals
achieved by a given concept relative to that which the concept might other-
wise attain with a different choice 01 words, properties, or phenomena. It
would be pointless, in other words, to complain that a certain definition of
'justice' was insufficiently differentiated because it was more difficult to
locate in the empirical universe than a certain definition of 'chair.' The rele-
vant standard of comparison here is other definitions of justice, or other
neighboring terms which might more adequately identify the instances in
question. As any new theory must prove itself superior to rival explanations,
any new definition must vie against rival definitions and terms that might be
employed in that particular empirical and theoretical context. Thus, in the case
of Geddes 's concept of administrative reform, the test of adequacy may be
operationalized in the following question: is there a term, or another set of
attributes, which would better fulfill the eight tasks of concept formation in
this research design? If the answer is yes, then Geddes may be faulted; if no,
then her concept stands.
This process of concept evaluation would be aided if all writers were as
frank in setting forth the pros and cons of their own terms as Geddes has been.
Indeed, such transparency should be considered on par with norms of open-
ness in other facets of research--e.g., in making data available to other schol-
ars, in making clear possible biases in the data, and so forth. Writers have an
obligation to state explicitly why (on the basis of which criteria) certain prop-
erties and terms were chosen, or excluded. In the case of neologism, it should
392 What Makes a Concept Good?
Discussion
To many writers, the semantic confusion besetting the social sciences (as
described in the opening section of this paper) is not a signal to clean house,
but rather a signal that we ought to investigate the sources of these inner lin-
guistic tensions. Overlapping definitions, internal contradictions between def-
initional properties, and imprecise operationalizations (to name only a few of
the most common sins) are, in this view, (a) natural to ordinary language, (b)
ineradicable from social-science discourse, and perhaps (c) desirable. To such
writers the present study no doubt exudes a strong and unpleasant odor of
'positivism,' since I am proposing that there is a uniform set of criteria guid-
ing concept formation within the social sciences, and that among such crite-
ria are norms of operationalizability and classificatory utility. Indeed, even to
invoke the notion of social science is to suggest the applicability of a natural-
scientific model of endeavor. Since this is not really what I am proposing, it
seems worthwhile to explore some of the broader epistemological questions
that lie behind the claims of the present study.
With the first of the foregoing propositions (that many of our conceptual
failures are normal to ordinary language) I am in wholehearted agreement.
The second proposition, however, is more problematic. Before proceeding
further, I should emphasize what should already be apparent: I am not, in the
fashion of classicallogic, proposing the creation of a taxonomic social science
language in which "the meaning of a term lis] fixed by laying down a set of
necessary and sufficient conditions for its application," and in which each
term would be distinguished from neighboring terms by one defining attrib-
ute, such that aH concepts could be arrayed on a single hierarchical grid. 76 This
would require agreeing upon standard definitions and enforcing them-a for-
midable task, one imagines, and not one necessarily productive of good social
science work. Whether even the natural sciences actually operate in this fash-
ion may be debated. n In any case, the objects ofresearch in the social sciences
refuse to lie still in the manner of rocks, animals, cells, and atoms. If the social
sciences are scientific at all-and this, of course, hinges upon how one
chooses to define science-they are surely scientific in a very different way
than the natural sciences.
Yet, the unworkability of logical positivism should not obscure the fact
that there is still a great deal separating the language of social science from
natural language-as codified, let us say, in dictionaries of standard usage.
One may approach the specialness of social science as a matter of methods
and of objects of study; it is also, I would argue, a matter of concepts. Like
natural scientists, Mennonites, Republicans-like virtually any sub-group of
the general population-social scientists use specialized terms and definitions
(often specific to a field or subfield) and, conjointly, a specialized set of cri-
teria to guide the process of concept formation. We can debate the extent of
this specialness, asking to what degree a technicallprofessional vocabulary
may be justified. Indeed, from a broad epistemological angle, this is what the
present study seeks to establish: under what circumstances, and for what rea-
sons, social science should deviate from norms of ordinary usage.
76. Kaplan, Logic o/Inquiry, 68. See also Jevons, Principies o/Science, 73; Riggs, "Defin-
ilion of Concepts."
77. See, e.g., Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar, Laboratory Lije: The Social Construction o/
Scientific Facts (Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1979).