Title: The Capability Approach As An Approach To Development
Title: The Capability Approach As An Approach To Development
Title: The Capability Approach As An Approach To Development
Address:
Development Planning Unit
University College London
34 Tavistock Square.
London WC1H 9EZ
E-mail: [email protected]
Abstract:
Amartya Sen’s Capability Approach is increasingly becoming influential in the
development economics literature (Todaro, 2006). The multidimensional approach to
poverty analysis has led to a series of studies aiming at quantifying the different
dimensions of well-being and how policies can affect them. The Capability Approach
has also contributed to bring agency and empowerment to the crux of contemporary
development thinking and practice. International development agencies such as the
World Bank are encouraging the quest of applying econometric tools to measure such
concepts in a manner that can lead to the production of a series of international
indicators and comparisons. While the writings of Amartya Sen have contributed
many other disciplines, the Capability Approach has not yet been applied
comprehensively apart from the area of development economics. This article aims at
applying the Capability Approach in a manner that can contribute development
practitioners to plan, monitor and evaluate development projects. It is argued in this
paper that by doing so, existing approaches and tools such as sustainable livelihoods
and rights-based approach can be complemented in a variety of ways.
1- Introduction: The Limitations of Development Practices
Post-development analyses have pointed out that ‘development’ is the means to the
westernization of developing countries. Through the banner of helping the poor,
‘universal values’ and ideologies, which normally are associated to the development
of international capitalism, are imposed through subtle mechanism, such as the
governance programmes and poverty alleviation policies. Critiques have also stressed
how radical development alternatives are co-opted and appropriated to the application
of conformism and business as usual. Instead of changing situations of subordination
and oppression, concepts such as participation have been used in an instrumental
manner, reproducing such processes rather than challenging them.
The Capability Approach has been explored in a variety of ways in the literature. Sen
(1999) attributes the origins of the focus of ‘development as freedom’ to the early
motivations of economics. The extant literature acknowledges Sen’s attempt to break
from utilitarianism by expanding the informational basis for development, moving
from an income led definition of development to one based on multiple ends. This
paper hopes to contribute to this literature by elaborating on the process to apply the
Capability Approach to programming and evaluation of development practices.
Sen’s ideas have been taken on board by different academics who have developed his
concepts into a framework called the Capability Approach. The aim of these
academics is to develop a broad normative framework for the evaluation of individual
well-being and social arrangements (Alkire, 2002; Chiappero Martinetti, 2000; Clark,
2002; Jasek-Rysdahl, 2001; Naussbaum, 1988; Qizilbash, 1996; Robeyns, 2003; Sen,
1999). The core characteristic of the Capability Approach is to move away from the
income-led evaluation methods, and focus on the ability people have to achieve the
things they value. Therefore well-being can be measured by assessing people’s
freedom and choices, rather than their level of income or consumption. According to
Sen (1985) and then Clark (2002) focus on utility or resources can be misleading, as
what is essential to capture is not the amount of commodities, but what it does to
people. By focusing on people’s freedom Sen (1985) argues that the Capability
Approach acknowledges that people differ in their capacity of conversion of goods
into valuable achievements due to personal and locational factors and social
arrangements.
According to Sen (1992) and Alkire and Black (1994), the Capability Approach
broadens the informational space for making evaluative judgements by
acknowledging the multidimensional nature of human well-being. In the field of
development, many other approaches have been moving away from the income led
definition of poverty, by including people’s perception and accepting the multiple
facets of poverty, however Deneulin and Stewart (2002) argue that they miss the
philosophical justification for the objectives they put forward, which Sen has
elaborated as the Capability Approach. At the core of the approach is the concept that
“development is about providing conditions which facilitate people’s ability to lead
flourishing lives” (Deneulin and Stewart, 2002: 62).
Meanwhile capabilities are the freedoms people have to achieve the lifestyle they
have reason to value. Gore (1997) notes that while functionings refers to
achievements, capabilities refer to the opportunity set. Furthermore, Sen (1992)
argues that evaluation of well-being should be measured within the space of
capabilities and not functionings, thus evaluation should focus on opportunities and
not achievements. Sen (1992) illustrates the difference by using the example of a
person that starves as a result of fasting on the one hand and lack of access to food on
the other to explain the need to focus on choice. By focusing on functionings, both
persons would be at the same level of deprivation, therefore the focus on opportunity
would portray a more realistic vision of people’s ability to achieve the things they
value. Thus, Sen (1992) distinguishes between ‘doing x’ and ‘choosing to do x and
doing it’.
By accepting the role of conversion factors affecting the process of realizing the
things one values, the Capability Approach includes social and structural elements at
the evaluative process. Nevertheless many authors have criticized Sen’s writings for
being too individualistic. Sen refuses to accept the role of collective capabilities and,
by doing so, researchers argue that he is excluding group or collective freedoms
(Gore, 1997; Carter, 1999; Evans, 2002; Deneulin and Stewart, 2002). Gore (1997)
argues that the Capability Approach cannot be labelled as excessively individualistic
in any simple way. As well as agency and conversion factors, Sen identifies social
functionings (such as ‘taking part in the life of the community’, ‘communicating’,
‘being well-integrated in society’, and using Adam Smith’s famous example,
‘appearing in public without shame’). While being more inclusive in the space of
functionings to collective values, Sen is more bias towards individual values in the
space of capabilities. Gore (1997) argues that Sen’s approach is individualistic in the
sense that it measures well-being in terms of individuals’ ability, not recognising the
role of collective resources. Gore (1997) defends the concept of ‘irreducibly social
goods’ that are such goods that are objects of value which cannot be decomposed into
individual occurrences. In other words, there are capabilities that are properties of
societies or groups rather than individuals. Therefore Stewart (2005) and Ibrahim
(2006) propose the concepts of group and collective capabilities.
While not explicitly accepting the concept of collective capabilities, Sen (1992, 1993)
argues that the Capability Approach is deliberatively incomplete, as it does not
specify a list of valuable capabilities or functionings. Furthermore, he does not
provide any clear practical guidelines to practitioners or researchers on how to assess
or identify capabilities (Comin, 2001). Sugden (1993) criticizes this incompleteness
by arguing that the broadness, multidimensional and context dependent nature of the
approach prevents it from having practical and operational significance. Such
criticisms led authors to propose a list of capabilities with the objective to focus and
operationalize Sen’s approach. Nussbaum (2000) argues that it is necessary to identify
a list of “functional capabilities”. On the other hand, Qizilbash (2002) reacts to a list
compiled by Nussbaum by arguing that it is too complete thus vulnerable to criticism
as being too universal and not taking into account individual and cultural differences.
Meanwhile Finnis (1979) and Griffins (1996) put forward similar approaches that
reach middle ground between Sen and Nussbaum. They argue for an irreducible list of
elements that would be present at any functioning identified by individuals with
different preferences.
Sen responds to these criticisms by arguing that “an agreement on the usability of the
Capability Approach – an agreement on the nature of the ‘space’ of value-objects –
need not presuppose an agreement on how the valuational exercise may be
completed” (1993: 48). Sen (2005) also refuses to accept a fixed list of capabilities by
arguing:
The review of the capability approach of the previous section already indicates some
components and concepts of the Capability Approach that would need to be adapted
for the purpose of an approach to development. To become a radical development
alternative, the Capability Approach needs to address local and structural processes;
the conceptual framework needs clear components that can be operational for
development practitioners while remaining open and not imposing universal values;
and finally participation and qualitative information need to be incorporated in the
process of elaborating or evaluating policies and projects. To address such demands,
this paper proposes: a) a focus on the conversion factors, transforming resources into
achieved functionings; b) the incorporation of power relations analysis in such
process; c) mechanisms to include participatory methods to the application of the
capability approach.
Therefore, it is proposed here a slightly different take on the Capability Approach that
focuses on resources and their transformation into achieved functionings. These
resources can be tangible (such as schools, transport, houses) or intangible (such as
policies). The transformation of resources is affected by a series of conversion factors,
which varies from context to context, person to person. Instead of focusing in
capabilities, this application focuses on the capability space, which includes choice,
ability and opportunity people have to transform resources into achieved functionings.
Within the capability space it is included individual, local and structural factors.
Individual factors are associated to one’s individual capacities, which could be
physical conditions, levels of literacy and so forth. For example blindness and
illiteracy are individual factors influencing people’s abilities to transform newspapers
into increased awareness. Local factors can be associated to facilities and collective
norms. For example the provision of a football pitch in a neighbourhood does not
mean that children from that neighbourhood will have more space for leisure, as
adults might control the use of that facility and not allowing children to play there.
Last but not least there are the structural factors shaping the capability space. Market
mechanisms and the political structure are for example some of the underlying
structural processes impacting on people’s freedoms. Therefore in the application of
the capability approach to assess the well-being of small producers of milk in Uganda,
it is necessary to take into account the impact of subsidies for milk producers in the
developed world. If land regularization of informal settlements in developing
countries is the resource assessed through the capability approach, the structural
factors can be associated to the formal market forces entering such settlements due to
regularization, pushing the poorest out through the increase of property price. The
objective of highlighting these three levels of conversion factors is to clarify the
diverse issues that comprise the capability space. These three levels of conversion
factors are interconnected shaping and influencing each other.
This drive towards elaborating a framework in the field of development that can focus
on the process of making and realizing choices, incorporating diversity and
multiplicity while sustaining conceptual building blocks resonates with Ostrom’s
(2005) application of the Institutional Analysis and Development framework. Ostrom
(2005) elaborates on the Action Arena, which is the place where institutions,
communities, and rules operate affecting the process of making/realizing choices.
Nevertheless, the two approaches differ in the sense that one focus on well-being and
agency, while the other mainly on operations of institutions. To illustrate this take on
the Capability Approach, figure one analysis the process of transforming the resource
“bike” into functionings.
Figure 1: Capability Space
In this context, the framework is applied to measure the impact of a project that
provides bikes for residents of a squatter settlement. The functionings are the various
things people value, their dimensions of well-being, listed here as security, mobility,
income, leisure, inner-peace and health. The first component of the capability space is
choice. Do residents from that squatter settlement have the choice to choose another
type of transport if they wish, such as bus? Would they ride because of lack of
alternative or for choice? The next components of the capability space are the ability
and opportunity to use the bike. The individual factors relate for example to residents
physical conditions, some might have some sort of disability which might impede
them from using the bike. Local factors such as collective norms might also impact
the conversion of resources. For example in certain contexts women might not be
accepted to ride bikes, or in some neighbourhoods might not be safe to ride a bike.
Finally, structural factors also influence this process of conversion, as the security and
conditions of roads or the availability of cycle paths would also influence one’s
freedom to ride.
Such conversion factors are assessed here in relation not only to their impact to
enhancing mobility, but also to the other functionings. Such functionings can be
aspirations that are in the process of being achieved or potential aspirations, not
necessarily pursued. In the context of the bike, one might have the freedom to use the
bike for leisure, but might choose not to as this person chooses to use the bike merely
to transport goods and generate income. In this case, the bike is contributing to the
achievement of the functioning income, while leisure is a potential aspiration.
Functionings have intrinsic and instrumental value. In the context of the bike,
mobility is an end in itself, but it also means on the generate income or achieve inner-
peace. Nevertheless, the evaluative space is people’s choice, ability and opportunity to
use the bike to contribute to the achievement of the various functionings identified,
those being pursued or merely potential.
Agency and Power
Figure one also stresses the importance of two components underlying the capability
space and the identification of functionings: power and agency. As argued in the
previous section, agency is addressed by the capability approach literature as one of
the pillars of the investigation and expansion of freedom. The concept of agency is
directly related to relations of power. It is argued here that by incorporating power
relations into the capability approach, structural and collective norms are explicitly
incorporated in the process of evaluating or planning policies and development
projects.
Agency is normally associated with one’s ability to choose. Croker (2007) defined it
as a special type capability, which underpins the whole process of the capability
approach. The literature has stressed the importance of the concept of collective
agency, which is associated to groups’ ability to make claims (Ibrahim, 2006).
Meanwhile the concept of power has attracted many different definitions, from the
focus on encroachments of individuals, to the focus on structural mechanisms and
knowledge.
Eyben (2004) reviews this broad literature on power relations and provides a
comprehensive approach to link power and poverty reduction which resonates with
this application of the capability approach. Eyben (2004) identifies five main
perceptions of power that are useful for development practice: power to, power over,
power with, power as knowledge, power structure (see table 2).
Power Over Power over takes into account the relational components of
power. The three dimensions of power by Steven Lukes
(1974) elaborate on how power is exerted. Such literature has
been taken on board by the critics of participation, by
analysing how participatory processes of decision making
might be perpetuating power imbalances, rather than
challenging them (Cooke and Kothari, 2001).
Power With Power with “is a term that describes common ground among
different interest and the building of collective strength
through organization and the development of shared values
and strategies” (Eyben, 2004:22). Therefore here power is also
understood as a positive strength to the process of change. As
identified by Scott (1985), the subordinates have mechanism
of resistance and acquire power through collective action
Power as Knowledge Power as knowledge is based on the Foucault writings that
perceive the production of knowledge associated to the
production of power relations. Thus discourses are created and
reproduced through power and knowledge. Post development
critiques apply such analysis of power to argue that
approaches to development and tools are seen as means to the
perpetuation of existing discourses of domination.
While Eyben associates Amartya Sen’s writings merely with the conceptualization of
power as power to, it is argued here that for the assessment of the process of
transforming resources into functionings it is necessary to take into consideration the
five notions of power. If capabilities are perceived as capacities, than it is correct to
argue that the capability approach only addresses people’s power to achieve the things
they value. But as the capability space is compiled by the various things that influence
the conversion of resources into functionings, power over, power with and power
structure becomes fundamental components that need to be unpacked. Nevertheless,
Ibrahim and Alkire (2007) while acknowledging these various processes of power
influencing agency, they focus their measurement analysis on people’s abilities to act,
rather than the structural preconditions for agency.
Furthermore, power also shapes people’s ability to identify the things they value. This
process has been called by Sen (1999) “adaptive preferences”. Such a concept has a
direct link to the idea of “false consciousness”, which according to Lukes (1974)
impedes people from knowing their real interests. The Freirian pedagogical tradition
has then argued that people need to have access to knowledge to develop a critical
conscious and overcome such process of domination.
Therefore, this take on the capability approach incorporates power analysis to make
visible the various types of power that operate in the process of valuing and achieving
functionings. However, still withstanding is the operational question of how can the
capability approach be applied and which tools can be used to unpack the relations of
power operating in a certain context.
1) The shift from According to Cornwall and Nyamu-Musembi (2004) while the
needs to rights basic needs approach is about more resources, infrastructure
and services, the RBA focuses on the equitable distribution of
existing resources and expanding peoples’ access to them.
2) People as Agents The second common principle that links most of the
of Change applications of the RBA is the perception of people as partner
citizens in the development process, and not needed
beneficiaries (Slim, 2002)
3) Enhancing By specifying an internationally agreed set of values and
Accountability norms, the RBA is explicit about its principles thus enhancing
citizens’ ability to claim for their rights and hold states to
account for their duties.
4) Wresting One of the central objectives of the RBA is to reclaim
Participation and participation and empowerment from the neo-liberal
Empowerment instrumentalist appropriation.
5) Challenging As explained by Mander (2005), “the first distinct feature of
Power Inequalities rights-based approaches lies in the recognition of the structural
causes of people’s impoverishment, of the fact that their
condition is the outcome of the active denial of their rights and
entitlements by social, economic and political structures and
processes” (2005:239).
6) Policization of Through international legal mechanisms, enhancement of
Aid participation, improving judicial systems, supporting good
governance and reflecting on power inequalities the RBA re-
politicizes aid. According to O’Brian (2005), apparent
neutrality of aid is partisan and promotes particular political
actors. Through the RBA, politics assumes a central stage of
development assistance, as aid is guided by higher, consensual
or universal political values.
The Capability Approach and the RBA have similar normative principles of
development. According to both approaches, development ought to concentrate on the
expansion or protection of a certain set of agreed norms or values. Meanwhile, they
are also different in a variety of ways. While one talks about an international set of
agreed rights, and the other focuses on the identification of the things people value
doing and being, it is argued that a list of agreed norms should guide development
praxis. Also, the conceptualization of development as freedom and the protection of
rights diverge over the process of achieving common concerns and motivations
(UNDP, 2000). Firstly, as outlined by Sen (2005), the Capability Approach takes a
broader evaluative space by focusing on the opportunity aspect of freedom, while
human rights are concerned with securing the process of realizing freedoms. Thus,
while the human rights discourse is mostly concerned with protecting the political
processes of transforming choices into achievements, the Capability Approach also
incorporates the analysis of people’s choices and abilities.
On the other hand the rights-based commentators advocate that Sen’s writings have
expanded the rights-based approach and that they have been crucial in applying the
legal framework comprehensively in other spheres of development practice (Gready
and Ensor, 2005). Nevertheless, Sen (1999) has clearly stated the limitation of the
human rights approach by arguing that “…there is something a little simple-minded
about the entire conceptual structure that underlies the oratory on human rights”
(1999: 227). Therefore, talking about capabilities and functionings would be
broadening the spectrum of the RBA, allowing it to be applied in a variety of contexts
with different purposes.
Physical Capital (also known as produced or man-made capital) comprises the stock
of plant, equipment, infrastructure and other productive resources owned by
individuals, the business sector or the country itself.
Social Capital is defined as the rules, norms, obligations, reciprocity, and trust
embedded in social relations, social structures, and society’s institutional
arrangements, which enable its members to achieve their individual and community
objectives. Social capital is embedded in social institutions at the micro-institutional
level – communities and households – as well as referring to the rules and regulations
governing formalised institutions in the market-place, the political system, and civil
society.
Natural Capital includes the stocks of environmentally provided assets such as soil,
atmosphere, forests, minerals, water and wetlands. In rural communities the critical
productive asset for the poor is land; in urban areas it is land for shelter.
Source: Moser and Norton, 2001: 7
According to DFID (1999), the SLF is: 1) people-centred, as argued by Carney et al.
(1999), working with people “in a way that is congruent with their current livelihoods
strategies, social environment and ability to adapt” (1999:8); 2) holistic and dynamic,
drawing a universal approach that can adapt to different and changing contexts and
purposes; 3) building on strengths and existent potentials; 4) focusing on long term
sustainability by focusing on stresses, shocks and assets that will not undermine the
natural resource base (Carney, 1998). These components of the SLF are very similar
to Sen’s Capability Approach. The livelihood literature frequently employs the
language of ‘capabilities’ and openly states that it has incorporated some of Sen’s
concepts. However a closer comparison between the two approaches reveals
conceptual and practical differences.
On the other hand, exactly for being technical and focusing on five clear domains SLF
becomes an easier framework to apply than Sen’s capabilities approach. It is also
easier to link with other approaches such as the combinations with the rights-based
approach. In this way, SLF has a more specific and clear space within the field of
development discourses. Its limitations can be addressed in combination with other
approaches, thus becoming a strong tool for the process of implementing development
programmes and overcoming deprivations.
5- Conclusion
Nevertheless, not assessed here are the underlying limitations of producing and
implementing development alternatives. This article engages with frameworks, their
weaknesses and strengths, rather than the analysis of the structures within which such
frameworks operate. However, the Capability Approach proposes spaces to
incorporate such analysis in the process of development. By thinking in terms of
capability space, institutional arrangements are assessed as fundamental players in the
process of influencing people’s ability to achieve the things they value. Therefore it is
argued here that approaches to development can incorporate explicitly this reflexivity
of their role in the process of moving from rhetoric into transformation, without being
coerced, manipulated and co-opted into preconceived goals.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank the Department of Planning of Oxford Brookes for being
supportive throughout my PhD process. I would also like to thank the Foundation of
Urban and Regional Studies for the partial funding of my Ph.D. project, which
generated the information for this paper. Particular thanks are due to my Ph.D.
supervisor Roger Zetter for his continuous advice and support. Final thanks to David
Alexander Clark and Michael Walls for their comments.
Bibliography
Cooke, B. and Kothari, U. (eds.) (2001) Participation: The New Tyranny? London:
Zed Books.
Eyben, R. (2004) Linking Power and Poverty Reduction. In Alsop, R. (ed.) Power,
Rights, and Poverty: Concepts and Connections. Working meeting DFID-World
Bank. March 23-24, 2003.
http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTEMPOWERMENT/Resources/PPFinalText.pdf
Finnis, J. (1979) Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Frediani, A. A. (2007) ‘Amartya Sen, the World Bank, and the Redress of Urban
Poverty: A Brazilian Case Study’. Journal of Human Development, vol. 8, n. 1,
pp.133-152.
Gasper, D. (2002) ‘Is Sen’s Capability Approach an Adequate Basis for Considering
Human Development?’ Review of Political Economy, vol. 14, n. 4, pp. 435-461.
Gore, C. (1997) ‘Irreducible social goods and the informational basis of Amartya
Sen’s capability approach’. Journal of International Development, 9(2) pp.235-250.
Hasan, A., Patel, S., Satterthwaite, D. 2005 ‘How to Meet the Millennium
Development Goals (MDGs) in Urban Areas’. Environment and Urbanisation, vol 17
n. 1 pp 3-19.
Mander, H. (2005) ‘Rights as Struggle – Towards a More Just and Humane World’.
In Gready, P. and Ensor, J. (eds.) (2005) Reinventing Development? London: Zed
Books
Moser, C and A. Norton (2001) To Claim our Rights: livelihoods security, human
rights and sustainable development. London: ODI.
Patnaik, P. (1998) ‘Amartya Sen and the Theory of Public Action’. Economic and
Political Weekly, vol. 33, n. 45, pp. 2855-2859.
Pieterse, N. (2000) After post-development. Third World Quarterly, Vol 21, No 2, pp
175–191, 2000.
Scott, J. (1985) Weapons of the weak: Everyday forms of peasant resistance. London,
Yale University Press.
Sen, A. (1996) ‘On the Foundation of Welfare Economics: Utility, Capability and
Practical Reason’. In Farina et al (Eds.) Ethics, Rationality and Economic Behavior.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Slim, H. (2002) ‘A Response to Peter Uvin, Making Moral Low Ground: Rights as
the Struggle for Justice and the Abolition of Development. Praxis: The Fletcher
Journal of Development Studies, vol. 17, pp 1-5.
Smith A. [1759] 1976. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Stewart, F. (2005) Groups and Capabilities. Journal of Human Development. Vol 6,
N. 2, pp. 185-204.
Uvin, P. (2002) ‘On High Moral Ground: The incorporation of Human Rights by the
Development Enterprise’. Praxis: The Fletcher Journal of Development Studies, vol
17, pp 1-11.