Sharpe, Matthew - The Poetic Presentation of Philosophy - Leo Strauss On Plato's Symposium (2013)
Sharpe, Matthew - The Poetic Presentation of Philosophy - Leo Strauss On Plato's Symposium (2013)
Sharpe, Matthew - The Poetic Presentation of Philosophy - Leo Strauss On Plato's Symposium (2013)
Matthew Sharpe
Deakin University, Philosophy and Psychoanalytic Studies
Abstract This essay undertakes a close analysis of Leo Strauss’s remarkable but under-
treated Leo Strauss on Plato’s “Symposium,” reading it as opening a privileged purview
of his own (and his students’) wider understandings of philosophy, poetry, and politics.
The essay begins by drawing out Strauss’s three framing justifications for his manner of
reading the Symposium as a document in the “ancient quarrel” of philosophy and poetry
concerning which of the two should rightly shape the culture and ethical ideals of
the Greeks (part 1). Then, following the course of Plato’s Symposium, the essay ascends
through Strauss’s readings of the first five speeches in Plato’s dialogue (part 2) toward
the highlight of Strauss’s reading, namely, his three remarkable sessions on Socrates’s
speech. Part 3 analyses Strauss’s reading of this speech up to its climax, which Strauss
argues involves the philosophical “demotion of poetry”: a criticism of poets as moti-
vated by the Eros of fame and of tragic poetry as at its best creating captivating images
of gods and heroes which reflect their creators’ self-love and patriotic love of “one’s own,”
as against any transpolitical truth. Part 4 then looks at Strauss’s unusual reading of the
culmination of Socrates’s great speech (Diotima on the “higher mysteries”) alongside
Alkibiades’s speech in the Symposium as representing Plato’s “poetic presentation of
philosophy.” The essay becomes more critical as it proceeds. Strauss’s reading of the
Symposium, like his reading of the Republic, is remarkable for its own “demotion of
metaphysics” in Plato, and in my concluding remarks, I will question this status, or
disappearance, of metaphysics in Strauss’s Platonism. Strauss’s reading of the Sym-
posium, like his wider oeuvre, aims at a defense of philosophy as meaningfully different
from and superior to poetry. Yet he is unable to give coherence to the central idea of the
I would like to thank William Altman and Daniel Townsend for supporting, reading, and
commenting on earlier drafts of this paper.
Poetics Today 34:4 (Winter 2013) DOI 10.1215/03335372-2389596
q 2014 by Porter Institute for Poetics and Semiotics
Good (versus the Beautiful) in Platonic thought, which he agrees with other commen-
tators is decisive for Plato’s attempt to differentiate philosophical inquiry from poetic
creation. So readers of On Plato’s “Symposium” can be left wondering about how Strauss
can metaphilosophically ground his elevated claims on behalf of philosophy versus the
poets and to what extent his own work remains a decisively rhetorical or poetic pre-
sentation of philosophy.
In other words, this occasion is really a particularly important one. We are likely
to hear interesting things which are not said on every occasion if I can listen to a
symposium.
Leo Strauss, Leo Strauss on Plato’s “Symposium”
output,5 his reading of Plato’s Symposium indeed promises a kind of royal road
to interpreting and evaluating the strengths and limitations of Strauss’s (1983)
“Platonic political philosophy.”6
Yet for all that, Strauss’s On Plato’s “Symposium” has generated only a small
critical response outside of Seth Benardete’s (2001a) editorial introduction to
the volume.7 The essay that follows aims to redress this exegetical shortfall. Its
method is to undertake a close review of this undertreated text by Strauss in a
way that reads Strauss’s Symposium as opening a privileged purview of his own
(and his students’) wider understandings of philosophy, poetry, and politics.
As the essay proceeds, I will also highlight the contrasts between Strauss’s
interpretation of Plato’s dialogues and other (notably Neoplatonic) ways of
reading Plato.
The essay begins by drawing out Strauss’s three framing justifications for
his manner of reading the text as a document in the “ancient quarrel” (Plato
1997h: 607b) of philosophy and poetry concerning which of them should
rightly shape the culture and ethical ideals of the Greeks (part 1). Then,
following the course of Plato’s Symposium, the essay ascends through Strauss’s
readings of the first five speeches in Plato’s dialogue (part 2) toward the
highlight of Strauss’s commentary, his three remarkable chapters on Socra-
tes’s speech in the Platonic Symposium. Part 3 analyzes Strauss’s (2001: 244; cf.
238) reading of this speech up to what he presents as its climax, an alleged
“philosophic demotion of poetry” depicting its beautiful productions as
motivated by poets’ sublimated self-love and love of fame rather than the
suprapolitical search for wisdom. Part 4 then looks at Strauss’s (2001: 248)
unusual reading of the conclusion of Socrates’s great speech (Diotima on
the “higher mysteries”) and Alkibiades’s intervention as representing Plato’s
“poetic presentation of philosophy.”
The reader is forewarned that the essay becomes progressively more criti-
cal as it proceeds. Strauss’s reading of the Symposium, like his reading of the
Republic (Strauss 1964), is remarkable for what might be called the “demotion
of metaphysics” in Plato. In my concluding remarks, I will question Strauss’s
Symposium on this issue of the status, or disappearance, of metaphysics in
5. For recent treatments of the importance of the poetry/philosophy relation in Strauss, see
Janssens 2010 and O’Mahoney 2011. See also Bloom 1968, 1977; Drury 2005: 65 – 75; Janssens
2008: esp. “Epilogue”; Pangle 1983: 10 – 18, 2006: 45 – 56, 76 – 80; Smith 2007: 4, 7, 49, 123 – 25;
Zuckert 1996: 109 – 68, esp. 133ff.; Zuckert and Zuckert 2006: 45 – 58, 102, 129, 163.
6. This is not to say that Strauss’s work more widely has not influenced students to engage with
the Symposium. The reader can consult, for example, Benardete 2001b; Bloom 2001; Nichols
2004; Rosen 1999. These works, however, predate the publication of Strauss’s On Plato’s
“Symposium,” and many make convergent but different specific claims about the text.
7. But see Hemmenway 2003. Hyland 2003 is also a critical review. Cf. Gerson 2006; Reitsma
2006; and below.
Strauss’s Platonism. Strauss’s reading of the Symposium, like his wider oeuvre,
aims at a defense of philosophy as meaningfully different from and superior to
poetry as both an intellectual practice and a means of education and thinking.
Yet Strauss’s way of reading tends to draw us away from philosophical argu-
mentation toward the rhetorical or poetic framing of philosophical argu-
ments in the texts he examines, understanding this poetic presentation of
philosophy as justified by philosophers’ need for political caution in present-
ing their inquiries to the wider public. In On Plato’s “Symposium” Strauss is
unable to give a coherent account of the central Platonic idea of the Good
(versus the Beautiful), which he agrees with other commentators should
be decisive in differentiating philosophical inquiry from poetic creation.
Accordingly, the reader of On Plato’s “Symposium” is left wondering how
Strauss can metaphilosophically ground his elevated, seemingly “Platonic”
claims on behalf of philosophy versus the poets and to what extent his own
work remains a decisively rhetorical or poetic representation of philosophy.
state), we need to understand the place and limits of people’s political con-
cerns and obligations relative to other dimensions of human experience:
“One cannot understand the political without understanding somehow the
non-political” (Strauss 2001: 10).24 In particular, Strauss specifies, we need
to understand the relations of politics to those “sub-political” things (like
geographic or economic factors) that precede and ground peoples’ political
concerns and to those “supra-political things” that transcend but decisively
affect political concerns. The latter category includes the ethical or religious
ideals that people pursue through their political speeches and actions: free-
dom, empire, salvation. And it is here, among these “suprapolitical” factors,
that Platonic Eros belongs. For Plato and the other classical Greek philoso-
phers and Sophists — so Strauss (ibid.) argues in On Plato’s “Symposium” and in
Natural Right and History (1952) — it is first of all physis (roughly, nature) that
constitutes the reality or standard which “transcends the political in dignity
and which gives politics its guidance” (see also Strauss 1952: 88 – 97, 120 – 34).
Yet Strauss (2001: 10) hastens to add (albeit somewhat enigmatically): “It is
somehow the contention of Plato that the nature of man and, in a way, the
nature of the whole [of nature, the cosmos, all things], is eros.”
This relevance of Eros — as a natural, suprapolitical force affecting politi-
cal life — explains why Strauss (ibid.: 11) feels able to assure his students that
the Symposium’s subject, appearances notwithstanding, touches “the foun-
dation of the political — the natural. Somehow [sic ] this is strongly identified
with eros.” True, the Symposium is in one way “the most emphatically non-
political dialogue” in Plato’s oeuvre; this Strauss concedes to almost every
other reading of the text. After all, its direct subject, Eros, is “in essential
tension with the political element” (ibid.: 10). Yet at the same time Strauss
always contended that “Platonic political philosophy” centrally concerns this
very tension between politics and pursuits — including erotic pursuits, like
philosophy’s love of truth — whose aims are tangential to political proprieties
and concerns; and so the Symposium becomes for him a key to Plato’s political
thinking.25
This reference to philosophical or theoretical inquiry as decisively supra-
political brings us to the final and most important point highlighted in
Strauss’s opening remarks about the literary or poetic setting and action of
Plato’s Symposium. Alongside the philosophy/poetry querelle (quarrel), and the
nature of Eros, Strauss, like other commentators, sees the Symposium as prom-
24. I note that the “somehow” here is timely, otherwise the claim might license the relevance of
nearly anything for the understanding of nearly anything else.
25. At stake in Strauss’s reading of the dialogue, in any case, is what he terms the “suprapolit-
ical” end of politics, which at its highest for Strauss (2001: 91), as for Plato, is in some way (see
below) philosophy or theoria itself.
In this essay it will be impossible to do full justice to all the minute details
of Strauss’s On Plato’s “Symposium” : a consideration that might go some way
Poetics Today
Implicated in Implicated in scan- First accused of
scandal of 416 dal of 416 scandal of 416
Pupil of Hippias Pupil of Hippias Pupil of Euripides Pupil of Socrates
Weak drinker Weak drinker Weak drinker Strong drinker Strong drinker Strong drinker Strong drinker
Beloved of Lover of Aga- Lover of Phaedrus Beloved of no Most beautiful in Lover of Agathon, (former) lover of
Eryximachus thon one in the dia- body, beloved of beloved of Socrates Socrates and Aga-
logue — thus of Pausanius, Socrates, thon
Plato? (Strauss Alkibiades
2001: 254)
One-sided love One-sided love Love is mutual Love is mutual: Love is mutual, the Sum of bodily Eros, Love is love of self or
of older lovers defense of ped- bringer of peace to Eros for kalon, and “of one’s own”
for beloved erasty as highest, people and gods philosophical Eros (Strauss 2001: 282)
youths most manly love
Eros is sexual Eros is sexual Eros is cosmic: dis- Eros is human Eros more than sex- Eros beyond sexual Eros as bodily
(human only) (human only); tinction between only, although it ual in its products: only; beyond indi-
distinction noble versus base recalls the cos- makes the virtuous, viduals; points
between noble Eros becomes that mic, pre-Olym- peace toward “the Good”
and base Eros between healthy pian gods — Eros and/or Beauty
(body and soul) and unhealthy Eros is tragic
Within nomos Within nomos Eros is a natural Eros as protest Eros as love of kalon, Eros as desire for Disregard of law:
Published by Duke University Press
(law or conven- (no mention of force of attraction of against nomos the Beautiful sempiternal posses- paranomia
tion): satisfied nature) while opposites for har- and the Olympi- and/or noble; sum sion of the Good, to
with established wanting to mony — Empedo- an gods; aim at of all virtues give birth, or to
Sharpe
nomoi concern- change Athenian cles cosmic gods (cf. create by the
Poetics Today
ing love as a laws concerning Plato, Epinomis) inspiration provided
†
beloved pederasty: leans by Beauty
575
Poetics Today
toward explaining the widespread critical silence on this text. Strauss charac-
teristically mines the Platonic dialogue for nearly every imaginable point
of literary or poetic detail to bring out the complexity of Plato’s text, which
escapes other readers. This means observing the differences among the char-
acters of the ten speakers: their ages; their “softness” or “hardness,” based on
whether they drink alcohol; their erotic statuses, whether as lovers or beloved;
their philosophical, sophistic, or technical educations; whether their speeches
are “inspired” and, if so, by what muse or power. Strauss’s commentary also
involves a series of similarly precise contrasts drawn among the speeches of
the characters: in particular, whether Eros is a god; the age of the god; Eros’s
relations with the other gods; whether Eros the god always existed or was
generated by parents; whether the speaker mentions Eros’s cause or origin,
his nature, or his boons for human beings; whether the speaker treats love as
one-sided (Phaedrus and Pausanius) or mutual (Eryximachus and Aristoph-
anes), as an exclusively human thing (most strongly, Aristophanes), or as a
cosmic principle (Eryximachus and Socrates); whether he praises pederasty,
keeps silent about it, or opposes the practice; and the difference in the
particular virtues that the different speakers assign either to Eros’s benevo-
lence (for instance, Phaedrus identifies these virtues as manliness or cour-
age [andreia ] [ibid.: 48 – 49, 55], while Pausanius instead looks successively
to wisdom, freedom, and moral decency [ibid.: 79 – 80]) or to Eros himself
(ibid.: 181).
In Strauss’s hands, each of these details becomes what the structuralists call
a “signifier,” although Strauss would doubtlessly disapprove of the term. For
him, every Platonic statement takes on significance in its contrast with the
other possibilities instantiated, or not instantiated, elsewhere in the text. Each
of these contrasts thus contributes, however minutely, to the larger literary
or poetic meaning of the whole. As Strauss (ibid.: 5) underlines in his intro-
ductory remarks concerning his famous theme of “logographic necessity”
drawn from Plato’s Phaedrus (1997f ): “There is nothing superfluous, nothing
meaningless in a Platonic dialogue . . . we must consider everything in a
dialogue.”28
In the particular case of the Symposium, Strauss’s key hermeneutic claim is
that each of the speeches made by the characters other than Socrates is
intended by Plato as a partial account of the phenomenon of Eros. This
means that, while each is refuted by Socrates’s more complete account, it
28. On logographic necessity, see Strauss 1968: 120 – 21 and most famously Strauss 1988b:
22 – 37. See also Strauss 1964: 50 – 62 on the Platonic dialogues specifically; cf. Lampert 2009;
Smith 2007: 7 – 10, 37 – 40, 89 – 93.
and political laws, so for Strauss the tragedian Agathon gives an inspired
praise of Eros as animating the distinctly political desire for fame.30
Equally, Strauss’s reading of the Symposium suggests that a parallel ascent
between what each of the uninspired and inspired speeches proposes is cen-
tral to properly understanding and praising Eros. This ascent (indicated by
the vertical arrows in Table 2) passes from love of “me and mine,” what
Strauss calls “love of one’s own,”31 through the love of virtue, beauty, and
fame — Strauss sees them as associated by the Symposium, as we will see in part
3 — toward the more comprehensive visions of Eros Strauss perceives in
Eryximachus and Socrates, the doctor and the philosopher.32
30. See part 3.
31. As this expression is unusual, in what follows I will use it interchangeably with self-love,
although it embraces extended forms of self-love, including love for family, ancestors, one’s
fellow citizens, and one’s reputation or fame.
32. These three stages of erotic ascent seem to Strauss (2001: 10) directly comparable with the
three parts of the psyche about which we learn in the Republic book 4: epithymos (bodily desires,
centering on the self ), thymos (spiritedness, pride), logistikos (reason, rational reflection), in which
Eros, characteristically for that dialogue, is submerged within the lowest part, epithymia. Eros’s
invisibility in the Republic, Strauss (1964: 64 – 65; 1989a: 125 – 26, 155 – 56) thinks, is a constant
and important feature of it. In a full reading of Strauss’s (2001: 35, 95, 113 – 16, 148) text, it
would be important to note his idiosyncratic emphasis on the importance of Eryximachus,
whose uninspired speech tying love to medicine is often passed by. Eryximachus, the unerotic
doctor, presents a cosmological account of Eros heavily influenced by the very kind of pre-
Socratic physikos (nature) — namely, Empedocles — whose teachings the young Socrates had
been fascinated by (Phaedo [Plato 1997e], 97c – 100a; see Strauss 2001: 115 – 16). Strauss, his
own distinction between philosophy and political philosophy notwithstanding, asserts that
Eryximachus’s is perhaps the highest possible praise of Eros (Strauss 2001: 113) and that the
physician is “in a way, the most competent man” present (ibid.: 35). In line with this, Strauss
(ibid.: 180, 218) hesitates between assigning the most significant place in the Symposium, after
Socrates, to Aristophanes or to Eryximachus. Strauss (ibid.: 152 – 53, 258 – 59) also underlines
that Socrates praises how “beautifully” the physician has spoken: high praise indeed. The fact
that Eryximachus only speaks before Aristophanes after they change places, due to Aristopha-
nes’s hiccups, indicates for Strauss (ibid.: 95, 148) some deep, unspecified connection between
the speeches of the natural philosopher and the comic poet. By implication, Eryximachus’s
cosmological account of Eros as a force of attraction binding together all things anticipates, at
a physical level, what the Socratic Eros will depict at the higher level of the psyche and the
Platonic Ideas. However, when we look to Strauss’s analysis of Socrates’s speech for an argu-
ment establishing this elevated implication and actually delivering an account of Eros as such a
natural force, we are disappointed (see part 4).
33. The best account on Strauss’s and his students’ use of such abstract nouns ( politics, the city,
man, poetry, philosophy, ancients, moderns) and the issues associated with this use is Klosko 1986: 280.
34. Strauss (2001: 137) reads Aristophanes’s speech as positioning Eros as basically “a desire for
the ancient nature, for the state in which man had the loftiest thoughts, in which he thought of
conquering heaven, or rather Olympus.” Hence the Olympian gods, whom Strauss will associ-
ate with the civic virtues, oppose this Eros, or reshape it by dividing human beings. So most
humans at least become erotically concerned not with challenging the gods but with seeking
their other halves.
35. Strauss’s meaning that the polis is unnatural is unclear here: the context suggests that the
recourse to violence backing laws, necessitating individuals’ deferrals of satisfaction in the name
of maintaining political order, makes the city “unnatural.” There is a clear tension between
Strauss’s view here and the Aristotelian conception of humans as by nature political animals, in
a way that could be argued to challenge Strauss’s presentation of his work as a return to classical
political rationalism.
36. This harshness is, for example, at the center of Smith’s “Leo Strauss’ Platonic Liberalism” in
Reading Leo Strauss (2007). In fact, as Smith (ibid.: 98 – 100) alerts us, this essential harshness
or element of “compulsion” in “the political” is centrally present in Strauss’s reading of the
Republic in City and Man (Strauss 1964: 124ff.; see esp. 128: “Yet justice . . . is not intrinsically
attractive or choice-worthy for its own sake . . . it is not noble but necessary”). See also Strauss
1989a: esp. 115 on the “problematic” status of nomoi (laws) per se. It is revealing just how open
Strauss (2001: 85) is on this unsalutary set of claims in his commentary on the Symposium: “There
is a certain harshness which belongs essentially to political life, which shows the tension between
eros and political life.”
Table 3 The seven parts of Socrates’s speech (numbered on the left), matched to
the seven speeches of Symposium (with Strauss’s notation of parts I, II, III; subparts
A, B, C; and subsections 1, 2, 3)
(1) I Symposium 198b – 199c: introduction, Phaedrus’s speech [?]41
discussion of Socrates’s rhetoric (Strauss
2001: 174 – 78)
(2) II Symposium 198c – 201c: dialogue with Pausanius’s speech [?]
Agathon (Strauss 2001: 178 – 84)
(3 – 7) III Symposium 201c – 212c: the recounting of
Diotima’s speech to the young Socrates,
itself divided into three parts
(3) III.A Symposium 201c – 204c: Diotima’s myth of Eryximachus’s speech [?]:
Eros’s origins, where he is spoken of as a Eros as a cosmological
daimon, not a god, bearing messages force
between mortals and gods (Strauss 2001:
184 – 98)
(4) III.B Symposium 204c – 207a: central fourth section, Aristophanes’s speech:
Eros as desire for sempiternal possession of bodily Eros, search for
the Good, to “give birth in beauty” (Symp. one’s other half, as in
206b), primarily through bodily procreation sexual coupling
(Strauss 2001: 198 – 215)
III.C Symposium 207a – 212c: on the causes of Eros,
in three subsections
(5) III.C.1 Symposium 207a – 208b: Eros as desire for Agathon’s speech: Eros
immortality (sans the Good), physiological tied to desire for fame
(6) III.C.2 Symposium 208b – 209e: Eros as desire for Socrates’s own speech:
sempiternal possession of the Good through Eros tied to philosophy
the love of fame (Strauss 2001: 223 – 30)
account of Eros (ibid.: 216 – 23)
(7) III.C.3 Symposium 209e – 212c: highest erotic Alkibiades’s speech: Eros in
initiation (epoptika) of the philosopher, the general subordinated to an
two versions of the ladder of love, and the account of Socrates
vision of the Beautiful (Strauss 2001:
230 – 39) himself
praise a thing one should speak the truth (Symp. 198c – d; Strauss 2001:
175). However, as Strauss observes in Agathon’s favor, the demands of
praising a thing may run against those of telling the entire truth con-
cerning its nature or deeds unless the thing in question is morally or
41. Strauss does not himself dot all the I ’s about each of these parallels between the seven parts
of Socrates’s speech and the seven speeches in the dialogue. In Strauss’s (2001: 183) defense, he
presents the microcosm-macrocosm schema tentatively, “as a real question” to pursue, before
then using this scheme in all that follows. The question marks in square brackets indicate
cases where the parallels between the parts of Socrates’s speech and the paired speech in the
Symposium are not made explicit by Strauss.
intellectually perfect. In that case, one will select only the most beautiful
of the thing’s qualities or deeds and remain silent about its less edifying
aspects. And this is just what Socrates in fact says he will now do
regarding Eros (Symp. 185d), according to Strauss.
This difference between praising and telling the full truth allegedly
shapes the whole of Socrates’s speech as a speech of praise for Eros
(Symp. 198b – 212c). As such, it untruthfully “abstracts from” the lower,
more unseemly bodily or ugly side of Eros, which was highlighted
in Aristophanes’s depiction of love as the search for bodily reunion
with one’s lost “other half.” In its basest form, Strauss agrees, Eros in-
volves this bodily love and desire for possession. By contrast, the priest-
ess Diotima’s revelations to the younger Socrates concerning the
“mysteries” of Eros assert “unbelievably” that Eros, in its highest phil-
osophical form, transcends such egoistic, physical desires altogether
(Strauss 2001: 183, 213). In short, against most commentators on the
Symposium, Strauss (ibid.: 183) argues that we should beware of reading
Socrates’s culminating famous description of the “ladder of love” that
ascends toward a pure vision of the Beautiful as a truthful represen-
tation of either Eros or philosophy. Instead he interprets this speech as a
partial, merely “poetic presentation of philosophy” (ibid.: 248): a noble,
if not deceptive, praise of Eros and philosophy, which as such untruth-
fully “abstracts” from their less edifying or elevated aspects and will
need to be corrected.
b. Strauss claims that the central section of Socrates’s speech — according
to his sevenfold division, Symposium 204c – 207a (III.B in Table 3) — at
once points to the decisive importance of the Good as the aim of the
Platonic Eros but then fails to deliver anything like an adequate account
of this Good.
At Symposium 204c – 207a, Socrates recounts how Diotima instructed
him as a young man that love, truly conceived, involves the desire to
possess good things forever and “to give birth in beauty” (Symp. 206b).42
Given Strauss’s (2001: 47) idiosyncratic hermeneutic supposition that
“the most important in Plato is always in the centre” (see also Strauss
1988b: 22 – 37), his analysis of this section should point to what he sees as
42. In intriguing confirmation of Strauss’s hypothesis concerning the way the parts of Socrates’s
speech reflect the seven speeches of the dialogue as a whole, this fourth section of Socrates’s
speech is where Diotima — with remarkable divination — seems to refute Aristophanes’s speech
(to the effect that love is a search for the Good, not one’s “other half ”), the fourth in the
Symposium as a whole. Since the speech is at this point recollecting an exchange between
Socrates and the priestess twenty-five years before Agathon’s party, Strauss (2001: 203) dryly
comments that “we know better” than to think that Socrates is telling the whole truth here.
c. The third key claim emerges from Strauss’s analysis of the subsection of
Socrates’s great speech that he labels “III.C.2,” the imputed sixth part
of Socrates’s speech (Symp. 208b – 209e).44 Eros at its peak stimulates
mortals to produce great discourses concerning virtue (Symp. 209b – c).
Poetic works, like those of Homer or Hesiod (Symp. 209c), or the great
founding law codes left behind by Lycurgus or Solon are the creative
products of Eros in this sense (Symp. 209d). On this basis, Strauss argues,
this part of Socrates’s speech contains Plato’s fullest or most adequate
account of poetic creation and whatever fully considered criticisms of
poetry he has to offer.
Thus “poetry at its best generates political prudence, [and] edu-
cates great statesmen and legislators” (Strauss 2001: 229). While this
might sound a fairly elevated political calling, what it means for Strauss
is that poetic creation never transcends the political realm and so never
meets Plato’s requirement from a fully adequate or inspired erotic
practice, like philosophy. On one side, that of virtue, “the poets,
these wonderful men, produce a virtue which is not genuine virtue”:
it is rather, at best, “political prudence,” which Strauss (ibid.: 245), like
the Neoplatonists, sees as “a shadow of true [intellectual or philosoph-
ical] virtue.” On the other side, that of Eros, Strauss (ibid.: 169 – 70,
210 – 11, 223 – 30) more idiosyncratically claims that Plato has unveiled
for us at this point of the text — and in several passing observations in
Agathon’s speech — the underlying, baser motives behind the marvel-
lous beauties produced by the poets. The poets are essentially not moti-
vated by the noble love of Beauty that Agathon’s speech had extolled.
Instead, in unflattering contrast to the philosophers — animated by
their nominal love of the Good — the poets are driven by a love of fame
and, beneath it, by the same love of self that Aristophanes’s speech has
positioned at the heart of all Eros.
Good, Strauss (2001: 212) suggests that Plato chose to “abstract” from “love of the beautiful” —
the principal idea concerning Eros contributed by the tragedian Agathon — in order to “see
what comes out of it [such an abstraction].” (Then, Strauss claims, the component of love of
one’s own returns in III.C.1 [Symp. 207a – 208b], and love of the Beautiful returns in III.C.2
[Symp. 208b – 209e].) Given that the result of the alleged “abstraction” here is so unsatisfactory
and so distant from Plato’s claims about Eros elsewhere, the reader may doubt whether this
really was Plato’s intention.
44. As the allegedly sixth division of Socrates’s speech, Diotima’s remarks here are matched
in Strauss’s larger interpretive schema (table 3) to Socrates’s speech as a whole, the sixth of the
Symposium. So again, we are prompted by this formal consideration to consider Symposium
208b – 209e as crucial for understanding the dialogue. And indeed Strauss claims that this
part of Socrates’s speech contains the heart of Plato’s critique of poetry and the form of
Eros which inspires poetic creation.
cities. This explains why Strauss views tragedy as a higher art than comedy.
The tragedian
establishes the beautiful delusion, the salutary delusion [about the gods and he-
roes], which the comic poet destroys . . . tragic poetry enchants, comic poetry
disenchants. . . . There is a fragment of Heraclitus of which one cannot help think-
ing in this connection. There is one thing and only one thing which is wise, which
wishes and also does not wish to be called Zeus, i.e., to be seen in human form. It
wishes to be seen, to be called Zeus — tragedy; it does not wish to be called Zeus —
comedy. (Ibid.: 169 – 70)48
How, then, does Strauss regard this extremely elevated, albeit highly polit-
icized, view of tragic poetry as linked to Plato’s alleged demotion of poetry and
his assertion of philosophy’s superiority to it in political and pedagogic terms?
Strauss’s claim that the poets created the gods of the Greeks is already more
analogous to Epicurean and other materialist critiques of theological beliefs
48. For Strauss, this also explains the higher status and capacity of the tragedian, signaled at the
Symposium’s close. If the tragedian can poetically produce the Olympian gods, then he or she
must be disenchanted, since he or she does not believe in the gods’ independent existence or
eternity: he or she does not share the belief that plays no small part in explaining their “enchant-
ing” appearance to the many. But, Strauss then asserts, if he or she is disenchanted himself or
herself, then the tragedian must also be able to disenchant others.
49. Cf. Strauss 1989a: 171 – 83, esp. 179.
than to views standardly associated with Plato. Strauss (2001: 210 – 11, 217,
223 – 30) not only dethrones the gods from their Olympian heights, recon-
ceiving them as merely human creations, but also explains the particular
features of the Olympian gods by treating them as the sublimated projections
of the psyches of their all-too-human poetic creators (Symp. 208b – 209e).
Having done this, Strauss argues — all on the basis, he says, of a close reading
of the Symposium — we see that the poets’ motivating erota (desires) are far less
elevated or kalon than the beauty of their creations might first suggest and far
beneath the transcending dignity that Plato claims for philosophy.
To take up Diotima’s language, Strauss (2001: 159 – 60) agrees that the
tragic poets beget beautiful speeches concerning virtue and the gods out
of Eros of beauty. This human Eros of beauty (kalon) explains one aspect
of these Olympian deities as poetic creations: their undying physical beauty
and perfection (ibid.: 210). However, Strauss observes, these gods were not
simply beautiful: they had for the Greeks another, harsher side. As the ambi-
guity in the Greek term kalon (signaling both beautiful and noble) might
indicate, the other side of these deities involved their angry or law-preserving
functions as sponsors and protectors of the Greek cities’ fortunes, nomoi, and
customs (ibid.: 165, 209).
Which form of Eros might, then, psychologically explain the poets’ envis-
aging this avenging, law-preserving side of the Olympian gods? Only, in
Strauss’s opinion, the love of self or of “one’s own” — the baser side of Eros that
the speech made by the comic poet Aristophanes has hilariously emphasized.
Hence this passage, which recalls Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality
(1994): “The gods are created by love of the beautiful, on the one hand —
therefore they are eternally young and eternally beautiful — and by eros of
one’s own, on the other. Of one’s own, the descendant of one’s ancestor, the
Figure 1 Strauss’s erotic theogony explaining psychologically the poets’ creation of the
Olympian gods
deification of the ancestor, and on a higher level the gods of the polis who are
concerned with right, the avenging gods” (Strauss 2001: 109).
The desire to protect and promote one’s own family, tribe, or city — to be
honored as such a benefactor — can motivate the noble willingness to sacrifice
one’s own life, as Diotima indicates. This is the nobility and abiding value of
such extended self-love to the city and hence (for Strauss [ibid.: 86, 94]) its
connection to moral or civic, as against intellectual or philosophical, virtue
(see part 2). Such seemingly self-transcending nobility has indeed inspired
poetic works of such lasting beauty as Homer’s Iliad (1990) which consecrate
the words and deeds of heroes like Achilles, fired by the desire for immortal
fame. However, Strauss (2001: 209) emphasizes, patriotic or filial love — no
less than the desire for fame — remains an extended form of self-love or “love
of one’s own.” Moreover, in Agathon’s speech concerning Olympian gods
like Hephaestus, Athena, and Zeus — patron gods of the Greek poleis —
Strauss (ibid.: 164 – 66) sees Plato depicting these highest products of poetic
creativity as themselves moved by a desire for fame: to be “noteworthy and
brilliant” (Symp. 197a).50 These Olympians thus reflect their poetic creators’
wish to perpetuate their own selves or identities beyond the span of any mortal’s
life, in the lasting memory and good opinion of their fellow citizens.51 In this
way the poets’ gods embody a form of Eros more elevated than sexual desire
or the desire for biological procreation, but this form of Eros still both appeals
to and relies upon one’s own particular city and customs. Nothing more truly self-
transcendent, transpolitical, or philosophically elevated is involved (Strauss
2001: 217).52 Here we arrive at Strauss’s reasoning for the claim that the
Symposium involves the decisive demotion of poetry, albeit “infinitely more
polite” (2001: 244) than what which Plato puts in Socrates’s mouth in Republic
books 3 and 10.
In the Symposium as Strauss (ibid.: 169 – 70, 209 – 11) reads it, Plato fully
respects the elevated claims of poetry to educate the Greeks and engender
their highest gods, heroes, and ideals of conduct. Yet, Strauss claims, if we
50. Hephaestus’s limp, Strauss observes, shows that the view of the gods as born of a love of
Beauty needs some qualifications.
51. After all, immortal fame exists in the memory or recognition of people, as when the great
founding legislators that Diotima mentions were deified (Symp. 209e, which forms the end of
Strauss’s III.C.2 in his division of Diotima’s great speech).
52. Cf. also the following: “The gods have been created by eros and it is only another version
to say they have been created by the poets, or the poets were guided in eros in creating the
gods. . . . But what about love of one’s own? The love of one’s own leads to the polis. It leads first
to the family, and the family cannot exist without the polis. . . . The human race is sempiternal,
at least as is said here; the polis is not sempiternal, and it is, therefore, in need of gods. These
gods, as guardians of the polis, are primarily the guardians of right. They are avenging gods”
(Strauss 2001: 209).
read the dialogue closely — and his “close” reading involves a good measure
of his own interpretive creativity — we can see that Plato believes poetic
creation to remain deeply mired in self-love as opposed to philosophy and
its claimed (albeit so far unexplained) capacity to inspire some kind of Eros of
the Good and transpolitical truths concerning “the whole” (see part 4). At
most, the poets’ creations can educate the young to merely moral virtues,
which we saw in part 2 that Strauss (ibid.: 86, 94) wants somehow to rank
beneath the more elevated intellectual or philosophical virtues. Above all,
the gods that the poets sing about are their own creations, politically edifying
fictions, not discovered, transpolitical truths (ibid.: 169 – 70, 211). More pro-
saically, the poet-born gods of the city are the creations of the poets’ desire for worldly
fame: their shapes are elevated sublimations of their own ancestors and of their
own wish for bodily perfection and immortality (ibid.: 164 – 66, 217). Accord-
ingly, beneath all the beauty of the poets’ works, Strauss (ibid.: 245) argues,
Plato unveils an all-too-human love of self — and as such, an Eros which is for
him inescapably lower in dignity than the philosophical love of the Good, or
the truth, and of true virtue.
If Strauss (ibid.: 244) is right, then, the thrust of the Symposium as a whole is
“the demotion of poetry” within the context of its rivalry with philosophy.
It is now time to examine this thesis more critically and further inquire
whether Strauss’s own depiction of philosophy can sustain this “demotion”
of its ancient opponent.
If the demotion of poetry is the key meaning of the Symposium, then 208b –
209e (part III.C.2 of Socrates’s speech) must represent its pinnacle.53 The
remaining part of Socrates’s speech as Strauss divides it must in his eyes suffer
its own kind of “demotion,” since it comes after this Socratic pinnacle (III.C.3,
209e – 212c, in Table 3). But however intriguing such a hermeneutic claim
is — and, as I will suggest, however true it is to Strauss’s intention — it raises
deep problems, which I now want to bring out and weigh in the remains of
this essay. After all, the final part of Socrates’s speech involves Diotima’s
famous depiction of the ladder of Eros leading up from lower mysteries to the
highest philosophical initiation, a vision of absolute Beauty:54 “the beautiful
itself in its purity, cleansed and clean, unmixed, and not filled with human
flesh and colours and much other mortal nonsense” (Symp. 211d – e). For this
reason, whether readers have celebrated the resulting ideal of Platonic love as
pointing beyond individuals, bodies, and sexuality toward Beauty and truth
(Symp. 212a) or lamented that it renders Eros, philosophy, and the soul imper-
sonal, disembodied, and inhuman,55 nearly all interpretations of the dialogue
have taken this culmination of Diotima’s speech to be the highest metaphys-
ical moment in the dialogue,56 not to mention a canonical statement of Plato’s
deepest views on Eros and the goals of philosophy.57 Importantly for us, this
53. Referring to Strauss’s wider schema that relates the parts of Socrates’s specific speech and
the seven speeches of the Symposium itself (tabulated above), this subsection is the sixth part of
Socrates’s speech. It would thus supposedly mirror, in terms of significance, the lofty impor-
tance that commentators agree should be accorded to the speech of Socrates, Plato’s hero, as a
whole.
54. In the following text, Good, Beauty, and the Beautiful are used in the Platonic sense, to name
abstract metaphysical Ideas or Ideals, and will be capitalized.
55. Preeminently Nussbaum 1986 and Vlastos 1981.
56. For the classical statement of a position that celebrates the idea that love culminates in
wordless contemplation and holds this to be central to Platonic philosophy, see Plotinus’s (1952)
Enneads 1.6.7 with 3.5 and 5.8. For modern commentators, see Gerson 2006: 56 – 71; Shorey
1933: 196; and the Tübingen school works Kramer 1990: 10, 104 – 7, 178; Szlezak 1993: 87,
2012: 139. For modern commentators who accept that this is Plato’s highest view on love but
dispute its adequacy as a vision of Eros, see Martha Nussbaum (1986) and, more influentially,
Gregory Vlastos (1981). A recent collection on the interpretive debates about the Symposium is
Lesher et al. 2006, and Ferrari 1992 surveys the issues associated with interpreting Platonic love
in the text.
57. Several commentators have argued that, while Diotima’s speech should indeed be taken as a
truthful, if poetic, expression of Plato’s thought, it is not the vision of Beauty alone that renders
the philosopher blessed or immortal but the ability she or he is then said to gain to produce
images of virtue and convey them to others — which calls into question the immortality of the
individual soul, since the philosopher in this case assumes “immortality” in the memory of her
or his living pupils and the next generations (see Hackforth 1950; White 2004). Strauss’s
position, we will see presently, suggests that Diotima is not to be taken as a truthful represen-
tation of Plato’s real account of philosophy, so that there is no commitment to any account
of immortality beyond the immortality of fame. This contention has been argued by several
modern commentators, notably Jacques Lacan (1960 – 61), Harry Neumann (1965), and,
following Strauss, Stanley Rosen (1999) and before them Uleich Wilamowitz-Moellendoeff
(1920: 169 – 78). For a survey of the recent positions concerning Diotima, whether her speech
promotes personal immortality and on which basis (vision of Beauty or communication to
others of images of virtue), see Scott and Welton 2008: 253 – 54.
58. Compare Symposium 211d – 212a, the culmination of Diotima’s higher mysteries of Eros
(Symp. 210a), with 209d – e, the culmination of the lower mysteries, which lies in the begetting of
the works or “offspring” (ekgona, paidas) of the great poets and lawmakers.
59. Cf. esp. Nussbaum 1986.
60. Among other commentators, Strauss notes the dramatic significance in the Symposium of
the way that Alkibiades bursts in at the very moment that Aristophanes has raised his hand to
protest about Socrates’s speech (Symp. 212c). Alkibiades’s interruption of the natural philoso-
pher Hippias in Plato’s Protagoras (1997g) served in that dialogue, Strauss claims, to derail open
philosophical discussion of the Sophist’s philosophical claims. Just so, in the Symposium Strauss
suggests that we should take Alkibiades’s interruption as clearly meant to prevent us from taking
the higher account of love that Diotima has just been introducing as anything like a direct or
truthful account of philosophy and Eros.
61. I cannot unpack every detail of Strauss’s remarkable analysis here. For Strauss, as for
other commentators, the speech shows that Socrates surpassingly possesses the same virtues
that Diotima’s speech attributed to Eros himself: notably poverty or need — at base, the
need for wisdom — and endurance, although not justice, the political virtue par excellence
(Symp. 218a – b; cf. Strauss 2001: 269, 271, 283). For Strauss, notably, there are six stages in
Alkibiades’s attempted seduction of the philosopher, culminating in the frank, rejected offer of
Alkibiades’s body in exchange for Socrates’s knowledge. Given Strauss’s (2001: 273, 268) pre-
dilection for this kind of gematria, this might suggest that there is for him a parallel between
Alkibiades’s attempt at seduction and Socrates’s seven-part speech as a subtler form of seduc-
tion of the hearers or readers. Socrates famously rejects Alkibiades’s physical advances, leading
to Alkibiades’s affronted, noncomprehending allegation of Socrates’s hybris. Strauss (ibid.:
282), by contrast, accepts Alkibiades’s proposal as veridical: see my concluding remarks.
62. Note the first person pronoun, which Strauss suggests is important in reading great philos-
ophers. In the light of his analysis of the tragedians as “theōn poeitai ” (creators of the gods) above,
this cannot be an idle remark. For a modern comparison, oddly close in many ways to Strauss
on this and other points, including metaphysical agnosticism, see Lacan 1960 – 61. On Alki-
biades as raw material for the poets’ gods, Lacan (ibid.: XI, 13) makes the same kind of claim
about Alkibiades’s entrance, comparing it to the scandalous intrusions of these gods into human
affairs: “The ancient gods did not shilly-shally about it: they knew that they could only reveal
themselves to men on the rock of scandal, in the agalma of something which violates all the rules
as a pure manifestation of an essence which . . . remained completely hidden, the enigma of
which was completely behind, hence the demonic incarnation of their scandalous exploits.”
63. Recall part 3: poetry at its highest, in tragedy, can produce the kinds of Homeric or Hesiod-
like representations that shape political cultures; it can never transcend the political realm
entirely, in putative contrast to philosophy.
64. See note 57.
ascent in the Symposium (ibid.: 234). Moreover, as in City and Man, we are
told that Plato’s doctrine of the Ideas is “apparently fantastic” or “absolutely
absurd,” in definitive contrast to nearly all other readings of Plato, ancient,
medieval, or modern (ibid.: 199).73 These Ideas, Strauss (ibid.: 235) instead
claims, seemed to have had a self-evidence for the Greeks: witness the ready
ability of Glaucon and the others to understand them in the Republic (see also
Strauss 1964: 120 – 21). Strauss suggests that such understanding worked by
analogy to the Greeks’ beautiful statues, artistically representing general
principles like Victory or Wisdom or Courage.
But you can see the problem here. We are being told that the most august,
suprapolitical Platonic doctrine — the Ideas at the heart of the philosophical
search — are in effect so many more artistic or, remembering the operative
Greek sense of poiēsis here, poetic creations. If so, then Plato’s abiding excel-
lence for Strauss can only be as a kind of poet, not qualitatively different from
the begetters of edifying gods and mythoi that his Socrates defeats in the
contest of the Symposium. Indeed Strauss (2001: 135) says as much: “Therefore,
I can say that the ideas take the place of the gods and this is ultimately true.
The critical question which arises and is not necessarily critical of Plato, is: are the
ideas as ordinarily presented by Plato not also the products of the eros for
beauty, just as the gods are such products?” (my emphasis).
As for Strauss’s direct comments in On Plato’s “Symposium” concerning the
Good which I outlined in part 2 and which Strauss presents as demarcating
philosophy from poetry, these are even more skeptical, if possible, than
Strauss’s remarks on the Ideas.74 In the central part of the Socratic speech
(III.B, Symp. 204c – 207a), Strauss points out, the Good is raised as a subject
only in passing, while Socrates teaches how love desires to procreate in Beau-
ty. And here is all that Strauss (2001: 210 – 11) then tells us in all of On Plato’s
“Symposium” concerning the Good that should define philosophy’s difference
and superiority to poetry:
We have the element of immortality in the fact of sempiternal procreation. Where
do we find the fact of the good? It must be implied in there. Mere being. That
73. Strauss’s skepticism concerning the Ideas is clearly addressed and avowed in scholarship
on his work. For example, see Pangle 1989: vii – ix; Smith 2007: 100 – 103; Zuckert 1996: 154; cf.
also Robertson 1999.
74. On this subject and the relation of the Good to the Beautiful (kalon), the noble (also kalon),
the just, and the useful in Strauss’s Xenophon — wherein the reduction of good to a relative
adjective (“good for x, y” or even “useful for”) is suggested — see Strauss 1972: 44, 75, 85, esp. 76 –
77 and 119 – 20. Strauss’s (ibid.: 119 – 20) final comment on the decisive matter states that the
Good and the noble are the objects of practical reason ( phronēsis), not of philosophical sophia,
and the context (where the relation of the Good to the Beautiful has been raised) indeed suggests
that philosophy’s concern for “the beings” as “beings simply” places it beyond any concern with
the Good, as philosophy per se stands in tension with “the city.”
might be, and . . . this question will be taken up by Diotima in the next part of her
speech. And in this part, where the same phenomenon is discussed — procre-
ation — the good is dropped. Procreation supplies sempiternity. The good is out,
because mere being in the narrow sense is hardly good.
Concluding Remarks
So what positive lesson, if anything, can the reader derive from Strauss’s
On Plato’s “Symposium” about the decisively suprapolitical nature of philosophy,
above poetry and the cities, whose mythoi the poets create through love of
fame and of self? It seems to me that, by the end of the book, only one such
teaching has emerged. But it — like Alkibiades’s speech — concerns Socrates’s
specific nature and hybris, not philosophy itself and how it might transcend
poetry. Indeed like Alkibiades’s speech and Strauss’s deflations of both the
Good and Diotima’s ladder of love as “poetic presentations of philoso-
phy,” it unearths the apparently base element in philosophical Eros that
Diotima’s speech had “abstracted” from. In short — despite all of Alkibiades’s
clear motives as a disappointed lover for misrepresenting his master — Strauss
accepts Alkibiades’s claim that, beneath all Socrates’s rhetoric about the
pursuit of the truth or the Good, the philosopher is animated by a sublimated
form of self-love.
Recall that Alkibiades insists that he will speak only the truth in his speech
and that Socrates does not stop him. Alkibiades then asserts that, beneath
Socrates’s idiosyncrasies, there is a consuming need to be loved by his young
admirers: “He has done this to me, however, but also to Charmides the son of
Glaucon, Euthydemus the son of Diocles, and very many others, in deceiving
whom, as if he were a lover, he becomes rather the beloved instead of a lover”
(Symp. 222a – b). He resembles Agathon’s gods, embodying love of one’s self. It
is this depiction of Socrates’s hybris that Strauss (2001: 282) asks us to accept
as the definitive account of the Symposium’s grandest theme: the nature of
philosophy (see part 1): “[Socrates] brings others not to love the beautiful in
Socrates, but Socrates,” the man, himself. Not the least problem with this
reading is how, rather than clarifying Socrates’s putative difference qua phi-
losopher from the poets whom, Strauss says, are “demoted” by Plato exactly
for creating out of self-love and the Eros of fame, it completely annuls this
difference once more. The love of philosophy as embodied by Socrates does
not transcend the love of self. A prodigy of this self-love, Socrates is just the
better able to seduce through his, or Plato’s, poetic presentation of philos-
ophy to young men. The same measure that Plato applies to “demote” the
[sic ] there is something hidden there, but I have not been able to crack that
out.”
References
Altman, William
2010 “The Hindenburg Line of the Strauss Wars,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (1):
118 – 53.
Aristophanes
n.d. Clouds, translated by Ian Johnston, records.viu.ca/,johnstoi/aristophanes/clouds.htm
(accessed August 15, 2013).
1963 Frogs, Translated by W. B. Stanford (London: Macmillan).
1997 Assembly of Women. Translated by Robert Mayhew (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books).
2004 Thesmophoriazusae, edited with introduction and commentary by Colin Austin and
S. Douglas Olson (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Batnitzky, Leora
2006 Leo Strauss and Emmanuel Levinas (New York: Cambridge University Press).
Benardete, Seth
2001a “Foreword,” in Strauss 2001: vii – ix.
2001b “On Plato’s Symposium,” in Plato’s “Symposium,” translated by Seth Benardete with
commentaries by Allan Bloom and Seth Benardete, 179 – 99 (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press).
Bloom, Alan
1968 “Interpretive Essay,” in Plato’s “Republic,” translated by Alan Bloom, 305 – 436 (Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press).
1974 “Leo Strauss: September 20, 1899 – October 18, 1973,” Political Theory 2 (4): 372 – 92.
1977 “Response to Hall,” Political Theory 5 (3): 315 – 30.
2001 “The Ladder of Love,” in Plato’s “Symposium,” translated by Seth Benardete with
commentaries by Allan Bloom and Seth Benardete, 55 – 174 (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press).
Burnyeat, Miles
1985 “Sphinx without a Secret,” New York Review of Books, May 30, 30 – 6.
Deutsch, Kenneth, and John Albert Murley, eds.
1999 Leo Strauss, the Straussians, and the American Regime (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield).
Drury, Shadia
1987 “Leo Strauss’s Classic Natural Right Teaching,” Political Theory 15 (3): 299 – 315.
2005 The Political Ideas of Leo Strauss (New York: St. Martin’s).
2007 “Reply to Smith,” Political Theory 35: 73 – 4.
Ferrari, Giovanni
1992 “Plato’s Concept of Love,” in The Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by Richard Kraut,
248 – 66 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Germino, Dante
1991 “Blasphemy and Leo Strauss’s Machiavelli.” Special issue, “The Thought of Leo
Strauss,” Review of Politics 53 (1): 146 – 56.
Gerson, Lloyd
2006 “A Platonic Reading of Plato’s Symposium,” in Lesher et al. 2006: 47 – 71.
Gourevitch, Victor
1968 “Philosophy and Politics, II,” Review of Metaphysics 22 (2): 281 – 328.
Hackforth, R.
1950 “Immortality in Plato’s Symposium,” Classical Review 64 (2): 43 – 5.
Hadot, Pierre
1996 “The Figure of Socrates,” in Philosophy as a Way of Life, edited with an introduction by
A. Davidson, translated by Michael Chase, 149 – 78 (London: Blackwell).
Hemmenway, Scott R.
2003 Review of Strauss, Leo Strauss on Plato’s “Symposium” and Plato, Plato’s “Symposium” (new
edition translated by Seth Benardete, with commentary by Allan Bloom and Seth Benar-
dete), International Journal of the Classical Tradition 10 (1): 123 – 5.
Hyland, Drew A.
2003 “The Straussian Method” (Review of Strauss, Leo Strauss on Plato’s “Symposium”), greek
-works.com, February 3, www.greekworks.com/content/index.php/weblog/extended
/the_straussian_method.
Janssens, David
2008 Between Athens and Jerusalem: Philosophy, Prophecy, and Politics in Leo Strauss (Albany: State
University of New York Press).
2010 “The Philosopher’s Ancient Clothes: Leo Strauss on Philosophy and Poetry,” in Moder-
nity and What Has Been Lost: Considerations on the Legacy of Leo Strauss, edited by Pawel Armada,
and Arkadiusz Górnisiewicz, 53 – 71 (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s).
Klosko, George
1986 “The ‘Straussian’ Interpretation of Plato’s Republic,” History of Political Thought 7 (2):
275 – 93.
Kramer, Hans Joachin
1990 Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics (Albany: State University of New York Press).
Lacan, Jacques
1960 – 61 The Seminar of Jacques Lacan VIII: Transference. Translated by Cormac Gallagher
(London: Karnac).
Lampert, Laurence
1996 Leo Strauss and Nietzsche (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
2009 “Strauss’ Recovery of Esotericism,” in The Cambridge Companion to Leo Strauss, edited by
Stephen B. Smith, 63 – 92 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Lasswell, Harold
1986 [1930] Psychopathology and Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Lesher, James, Debra Nails, and Frisbee Sheffield, eds.
2006 Plato’s “Symposium”: Issues in Interpretation and Reception (Cambridge, MA: Center for
Hellenic Studies).
Meier, Heinrich
2002 “Why Political Philosophy?,” Review of Metaphysics 56 (2): 385 – 407.
2006 Leo Strauss and the Theologico-Political Problem (New York: Cambridge University Press).
Minowitz, Peter
2009 Straussophobia (Lanham, MD: Lexington).
Murley, John A.
2005 Leo Strauss and His Legacy (Lanham, MD: Lexington).
Neumann, Harry
1965 “Diotima’s Concept of Love,” American Journal of Philology 86 (1): 33 – 59.
Nichols, Mary
2004 “Socrates’ Contest with the Poets in Plato’s Symposium,” Political Theory 32 (2): 186 – 206.
Nietzsche, Friedrich
1994 On the Genealogy of Morality, edited by Keith Ansell-Pearson, translated by Caroline
Diethe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Norton, Anne
2004 Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).
Nussbaum, Martha
1986 “The Speech of Alcibiades: A Reading of the Symposium,” in The Fragility of Goodness,
165 – 99 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
O’Mahoney, Paul
2011 “Opposing Political Philosophy and Literature: Strauss’s Critique of Heidegger and
the Fate of the ‘Quarrel between Philosophy and Poetry,’ ” Theoria 58 (126): 73 – 96.
Pangle, Thomas
1983 “Introduction,” in Strauss 1983: 1 – 26.
1989 “Introduction,” in Strauss 1989b: vii – xxxvii.
2006 Leo Strauss: An Introduction to His Thought and Intellectual Legacy (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press).
Plato
1997a Apology. Translated by G. M. A Grube, in Plato: Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper,
17 – 36 (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing).
1997b Epinomis. Translated by Richard D. McKirahan, Jr., in Cooper, Plato: Complete Works,
1617 – 33.
1997c Gorgias. Translated by Donald J. Zeyl, in Cooper, Plato: Complete Works, 791 – 869.
1997d Parmenides. Translated by Mary Louise Gill and Paul Ryan in Cooper, Plato: Complete
Works, 359 – 97.
1997e Phaedo. Translated by G. M. A. Grube, in Cooper, Plato: Complete Works, 49 – 100.
1997f Phaedrus. Translated by Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff, in Cooper, Plato:
Complete Works, 507 – 56.
1997g Protagoras. Translated by Stanley Lombardo and Karen Bell, in Cooper, Plato: Complete
Works, 746 – 90.
1997h Republic. Translated by G. M. A Grube and C. D. C. Reeve, in Cooper, Plato: Complete
Works, 971 – 1223.
1997i Sophist. Translated by Nicholas P. White, in Cooper, Plato: Complete Works, 235 – 93.
1997j Symposium. Translated by Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff, in Cooper, Complete
Works, 457 – 505.
1997k Thaeatetus. Translated by M. J. Levett and Myles Burnyeat, in Cooper, Plato: Complete
Works, 157 – 234.
Plotinus
1952 Enneads, translated by Stephen MacKenna and B. S. Page (Chicago: Encylopaedia
Britannica).
Reitsma, Mark
2006 “Leo Strauss’ Postmodern Interpretation of Plato’s ‘Symposium’ 172a – 180b.” Thesis,
Dalhousie University.
Robertson, Neil
1999 “Leo Strauss’s Platonism,” Animus 4: 34 – 43, www2.swgc.mun.ca/animus/articles
/volume%204/roberts4.pdf.
Rosen, Stanley
1999 Plato’s “Symposium” (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s).
2003 Hermeneutics as Politics, 2nd ed. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).
Scott, Gary Alan, and William A. Welton
2008 Erotic Wisdom: Philosophy and Intermediacy in Plato’s “Symposium” (Albany: State University
of New York Press).
Sheppard, Eugene
2006 Leo Strauss and the Politics of Exile: The Making of a Political Philosopher (Waltham, MA:
Brandeis University Press).
Shorey, Paul
1933 What Plato Said (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Smith, Stephen
2007 Reading Leo Strauss (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Strauss, Leo
1952 Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
1964 “On Plato’s Republic,” in The City and Man, 50 – 138 (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press).
1968 Thoughts on Machiavelli (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
1970 Xenophon’s Socratic Discourses (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s).
1972 Xenophon’s Socrates (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s).
1983 Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
1988a “On Classical Political Philosophy,” in What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Essays,
78 – 94 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
1988b Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
1989a “The Problem of Socrates: Five Lectures,” in Strauss 1989b: 103 – 83.
1989b The Rebirth of Classical Rationalism, edited with an introduction by Thomas Pangle
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
2000 On Tyranny: Including the Strauss-Kojève Correspondence, edited by Victor Gourevich and
Michael S. Roth (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
2001 Leo Strauss on Plato’s “Symposium,” edited with foreword by Seth Benardete (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press).
Szlezak, Thomas A.
1993 Reading Plato (London: Routledge).
2012 “The Idea of the Good as Arche,” in The Other Plato: The Tübingen Interpretation of Plato’s
Inner-Academic Teachings, edited by Dmitri Nikulin, 121 – 42 (New York: State University of
New York Press).
Tanguay, Daniel
2007 Leo Strauss: An Intellectual Biography (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).
Tarcov, Nathan
2010 “Leo Strauss’ ‘On Classical Political Philosophy,’ ” Perspectives on Political Science 39 (2):
72 – 6.
Thucydides
1972 The History of the Peloponnesian War, translated by Rex Waener with introduction and
notes by M. I. Finley (London: Penguin).
Vlastos, Gregory
1981 “The Individual as Object of Love in Plato,” in Platonic Studies, 3 – 34 (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press).
White, F. C.
2004 “Virtue in Plato’s Symposium,” Classical Quarterly 54 (2): 366 – 78.
Wilamowitz-Moellendoeff, Uleich
1920 Platon (Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung).
Xenos, Nicholas
2008 Cloaked in Virtue (New York: Routledge).
Zuckert, Catherine
1996 Postmodern Platos (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Zuckert, Catherine, and Michael Zuckert
2006 The Truth about Leo Strauss (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).