Music Education - Navigating The Future
Music Education - Navigating The Future
Music Education - Navigating The Future
The future is a funny thing. Everyone would like to know it. But, no one
can. We can only deal with the present based on our knowledge of the
past and the projection of our vision of the future. We know that at this
point in the first part of the 21st Century information and technology are
driving the pace of change and discovery at an unprecedented rate. This
knowledge should affect the way that we as humans interact with the
world including how we engage with music, and more importantly the
teaching and learning of it. Music Education: Navigating the Future is
written by both (1) authors who were at the time of this publication
ambitious early career professors trying to earn tenure and receive promo-
tion, and (2) veteran scholars and researchers who have paved the way
for the present generation of leaders in music education. Through their
combined efforts the authors were able to well articulate what the profes-
sion now needs as it moves forward. The end result—the coming together
of past, present, and future—is a work that will be held in high regard by
the profession for years to come. Music Education features chapters on
music and leisure, new forms of media in music teaching and learning, the
role of technology in music learning, popular music tuition in the expan-
sion of curricular offerings, and the assessment of music education research.
As such, it is an excellent reference for scholars and teachers as well as a
guide to the future of the discipline.
1 Music Education
Navigating the Future
Edited by Clint Randles
Music Education
Navigating the Future
Typeset in Sabon
by Apex CoVantage, LLC
This book is dedicated to Bennett Reimer. Thank you, Professor
Reimer, for enriching our lives with your work in music and
words. Music education is better off as a result of your efforts.
This page intentionally left blank
Contents
Preface xi
Acknowledgements xiii
PART I
Working Within the Domain
History
1 Music Education History and the Future 3
MICHAEL L. MARK
Perspective
2 In Response to Michael Mark 13
BENNETT REIMER
Philosophy
3 Difference and Music Education 16
LAUREN KAPALKA RICHERME
Perspective
5 The Virtues of Philosophical Practice in Music Education 43
WAYNE BOWMAN
viii Contents
PART II
Making Sense of Our Tools
7 Inter/Trans/Multi/Cross/New Media(ting):
Navigating an Emerging Landscape of Digital Media
for Music Education 91
EVAN S. TOBIAS
Perspective
9 The Technology-Music Dance: Reflections on
Making Sense of Our Tools 139
DAVID BRIAN WILLIAMS
PART III
Visualizing Expansion
Popular Music
12 Seeking “Success” in Popular Music 183
GARETH DYLAN SMITH
Contents ix
Early Childhood
13 “Pssst . . . Over Here!” Young Children Shaping the
Future of Music Education 201
ALISON M. REYNOLDS, KERRY B. RENZONI, PAMELA L. TUROWSKI,
AND HEATHER D. WATERS
Teacher Education
14 Identity and Transformation: (Re)Claiming
an Inner Musician 215
KAREN SALVADOR
PART IV
Guiding Researchers
Research Snapshot
15 Methodological Trends in Music Education Research 235
MICHAEL S. ZELENAK
Qualitative Approaches
16 Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis: A Pathway
for Music Education 253
MARISSA SILVERMAN
Perspective
18 Commentary on Research Snapshot
and Qualitative Approaches 292
RICHARD COLWELL
Quantitative Approaches
19 Structural Equation Modeling and Multilevel Modeling
in Music Education: Advancing Quantitative Research
Data Analysis 299
NICHOLAS STEFANIC
x Contents
Perspective
20 Reflecting on Guiding Researchers 314
PETER R. WEBSTER
PART V
Plotting a Course of Action
Conceptualizing Change
21 A Theory of Change in Music Education 323
CLINT RANDLES
Perspective
22 The Role of Subversion in Changing Music Education 340
JOHN KRATUS
It’s the end of the world as we know it, and I feel fine.
REM
The future is a funny thing. Everyone would like to know it. But of course
no one can. We can only, as Eisner states, deal with the present. We know
that at this point in the first part of the 21st century, information and
technology are driving the pace of change and discovery at an unprece-
dented rate. This knowledge should affect the way that we as humans
interact with the world, including how we engage with music and music
education. Technology is not in the driver’s seat, though; we are. We choose
how we will act based on our goals and values as human beings. Of course,
we have a history of how we have behaved and performed in the past to
guide our theory and practice. This book is about bringing together voices
of experience with some of the voices who will play a role in steering the
ship—Music Education—as it moves into the future.
Few things that are worth our considerable time are easy. This project
was no exception. The Suncoast Music Education Research Symposium
IX (which I chaired), with the title Navigating the Future, is where the
idea for this book started. The event was held at the University of South
Florida in February of 2013. It brought together many of the scholars
that have written for this text. In fact, many of the chapters were first
projects that were accepted for presentation at the symposium. That being
said, this collection of chapters is not a conference proceedings. The work
took on a much larger form when I invited many scholars and research-
ers from around North America to read, respond, critique, comment, and
sometimes provide entirely new insights on the topics that surround the
initial chapters.
xii Preface
RISING STARS
Many of the chapter writers were at the time of this publication ambitious
assistant professors trying to earn tenure and receive promotion. However,
all of them had spoken at many of the premier national and international
conferences in music education. They were chosen to be a part of this
project as I felt they represented some of the most promising newer voices
in the profession. Of course no one can ever be sure of these things.
Hopefully time has been kind to my earlier predictions.
EXPERIENCED VOICES
Figures like Richard Colwell and Bennett Reimer have been around in the
field of music education for the better part of 50 years. They can speak
well about what the profession needs as it moves forward. What better
writers for their respective sections? There was not a template for what
each of the experienced authors’ perspectives were supposed to look like.
I left the decision for what each section needed up to the writers. This
ambiguity going into the writing stage has resulted in a very unique book,
one that we hope will be useful to the profession as it represents the desires
and intuition of not one younger voice or even many younger voices, but
that of younger and more experienced voices working as one.
COMING TOGETHER
The most striking quality of this book is the juxtaposition of newer gen-
eration thinkers and older generation thinkers laboring side by side to
conceptualize the future of the profession. It is no small feat to gather such
a diverse group of writers. Throughout the project there was a common
bond that united all—the belief that the very best manifestations of music
and music education should and must survive and thrive in the lives of
the citizens of the world. I am pleased with the resulting product. The
work that we have accomplished here will benefit generations of music
educators to come and will serve as a time capsule for this point in the
history of the profession.
Clint Randles
Tampa, Florida, 2014
Acknowledgements
A warm thank you to my colleagues and members of the Center for Music
Education Research at the University of South Florida for their support of
this work. Most of all I would like to thank Jack Heller for fighting with
me during this my first four years in higher education. You have made me
stronger my friend. As long as I am living and working in music education
I will remember our time together fondly. The world needs more scrappy
old academics to hone the younger generation. (I’m smiling as I write this,
Jack.) Together, we represent the DNA of this book—the coming together
of groups of minds for the good of the whole. I hope that some day I can
do for someone else what you have done for me.
I would also like to thank my graduate and undergraduate students here
at USF for inspiring me to work diligently on projects that have the poten-
tial to make music and music education better for future generations of
students. It makes all of this work worthwhile when I think that these
ideas will be in the hands of such wonderful musicians and teachers who
will help change the music education world for the better. You have made
it a joy to get up every morning. I wish all the best for you in all of your
future endeavors. Know that you will always have a special place in my
heart.
This page intentionally left blank
Part I
INTRODUCTION
This chapter describes four historic rationales that supported music educa-
tion during certain periods of American history and how they were made a
real part of American life. Taken together, they describe a history of success
for music education in a changing world. The four rationales illustrate how
music education has adjusted to social, political, and economic change and
how it became an integral part of those contexts. This brief review of the
role of music education in American life shows that it has historically been
tied closely to the greater society, and that music teachers have been valued
since the early times of our nation.
As times changed, so did music education. But some things do not
change because they are right and because they work. An instructive
example of something that has not changed throughout Western history is
the contribution that music education has always made to the society that
sponsors it. Another example is the joy of learning and making music in
school settings. Music has existed in schools throughout Western history,
often for religious purposes, at other times for a variety of other cultural
reasons.1 These are historic truths that music educators might convey to
administrators and other decision makers who influence the role of music
in schools.
A simple, basic principle that is probably known to most music educa-
tors expresses what it is that has made music education so successful for
so long: education follows society. Society establishes new needs and new
goals and music education adjusts. We, the music educators, lead from the
rear, not the front, and this is how it has to be. It is why certain important
planning symposia have been held periodically. For example, the primary
purpose of the influential 1967 Tanglewood Symposium was to identify
the role of music education in a society already undergoing such rapid
change that it was no longer possible to predict needs beyond the next few
years. A character in the novel Gone Girl (Flynn, 2012, p. 9) said it well:
“We had no clue that we were embarking on careers that would vanish within
4 Michael L. Mark
a decade.” And the speed of societal change becomes faster and faster to
this day.
The four rationales are derived from the principle that education follows
society. They serve as a backdrop for a look at the broad scope of American
history during the last 175 years. These are the rationales:
The narratives that follow illustrate how music education has supported
national goals and even helped further them at times. Each rationale had impli-
cations for classroom practices. They influenced the day-to-day work of music
educators in one way or another. These four rationales—cultural elevation,
cohesive society, commercial prosperity, social justice—are points of reference
for a look at the broad scope of American history during the last 175 years.
Each rationale had a place in American history and each had a role in shaping
music education.
Music Education History and the Future 5
THE FOUR RATIONALES IN AMERICAN LIFE
• America
• Annie Laurie
• Auld Lang Syne
• Blow, Ye Winds, Heigh-Ho
• Dixie
• Drink to Me Only with Thine Eyes
• Flow Gently, Sweet Afton
• Home, Sweet Home
• How Can I Leave Thee
• Love’s Old Sweet Song
• My Old Kentucky Home
• Nancy Lee
• Old Folks at Home
• Round: Row, Row, Row Your Boat
• Round: Lovely Evening
• Star Spangled Banner
• Sweet and Low
• The Minstrel Boy
AN ERA OF REFORM
Knowledge of the three critical periods in American history and the story
of school bands could assist in the professional planning process and in
advocacy efforts. Music educators involved in these activities might build
a knowledge base of how music education has served the United States for
almost two centuries. Realistically, however, one must ask, “Do planners
really take long ago events into account?” Probably not, but, historical prec-
edents do exist. They are an important part of American history and music
educators should know their own professional history, just as all Americans
should know American history. It helps us understand how things came to
be as they are now, and it is a source of professional and national pride.
Despite the many historic and current complications associated with declin-
ing budgets and ever-changing curricula, school music has contributed to
American culture for close to two hundred years. Recognizing the profes-
sion’s vibrancy, vision, and vitality, it would be unrealistic to deny its influ-
ence on American life beyond the walls of academia.
It is especially important for music educators to keep in mind that while
their work is shaped by events beyond the schools, they themselves exert
their own cultural influences outward to society. Cultural elevation, societal
cohesiveness, commercial prosperity, social justice—these are all important
aspects of a society that depends in substantial, meaningful ways on the
music education profession. Because music education benefits the individ-
ual, the school, the community, and the nation, music educators have a wide
range of opportunities to examine relationships between societal need and
music education.
We hope that future generations of music educators will take the time
to understand our era and its social, economic, and political contexts so
that we will help them as they plan for their future. We hope that they will
look back and affirm that we, the first new generation of music educators
of the 21st century, advanced both our profession and American society in
meaningful ways.
12 Michael L. Mark
NOTES
1. See Mark, Music education: Source readings from ancient Greece to today, 2013.
2. Although the Court decided that school segregation was illegal, it did not
require them to be integrated. This has been the cause of much confusion and
dissension since that decision was handed down.
REFERENCES
NOTES
Do you recall the worksheets for children that ask them to distinguish
between similar and different objects? For example, one might include a
row of three apples and one banana preceded by the question, “Which one
is different?” Children learn early on to identify similarities and differences.
In fact, for thousands of years, such distinctions have enabled humans to
survive, doing everything from recognizing edible plants to finding their
way back to shelter. At first glance, difference seems like a straightforward
concept, and the statement “we need to think differently about music educa-
tion” appears simplistic and obvious.
Yet, with the advent of supermarkets, GPS systems, and smart phones,
humans may find themselves spending only minimal time and energy recog-
nizing differences between items and places. In a world of replication, rapid
growth, and ongoing change, perhaps there might exist alternative ways of
understanding difference. For example, perhaps one could focus on how the
apples on the worksheet differ from each other and from themselves over
time.
In order to examine the concept of difference, I begin by analyzing how
Western philosophers commonly understand difference. Next, I investigate
how the twentieth-century French philosophers Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari posit an alternative conception of difference. Third, I show how
Deleuze and Guattari’s philosophical figuration of a body without organs
adds nuance to Western philosophers’ writings about difference. Lastly, I
draw on Deleuze and Guattari’s emphasis on continual difference rather
than discrete differences to posit the possibilities of examining to the ques-
tions “When is music?” and “When is education?”
Before explaining how one might conceive of difference in a new way, I will
first examine how humans have traditionally articulated the concept of dif-
ference. The concept of difference implicit in a children’s similar/different
worksheet actually dates back a couple of millennia. Exploring how humans
Difference and Music Education 17
conceive of difference involves investigating our explicit or implicit under-
standings about the nature of human perception. In The Republic, Plato
(1973) conceives of worldly objects and qualities, such as love and good-
ness, mimicking what he termed Forms, or archetypes or essences, of those
objects and qualities. In other words, people perceive a fellow human as
“good” by comparing her to an ideal Form or archetype of “goodness.”
Using Socratic dialogue, Plato articulates the notion of absolute beauty,
writing:
Then those who see the many beautiful, and who yet neither see abso-
lute beauty, nor can follow any guide who points the way thither; who
see the many just, and not absolute justice, and the like,—such persons
may be said to have opinion but not knowledge? . . . But those who see
the absolute and eternal and immutable may be said to know, and not
to have opinion only?
(p. 173)
This conception results in a dualism between the world of Forms and the
world of perception; beauty exists in the world of perception, but “absolute
beauty” exists only in the world of Forms. Although apples exist in a seem-
ingly endless number of variations, Plato asserted the existence of a single
ideal Form of an apple that transcends time and space and that all apples
mimic. These ideal Forms allow humans to distinguish between everything
from apples and cookies to goodness and justice.
While Western philosophers such as Aristotle have critiqued Plato’s divi-
sion between perception and Forms,1 a conception of existence based on
similarity and stability continued to dominate Western philosophy for hun-
dreds of years. For example, in Critique of Pure Reason, Kant (1781/2007)
espouses a philosophy based on similarity and stability rather than differ-
ence and fluctuation. Describing his principle of the unity of apperception,2
Kant states:
There are not, therefore, two kinds of languages but two possible treat-
ments of the same language. Either the variables are treated in such a
way as to extract from them constants and constant relations or in such
a way as to place them in continuous variation.
(p. 103)
but in more or less ‘contracted’ state” (pp. 145–6). Figure 3.1 visualizes Berg-
son’s cone for a fifteen-year-old person, with the cone’s point representing
the present. At each passing present moment, illustrated by the continually
moving point of the cone, a person’s entire past exists and grows as the cone’s
point moves forward in time. For example, when a person reaches fifteen
years of age, she experiences each minute of her fifteenth birthday as both the
present moment and as a compressed version of every moment from the past
fifteen years. The present and the past exist concurrently.
According to Deleuze and Guattari (1991/1994), the past does not exist
exactly like the present but rather as “virtual.” They explain the “virtual”
as the chaos “containing all particles and drawing out all possible forms,
which spring up only to disappear immediately,” elaborating that the “vir-
tual” denotes not only the past but also the future that actualizes in the
present (p. 118). Each passing moment consists of the present as well as the
“virtual” past and future. Similarly, in his chapter, Talbot uses the cultural
mechanism of prolepsis to offer a detailed explication of how music educa-
tors draw on their own pasts in order to project futures onto students.
We cannot choose what parts of our past and future influence our present
thoughts and actions. A teacher’s early exposure to everything from artistic
activities to reading inevitably affects her current engagement with music
education. Our entire history and future resides in every new moment. Such
a conception of time contrasts the notion that time exists purely linearly and
that each present moment relates little to others.
So how does this conception of time relate to difference? In short, May
(2003) asserts that for Deleuze, difference comprises time’s essence: “The
content of time, since it cannot come in the form of identities or samenesses,
must be difference” (p. 146). Since the past constitutes an integral part of
the present, even repeated actions occur differently each time. For instance,
my performance of a B flat scale is never the same; each time I repeat it, I
actualize every prior experience of that scale, as well as the entirety of my
past and future, in the present moment. I therefore experience the scale
as a singularity with each repetition. Time not only enables difference, it
demands it. Returning to the example of the saxophone, equating time with
difference necessitates acknowledging that the saxophone changes with each
passing moment. The saxophone differs not only from other instruments
Difference and Music Education 21
and objects, but also continually differs from itself. Likewise, the student
perceiving the saxophone perpetually alters along with his or her evolving
observations and experiences.
While philosophers such as Plato and Kant posit an ontology of existence
based on sameness, Deleuze and Guattari (1980/1987) assert an ontology of
existence based on difference. As May (2005) explains, Deleuze inverts the
traditional relationship between identity and difference, writing, “It’s not
identity that captures what things are; it’s difference that does it” (p. 81).
Rather than centering the stability of people, objects, practices, and ideas
over time, Deleuze and Guattari challenge readers to seek out the diverse
chaos that constitutes existence.
Imagine if we approached the National Music Standards through Deleuze
and Guattari’s (1980/1987) ontology of existence. While Deleuze and Guat-
tari’s philosophy does not contradict the notion of exploring “a varied rep-
ertoire of music” (Consortium, 1994), teachers drawing on their writing
might emphasize how each piece or musical endeavor changes from moment
to moment and day to day. For example, within such a framework, music
educators might exert less energy contemplating how “Ode to Joy” or “Sing,
Sing, Sing” matched prior renditions of those pieces and instead focus on
how they differed from previous articulations and from themselves over
time. They would abandon aiming for “ideal” musical experiences, instead
seeking out diverse ones. Rather than differentiating between categories of
practices such as composing or listening, music educators seeking qualita-
tive difference could ask how they and their students could engage in such
endeavors differently. They would view standards and curricula as continu-
ally evolving and foreground the temporal processes of singing, performing
on instruments, improvising, composing, reading notation, listening, and
evaluating, emphasizing their integration and variability over time.
Understanding Deleuze and Guattari’s conception of a world constitu-
tive of difference means envisioning existence as ongoing motion rather
than stability. As Colebrook (2002) writes, “Deleuze insists that we need to
begin from a mobility, flux, becoming or change that has no underlying
foundation” (p. 52). May (2005) echoes this notion, explaining that for
Deleuze, “Difference is not a thing, it is a process. It unfolds—or better, it is
an unfolding (and a folding, and a refolding). It is alive” (p. 24). Difference
exists as constant movement, resisting all efforts to grasp, limit, or define it.
Deleuze and Guattari (1980/1987) emphasize the temporal, changing nature
of an existence composed of difference.
The body without organs contrasts concepts and principles, such as Kant’s
unity of apperception, that define humans as stable and stagnant beings. The
images of walking on your head or singing with your sinuses challenges the
notion that organs and bodies serve single purposes and prompt alterna-
tive thinking about default assumptions regarding our ways of being in the
world.
Difference and Music Education 23
It is important to note that the body without organs is a philosophical
figuration and not a metaphor. St. Pierre (1997) distinguishes between philo-
sophical figurations and metaphors, asserting:
A SHORT ANECDOTE
NOTES
REFERENCES
Colebrook, C. (2002). Understanding Deleuze. Crows Nest, NSW, Australia: Allen &
Unwin.
Consortium of National Arts Education Associations. (1994). National standards
for arts education. Reston, VA: Music Educators National Conference.
Deleuze, G. (1995). Negotiations: 1972–1990. (M. Joughlin, Trans.). New York,
NY: Columbia University Press. (Original work published 1990)
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophre-
nia. (B. Massumi, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. (Original
work published 1980)
Deleuze, G., & Guattari F. (1994). What is philosophy? (H. Tomlinson & G. Burchell,
Trans.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press. (Original work published
1991)
Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. New York, NY: Minton, Balch & Company.
Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of world making. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing
Company.
Hozer, M., & Raymont, P. (2010). Genius within: The inner life of Glenn Gould. In
S. Lacy (Executive producer), American masters. Toronto, Canada: White Pine
Pictures.
Kant, I. (1997). Critique of pure reason (2nd Ed.). (P. Guyer & A. Wood, Trans.).
New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1781)
May, T. (2003). When is Deleuzian becoming? Continental Philosophy Review, 36,
139–53.
May, T. (2005). Gilles Deleuze: An introduction. Cambridge, United Kingdom:
Cambridge University Press.
Pereboom, D. (2009). Kant’s transcendental arguments. In Stanford encyclopedia of
philosophy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-transcendental/
Plato. (1973). The republic and other works. (B. Jowett, Trans.). New York, NY:
Anchor Books.
St. Pierre, E. A. (1997). An introduction to figurations: A poststructural practice of
inquiry. International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education, 3(10), 279–84.
4 A Proleptic Perspective
of Music Education
Brent C. Talbot
INTRODUCTION
NARRATIVE
In spring of 20071 I was hired to take over an eighth grade general music
class in a suburban school in upstate New York in order to reduce the disci-
plinary conflicts a choir director had been experiencing with his large eighth
grade all-boys choir. The school’s administration, district music coordinator,
and the middle school music teachers strategized that they could better man-
age the students’ behavior by dividing the 70-member choir and using the
eighth grade general music teacher as a second choir director. They hired me
to cover the one section of eighth grade general music that met during the
same period as the choir.
Coming into a classroom in mid-March posed three main challenges.
First was establishing myself in a community of practice (Lave & Wenger,
1991) in which the participants had preestablished roles, identities, rou-
tines, rituals, and governing rules for teaching, learning, and behavior in the
classroom setting. Students filled out worksheets and performed tasks on
instruments for the teacher that were evaluated by the teacher and measured
based on completion of the tasks assigned. Therefore, a second challenge for
me was trying to introduce the class to a constructivist approach with which
my philosophy of teaching was more closely aligned. Like Jerome Bruner
(1990), I find constructivism in cultural psychology to be a profound expres-
sion of democratic culture:
A third challenge was trying to help the students reconstruct their class
narrative and identity (Bruner, 1990; Cronon, 1992; Middleton & Brown,
2005; Mishler, 2004; Vygotsky, 1987), which they had appropriated (Rog-
off, 1998; Wertsch, 1998) from various students, teachers, and administra-
tors, as being “bad” (McDermott, 1993; O’Connor, 2003).
A Proleptic Perspective of Music Education 31
The district curriculum I inherited mandated that I cover a musical the-
atre unit, explore the “Star-Spangled Banner,” and continue with perfor-
mance tasks on various instruments before the end of the year. I did not feel
comfortable continuing with the previous teacher’s agenda before having
the opportunity to get to know the students with whom I would be work-
ing and decided—with permission from the district coordinator—to put the
curriculum on hold for a few weeks to better understand the individuals in
the class. After our initial introductions I asked the students to participate
in a music identity project (Talbot, 2013), where we explored various genres
of music and their relationships to the students’ identities. I wanted to find
out the students’ musical preference(s), explore what role(s) music played in
their lives and identities, and provide them an opportunity to articulate and
perhaps reconstruct their class narrative away from one that was “bad.”
From this project we explored stereotypes, identities, and narratives, apply-
ing them to larger constructs like group, class, and nation. We extended this
thinking through a world music unit that turned our focus to the music of
the Caribbean and Latin America, looking specifically at how musical prac-
tices, including dance and musical styles and performance, in the Caribbean
and Latin American countries are used to define whole nations (Austerlitz,
1997; Averill, 1997; Duany, 1994; Hobsbawm, 1990).
At the beginning of May, the eighth grade general music class and I had a
significant transformative moment, in which myself, the participants, and the
physical space dramatically changed as a result of a series of events. After six
weeks of being off the curriculum, I decided a nice transition would be to take
our discussion of group, national, and ethnic identity and show how these
concepts were represented in musicals like West Side Story. Not only were
the students able to draw upon the mambo and salsa stylistic features and
dance steps from the Caribbean music unit, they also began to see musicals as
a genre in which our nation tells its own narrative (Cronon, 1992). The next
time we met, the class made an extensive list of all of the musicals we could
recall, naming about forty ranging from South Pacific to Wicked. We then
looked at this list and tried to identify various categories in which the titles
could be placed. The students categorized them into five genres: religious ori-
ented (Jesus Christ Superstar), gang related (West Side Story), rock musicals
(Hair), period pieces (Ragtime), and movie musicals (High School Musical).
During our brainstorming session someone suggested that we make our
own musical. To begin the process, we brainstormed what defined a musi-
cal (storyline, music, acting, dancing, singing, staging, etc.) and all of the
various roles needed to develop and execute a musical production (script
writer, lyricist, composer/arranger, choreographer, director, music director,
set-designer, costumer, make-up specialist, lighting designer, sound engineer,
actors, dancers, and musicians). Each one of us chose and encouraged each
other into roles which we were most skilled in or interested in learning. In
the end there were two screenplay writers, one composer/arranger, one pia-
nist, one guitarist, two percussionists, a sound engineer, a lighting designer,
32 Brent C. Talbot
a person to operate the camera, a director, a critic, a set and poster designer,
and nine actors—one of whom requested adamantly that his character have
a dramatic death scene. Many types of leaders emerged and I found myself
most useful in facilitating equipment needs or mediating creative disputes
among group members.
Once the roles had been established, we grouped ourselves in different
areas of the room. The creative and organic nature of this lesson changed
both the atmosphere and the physical space of the classroom. The screen-
writers got together at a table in the back of the room. The actors moved
a table to create more space for the nine members of that group. The com-
poser went to the piano and started playing a familiar piece by Mozart; she
then deconstructed the piece and began changing the meter and arpeggiat-
ing the chords to make it her own. The percussionists pulled out chairs and
began playing along with congas and auxiliary percussion.
The director, who was encouraged into that role by the group because
he was “the loudest,” pulled me aside and said, “I think this is cool.” The
group in charge of lighting, sound, and video asked what they should be
doing. I asked, “Who is in charge of the audio/visual equipment in the build-
ing?” They responded, “Mr. Jones.” I replied, “Guess you need to go find
Mr. Jones.” One of the three said, “I think he’s in room 120.” They checked
the directory on the wall and hurried out the door, returning ten minutes
later with a boom poll, mics, headphones, and a video camera.
I went to check on the writers to see how they were doing with their
plot. They said, “OK. All we’ve got so far is that there’s a henchman who is
paid by one mob family to take out the son of another mob family’s boss.
The cops are tipped off by someone close to the henchman, and it all goes
down at a warehouse on the outskirts of town.” “Good,” I replied. “Now
start writing for nine characters. We’ll need at least one page by Monday.”
“Yeah,” one of them said, “we can get together over the weekend and write
a ton.” One student, who had not spoken all term, was sketching a horse on
some notepaper. The director came up and said, “Hey T-Bot, look at Amy’s
drawing. It’s awesome.” I suggested to Amy—who had initially not wanted
any role—that she consider creating the poster for the show. She smiled
and said, “OK.” The bell rang and the students reluctantly gathered their
belongings. A sense of disappointment was felt in the air.
INTERPRETATION
Learning for Lave and Wenger is a process that takes place in a par-
ticipation framework, not in an individual mind. This means, among
other things, that it is mediated by the differences of perspective among
the co-participants. It is the community, or at least those participating
in the learning context, who “learn” under this definition. Learning is,
as it were, distributed among co-participants, not an action of one per-
son. . . . [Similarly], understanding is not something a person does in his
or her head, nor does it ultimately involve the mental representations of
individuals. Understanding is not seen to arise out of the mental opera-
tions of a subject on objective structures. Instead, Lave and Wenger
locate learning [and understanding] not in the acquisition of structure,
but in the increased access of learners to participating roles in expert
performances.
(p. 15)
By exploring their musical identities, I had asked the participants of the class
to produce their own narratives by drawing upon the cultural resources
and tools they draw upon in and out of school. As other writers, anthro-
pologists, philosophers, and psychologists have pointed out (Bakhtin, 1981;
Bruner, 1990; Vygotsky, 1987), our cultural resources and tools invariably
have a history of use by others; they are always half someone else’s. This
lead to questions about how our identities and narratives in and of the
classroom are built into the very cultural resources and tools we employ as
learners and teachers. I began to wonder how we could coordinate these
resources and tools to help shape our learning environment.
In order for our class to shift from a teaching curriculum to a learning
curriculum, I—as the teacher—had to first critically examine and recon-
struct my own understanding of learning and teaching and (re)interpret
what it means to be a teacher, a learner, and part of a classroom cul-
ture. I began by recalling what Bruner (1990) offers about participation
in culture and our ability as humans to construct individual and group
understanding:
Prolepsis
I draw upon Michael Cole’s (1996) cultural approach to viewing ontogeny
and the idea of prolepsis to get at this idea of past, present, and future
pathways.
PAST
ST FUTURE
Geological Time
Phylogeny
1 2
History (Culture)
Ontogeny: Mother
3
Ontogeny: Child
Microgenesis
A Proleptic Perspective of Music Education 37
Cole (1996) explains:
[That on this illustration,] the horizontal lines represent time scales cor-
responding to the history of the physical universe, the history of life on
earth, (cultural-historical time), the life of the individual (ontogeny),
and the history of moment-to-moment lived experience (microgenesis).
The vertical ellipse represents the event of a child’s birth. The distribu-
tion of cognition in time is traced sequentially into (1) the mother’s
memory of her past, (2) the mother’s imagination of the future of the
child, and (3) the mother’s subsequent behavior.
(p. 185)
Cole suggests in this sequence that the ideal aspect of culture is transformed into
its material form as the mother and other adults structure the child’s experience
to be consistent with what they imagine to be the child’s future identity.
This is easier to understand through an exercise I do with students in their
first year on campus. At the beginning of each year, I ask them to close their
eyes and ponder the following questions about themselves:
To illustrate the point that our projected pathways may not be our own, I
discuss my own experiences as an emerging adult (Arnett, 2000).
Throughout my childhood, my parents’ future projection for me was to
become a businessman and marry a woman. This was experienced through
conversations, questions, and suggestions my relatives would make as to where
I should attend college and about whom I should find sexually desirable. I
discovered somewhere along my ontogeny/lifespan that I possessed a great
interest in music and teaching and I also came to understand my sexuality dif-
ferently. Because these projections of my identity conflicted with my parents’, it
was inevitable that a disruption of these projections would occur; and as such,
I forged a new identity and a new narrative for myself and my family.
Cole (1996) argues that prolepsis is an important process of socializa-
tion/enculturation, and is based upon the mediation of cultural values
and norms that are grounded in both the transmitter’s past experiences
and the expectations for the receiver’s future roles. The assumption that
the world will remain similar for future generations greatly informs the
38 Brent C. Talbot
developmental experiences to which adults expose youth (Wyn, 2005). By
being aware of prolepsis, music teachers can better understand the role
we play in projecting and mapping our own past, present, and future onto
our students.
The combination of the teacher’s past personal experience(s) coupled
with their future expectations set forth by adult role model(s) serves as pos-
sible catalysts for the constriction of the activities, knowledge, language,
beliefs, and behavior(s) used in the classroom setting (Cole 1996; Erikson,
1968). For example, as Slattery (2012) points out:
CONCLUSION
NOTE
1. During this time, I was also employed in the Rochester (NY) City School
District and found teaching in both settings to be significantly different in
terms of demographics as well as approaches to curriculum and teaching. To
help understand the changes in my teaching and in my own identity, I jour-
naled regularly and kept video and audio of my classrooms.
REFERENCES
Arnett, J. (2000). Emerging adulthood: A theory of development from the late teens
through the twenties. American Psychologist, 55(5), 469–80.
Austerlitz, P. (1997). Merengue: Dominican music and Dominican identity.
Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
A Proleptic Perspective of Music Education 41
Austerlitz, P. (1997). Merengue: Dominican music and Dominican identity.
Philadelphia:Temple University Press.
Averill, G. (1997). A day for the hunter, a day for the prey: Popular music and power
in Haiti. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Barab, S. A., & Duffy, T. M. (2000). From practice fields to communities of prac-
tice. In D. H. Jonassen & S. M. Land (Eds.), Theoretical foundations of learning
(pp. 25–55). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Barrett, M. S., & Stauffer, S. L. (2009). Narrative inquiry in music education:
Troubling certainty. New York: Springer.
Barrett, M. S., & Stauffer, S. L. (Eds.) (2012). Narrative soundings: An anthology of
narrative inquiry in music education. New York, NY: Springer.
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Clandinin, D. J., & Connelly, F. M. (2000). Narrative inquiry: Experience and story
in qualitative research. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Connelly, F. M., & Clandinin, D. J. (2006). Narrative inquiry. In J. L. Green, G.
Camilli, & P. Elmore (Eds.), Handbook of complementary methods in education
research (pp. 477–87). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Cronon, W. (1992). A place for stories: Nature, history, and narrative. Journal of
American History, 78(4), 1347–76.
Duany, J. (1994). Ethnicity, identity, and music: An anthropological analysis of
Dominican merengue. In G. H. Béhague (Ed.), Music and black ethnicity: The
Caribbean and South America (pp. 65–90). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction
Publishers.
Erikson, E. (1968). Identity: Youth and crisis. New York, NY: Norton & Co.
Giroux, H. (2003). Neoliberalism and the disappearance social in Ghost World.
Third Text, 17(2), 151–61.
Heath, S. (2004). Risks, rules, and roles: Youth perspectives on the work of learning
for community development. In A. Perret-Clermont, C. Pontecorvo, L. Resnick,
T. Ziittoun, & B. Burge (Eds.), Joining society: Social interaction and learning
in adolescence and youth (pp. 41–70). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
Press.
Hobsbawm, E. (1990). Nations and nationalism since 1780: Programme, myth, real-
ity. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
James, W. (1890/1950). The principles of psychology. Mineola, NY: Dover
Publications.
Keith, K. D. (Ed.) (2011). Cross-cultural psychology: Contemporary themes and per-
spectives. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Kirshner, D. & Whitson, J. A. (1998). Obstacles to understanding cognition as situ-
ated. Educational Researcher, 27(8), 22–8.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimate peripheral participation.
New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (2002). Legitimate peripheral participation in communities of
practice. In H. Roger, F. Reeve, A. Hanson, & J. Clarke (Eds.), Supporting lifelong
learning: Vol. 1. Perspectives on learning. New York, NY: Routledge.
McDermott, R. P. (1993). The acquisition of a child by a learning disability. In S.
Chaiklin and J. Lave (Eds.), Understanding practice (pp. 269–305). New York,
NY: Cambridge University Press.
Middleton, D., & Brown, S. D. (2005). The social psychology of experience: Studies
in remembering and forgetting. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Miller, P. J., & Goodnow, J. J. (1995). Cultural practices: Toward an integration
of culture and development. In J. J. Goodnow, P. J. Miller, & F. Kessel (Eds.),
42 Brent C. Talbot
Cultural practices as contexts for development (pp. 5–16). San Francisco, CA:
Jossey-Bass.
Mishler, E. (2004). Historians of the self: Restorying lives, revising identities.
Research In Human Development, 1(1&2), 101–21.
Moll, L. C., Amanti, C., Neff, D., & Gonzalez, N. (1992). Funds of knowledge for
teaching: Using a qualitative approach to connect homes and classrooms. Theory
Into Practice, 31(2), 132–41.
O’Connor, K. (2003). Communicative practice, cultural production and situated
learning: Constructing and contesting identities of expertise in a heterogeneous
learning context. In S. Wortam & B. Ryhmes (Eds.), Linguistic anthropology of
education (pp. 61–92). Westport, CT: Praeger.
Penuel, W., & Wertsch, J. (1995). Vygotsky and identity formation: A sociocultural
approach. Educational Psychologist, 30(2), 83–92.
Prolepsis. (2012). In Merriam-Webster.com. Retrieved January 22, 2013, from www.
merriam-webster.com/dictionary/prolepsis
Rogoff, B. (1998). Cognition as a collaborative practice. In D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler
(Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2. Cognition, perception, and lan-
guage. New York, NY: Wiley.
Rymes, B. (2001). Conversational borderlands: Language and identity in an alterna-
tive urban high school. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
Slattery, P. (2012). Curriculum development in the postmodern era. New York, NY:
Garland Publishers.
Stone, A., & Wertsch, J. V. (1984). A social interactional analysis of learning dis-
abilities. Journal of Learning Disabilities, 17, 194–9.
Stone, C. A. (1993). What is missing in the metaphor of scaffolding? In E. A. Forman,
N. Minnick, & C. A. Stone (Eds.), Contexts for learning: Sociocultural dynamics
in children’s development. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Talbot, B. C. (2013). The music identity project. Action, Criticism, and Theory for
Music Education, 12(2): 60–74.
Vygotsky, L. (1987). The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky. Vol. 1. Problems of gen-
eral psychology. (N. Minick, Ed.). New York, NY: Plenum.
Wertsch, J. V. (1998). Mind as action. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Wyn, A. (2005). What is happening to “adolescence”? Growing up in changing
times. In J. Vadeboncoeur & L. Stevens (Eds.), Re/Constructing “the adolescent”:
Sign, symbol, and body. New York, NY: Peter Lang.
5 The Virtues of Philosophical
Practice in Music Education
Wayne Bowman
I should not like my writing to spare other people the trouble of thinking.
But, if possible, to stimulate [them] to thoughts of [their] own.
—Ludwig Wittgenstein
I have already made some fairly strong assertions about what philosophy is
not. But what interests me here are not the numerous things-not-philosophy
that make no claim to philosophical status. My concern is, rather, the things
commonly mistaken for philosophy: endeavors that resemble certain of its
features while compromising its most promising potentials. I believe that
inspirational rhetoric and advocacy are prominent among the endeavors
most commonly mistaken for philosophy. But what others might we iden-
tify? What are the rivals of responsible philosophical practice in music
education?
One notable rival is discourse that is deliberately inscrutable, that uses
linguistic complexity to impress or obfuscate rather than to clarify or illu-
minate issues.7 In music education’s particular case we should probably
add discourse that is devoid of discernable implications for practice. To be
sure, philosophy often wrestles with issues that are complex, abstract, and
theoretical. But as has been aptly observed, “For every complex problem
there is an answer that is clear, simple, and wrong.”8 Those who criticize
philosophical inquiry for its failure to provide catchy aphorisms that fit on
bumper stickers, then, are looking for the wrong thing in the wrong place.
Complex questions require deep answers that draw careful distinctions,
seek precision, and respect the complexity of reality. However, complexity,
accuracy, and precision do not mean opacity or indifference to the practical
concerns at the heart of music education. Responsible philosophical practice
steers clear of language and ideas that are gratuitously complex; it shuns
distinctions that do not make differences. Philosophy is not needlessly dense
or impenetrable, nor does it dispense simplistic slogans. Nor is it merely
theoretical: indeed, good theory is probably among our most practical pro-
fessional assets.
Second, philosophy is not a merely personal theory of this or that: phi-
losophy is not the assertion of personal beliefs. It does not consist of deeply
held conviction. Although everyone has beliefs and opinions, and usually in
abundance, few of these amount to philosophy in a disciplined sense. The
notion that everyone is somehow entitled to his or her own “philosophy”
is deeply misguided, then: a symptom of the devaluation of philosophical
knowledge. Unexamined opinion and unsubstantiated belief may be things
46 Wayne Bowman
to which everyone is entitled in some way or other, but they are not philo-
sophical. “My philosophy is that the best musicians make the best music
educators”; “My philosophy is that music makes people aesthetically sen-
sitive”; “My philosophy is that children have to be taught what to think
before they can think for themselves”: claims like these operate on roughly
the same level as “My philosophy is that a woman’s place is in the home,”
which is to say they are better considered prejudice than philosophy. Phi-
losophy involves systems of warranted belief: accounts developed with care,
in light of competing alternatives, and subjected to rigorous critical scrutiny.
At its best, its claims tend to take the form of hypotheses: of positions pre-
sumed valid yet open to ongoing analysis and, when warranted, revision.
Unlike mere opinion, philosophy carefully incorporates mutually accepted
ways of testing the merits of competing views. Without these, belief systems
become ideological turf wars in which victory is more important than truth
and the victors are those who shout louder or are better able to harness
institutional channels to disseminate their views. Responsible philosophi-
cal practice submits to analytical and discursive standards. The notion that
all such standards are purely arbitrary and that, therefore, all philosophical
perspectives are equally valid—that anyone is entitled to his or her own
“philosophy”—is not unlike the silly claim that everything is beautiful in its
own way. This kind of anything-goes relativism is anathema to philosophi-
cal inquiry.
Third, philosophy is not synonymous with logic and reason. While
many of its accomplishments stem from adherence to rational principles,
it should not be equated with strict adherence to logical argument or posi-
tivistic proofs. Philosophy is not a knock-them-dead affair with logical
tools and rational strategies capable of conferring upon its practitioners
insights that magically transcend all perspective or point of view. While
committing to the pursuit of truths through reason—and while embracing
things like clarity, precision, and accuracy—philosophy does not consist
in technically adept applications of logic. Nor does responsible philoso-
phy presume itself capable of revealing “the” truth, of attaining ultimate
insights into the innermost essences of the things upon which it is brought
to bear. It seeks to enhance understanding without presuming itself a pur-
veyor of absolute truths. In other words, good philosophy is fallibilistic:
it acknowledges its potential shortcomings, and advances its positions as
working hypotheses. It is a perspectival affair, always situated and invari-
ably partial in its purview; and yet it embraces principles of rational dis-
course, rejecting things like obfuscation and deceit. Philosophy respects
reason and seeks to be reasonable, but logic and consistency are not the
sole measures of its worth.
Fourth, philosophy is not purely intellectual or theoretical, an introspec-
tive undertaking isolated from the “real world” and devoid of practical sig-
nificance. As I said earlier, it does not pursue distinctions that do not make
practical differences. Because music education is defined by its achievement
The Virtues of Philosophical Practice in Music Education 47
of right results—musically and educationally—music education philosophy
is necessarily and especially concerned with the connections between beliefs
and actions. It is not unique in this regard: the ancient Greeks conceived of
philosophy not just as the pursuit of “wisdom” in the abstract or for its own
sake, but rather as the pursuit of answers to questions about how best to
act, how best to live, what kind of person to be. Philosophy in its original
sense was not a highly specialized, introspective affair, but an undertaking
with broad practical significance, and essential to living well. The trajec-
tories of music education philosophy have too often run in quite different
directions, consisting of “mind trips” by and for philosophers—not unlike
Babbitt’s (1958) infamous notion of musical composition as a practice by
and for composers.9 Philosophical practice that ignores its connections to
what Dewey called ends-in-view quickly becomes marginal, failing to deliver
the goods it exists most fundamentally to serve.
Fifth, philosophy is not fashion.10 By this I mean that philosophy does
not consist in trends embraced for their novelty, popularity, or “currency”
(viewpoints-du-jour), only to be tossed aside in pursuit of the next new thing.
While it seeks to acknowledge and accommodate shifts in musical and edu-
cational practice, responsible philosophy is not notable for abrupt lurches
this way or that. It does not casually discard previous findings in pursuit
of mere novelty. Its history is progressive, and does not consist of arbitrary
successions of unrelated interests and agendas. In other words, noteworthy
philosophical innovations draw their nourishment from roots that extend
into previous efforts and ways of thinking—things that delineate what kinds
of future contributions count as genuinely philosophical. For this and other
reasons, genuinely philosophical expertise is, like musical and instructional
expertise, acquired through extensive periods of practical immersion devoted
to learning and refining appropriate habits, attitudes, and inclinations. Good
philosophy does not emerge ab initio or change with the seasons, in no small
part because what constitutes responsible practice is determined by relation-
ships with others who are similarly engaged and whose engagement is impor-
tantly shaped by the achievements of predecessors.
The last misconception I will mention here is the assumption that philo-
sophical inquiry is a mere “research methodology”11—one set of research
techniques and procedures among many; simply an alternative way of
organizing and analyzing “data.” Philosophy’s purview is far more exten-
sive, comprehensive, and foundational than that, and its fabric much more
intricate. Whatever its similarity—as a mode of inquiry—to research tech-
niques in general, engaging in philosophy differs in important ways from
conducting case studies, developing multiple regression formulas, or testing
hypotheses by isolating and manipulating independent variables. Philosoph-
ical practice typically deals in abstract, rational reflection, and is concerned
with what can be known through different kinds of inquiry. And because
it is, as suggested earlier, devoted to the identification, formulation, and
analysis of problems—which are fundamental to all research—it is not so
48 Wayne Bowman
much a method or technique as a foundational practice.12 It contributes in
crucial ways to how any and all research is conceptualized, executed, evalu-
ated, and applied to practice. Construing it as a mere research methodology
significantly underestimates philosophy’s aims, purposes, range, and utility.
WHAT PHILOSOPHY IS
On a basic level, practices consist in human actions: they are things people
do. However, people do many things, and most of these do not warrant
being considered practices.15 This section will seek, therefore, to identify
what I mean when I assert that practices—like philosophy, I am suggesting,
but also like music—differ in important ways from mere activities; why
practices are not reducible without significant loss to techniques; and why
distinctions among practices, technical endeavors, and mere activities are
worth drawing carefully.
How do practices differ from other modes of human activity? In the first
place, practices involve actions not mere activity: practical activity is inten-
tional, devoted to the pursuit of ends-in-view. Authentically engaged prac-
titioners embrace means that are intimately related to the practice’s proper
ends—ends acknowledged by fellow practitioners as the reasons their
actions, and embraced by them as the proper way of carrying them out.
There is an intimate and dialectical relationship between the ends a practice
serves and the ways true practitioners may be expected to pursue them. This
relationship is not rule governed, but a consensual, intersubjective affair
where what constitutes right or authentic action (action that pursues the
right ends, in the right way, to the right extent, and so forth) is subject to
interpretation, critique, and continual modification. Accordingly, which of
a practice’s numerous ends distinguish and define it (which are the ones
without which it could no longer exist) and what kinds of action (or whose)
most faithfully represent the practice are open questions.
Practices are habitual modes of collective action guided by ethical, as
distinct from technical, considerations.16 They are intentional, cooperative
modes of activity devoted to the attainment of ends whose priority and
means of attainment are not set in stone. What constitutes the nerve of a
given practice is thus necessarily subject to critical scrutiny and debate; and
the resultant dynamic tensions are crucial to a practice’s vitality as a prac-
tice. A practice, Higgins (2012) explains, is a
NOTES
1. Please note the use of quotation marks here. I use them because “practical” is
commonly, but inappropriately, used in this way. “Technical” would be a more
fitting term, for reasons that will become clear in due course.
2. Exposure is often all we seek to accomplish: a strategy that resembles conven-
tional and largely unsuccessful approaches to “music appreciation.”
3. Among its many consequences: our casual substitution of philosophies of
“art” and “the arts” for philosophy of music education.
4. See Bowman (2005). It might be countered that “better questions” are them-
selves “products” in a manner of thinking. My point is that philosophical
action consists more fundamentally in framing and posing questions than in
answering them so as to bring an end to the process.
5. By “ethical” I do not mean “moral.” Although the differences between these
terms are both substantial and important, space does not permit me to explore
them here. See Higgins (2011, 2012) and Williams (1985) for illuminating
accounts of the distinction.
6. Clearly the claims I will advance here are normative in nature. Because philo-
sophical work clearly exists that contradicts these claims, some might pre-
fer to read these as assertions about philosophy done well, or responsibly. I
have written more extensively about some of these issues in Bowman & Frega
(2012a, 2012b).
7. This is the “baffle-them-with-BS” strategy.
8. Attributed to H. L. Mencken.
9. This title was not Babbitt’s, but that need not concern us here.
The Virtues of Philosophical Practice in Music Education 59
10. It might also be argued that it is not particularly fashionable, but if it’s not
fashion that seems to beg the point.
11. Of course, it can be and has been widely represented as such. My point is not so
much that it lacks a specific technique or “method”—although that might well be
argued—but that it is not properly understood as one kind or species of research
among many. Its roots penetrate deeply into all areas of research, and the shortcom-
ings of many a research project can be traced to neglect of philosophical issues.
12. A claim by Wittgenstein (1958, §133) may warrant consideration here: “There
is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed methods, like different
therapies.”
13. Or, perhaps more precisely still, a constellation of diverse human practices,
without a single unifying core.
14. The particular understanding of “practice” I advance here is neo-Aristotelian
in nature, with intimate connections to virtue ethics. Space constraints prevent
extensive elaboration here, but MacIntyre (1984), Dunne (2005), Higgins (2011,
2012), and Bowman & Frega (2012a, 2012b) offer more detailed accounts.
15. Misinformed criticisms of David Elliott’s claim that music is fundamentally
“something people do” (Elliott, 1995, p. 14) generally fail to grasp that his
broader concern lies with the distinctive kinds of doings musical practices
involve. That music involves human activity is but the beginning of an argu-
ment pursuing a much more significant point.
16. This is not to say that practices cannot draw upon technical considerations,
only that the latter are not constitutive. Please note once again my concern that
“ethical” not be equated with “moral.” See note 5.
17. That practices are cumulative pertains in important ways to my claim that
philosophy is not fashion. The claim to creative extension reminds us that
what constitutes right action differs between practices, changes over time, and
is necessarily open to criticism.
18. Fortunately, excellent explanations can be found elsewhere. See especially
MacIntyre (1984), Dunne (1997, 2005), and Higgins (2011, 2012).
19. These can also easily elude would-be practitioners whose engagement is techni-
cal rather than practical.
20. Although I will draw on this Aristotelian view in what follows, I do not embrace
the idea that virtues are “means” in any but a broad, metaphorical sense. The
right course of action in practical situations cannot be specified without care-
ful context-specific considerations, and the notion that right action consists
invariably in moderation is a depressing one.
21. Indeed, a three dimensional representation of these interrelationships and tensions
would better exemplify their ethical nature than my two dimensional chart.
22. Note that this question is less about how one should write than how one
should live; more, it might be said, about being than knowing.
REFERENCES
When stories of music in the 20th Century are told, the importance of sound
recordings will be central to their plots. Certain concerts will, of course, also
be remembered, such as the 1913 Paris premiere of the Rite of Spring, Mar-
ian Anderson’s 1939 recital on the steps of the Lincoln Memorial, and the
Woodstock Music and Art Fair of 1969. But it is impossible to think about
music of the past hundred years without an essential place for recordings:
Enrico Caruso’s 78s, Louis Armstrong’s Hot Five and Hot Seven recordings,
the ten thousand recordings made by Duke Ellington, and the Beatles and
the British Invasion. Recordings also afforded musical realms built from
recordings, such as hip-hop sampling and techno music. The more recent
extension of recordings into new media represents the latest extension of
the possibilities of circulation and creation via sound recording. One cannot
credibly tell the story of our century’s music without sound recordings, the
emergence of which is the central concern of the present article.
Recordings are not merely a way to store music and make it more acces-
sible; they are a catalyst for profound changes in music, musician, and audi-
ence. In this sense, sound recording is a blanket term meant to invoke both
media and the networks that constitute them—media such as the gramo-
phone, radio, and MP3; and the networks of each medium, assemblages
of people, practices, institutions, and technologies. This understanding of
sound media as contingent networks of recurring relations builds on work
in sound studies, especially Sterne (2003, 2012a). This particular approach
also resonates with educational efforts to study technological change from
a pragmatic philosophical perspective, a Deweyan approach with a strong
contemporary literature (Hickman, 2001; Waddington, 2010).
Before moving forward with an account of the shifting locus, it is impor-
tant to acknowledge the many other writers who have considered technolog-
ical shifts and their relationship to art, a rich intellectual heritage that informs
the present account. Benjamin (1935/1968) provided a Marxist accounting
of art in the rising age of technological reproduction, finding a withering
of works with aura and a rise in a doctrine of art for art’s sake. McLu-
han (1962/2008; 1964/2003) theorized that each era was dominated by a
64 Matthew Thibeault
particular sense, such as the dominance of the visual sense in the print age, or
our current audile-tactile “field of electronic all-at-onceness” (1962/2008, p.
63). Heidegger (1954/1977) presented technology as a framework for being,
within which humans were reduced to standing resources, with art as an
antidote to this reduction of being. Borgmann (1984), following Heidegger,
developed the device paradigm to convey the process by which technol-
ogy reduces once-rich focal practices such as playing the piano, to always-
available commodities—recordings provided by devices such as speakers.
Attali (1977/1985) provides a sweeping account of shifting networks in the
political economy of music, from the ritual and sacrificial origins through a
network of representation made possible by sheet music, then to the repeat-
ing network of recordings, finally heralding a coming network of composi-
tion that he relates to free jazz.
While many writers explore change as a progression wherein technologi-
cal changes and advances contribute to shifting practices, others, notably
ethnomusicologists, have discussed these innovations without such direc-
tionality. Nettl (2005) discusses modes of musical transmission: from aural,
to written, to printed, to recorded, noting, “These could even represent a
chronological order, valid for Western civilization, but it is also a continuum
of relationships, from close to distant, among composer, performer, and lis-
tener” (p. 292). Turino (2008) presents a four-field framework based on
Peirce’s semiotics: participatory and presentational musical fields within live
music practices, and high fidelity and studio audio art musical fields for
recorded music. Like Nettl, Turino stresses the possibility for all fields to
be present and active, to ebb and flow, while noting a progression in places
such as the United States and Zimbabwe, where the pressures of a capital-
ist system for commodification favor the easily commodified presentational
and high fidelity fields.
While each of the previous accounts provide tools and conceptions for
making sense of the profound changes in music over the past hundred years,
central to educators are the experiences of young people in their daily lives,
which are explored here through the gradual but profound shifting locus
of musical experience. Figure 6.1 provides a visual overview of the basic
argument. The ways that music was most commonly experienced in the
Western world shifted over one hundred years; from face-to-face live per-
formance, to recordings (which we might refer to today as analog media),
and currently to new media—perhaps most memorable when shortened to
a shift from performance to recording to data. Whereas nearly all musical
experience was once had in the physical presence of live performers, today
nearly all musical experience comes through sound recordings experienced
via new media. The Kaiser Family Foundation (Rideout, Foerh, & Roberts,
2010) estimates that school-age children in the United States spend nearly
eight hours of each day engaging with media, and a recent survey by Neilsen
Media (2012) found that “more teens listen to music through YouTube than
through any other source (64%)” (p. 1).
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 65
Figure 6.1 A conceptual visualization of the shift in the locus of musical experi-
ence over the 20th century from performance to recording to data. Former loci of
experience persist, but it is argued that musical habits are heavily influenced by the
dominant locus, an influence that changes the context and meaning of older loci.
What makes the shifting locus compelling for educators is the relation
of experience to habit formation in the educational process. Habit has been
a central concern for pragmatic philosophers and psychologists discussing
education, including James (1899) and Dewey (1938/1963). Turino uses
habit to discuss learning, proposing “a unitary framework for thinking
about the concepts of self, identity, and culture in relation to each other—a
framework based on the focal concept of habits” (p. 94). Habits both flow
from and are shaped by our experiences, and as Turino notes, habits are
central for the richer notions of self, identity, and culture.
As the locus of musical experience has shifted from performance to
recording to data, there has been a change in the ways in which musical
experiences were had and the subjective meanings of musical experience.
Attention to the locus brings attention not to the moment a technology
emerges, but to when that technology has become a widespread compo-
nent of experience. While sound recording can be dated back to the 1857
invention of the phonautograph, this paper focuses on the early 20th cen-
tury as the period when sound recording flourished, rapidly becoming more
ubiquitous over several decades through innovations in the gramophone,
phonograph, film, and broadcast radio. Technologies gain importance for
consideration by educators as they become a part of everyday life, as they
become a likely part of the experiences that beget habits.
The locus also reminds us not to focus on the technology in isolation, but
as part of a larger network of people, practices, institutions, and technolo-
gies. Just as Benjamin (1935/1968) wrote of an age of mechanical reproduc-
tion, thereby indicating changes that would reach perhaps all aspects of art
and not only the works that were reproduced, so we can find implications
for the locus in areas that appear less technological. Even a concert choir
should be understood as deeply enmeshed with the shifting locus: from new
competition for audience time outside and inside the concert hall; to audi-
ences who expect more of performers, having heard so much edited, per-
fected, and now Auto-Tuned music; and to the social significance of that
concert as the world around it changes. This kind of attention to the shifting
66 Matthew Thibeault
locus invites us to explore the implications of Marx’s famous words, “The
forming of the five senses is a labor of the entire history of the world down
to the present” (Marx & Engels, 1844/1988, p. 108).
The shifting locus provides a fit for music educators who need to come
to terms with technology without losing the social and educational dimen-
sions, and who require richer causal accounts of technology that go beyond
technological determinism (Ruthmann et al., 2015; Smith & Marx, 1994).
While there are many possible approaches to understanding the enmesh-
ment of music, technology, and education, the particular needs of educators
are here foregrounded by focusing on the enmeshment of people, practices,
institutions, and technologies as they become ubiquitous enough to form
the basis of habits. Whether one wishes to resist or embrace this shifting
locus, the conceptualization presented in this article can help music educa-
tors organize action and begin to make sense of the fact that to perform in
the world now involves different values and practices than to have done so
when performance was the locus of musical experience.
The view of the shifting locus is derived here from two short stories where
music plays a central but contrasting role, and the exploration of the careers
of three musicians whose work is both held in high regard and emblematic,
perhaps even a prototype, of each locus. The view of the performance locus
comes through James Joyce’s (1914/1969) story “The Dead.” The skeptical
resistance to recording is captured through an examination of John Philip
Sousa’s (1906) essay, “The Menace of Mechanical Music.” Glenn Gould’s
writings and interviews allow a shift to the evangelistic adoption of the possi-
bilities of recording, and the full extent of the data locus of today is achieved
through an examination of Richard Powers’s (2008) story “Modulation.”
Fiction provides not only rich accounts, but the opportunity to take into
consideration the cultural and subjective side of sound from the perspective
of those who lived within those cultures. As noted by Bijsterveld (2008),
introducing her study of the problem of public noise, “Our challenge, then,
is to historicize the sensory experience of sound and to listen to the sounds
of technology through the ears of those people who complained about these
sounds” (p. 26). This follows also the spirit of work by Schafer (1977/1994),
whose World Soundscape Project created a database of thousands of accounts
and mentions of sound in literature. The article closes with a recapitulation
of the ways that music educators might begin to take more seriously the real-
ity of teaching and making music within the new media era.
James Joyce’s (1914/1969) “The Dead,” the final story in his collection
Dubliners, offers a glimpse of the world just before sound recording became
a ubiquitous part of everyday life. Published in 1914, Joyce wrote “The
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 67
Dead” in 1907, and set the story during a dinner held on Epiphany in 1904.
To read Joyce’s story is to be immersed in a time when music was nearly
always experienced through face-to-face live performance.
In “The Dead,” Gabriel Conroy and his wife Gretta attend the annual
dance given by his Aunts Kate and Julia Morkin. Both sisters are singers and
music teachers. The story is built around musical moments such as this one,
where Joyce describes pianist Mary Jane’s accompaniment of Aunt Julia [all
quotes retain Joyce’s unique spelling and punctuation]:
—O, well, said Mr Bartell D’Arcy, I presume there are as good singers
to-day as there were then.
—Where are they? asked Mr Browne defiantly.
—In London, Paris, Milan, said Mr Bartell D’Arcy warmly. I suppose
Caruso, for example, is quite as good, if not better than any of the men
you have mentioned.
—Maybe so, said Mr Browne. But I may tell you I doubt it strongly.
—O, I’d give anything to hear Caruso sing, said Mary Jane.
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 69
—For me, said Aunt Kate, who had been picking a bone, there was
only one tenor. To please me, I mean. But I suppose none of you ever
heard of him.
—Who was he, Miss Morkan? asked Mr Bartell D’Arcy politely.
—His name, said Aunt Kate, was Parkinson. I heard him when he
was in his prime and I think he had then the purest tenor voice that was
ever put into a man’s throat.
—Strange, said Mr Bartell D’Arcy. I never even heard of him.
—Yes, yes, Miss Morkan is right, said Mr Browne. I remember hear-
ing of old Parkinson but he’s too far back for me.
(p. 254)
Unlike Mr. Browne, it hardly makes sense to ask where good singers are
today. Today, musical voices are always everywhere, digitally available at all
times. For Joyce’s characters, the best singers were most commonly heard in
centers of power and commerce. Ironically, Mary Jane longs to hear Caruso,
who in 1904 was just beginning to record under his first contract, soon to
become the most famous recorded voice. Unlike the disappeared voice of
Parkinson, and while not as Mary Jane hoped, everyone today and forever-
more can hear Caruso.
Joyce’s story evokes how performers and their efforts continued to exist
within the memories of the living. This aspect of music, the emotional mem-
ories that persist, is key to the central epiphany of “The Dead.” As Gabriel
and his wife are preparing to leave, he sees her at the top of the staircase,
transfixed by a singer he cannot hear over the din of the rest of the party.
She is listening as someone sings The Lass of Aughrim. Back at their hotel,
Gretta reveals that the song had been sung to her by Michael Furey, a past
love who died when young. The final words of the story capture Gabriel’s
thoughts as he looks at the snow falling outside his window:
It was falling, too, upon every part of the lonely churchyard on the hill
where Michael Furey lay buried. It lay thickly drifted on the crooked
crosses and headstones, on the spears of the little gate, on the barren
thorns. His soul swooned slowly as he heard the snow falling faintly
through the universe and faintly falling, like the descent of their last
end, upon all the living and the dead.
(p. 286)
A year before Joyce began writing “The Dead,” John Philip Sousa wrote his
infamous critique of recording technology and the potential threats to live per-
formance, “The Menace of Mechanical Music” (1906). As Katz (2012) notes,
“Given Sousa’s prominence in early twentieth-century American culture and
the widespread discussion that his article generated, it is fair to say that he,
more than anyone else, set the terms of the debate about the value and influ-
ence of sound-reproducing technologies” (p. 462). Just as reading Joyce helps
tell the story of the performance era, Sousa’s views allow us to better under-
stand the apprehension and sense of imposition felt as recordings worked their
way into the world and interacted with people to change the wants, needs,
values and practices around music. Sousa also clearly articulates versions of
several key positions that live on in many music educators’ philosophies today.
Sousa dealt with mechanical music—player pianos as well as phono-
graphs and cylinder players. Throughout his essay, he draws a sharp dis-
tinction between live music and recorded music. For Sousa, machine music
could never convey the essential human component. From the opening sen-
tence, machines are portrayed as displacing human thinking, interpreting,
and performing:
Sousa is at his most poetic when proclaiming the connection between live
performance and musical value, championing experiences like those cap-
tured by Joyce:
Music teaches all that is beautiful in this world. Let us not hamper it
with a machine that tells the story day by day, without variation, with-
out soul, barren of the joy, the passion, the ardor that is the inheritance
of man alone.
(1906, p. 282)
For Sousa, soul, humanity, and intelligence can exist in music when made
live, but not when bleached out by machines that present music without any
variation. He also located humanity in variations that naturally occur in
each unique presentation of music. To estrange music from live performance
separates it not only from human performers, but results in music devoid of
all humanity, exchanging soul for the same story day by day.
Sousa predicted that musical taste would suffer should machine music
proliferate its emaciated conception of music. He wrote, “I forsee a marked
72 Matthew Thibeault
deterioration in American music and musical taste . . . by virtue—or rather
by vice—of the multiplication of music-reproducing machines” (p. 278). He
saw the history of music in terms of the enhanced expression of the human
soul, worrying that people’s experiences would be limited to machines,
“which are as like real art as the marble statue of Eve is like her beauti-
ful, living, breathing daughters” (p. 279). Seen from Sousa’s rich notion of
musical connection, mechanical music, and the ersatz experience it pro-
vided would naturally cramp and deaden living musicians. His examples
evoke displacement and replacement across the range of musicians: infants
put to sleep by machinery, love songs caroled by gramophone, soldiers ral-
lied to battle by “a huge phonograph, mounted on a 100 H.P. automobile”
(p. 282).
The envisioned decline in taste and the gradual displacement of human
musicians led Sousa to predict problems for music education. These prob-
lems existed both through the damage machine music would inflict upon
taste, as well as the continued displacement of amateur musicians in the face
of the effortlessness with which music was recreated by machines; essentially,
the decline of house-music culture. Sousa located a love of music among the
working classes, evidenced by their purchase and study of instruments like
the guitar, mandolin, and banjo. He goes on to declare:
The cheaper of these instruments of the home are no longer being pur-
chased as formerly, and all because the automatic devices are usurping
their places. . . . And what is the result? The child becomes indifferent
to practice, for when music can be heard in the homes without the labor
of study and close application, and without the slow process of acquir-
ing a technic [sic], it will be simply a question of time when the ama-
teur disappears entirely, and with him a host of vocal and instrumental
teachers, who will be without field or calling.
(p. 280)
Sousa worried that those who might continue to play would experience
mechanical music to such an extent to cause irreparable harm. Sousa warned
that real music would cease to exist, or that those attempting to make it
would see their efforts hampered by exposure to music without humanity:
Children are naturally imitative, and if, in their infancy, they hear only
phonographs, will they not sing, if they sing at all, in imitation and finally
become simply human phonographs—without soul or expression?
(p. 281)
Sousa’s sense of music grew from the ritual and spectacle of live perfor-
mance, and Warfield (2011) argues that his approach to performance was
heavily shaped by his work in the theaters of Washington, D.C. Sousa so
disdained recordings that he famously refused to conduct his band for any
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 73
recording dates or broadcasts until 1929, three years before his death. He
articulated strong beliefs and a coherent view of the ways recorded music
might negatively impact the musical world he knew and loved. Today, as we
begin to imagine how different music was for Sousa and Joyce, their writings
allow us to imagine how strange our world would have sounded to them.
Anecdotally, when working with preservice teachers and graduate stu-
dents, most agree with Sousa. Their values emanate from habits of per-
formance, and they continue to privilege their work within a network of
practices built on performances with sheet music. I frequently hear com-
ments about how one can’t judge a performer or know a work until heard
live, and that recordings often allow edits they consider a form of cheating.
But few go quite as far as Sousa did. Most are thrilled and honored to par-
ticipate in the recording sessions their ensemble directors have arranged.
And though students may still favor live over recorded music, few would
deny humanity and soul to recordings such as Louis Armstrong’s “What a
Wonderful World.”
The first half of this paper presented views from those who lived through
the rise of sound recording technology. Joyce and Sousa’s ideas about music
were born out of the performance locus, and they lived on through the emer-
gence of recordings. Although recordings were immediately popular, it was
not until the 1960s that musicians, born and raised in the recording era, did
come to appreciate and understand the artistic and aesthetic possibilities of
the recording era. Many began to appreciate and sing the praises of that which
Sousa had feared so much, though none more eloquently than Glenn Gould.
The concert has been replaced, you know. . . . Technology has the capa-
bility to create a climate of anonymity and to allow the artist the time
and the freedom to prepare his conception of a work to the best of his
ability, to perfect a statement without having to worry about trivia like
nerves and finger slips. It has the capability of replacing those awful
and degrading and humanly damaging uncertainties which the concert
brings with it; it takes the specific personal performance information
out of the musical experience. Whether the performer is going to climb
the musical Everest on this particular occasion no longer matters. And
it’s for that reason that the word “immoral” comes into the picture. It’s
a difficult area—one where aesthetics touch upon theology, really—but
I think that to have technology’s capability and not to take advantage
of it and create a contemplative climate if you can—that is immoral!
(Gould, 1984a, p. 452)
74 Matthew Thibeault
Recordings completely replaced the concert for Gould in his work—he
famously retreated from the stage forever in 1964, both as a performer and
as an audience member. He spent the rest of his life making music in the stu-
dio. Fifty years after Sousa fought to keep performance alive in the emerg-
ing networks of recording, Gould completely rejected live music. Sousa,
then, is the Cassandra of the early recording age, and Gould, with his com-
plete embrace of recording, is a herald of a world where music can exist
completely outside face-to-face performance. Their respective orientations
toward recording expose fundamentally changed conceptions of music,
musician, and audience as the locus of experience and habit shifted from
performance to recorded networks.
Of course, attitudes toward recording changed in part due to advances
in recording technology. Sousa’s band had to arrange itself around a single
microphone; Gould used multiple microphones for even a single piano.
Sousa’s band recorded using a mechanical process; Gould used the more
sensitive electronic recording techniques that became available after 1925.
Bands in Sousa’s time could not splice together takes, while Gould artfully
spliced. Stereo recordings replaced the monaural soundscape with a three-
dimensional panorama for the listener. Finally, Gould had access to long-
play records, allowing for much longer works to be captured and shared. As
recordings became more prevalent, and as technical advantages expanded,
wants, needs, values, and practices also evolved. Gould, perhaps better than
anyone, understood and articulated a far-reaching new conception radically
different from any that could have emerged through live performance alone.
Whereas Aunt Julia was in the room and intimately connected to Gabriel
and Freddy as she sang Arrayed for the Bridal, had she made a recording
she would have been separated from her audience. Recordings gained per-
manence while losing the traditional connection. As Benjamin (1935/1968)
noted, this is analogous to the difference between an actor on stage and one
in a film. On stage, an ephemeral connection exists between audience and
performer, and the performer can respond to the audience. By contrast, a
film actor may be filmed in multiple takes, perhaps from multiple angles,
and often out of sequence from the final film. For Benjamin, with regard to
the final product of the film, “During the shooting [the actor] has as little
contact with it as any article made in a factory” (p. 231).
Just as films found advantage in estrangement, Gould envisioned benefits
Sousa did not. Two years before he stopped performing, Gould published
the essay “Let’s Ban Applause,” wherein he stated, “I have come to the con-
clusion, most seriously, that the most efficacious step which could be taken
in our culture today would be the gradual but total elimination of audience
response” (1962/1984b, p. 246). Given the estrangement of recordings, it
would seem that Gould supposed concerts and recordings could be brought
into harmony by trying to import the estrangement of recordings into the
concert hall via what he called GPAADAK, or the Gould Plan for the Aboli-
tion of Applause and Demonstrations of All Kinds (p. 248). Furthermore,
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 75
Gould explicitly invokes the example of listening to a recording as a tem-
plate for concert etiquette in countering the claim that applause is a natural
response to a performance:
Just as James Joyce evoked the performance locus, Richard Powers’s short
story “Modulation,” written one hundred years after “The Dead,” richly
represents the dense network of music via the Internet and new media:
This quote captures much about the new media world: a drastic rate
of change as connections are made across the globe, mixing and mash-
ing of music drawn from hundreds of years of history, and the rise of an
amateur culture of creativity that blurs the line between their work and
that of professionals, remaking the idea of house-music culture. The hun-
dreds of re-creations posted by others point to participant audiences whose
contribution rises to a level that blurs the distinction between creator and
audience.
Powers, formidable when writing about music as well as science and
technology, presents, through “Modulation,” an extreme view of music in
the new media era. The plot centers on the global dissemination and even-
tual synchronized activation of a musical computer virus. These events
tie together four separate characters whose musical lives capture much
about music in today’s world: Toshi Yukawa, a former music pirate, works
with record companies to find other pirates; journalist Marta Mota writes
about the uses of music by the American military in Iraq; ethnomusicolo-
gist Jan Steiner looks back on his life’s research through recordings; and
DJ Mitchell Payne presents a set of “chiptune” 8-bit audio that satisfies
his audience’s “nostalgia for the blips and bleeps of their Atari childhood”
(p. 91). Music is nearly always experienced via mobile phones, iPods, lap-
tops, and other computers. Echoing Sousa’s worries, Steiner notes that all
of these are “an instrument that everyone could learn to play without any
effort” (p. 91).
Nearly all the music and audio experienced in “Modulation” is recorded
and shared digitally. For example, Marta is embedded as a journalist to
write about troops preparing for battle, and Toshi’s work focuses on inves-
tigating endless networks of pirates trafficking in downloaded music files.
If one holds an expanded notion of what can constitute a performance, two
examples are found in the story. One evokes a present day Aunt Julia, as
Marta connects to her boyfriend via Skype to help rid her of an earworm:
A song sung, the repertoire itself from broadcast media, filtered and medi-
ated by tinny microphone and tiny speaker, virtually re-presented nearly three
thousand miles away. The second instance of performance is DJ Payne’s set
for the Chiptune Blowout:
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 79
But as soon as he got the backing tracks looping, the MSX emulator
bumping, and his Amiga kicking out the MIDI jambs to the principal
theme from the old blockbuster game Alternate Reality, he remembered
just what Face-to-Face was all about, and why nothing would ever
replace live performance.
(p. 98)
DJ Payne’s live work consists of triggering loops and working with digital
information via MIDI. He plays a role closer to conductor and composer,
more invoker and gatekeeper, than performer. However, for Payne, getting
background tracks looping to a video game soundtrack is performance.
Joyce and Sousa’s vision of music exists for Powers as only a distant
echo. There is irony in Power’s description of Payne’s work, Sousa’s machine
music, as live performance. It is also likely that Sousa would have been not
fully comfortable calling the singing of Marta’s boyfriend a performance.
Gould as evangelist would have welcomed the world DJ Payne presents, but
Gould never predicted just how far the culture would change. In Gould’s
terms, Payne represents the rise of the participant listener come full circle,
a participant listener as performer, and the triggering and playing of prere-
corded and synthesized music as performance.
In place of traditional performance, music is presented throughout “Mod-
ulation” in a variety of modern roles: as a virus, as a means for exploitation,
as a pharmaceutical, and constantly as a commodity. Toshi reflects on the
corporate nature of the relationship between music and consumer:
There was pay what you want and genetic taste matching and music
by statistical referral. Customers who liked Radiohead also listened to
Slipknot. If you like Slipknot, you may also like the Bulgarian Women’s
chorus. The vendors had your demographic, and would feed it to you in
unlimited ninety-nine cent doses or even free squirts that vanished after
three listens. He owed his job to saltwater syndrome. Drinking made
you thirsty. Buffets bred hunger.
(p. 93)
And here it was again, after an eternity away: a tune that sold nothing,
that had no agenda, that required no identity or allegiance, that was
not disposable background product, that came and went for no reason,
brief as thunder on a summer night.
(p. 102)
Many of the lectures I gave in the 1980s would end with a skeptic
in the audience pointing out loudly and confidently that only a tiny
minority of people would ever write anything online for others to read.
They didn’t believe a world with millions of active voices was remotely
possible—but this is the world that has come to be.
(p. 101)
The consolidation of power in the recording era, then, gave way to what
appears to be a democratization of access to the means of creation and dis-
tribution. The inexpensive home studio, the personal website, and the ease
with which art in digital form can be shared and enjoyed is perhaps the most
fundamental change of the new media era, changes that closely align with
the notion of convergence culture put forward by Jenkins (2006).
Another consequence flows from the ease of distribution as we transi-
tion from a recording era, namely, the rise of an overabundance of content.
Recordings that were tangible were limited to the estimated commercial
audience; but in the digital world, copies are created on demand. Review-
ing a recent biography of Keith Richards that locates access to then-scarce
blues records as critical for the creation of the Rolling Stones, Dan Chiasson
(2011) captures this transition:
The experience of making and taking in culture is now, for the first time
in human history, a condition of almost paralyzing overabundance. For
millennia it was a condition of scarcity. . . . Nobody will ever again
experience what Keith Richards and Mick Jagger experienced in Dart-
ford, scrounging for blues records. The Rolling Stones do not happen in
any other context: they were a band based on craving, impersonation,
82 Matthew Thibeault
tribute: white guys from England who worshiped black blues and later,
to a lesser extent, country, reggae, disco, and rap.
(p. 19)
To better understand some of the values and practices of the new media
era, this article now considers as an emblematic example Otis Jackson Jr.,
who performs under many monikers but is best known as Madlib. His
name aptly recalls Mad Libs, the fill-in-the-blank games that originated in
the 1950s, an approach Jackson uses in his music and even in his fictional
biography, which samples heavily from that of Redd Foxx (Stones Throw
Records, n.d.a.). His work illuminates many of the avenues by which musi-
cians are expanding their horizons, creating in new ways, and using samples
of music to connect with audiences beyond performance.
Madlib, like many musicians today, does much of his recording and music
making from a home studio, profiled in the book Behind the Beat: Hip
Hop Home Studios (Raph, 2005, pp. 99–105). His home studio is emblem-
atic of new media music production: it is filled with tens of thousands of
records from which he draws samples, beats, and ideas. Also visible are
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 83
many traditional instruments: drum set, double bass, various percussion,
and piano keyboard. Additionally, one can see a host of production tools
such as mixers, microphones, turntables, and sample trigger hardware.
The rise of the home studio can certainly be seen as part of the larger
trend of the democratization of tools and means of distribution previously
limited to corporations. Previously, most distributed music came about
through studios such as Abbey Road or Motown, what Cogan and Clark
(2003) capture with the title of their book Temples of Sound. The rise of the
home studio is made possible by the lowered cost of computing and record-
ing equipment. As a consequence, this equipment has become a central part
of the creative process. Whereas Gould would go to a studio to record,
Madlib’s and others’ work relies on constant access to studio tools that
supplement or replace more traditional instruments as the vehicle for musi-
cal creativity. In short, a studio is his primary instrument. Frere-Jones (2008)
notes how the studio-based musician has become the emblematic musician
of the new media locus, writing of producer Flying Lotus, “His setup is typi-
cal of the twenty-first-century musician: a collection of laptops, keyboards,
and processing units, none of them large and most of them portable” (p. 2).
Madlib’s voice is extended using technologies, for instance through his
work under the alter ego Quasimoto. As Quasimoto, he raps with a voice
pitched higher than Madlib’s voice. This is achieved by first making a beat,
then rapping atop a slowed-down version, then returning the combined
recording back to the original speed. This higher voice is mixed into the
final recordings alongside Madlib’s voice at the original pitch, allowing for
contrasts and conversations.
In another creative approach, Madlib began releasing recordings in 2001
under the name Yesterday’s New Quintet, which consisted solely of Jackson
recording all the instruments while listing fictitious collaborators with color-
ful names like Malik Flavors, Monk Hughes, and Joe McDuphrey. In some
instances, he samples previous recordings of himself, and subsequent record-
ings made through the same process were released under a further list of new
group names like The Jazzistics, The Young Jazz Rebels, Suntouch, The Last
Electro-Acoustic Space Jazz & Percussion Ensemble, and The Yesterdays
Universe All-Stars. The use of real instruments but a host of pseudonyms
creates a link to the obscurity hip-hop producers prize, the delight in finding
recordings of forgotten and failed musicians who might have left behind a
few seconds that can be looped or recombined to be given new life.
Similar to a jazz musician who intentionally inserts quotes of other songs
into their solos, today’s producers weave webs of significance that combine
a knowledge of songs and how they have been used by producers. Joseph
Schloss (2004) presents an example from Madlib that must be quoted at
length due to the richness of connections:
Madlib completes a cycle: the 1977 album has a short portion sampled,
numerous producers use it in combination with other samples for their own
work, and Madlib comes along and incorporates samples of their songs,
along with his own instrument playing, to produce a cover of the original
song that is aware of the numerous other uses. For a listener steeped in hip-
hop, Madlib creates a work that acknowledges the recording as only the
beginning of a creative process of reinterpretation. This process has even
been welcomed by record labels, with Madlib invited by Blue Note records
to remix their catalog, released as Shades of Blue, another album that seam-
lessly mixes samples and remixes with overdubbed instruments.
Madlib has plundered from and reworked his own releases, notably his
work with MF DOOM as the group Madvillain. Their 2004 album Mad-
villainy was a critical success, with Madlib’s production captured by New
Yorker critic Frere-Jones (2004): “Madlib, especially, seems able to hide
music inside other music. His samples lie on each other like double expo-
sures, or like a cassette tape that allows the previous recording to bleed
through the new one.” Four years later, Madlib released a new album, Mad-
villainy 2—The Madlib Remix, consisting of the original rhymes by MF
DOOM atop all new beats, giving the same recordings of the rap an entirely
new sonic context.
When recordings largely replace performing, it is possible to release more
recordings, and Madlib’s official discography on the Stones Throw record
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 85
label’s website (Stones Throw Records, n.d.b), accessed in July of 2011,
quantifies and categorizes his releases as follows: 113 entries for “Artist/
Group Recordings,” 6 entries under “MC (not producer),” 79 entries for
“Producer,” 22 entries for “Remixes,” and 18 entries for “Mixtapes, Video,
Promo, Misc.” In other words, in the 15 years Madlib has been commer-
cially releasing recordings, he has released on average 14.7 recordings each
year, for a total of 220 releases (and this figure omits works distributed on
the Internet but not commercially released). In 2010 alone, he put out a
series called “Madlib Medicine Show,” which was described in the press
release as:
The even-numbered releases are mixtapes, Madlib works due to the kinds
of changes Gould foresaw for the participant listener: Madlib’s shortening
or lengthening or excerpting of a recording; the change of pitch or tempo;
the juxtaposition of tunes on the particular mix; and the layering and mixing
in of other material. Madlib often includes spoken word text of old “party
records,” explicit comedy from African American performers like Redd Fox
or Moms Mabley. Several of these mixes are released under another name,
Beat Konducta, one that playfully joins the classical notion of a conductor
with one who works with previously recorded beats.
Madlib exemplifies some of the possibilities of music in the new media
era: the ability to build new creations from existing recordings from across
history and around the world, the ability to play traditional instruments in
new and old contexts, the home studio as a central creative tool, and the use
of recordings and the Internet as primary venues for sharing music. While
much room for greater understanding and consideration of Madlib’s ways
of making music exist, music educators are increasingly addressing these
kinds of creativity (Burnard, 2012; Randles, 2012; Tobias, 2015).
The story of music in the 20th century presented here foregrounds the
increasing importance of sound recording, and the narrative draws a dis-
tinction between musical experiences had through performance, recording,
and new media. An aim of this story is to complicate our notions of per-
formance in a new media era. One hundred years ago, performance could
86 Matthew Thibeault
viably be said to account for nearly all musical experience; today, perfor-
mance is an increasingly diminished portion of our overall experiences with
music, and in the case of some types of music, an impossibility.
To illustrate the changes of the shifting locus, this article focused on sub-
jective musical experience as presented in “The Dead” and “Modulation,”
and also by tracking practices of musicians who are emblematic of each
locus—Sousa, Gould, and Madlib. Through the work of these writers and
musicians, large shifts are apparent. These shifts are consequential for edu-
cators because, as the locus of experience shifted, differing musical habits
were formed. Marx, quoted previously, argued for recognition of the role
played by modernity in the formation of the senses. Adorno (2009) wrote
in the late 1930s of the problem of a “new type of human being” (p. 461),
arguing against the notion that human nature is unchanging and that, “in
certain situations, this culture becomes such a contrast to real living condi-
tions that it can no longer carry out the task imposed on it. . . . The fic-
tion is maintained that inducing people to listen to Beethoven symphonies,
read Milton, and gaze upon Raphael madonnas [sic] is equally ‘progressive’
and humanistic at all times” (pp. 461–2). Adorno, like Marx, saw radical
changes in the social conditions and productive forces brought about in con-
cert with modernization and technologization, writing, “Regardless of how
educators might assess such issues as drive structure, sublimation or culture,
their work is only of use if their reflections take the real changes that have
gone on, both in people and in the power of culture, into account without
any illusions” (p. 462).
It may be the case that little, if anything, of the new media locus as evoked
by Powers can meaningfully be taught through performance. This musical
world of data is largely foreign to music education practices characterized
by competitions and festivals, emulation of military bands, and makers of
traditional band and orchestra instruments. As Cavicchi (2009) notes about
what I describe as the recording locus:
The recording industry has been in existence since the 1910s, urban
blues and rock ’n’ roll have been around since the 1940s, and MTV’s
codification of music and fashion is over twenty years old now. Yet
only rarely do the behaviors associated with modern, commercial, and
popular music—from DJing and dance to power chords and social
protest—make it onto the radar of school musicality, except as phe-
nomena to ignore or even oppose.
(p. 103)
In “The Dead,” Mary Jane says that she’d give anything to hear Caruso.
Some music educators may believe that we did give up everything special
about music, gaining the ability to hear Caruso’s wonderful voice for eter-
nity in exchange for the humanity and soul estranged by the preservation
process. For those music educators who remain wedded to the performance
The Shifting Locus of Musical Experience 87
locus and the values that flow from it, they will continue to hold similar
beliefs, perhaps to notice only what is lost, and to cling to the idea that only
live performance can provide worthwhile musical experiences. This paper
makes clear that this is far from the only option, and that other ways to
understand and appreciate differing mediated networks of music exist—
ways that educators can both enjoy and understand, including how these
practices change the context and meaning of performance approaches.
Mediated networks are consequential for educators, above all, because
these networks are the locus of musical experience from which habits
emerge, the networks within which the majority of musical experience
occurs today. People today have experiences predominantly through new
media, which afford a different set of possibilities and different kinds of
experience than when music was primarily experienced through physical
recordings and radio broadcasts, or had via performances. From an educa-
tional standpoint, habits connected with these shifting loci are constitutive
of notions of self, identity, and culture. Even when making music in the
traditional context, such as a church choir, it can be argued that the sing-
ers and audience bring with them habits formed in the new media locus of
music as data, habits with different expectations and aspirations than those
in Joyce’s time.
It is beyond the scope of this paper to settle these issues. My goal instead
has been merely to raise them to the attention of the field—to provide a
sense, a story, of some of the ways that technological innovation resonates
with changes in educational ideas. Hearing these resonances might lead to
alternate histories of some of the central movements within music education.
We might hear music appreciation as a technological practice, or reconsider
the introduction of recordings into pedagogy through the Suzuki approach.
We might notice how SmartMusic is an example of the rising importance
of algorithms for music education (Thibeault, 2014). These kinds of efforts
might better connect music education with the field of sound studies, and
build upon not only the work of current scholars (Pinch & Bijsterveld, 2012;
Sterne, 2012b), but the music educators whose work has inspired those in
sound studies, most notably Schafer (1977/1994) and Small (1977, 1998). It
would be a welcome development for music educators once again to engage
in the kinds of ideas once popular in our field, one where we surely still have
valued contributions to make.
My hope is that this paper, while at times speculative, nevertheless artic-
ulates a way of thinking about the mediated networks involving sound,
education, and technology that resonate in a meaningful way for educa-
tors. We can hear the world anew, we can hear our practices as educators
anew, and we can shift our dreams for the future based on a different
understanding of the past. It is a project both pleasurable and rewarding,
one that invites not only the social sciences but the humanities to help
enhance the conduct of educational practice as it relates to all aspects of
music in the world today.
88 Matthew Thibeault
REFERENCES
DIGITAL MEDIA
Digital media are media in digital form and are often referred to as new
media (Gee, 2010; Jackson, 2001; Lister et al., 2009; Manovich, 2002).
Lister, Dovey, Giddings, Grant, and Kelly (2009) highlight how the term
new media avoids reducing such media to technical or formal definitions,
stressing single aspects of the media, or particular technologies or practices
(p. 12). Given that the term new media can be problematic in terms of its
multiplicities, fluidity, and temporal or cultural issues regarding what is or
is not considered “new,” it is sometimes used interchangeably with digital
media.
The types of media to which the terms new media and digital media refer,
along with related aspects of engagement, interaction, and participation they
foster or limit, pose challenges to music educators. For the purpose of this
chapter I will refer primarily to digital media rather than new media. More
specifically I will address multimedia, intermedia, and transmedia as ways
of framing digital media and its potential integration in music programs.
To situate how people engage with music in relation to digital media, I
offer the conceptual frameworks of convergence culture and participatory
culture (Jenkins, 2006a, 2006b). Rather than thinking of these frameworks
as the only ways to conceptualize digital media and music, I encourage
readers to see convergence and participatory cultures as helpful for con-
sidering how digital media might be integrated in music programs in ways
that account for more than specific tools or techniques. While digital media
content such as sound recordings, music videos, graphic user interfaces for
controlling sound, or even code can all be valuable when contextualized for
music teaching and learning, this chapter focuses on content that includes
multiple media and how media can mediate musical engagement and learn-
ing. It is critical that music educators view such aspects of digital media in
connection with specific media, media practices, particular contexts, and
people’s artistic engagement to avoid reducing related dialogue to discrete
characteristics or technologies. For this reason, this chapter focuses primar-
ily on cultural contexts and overarching frameworks of which digital media
are a part.
Multimedia3
The very term multimedia forefronts the idea that multiple types of media
can and do coexist or work together as a medium or form of content. Music
educators have long included relationships between music and film, art
works, or written texts (Barrett, McCoy, & Veblen, 1997; Jenkins, 2008;
Lum, 2009; McConnell, 1947). From a pedagogical perspective, music edu-
cators often include visualizations of music such as listening maps (Blair,
2008; Dunn, 2006; Kerchner, 2009). The digital nature of digital media sup-
ports compelling ways to interact with or visualize music unavailable with
static or standard notation. For instance, Thibeault (2011) makes a case
for analyzing music with multimedia spectrograms as a way for students to
look at sound and notice aspects of music that are not communicated with
standard notation. Digital media support a spectrum of music visualization
and notation systems that can be animated and synchronized with sound.
Multimedia such as the vertical scrolling icons synced with sound in the
application Synthesia,4 highlighted standard notation synced with YouTube
videos in MuseScore,5 videos of select components of scores with accompa-
nying music,6 and close up views of one performing music combined with
information such as chords in music tutorials posted online,7 all demon-
strate how people leverage multimedia to mediate musical engagement in
contemporary culture.
100 Evan S. Tobias
Deemer (2013) discusses how composers are creating and sharing video
scores that focus on or animate notation with accompanying music to gener-
ate interest in their work. He draws attention to how viewing video scores
can bring certain aspects of the music into focus. While such media are not
yet used as notation for performers, media could be used to communicate
music to performers or listeners. As access to and understanding of digital
media increases among musicians, the notion of standard notation will need
to evolve along with how people leverage technology to communicate and
visualize music.
The ability to emphasize relationships between visual image and music
through digital media also allows for interpretive, artistic, and multimedia
analyses of music. For instance, one can combine a digital music recording
with imagery and text providing information about the music as YouTube
user Steve Macready did to create video analyses of art music.8 Visual and
sonic arrangements of music that leverage multitracking are also perva-
sive online such as those created by YouTube users Arronicstuff9 and Mike
Tompkins.10 Given the interactive potential of digital media and the desire
of many to engage with music in participatory culture, platforms such as
Soundcloud.com, Hooktheory.com, and YouTab.me support multimedia
musical analyses via the Internet. The ability to embed comments directly
in the context of music, as with Soundcloud, or synchronize music and
video with animated melodic, harmonic, and rhythmic information, as with
Hooktheory and YouTab, exemplifies how new media, multimedia, and
multimodality can afford engaging ways for people to interact with and
develop musical understanding.
Webb’s (2010) notion of cross-modal listening clips, or CLCs, provides a
helpful heuristic for understanding similar types of media and engagement.
Webb (2010) explains that:
The image content of CLCs is inextricably linked to, derived from and/
or strongly responsive to the properties (rhythmic, melodic, textural,
structural, and so on) of the musical “script” it is aligned with. As a
result, a reciprocal relationship occurs between how one interprets the
image content and how one listens to the music of a CLC.
(p. 315)
Intermedia
Though not exclusive to digital media, the characteristics and principles of
new media allow for content that blurs lines between existing forms, catego-
ries, or labels. Fluid in nature, intermedia can be seen as both an in between
state between media (Higgins, 2001) as well as a “fusion of several media
into a new medium—the intermedium—that supposedly is more than the
sum of its parts (Schröter, 2012, p. 16). Rajewsky (2005) describes a process
of media combination which is “the result or the very process of combining
at least two conventionally distinct media or medial forms of articulation”
(p. 52). Rajewsky (2005) explains that “these two media or medial forms
102 Evan S. Tobias
of articulation are each present in their own materiality and contribute to
the constitution and signification of the entire product in their own specific
way” (p. 52). What differentiates intermedia from multimedia is the degree
to which the combined media are interconnected, though this is a fine line
that in many cases could be debated.
Schröter (2012) suggests that some instances and perspectives of interme-
dia are similar to Wagner’s notion of Gesamtkunstwerk in favoring inter-
connected media over monomedia. Drawing on the work of Higgins (2001),
Schröter (2012) explains how:
In mixed media the mediated forms meeting there can at any time be
regarded by the viewer as separate while in intermedia or in intermedial
forms a conceptual fusion occurs, making it impossible to view only
one of its origins. Rather, it forces the viewer into perceiving them as
simultaneous and inseparable.
(p. 19)
Are the elderly woman and the cellist playing out the same role? The
film is seen in excerpts “inserted” into the music, so is the music driv-
ing the film, or the film the music? The music never “narrates” the
106 Evan S. Tobias
film, but somehow the two layers seem to extend one another around a
common subject. Furthermore, the live instruments are augmented with
an electronic soundtrack, which at some times seems closely related to
their music and at others appears to derive from the “concrete” sounds
of the action on screen. Are these plural realities or versions of a single
experience?
(para. 3)
Transmedia
Whereas intermedia addresses multiple media in the context of a single
work, a framework of transmedia addresses multiple media dispersed
across platforms such as websites, novels, films, video games, comic
books, or physical locations (Dena, 2009; Jenkins et al., 2009). Sometimes
referred to as “cross media,” “multiple platform,” “networked entertain-
ment,” or “integrated media” (Dena, 2009; Miller, 2008; Scolari, 2009),
transmedia projects are characterized as “exist[ing] over more than a sin-
gle medium . . . at least partially interactive,” and “[consisting of] differ-
ent components that are closely integrated and used to expand the core
material” (Miller, 2008, p. 151).
108 Evan S. Tobias
Jenkins (2006a) focuses primarily on transmedia storytelling projects,
typically as part of media franchises. Such projects can include the creation
of additional plotlines and stories across media platforms such as blogs,
websites, and other media; inclusion of fan-generated content, Twitter
accounts of characters, spinoff novels, and detailed wikis such as the Lost-
pedia, a community generated wiki that detailed all aspects of the series
Lost. According to Jenkins (2006a):
When [students] bring insights from other studies that in turn enrich
their expressive responses to music, the curriculum becomes integrated
into their ways of thinking, feeling, creating, judging, and valuing music
as a site for knowing themselves and their worlds.
(p. 369)
Leveraging new media in the context of transmedia has potential for stu-
dents to engage in music in such ways.
To summarize, transmedia constitutes a connected set of multiple media
across a range of platforms. Some transmedia projects are narrative in
nature. Transmedia projects can also be organized to allow for any par-
ticular element to be experienced on its own, while engaging with multiple
elements can contribute to meaning making and a deeper experience or
investigation of a particular phenomenon, idea, or art work. Transmedia
can connect to existing art works or serve as an art form or artwork. Engag-
ing with transmedia often includes playing a participatory role with the
media. Thus, transmedia works and projects can include content submitted
by those who choose to engage. Creating and engaging with transmedia can
foster relational thinking and emphasize connections between media, ideas,
artworks, and other aspects of the human experience that might not other-
wise have been apparent.
112 Evan S. Tobias
PATHWAYS FORWARD
NOTES
REFERENCES
In preparation for the 2012 annual joint meeting of the Association for
Technology in Music Instruction1 (ATMI) and the College Music Society2
(CMS), I invited three of my colleagues—Clint Randles, Matthew Thibeault,
and Evan Tobias—to join in a panel discussion of technological determin-
ism and music education. By technological determinism we are referring to
the common societal habit (Sterne, 2003) to anthropomorphize technology
by assigning it human characteristics such as agency (Smith, 1994), and the
ability to have “causal influence on social practice” (Bimber, 1994, p. 83)
in and of itself.
Technological determinism has its roots in music education in writings
beginning in the early 20th century (see Thibeault’s section later in this chap-
ter), continuing through the advent of computer-based music education in the
late 1960s where computer technologies were seen as a potential proxy for
the music teacher framed around “its potential” for providing individualized
instruction, audio-visual enhancement, and personalized feedback (Allvin,
1971; Kuhn & Allvin, 1967). In the 1980s, Jack Taylor (1983) presented a
model of a music computer-based instruction (CBI) system using line draw-
ings of instructional music technologies of the time (Figure 8.1). Taylor’s
“music CBI system” presents only physical representations of the various
pieces of technology that, when taken alone, privilege and focus the reader
on the technology itself rather than the students. However, in the body of
the article Taylor proposes a set of fictional dialogues between a student and
a computer illustrating how computers might be used to support and guide
musical learning. Taylor’s (1983) view is what Smith (1994) would refer to
as soft determinism, because he cautions that it would be a “mistake . . . to
regard computers and humans as separate, competitive entities” (p. 45). Tay-
lor argues that computers and related music technologies are extensions of
human practice in that “computers can become human-like in their teaching
characteristics” (p. 43).
While many proponents of technology in music education argue that
technologies are human constructions, best used when contextualized as
part of a broader “system” (Taylor, 1983), experiential context (Williams &
Webster, 1996/2008), or “relational pedagogy” (Ruthmann & Dillon, 2012),
Is It the Technology? 123
loudspeaker
loudspeaker
pitch
synthesizer
extractor plotter
video terminal
light pen with keyset audio amplifier
music keyboard
printer
video unit
Figure 8.1 Jack Taylor’s (1983) model of a music computer-based instruction system.
Evan S. Tobias
When thinking about Dvorák’s music, one might not envision computers
as part of the musical experience. However, for many people technology
mediates musical experiences even in the context of Western art music.
Consider for instance how one might use a computer and music application
to remix Dvorák in the style of the dance music genre dubstep (FetOo, n.d.)
or create a multimedia analysis of Dvorák’s music (Corksmusic1, 2010).
These examples demonstrate just two ways that people integrate technol-
ogy in their musical engagement. Music educators interested in the poten-
tial of engaging with music in similar ways, however, ought to be cautious
when integrating technology in their programs. Addressing the possibilities
or transformative potential of technology for music teaching, learning, or
musicianship can be enmeshed in perspectives characteristic of technologi-
cal determinism.
Is It the Technology? 125
Situating Technological Determinism
The aspect of technological determinism I will be focusing on in this section is
“the claim . . . that technology itself exercises causal influence on social prac-
tice” (Bimber, 1994, p. 83). Technological determinism rears its head with
claims of technology having beneficial or negative effects on music teach-
ing and learning. Statements such as “this app will completely transform the
classroom and help students learn how to play better in tune, understand
functional harmony, or develop as composers” or “this technology will dehu-
manize the musical experience and destroy the tradition of performing music
as we know it” are indicative of a technological deterministic stance. Though
these are extreme examples, similar perspectives can surface when one consid-
ers relationships between technology and music teaching and learning.
Ferneding (2007) argues that:
Technology Mediates
By framing the integration of technology from a perspective of mediation
one acknowledges the interaction between technology and context. Jones
and Hafner (2012) speak to “the process through which people appropriate
[technology] to accomplish particular social practices” (p. 13). They suggest
how focusing on mediation might call attention to the tension between affor-
dances (or possibilities for action) and constraints (limitations of action) of
digital media. However, while a particular software program might mediate
one’s development of aural skills, we can problematize the notion that a
software program inherently affords or constrains the development of aural
skills. Furthermore, we ought to consider what values are being embraced
when one asserts that a particular technology is most appropriate for a form
of musicianship or pedagogy.
For instance, whereas one educator might value efficiency and the ability
to gather quantitative data from a CAI program, another educator might
value the thinking and musical context involved when one remixes music
through using sequencing or DJ software. We might also consider the types
of aural skills developed through the use of particular technologies and how
they are integrated in practice. Decisions of whether technology should be
used, what technology to use, or how it might be used are often made in rela-
tion to affordances and constraints of technology. These types of decisions
can become mired in a technological deterministic perspective.
The affordances of the environment are what it offers the animal, what
it provides or furnishes for good or ill. The verb afford is found in a
Is It the Technology? 127
dictionary; but the noun affordance is not. I have made it up. I mean
by it something that refers to both the environment and the animal in
a way that no existing term does. It implies the complementarity of the
animal and the environment.
(p. 127)
Saying that use is situated and not confined to predefined options does
not mean that it is totally open to any and all possibilities. The physical
properties of artifacts ensure that there are always boundary conditions
on how we use them.
(p. 409)
Clint Randles
Personal Empowerment
Personal empowerment in this case is what an individual achieves through
the agency that technology mediates. It is a state of being where one is the
director of one’s own media-rich information world. What role did Steve
Jobs play in the development of personal computing empowerment? I rec-
ognize, like Sawyer (2012), that there was a sociocultural component to the
success of Apple computers that stretched beyond the individual contribu-
tions of Steve Jobs (p. 251). However, I would like to suggest here that
Jobs served as the brilliant leader, or “superstar” to use Sawyer’s termi-
nology (p. 234), of a personal computing revolution that took shape most
dramatically with the release of the Macintosh in 1984. Jobs believed that
technology was a mechanism to assist individuals in developing their own
capacities for self-expression.
Determinism, an extreme form of determinism, or “hard determinism”
(Smith, 1994, p. 2), is the belief that because something exists a certain
way—technology, or the activities that technology affords—society must
therefore act a certain way or react a certain way, based on the overwhelm-
ing power of that something over what we do. Jobs understood determin-
ism well. He probably in some way believed it. However, more importantly,
Jobs understood that human aesthetic—expressed in and through music,
movies, and art, among a host of other manifestations of media as some
of the highest expressions of human achievement—brings meaning to the
human experience. I would like to propose here that the way that Steve Jobs
balanced free will with deterministic beliefs, or “soft determinism” (Smith,
1994, p. 2), might be a healthy way for music education to approach the
idea of technological determinism in music education.
Free Will
While working at Atari during his young adult life, Steve Jobs shared his
beliefs regarding the relationship between determinism and free will with
a colleague: “We used to discuss free will vs. determinism. I tended to
believe that things were much more determined, that we were programmed. If
we had perfect information, we could predict people’s actions. Steve felt the
opposite” (Isaacson, 2011, p. 43). Perhaps Jobs recognized the potential
Is It the Technology? 131
liberating power that technology could have in the hands of humans who
themselves possessed a desire to experience beauty. One might argue that
Jobs—and his team of entrepreneurial thinkers, engineers, and designers—
possessed the vision to see what the world might look like when a com-
puter served as the hub for creative personal activity. Growing up, Jobs
was a subscriber to the Whole Earth Catalog, which sold tools and edu-
cational materials. On the first page of the first issue in 1968, a slogan
read: “a realm of infinite, personal power is developing—power of the
individual to conduct his own education, find his own inspiration, shape
his own environment, and share his adventure with whoever is interested”
(Isaacson, 2011, p. 58). Here, deterministic overtones are charged by the
power of human beings to control their own fate, to organize their own
worlds. In the end, free will wins out over determinism. It is the balance,
the tension if you will, between free will and “hard determinism” that
allows for “soft determinism” and the ability for human beings to order
their media-rich worlds (see Figure 8.2).
Cultural Creativity
Technological determinism can be framed a few different ways. As stated
previously, Smith (1994) makes the distinction between (1) “soft determin-
ism,” where technology is in a reflexive relationship with societal pressures,
and (2) “hard determinism,” where technology forces society to change,
independent from societal desires or constraints (p. 2). The first statement in
a way places society in the driver’s seat, while the second places technology
there. Human beings invent technologies that transform their experience.
The daily interaction of those technologies with human experience causes
132 Alex S. Ruthmann
humans to engage in cultural creative processes where those technologies
are concerned. Sawyer (2012) asserts:
A Way Forward
Isaacson (2012) described Jobs as possessing “the creativity that can occur
when a feel for both the humanities and the sciences combine in one strong
personality . . . ” (p. xix). I would like to suggest here that music education
might gain from enacting cultural creative processes that acknowledge both
free will and determinism. These two constructs, like the humanities and the
sciences, at face value might seem at odds with one another. However, they
can also be viewed as complimentary. Similar to the ideas of freedom and
constraint in the creativity literature (Barrett, 2003), when rubbed together
Is It the Technology? 133
or placed in close proximity, free will and determinism often produce action
of some kind.
Put in practical terms, the music education profession would do well
to embrace a “soft determinism” stance on the role of technology in the
transformation of local music making practices. Reflexivity between tech-
nology and human beings should be one of our goals. Local music teachers
then would be in the driver’s seat of the incorporation of new technologies
into expanded, culturally relevant music curricula. When in proper balance,
deterministic beliefs really are not that bad, when formed and transformed
by human beings who value truth, beauty, and goodness.
Matthew Thibeault
I have a memory from Cracked magazine in the late 1970s. The back cover
presented an advertising parody, with a headline that read, “Four out of
five dentists recommend sugarless gum for their patients who chew gum.
I’m the one who didn’t.”3 A black and white photograph depicted a dentist,
brown bag over his head, dumping a bag of sugar into his patient’s mouth
via a funnel.
Belief in technological determinism can seem akin to this ad. When defined
as technology driving change with an inevitable trajectory unalterable by
human effort,4 believing that technological determinism describes how our
world works is akin to the dentist who pours sugar into his patient’s mouth.
It is absurd.
In this portion of this chapter, I would like to offer an alternate view, a
brief attempt to present four ways that technological determinism makes
sense. My current view is that technological determinism, rather than an
ideology simply to be rejected, is closer to a problem like racism, one baked
into our culture in a way that produces what Eduardo Bonilla-Silva (2009)
refers to as “racism without racists.” We have determinism without deter-
minists. Of course, the problem of technological determinism is not in any
way as devastating as racism in America, but they similarly present as ubiq-
uitous ideologies publicly claimed by few, but which nevertheless run ram-
pant within our society. Both are supported in subtle and persistent ways
that require explication and critique to lead to confrontation and change.
A first way that deterministic arguments make sense is that they are
familiar. Deterministic accounts have been and continue to be prevalent. As
far back as one hundred years ago, John Philip Sousa (1906) worried that
machine music would end music education, sales of instruments, and leave
those who made music simply imitators of phonographs.5 In the 1960s,
Glenn Gould (1966/1984) wrote, “We must be prepared to accept the fact
that, for better or worse, recording will forever alter our notions about what
134 Alex S. Ruthmann
is appropriate to the performance of music” (p. 337), and famously pre-
dicted technology would cause the concert to become “dormant in the 21st
century” (p. 332). Today, most of us are familiar with the belief that Napster
changed music in profound ways, or have heard that Jon Bon Jovi held Steve
Jobs, through Jobs’s technological innovations, personally responsible for
killing the music business (Staskiewicz, 2011). We have heard that Google is
“making us stupid” (Carr, 2008). And Victoria Armstrong’s (2011) work on
the gendered nature of technology in music education presents examples and
a critique of deterministic hope, namely, that computers will automatically
make creativity and composition flourish in the classroom. These accounts
are all too familiar.6
A second way that technological determinism makes sense is our individ-
ualistic vantage point within society. It is rational to believe that I, person-
ally, haven’t done much to change the Internet, or contributed to the design
of the iPod. But I certainly do believe that I am a member of a society that
has profoundly contributed to the shaping of these technologies. It is only
when we see ourselves as part of a movement, such as the civil rights move-
ment or today’s efforts on behalf of the LGBT community, that we clearly
see ourselves as constituting a social force for change. The individualistic
paradigm so commonly found in Western societies, as compared with col-
lectivist notions popular elsewhere, likely makes us much more vulnerable
to deterministic arguments.
A third way in which determinism makes sense is that it legitimately helps
us begin looking for causes. At first glance, it does seem that the iPod and
MP3 have had effects on music. It is hard to disagree with the notion that
the Internet and computer music software are changing music, musicians,
and audiences in fundamental ways. These arguments also help to motivate
us to explore how technology is a part of change. Deterministic beliefs are
a sensible place to begin, as long as we move beyond them, and we should
be thankful for Marshall McLuhan’s (1964/2003) expansive vision, Jacques
Ellul’s (1964) dystopian vision, and the philosophical critique of technology
in contemporary life by Albert Borgmann (1984).
A fourth and last source of the sense of technological determinism is its
promotion by technological industries. Merritt Roe Smith (1994), writes
that:
In other words, Apple sells not only iPods, but an ideology of technologi-
cal determinism wherein so many of the great improvements of modern life
originate in the creative mind of Jonathan Ive and Phil Schiller.7 A web of legal
and intellectual property concerns also depend upon a deterministic account
Is It the Technology? 135
of technological change, and dissuade us from discussing, for instance, the
environmental degradation and obscene waste that often accompany tech-
nological innovation.8
I have shared four ways that technological determinism makes sense:
namely, that these arguments are familiar, that they resonate with our indi-
vidualistic vantage point, that they are a logical place to begin inquiry, and
that they are advanced by commercial interests. But to claim that technolog-
ical determinism makes sense is not to accept it as sensible, and the charge
of today’s panel is to challenge technological determinism. Perhaps the most
potent critique of technological determinism comes from Jonathan Sterne
(2003), who writes that these arguments “spring from an impoverished
notion of causality” (p. 8). In their place, he suggests:
NOTES
1. http://atmimusic.org/.
2. http://music.org/.
3. I use quote marks, but I’m constructing this from memory, so I’m likely a bit
off. But I maintain that the photo looked as I describe it. And memory of 1970s
hair on the dentist’s arms leads to the gendered pronoun.
136 Alex S. Ruthmann
4. It is important to note that many differentiate between “hard” and “soft”
determinism. Soft determinism is much more reasonable, having more to do
with the ways that technology exerts pressures on change. A classic explora-
tion comes from Williams (1973), who in discussing Marx writes, “We have to
revalue ‘determination’ towards the setting of limits and the exertion of pres-
sure, and away from a predicted, prefigured and controlled content” (p. 6).
5. Take, for instance, this poetic quote:
When a mother can turn on the phonograph with the same ease that she
applies to the electric light, will she croon her baby to slumber with sweet
lullabies, or will the infant be put to sleep by machinery? (Sousa 1906, p. 281)
6. I’ve also presented a critique of John Kratus’s recent work as having an implicitly
deterministic structure (Thibeault, 2011), a piece where I also presented a richer
version of the pragmatic conception of technology that is only implicit in this paper.
7. Sterne (2003) refers to this as the “male birth model” of technological innova-
tion (p. 181).
8. For example, Sue Halpern (2012) closes her review of Walter Isaacson’s (2012)
biography of Steve Jobs thusly:
Next year will bring the iPhone 5, and a new MacBook, and more iPods
and iMacs. What this means is that somewhere in the third world, poor
people are picking through heaps of electronic waste in an effort to recover
bits of gold and other metals and maybe make a dollar or two. Piled high
and toxic, it is leaking poisons and carcinogens like lead, cadmium, and
mercury that leach into their skin, the ground, the air, the water. Such may
be the longest-lasting legacy of Steve Jobs’s art.
REFERENCES
Music, like language and possibly religion, is a species specific trait of man.
—John Blacking, How Musical Is Man? 1973
The two chapters contributed by Tobias1 and Thibeault, and the set of
essays by Randles, Tobias, and Thibeault, provide material for philosophi-
cal thought, theoretical frameworks, and rich examples to contemplate as
we address the topic: Making sense of our tools. Music and technology are
inextricably intertwined. What an exciting dance we experience with tech-
nology, music practice, and music education.
I’ve been asked to comment on the writings and share my vision for the
future of music education from the vantage point of some 50 years of work-
ing with, and evangelizing music technology in support of, music education.
To facilitate references, I will refer to Evan Tobias’s chapter as “Landscapes,”
Matthew Thibeault’s chapter as “Shifting Locus,” and the third set of essays
as the “Determinism” chapter.
“Shifting Locus” provides rich stories from the 19th-century music life in
the home of Aunts Kate and Julia, to Sousa who rebelled against the new
recording technology, to Gould who embraced it to the extreme, to music
140 David Brian Williams
dissemination and sharing through the Internet and handheld devices in the
short story “Modulation,” and finally to Madlib and his über-multimedia
productions that grasp at anything analog or digital for music creativity.
The stories help frame three themes I wish to develop:
The three essays in the “Determinism” chapter by Randles, Tobias, and Thi-
beault examine the philosophical position of technology determinism from
various vantage points. Why is this important to a discussion of “making
sense of our tools” and music education? The technology determinist would
say that technology drives changes in how we experience and engage in
music and how we, as educators, deliver instruction and design our strate-
gies for student learning. The opposite of determinism, as the essays note,
is free will. The question is thus, who leads on the dance floor, technology
or music?
Randles develops the concept of “soft determinism” through the writ-
ings of Smith (1994) and the contributions to technology by Steve Jobs.
“Technological change drives social change,” he explains, “but at the same
time responds discriminatingly to social pressures” (Randles, p. 129). He
proposes “that the way that Steve Jobs balanced free will with determin-
istic beliefs, soft determinism, might be a healthy way for music education
to approach the idea of technological determinism” (ibid, p. 129). Seeking
a similar balance between determinism and free will, Tobias makes refer-
ence to Jones and Hafner (2012) and introduces “the tension between affor-
dances (or possibilities for action) and constraints (limitation of action) of
digital media” (Tobias, p. 126).
Thibeault’s essay offers four ways that “deterministic arguments make
sense” (Thibeault, p. 133): they are familiar to us; we believe we are part of
technology initiatives by participating in them; it helps us look for causes;
and they are promoted by corporate America. He is careful, on the other
hand, to stress that “to claim that technological determinism makes sense is
not to accept it as sensible.” The common denominator through the three
essays is the push-pull of technology with its “affordance and constraints”
against free will set in the cultural context of “a rich sense of their con-
nection with human practice, habitat, and habit” (Sterne, 2003, cited by
Thibeault, p. 135).
The dance between technology and the people and ways (procedures) they
make and experience music is a key thread throughout the three chapters.
As we emphasized in Experiencing Music Technology (Williams & Webster,
2008, p. 12):
144 David Brian Williams
It is important to understand that people using technology is the most
important component of a music system. Whatever great achievements
flow from the process of using technology in music making, it is not
the machines that should earn the credit. Rather, the human mind and
creative spirit are responsible. . . . We are the artists forming art, not
the machines.
Figure 9.1 Rogers’s (2003) diffusion of innovations curve as consumers adopt new
technology. Shown with the addition of Moore’s “chasm” between Early Adopter
and Early Majority and a projected adoption curve for technology in the music class-
room. Adapted from Rogers (2003) and Moore (2006).
The Technology-Music Dance 145
too complex, can be tried out before adoption, and has observable benefits”
(Surrey & Ely, 2007, para. 8).
Although Rogers’s work is most often applied to consumer models, the
concept also applies to technology’s influence on music, music practice, and
education. The three themes of my response, as well as the discussion of
technological determinism, fit nicely within this model. Technology success-
fully evolves through Rogers’s stages where innovators and early adopt-
ers challenge the new technology and their feedback brings about changes
and advancements in the technology that permit advancement to the “early
majority.” Rogers (2003) casts “the early majority” as more conservative
consumers, who are open to new ideas, and are active and influential in their
respective community.
Geoffrey Moore in Crossing the Chasm (2006) expands on the model
by focusing especially on the “chasm” between early adopters and the
early majority, emphasizing that many technologies do not make it across
to adoption by the early majority. LP stereo and CD recordings made
it across and evolved to the point where the most conservative “late
majority” and even a few die-hard “laggards” adopted the technology.
CD-ROM music multimedia education discs, streaming web media, and
GarageBand software have bridged the chasm at one time or another to
the “early majority” but perhaps not to the “late majority”—they tend
to be much more conservative and less open to trying new ideas and
technologies.
Eventually the technology becomes ubiquitous as the adoption curve
reaches saturation. At this point in its evolution, as Alan Kay (Tapscott, 1999,
p. 38) suggests, it may no longer be viewed as technology. A new genera-
tion assumes it always existed; or, it has been replaced and the new generation
never knew it existed. Our students of today do not view the CDs, MP3s,
desktop computers, and the Internet as “technology.”
How the adoption cycle fits with our discussions of technological determin-
ism is key to appreciating the technology-music dance and the democratiza-
tion of music engagement through technology. Where technology determines
application in music, I would suggest, is in the innovator and early adopter
stages. It is typically those who are most curious and most technology pro-
ficient who are willing to hang out on the leading edge and experiment with
ways to use technology in music making and music education. At this point
in the cycle instructional quality may be overwhelmed by the demands or
constraints of the innovative technology. A case in point is the considerable
variability in the current quality of music education apps for Android and
iOS devices—still in the innovator and early adopter stages—where the risk
of technology undermining instructional quality is most likely. Where “soft
146 David Brian Williams
determinism” comes into play is when the technology applications cross the
“chasm” to the early and late majority and pedagogy hopefully dominates.
For music in society at large, the cultural contexts of “human practice, habi-
tat, and habit” (Thibeault, p. 135) determine whether the technology is use-
ful and eventually becomes ubiquitous.
Tools that are adopted in society and bring freedom of musical expression,
unfortunately, do not necessarily make it across the chasm to adoption in
the music classroom. Someone shared an analogy a few years ago compar-
ing a classroom teacher to a physician. A doctor of 50 years ago, if trans-
ported ahead to the present, would be lost using the medical technology of
today. An educator or music educator transported ahead 50 years would
be at home enough to function as a teacher. The music teacher would find
comfort in the piano and chalkboard (or Smart Board essentially being used
like a chalkboard).
Change in education, as the Woodrow Wilson quote cogently expressed,
is very slow. Surveys by Reese (2003), Dorfman (2008), and Dammers
(2012) have found that music teachers are more likely to be in the majority
of adopters (early and late) only for technology that helps them personally:
word processing, notation software, email and web browsing, and the like.
Reese (2003) did a four-year follow-up of a 1998 survey of music teach-
ers in Illinois. “Administrative and communication uses of computers,” he
reported, as well as “uses away from students to prepare teaching materi-
als[,] continue to dominate the purposes for which teachers use comput-
ers most often” (p. 79). Confirming Reese, Dorfman (2008) found music
teachers in Ohio “tend to use technology more for personal pursuits and
for planning purposes than they do in pedagogical scenarios in which stu-
dents are engaged with technology” (p. 33). And in the most recent study,
Dammers (2012) concluded that “while previous surveys . . . have found
that instructional use of technology in music classrooms lags behind teach-
ers’ productivity uses, . . . a relatively small number of music educators are
moving beyond technology integration to teaching music in an environment
where technology is a defining factor” (p. 81).
These studies emphasize that few technologies make it across the chasm
to the early majority when it comes to integrating technology into the music
curriculum. Such a push back from the classroom culture would seem to
defy any notion of technological determinism. To use Tobias’s terms, the
non-technology constraints mask any consideration of affordances. Those
constraints being teachers’ time, energy, budget, lack of motivation, and lack
of experience and training with the technology.
148 David Brian Williams
VISIONING FOR THE FUTURE: THE CHALLENGE
Let us center our focus now on the key issue that overrides all others.
I return to the opening quote by John Blacking that music is a species-
specific behavior of humans; everyone has a natural, inborn desire to
engage with music in some form. When I try and make sense of the “tools”
and what the future may hold, the evidence provided in the readings offers
broad guidance for using the tools of music technology in society at large to
enable anyone to engage in musical expression. The significant challenge,
however, remains bridging the chasm to early and late majority adopters of
music technology in the classroom (the teachers) and effectively using the
technology in support of music teaching and learning. This is where music
education needs to be the most diligent in finding clarity for “making sense
of our tools.”
What can we do to serve this long-standing need? Briefly, I offer two pro-
posals among many we might consider: more inclusive training in technology
at the undergraduate level of music and, secondly, as educators, embracing
a model for curriculum development that ensures that technology supports
instructional strategy and is not a determinant of instruction.
Training
Peter Webster and I (Williams & Webster, 2013) have attempted, over the
past three years, to define a core set of technology competencies for which
every undergraduate music student should be able to demonstrate profi-
ciency before graduating. Our surveys of college music faculty have validated
the critical need for competency in using notation software; understanding
digital audio concepts, basic techniques for digital recording, and creating
a CD or streaming audio file; building a basic music workstation; using
presentation software; basic video editing; and understanding copyright and
intellectual property rights related to music.
We also have gathered data on how these competencies are taught and
the support and long-term planning schools have provided to ensure that
technology skills are integral to music learning. Fifty-eight percent of the
respondents in our most recent study indicated that “little is being done,” or
there is “little interest” in planning for delivery of music technology. Some
30% of respondents felt that students come to college with the necessary
skills and understanding or they acquire them on their own without need for
formal instruction. In contrast, Dammers and Phillips (2011), in examining
the technology skills of high school students intending to major in music
technology, reported that college instructors found them poorly prepared
for more advanced music technology study.
What can we deduce from this evidence? Primarily that music technology
competency is not a universal priority among undergraduate music pro-
grams in the United States, and how and where it is taught is not clearly
The Technology-Music Dance 149
defined or endorsed. The assumption that students learn these skills on their
own may be unfounded and demands further study.
Return to the analogy of the physician and the classroom teacher. The
physician’s world of practice has radically changed over 50 years because
technology is thoroughly embedded in required medical training and ongo-
ing professional development. Until we take this same strategy in college
music, not just for the music education curriculum, but throughout the
music undergraduate curriculum, our music teachers will enter the school
environment with minimal or no baseline skills for using technology in per-
formance, arranging and composing, engaged listening, presentations, and
instruction. Hence, when looking back across the chasm to the innovators
and early adopters in our profession, they are overwhelmed with finding
the time, motivation, and the skill sets to assimilate new technologies—all
those wonderful tools that these three chapters so generously and richly
present.
Figure 9.2 Mishra and Koehler’s (2006) TPACK model showing the dynamic and
transactional relationship between the three components and knowledge acquisition.
(Reproduced by permission of the publisher, © 2012 by tpack.org)
I recommend Dorfman’s and Bauer’s texts for further study of TPACK; the
model is extensively developed for integrating technology into music educa-
tion practice.
Clearly the three themes I proposed at the outset of this response to “Mak-
ing Sense of Our Tools” come through all of the diverse and deep thinking
shared in this section of Music Education: Navigating the Future. The tech-
nology-music dance is constantly evolving and absorbing changes in tech-
nology, the dance plays out in society at large and, hopefully, in the future,
to a much greater extent in the music classroom. At certain key points in the
evolution some dimension of music making is democratized and facilitates
for an ever greater population of people the ability to express themselves
with music as never before. The summary point I am hopeful you as the
152 David Brian Williams
reader take away is the need for making sense of the tools from a classroom
and pedagogical vantage point to ensure that what is accessible in society is
also used to enable new and improved ways for all of our students to learn
about and experience the multiple dimensions of music making.
In closing, as one who has been an innovator and early adopter in the
technology adoption cycle for music since the mid-1960s, I’d like to offer a
set of ten predictions for new technologies in the future:
Quoting Buzz Lightyear from Toy Story, “to infinity and beyond!”
NOTES
1. References cited in the chapters will not be restated in the Reference list below
and page numbers will refer to location in the respective chapter, not in the
original source.
2. The term “musicking” is defined by Christopher Small (1998, p. 9) as tak-
ing part in a “musical performance, whether by performing, by listening,
by rehearsing, or practicing, by providing material for performance (what is
called composing), or by dancing.”
REFERENCES
Bauer, W. I. (2014). Music learning today: Digital pedagogy for creating, performing,
and responding to music. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Blacking, J. (1973). How musical is man? Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Dammers, R. J., & Phillips, S. L. (2011, October). Making the connection: A study
of secondary and collegiate music technology programs. National Conference of
the Association for Technology in Music Instruction (ATMI) and College Music
Society (CMS). Richmond, VA.
Dammers, R. J. (2012). Technology-based music classes in high schools in the United
States. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education, 194, 73–90.
Dorfman, J. (2008). Technology in Ohio’s school music programs: An exploratory
study of teacher use and integration. Contributions to Music Education, 35,
23–46.
Dorfman, J. (2013). Theory and practice of technology-based music instruction.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Farrell, C. (2013, October 01). Why classical music is imperiled—sort of. Bloomberg
Businessweek. Retrieved November 12, 2013, from www.businessweek.com/
articles/2013–10–01/why-classical-music-is-imperiled-sort-of
Gross, D. B. (2013, July). Slooooooow: U.S. slips to 9th in Internet speed. CNNTech.
Retrieved from www.cnn.com/2013/07/24/tech/web/us-internet-speed
Johnston, L. D., O’Malley, P.M., Bachman, J. G., & Schulenberg, J. E. (1976–2009).
Monitoring the future: A continuing study of American youth (8th, 10th, 12th grade
surveys). Retrieved September 10, 2011, from www.icpsr.umich.edu/icpsrweb/
ICPSR/ssvd/studies?prefix=M
154 David Brian Williams
Leap Motion. (2013). Retrieved November 15, 2013, from www.leapmotion.com
Makey Makey. (2013). Retrieved November 15, 2013, from www.makeymakey.com
Mishra, P., & Koehler, M. J. (2006). Technological pedagogical content knowledge:
A framework for teacher knowledge. Teachers College Record, 108(6), 1017–54.
Moore, G. A. (2006). Crossing the chasm: Marketing and selling disruptive products
to mainstream customers. New York, NY: Harper Business.
Musiccreativity.org. (2013). Retrieved November 15, 2013, from http://musiccreativity.
org
MusicFirst: Cloud-based tools for music educators. (2013). Retrieved November 15,
2013, from www.musicfirst.com
NAMM (National Association of Music Merchants) (2003, April 21). Gallup orga-
nization reveals findings of “American attitudes toward making music” survey.
Retrieved November 13, 2013, from www.namm.org/news/press-releases/gallup-
organization-reveals-findings-american-atti
Reese, S. (2003). Four years of progress: Illinois teachers and schools using technol-
ogy. Illinois Music Educator, 63(3), 78–81.
Rogers, E. M. (2003). Diffusion of innovations (5th Ed.). New York, NY: Free Press.
Shamoon, E. (2013, October 18). World’s first live “wireless opera” baffles commut-
ers at L.A.’s union station. TechHive, Retrieved November 13, 2013, from www.
techhive.com/article/2056180
Sheets, H. M. (2013, October 25). Artists take up digital tools. New York Times.
Retrieved October 25, 2013, from www.nytimes.com/2013/10/27/arts/artsspecial/
artists-take-up-digital-tools.html
Small, C. (1998). Musicking: The meanings of performing and listening. Middletown,
CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Surry, D. W. & Ely, D. P. (2007). Adoption, diffusion, implementation, and insti-
tutionalization of educational technology. Unpublished manuscript, College of
Education, University of South Alabama, Mobile, AL. Retrieved from www.
usouthal.edu/coe/bset/surry/papers/adoption/chap.htm
Tapscott, D. (1999). Growing up digital: The rise of the net generation. New York:
Oracle Press.
Williams, D. B. (2012). The non-traditional music student in secondary schools of
the United States: Engaging non-participant students in creative music activi-
ties through technology. Journal of Music, Technology, and Education, 4(2–3),
131–47.
Williams, D. B., & Webster, P. R. (2008). Experiencing music technology (3rd Ed.).
Boston, MA: Cengage Learning.
Williams, D. B., & Webster, P. R. (2013, November). Defining undergraduate music
technology competencies and strategies for learning: A third-year progress report.
Paper delivered for The College Music Society/Association for Technology in
Music Instruction National Conference, Cambridge, MA. Retrieved from http://
teachmusictech.com/resources.html
10 Understanding the Tools
Technology as a Springboard
for Reflective Musicking
Frank Heuser
Every January, musicians of all flavors from the wide-ranging musical sub-
cultures of Southern California make a pilgrimage to Anaheim, not to visit
the amusement park that made the city famous, but rather to attend the win-
ter exhibition of the National Association of Music Merchants. Although
it is intended primarily for manufactures and music retailers, the annual
NAMM show is also a place where symphonic and studio performers,
concert artists and music educators gather to examine the innovations the
industry has developed over the previous year. Perhaps one of the most sig-
nificant revelations occurred at the 1983 NAMM show when Dave Smith,
the CEO of the synthesizer company Sequential Circuits Inc., publically
introduced the newly standardized Musical Instrument Digital Interface by
connecting a Prophet 600 with a Roland Jupiter-6 synthesizer (Chadabe,
2000; Holmes, 2003; Manning, 2013). Even at the moment of its birth, the
potential of MIDI to impact and shape the future of music seemed obvious.
The impending evolution of electronic media would soon blur established
definitions and challenge previous understandings of how music would be
created, accessed, learned, and understood as an incredible range of digital
tools were developed and became increasingly available over the subsequent
decades.
The three chapters in the portion of this book titled Making Sense of
our Tools provide historical context to the changing technologies that are
intertwined with all aspects of music and musicking. These chapters also
challenge music educators to give careful consideration to how these tools
will mediate traditional understandings and practices in the field as tech-
nologies open new avenues of creating, performing, interacting with and
conceptualizing music. Technology has, of course, always influenced music.
The mechanical innovations taking place as the harpsichord evolved into the
fortepiano induced Haydn and Mozart to abandon the earlier instrument
(Hess, 1953). Structural changes in the piano, which included an expanded
range, iron framing, steel strings, and felt hammers, allowed Beethoven and
subsequent composers to explore new expressive possibilities as sustaining
power improved in the instrument (Erlich, 1990). Increased neck length
(Rosen, 1971) changed the sound of the violin, and newly designed bows by
156 Frank Heuser
Francois Tourte allowed composers to write music which would have been
impossible to perform had it not been for the technological evolution of this
seemingly simple marriage of wood and horse hair (Ervin, n.d.). As the 19th
century progressed, the emerging virtuoso performers enabled by technolog-
ical enhancements in brass and woodwind instruments allowed composers
to explore and challenge the technical limits of those improved instruments.
However, the limits of composition were not always determined by technol-
ogy. In the Rite of Spring, Stravinsky chose to write beyond the conventional
range of the bassoon, thereby compelling future generations of performers
to extend the upper limits of playing (Grymes, 1998).
In contrast to the types of technological changes that impacted how music
was presented and composed in the era of performance, Matthew Thibeault
provides a compelling account of how the music listener, the music listen-
ing experience, and the ways we think about music have evolved since the
advent of sound recording. The jarring differences between the dichotomous
musical and social worlds depicted by James Joyce and Richard Powers
contextualize how new media influences the musical lives of young people
currently learning in our universities. Although students come into the acad-
emy having listened to a vast amount of recorded music, the curriculum
offered by most university music departments often seems as though we are
still preparing students to enter the acoustical world of pianist Mary Jane
and vocalist Aunt Julia, so aptly depicted by Joyce. The curricular tradi-
tions preserving this approach to music study remain beholden to practices
established in early German conservatories that emphasized preparation for
careers in orchestras and opera houses. It is understandable that perfor-
mance faculty members, whose own rigorous conservatory training enabled
achievement at a high professional level in Western art music, might have dif-
ficulty conceiving of university instruction being delivered in any other way.
However, modern students often lead multiple musical lives in which their
own interests in popular genres, world music, and digital media remain clan-
destine. By acknowledging and embracing the new media world described
by Powers, the academy might develop new conceptions of musicianship
that could in turn provide their students with the tools needed to creatively
renew their musical ideals. By juxtaposing these two authors in his essay,
Thibeault provides a view of where music has been and a glimpse of where
music education must go in the future.
The fears expressed in “The Menace of Mechanical Music” were fre-
quently echoed by acoustic musicians in the months immediately following
the introduction of MIDI. Like Sousa, music educators were also concerned
about what impact technology might have on the inclination of future gen-
erations to submit to the discipline required to learn the craft of live music
making. Similar apprehensions have recently been articulated by former
Rolling Stones bassist Bill Wyman who expressed disdain regarding tech-
nologically enabled video games such as Rock Band because “it encourages
kids not to learn, that’s the trouble. It makes less and less people dedicated
Understanding the Tools 157
to really get down and learn an instrument. I think [that] is a pity so I’m
not really keen on that kind of stuff” (quoted in Masters, 2009). Reiterating
this view is Pink Floyd’s Nick Mason who found that Rock Band “irritates
me having watched my kids do it—if they spent as much time practicing the
guitar as learning how to press the buttons they’d be damn good by now”
(Masters, 2009). It seems ironic that these artists, both of whom earned a
considerable portion of their living through recording, would be echoing the
sentiments of Sousa from a century earlier. There is just a hint in Thibeault’s
essay that current undergraduate music education students may hold views
similar to these two rock musicians. Even though future music teachers have
grown up in the new media era, they may not be immediately welcoming
of technology in their future professional work. Their comments about the
need to make musical judgments based on live performances suggest that
many maintain educational ideals more in tune with the world described by
Joyce than of the new media era in which they matured.
Understanding new media remains challenging because the rate of tech-
nological progress is constantly accelerating and requires a willingness to
navigate a multiplicity of continuously evolving meanings. Even those deeply
immersed in the digital world portrayed by Powers in “Modulation” can be
confused by the plethora of constantly emerging terms associated with new
media. Although a chapter titled “Inter/trans/multi/cross/new media(ting):
Navigating an emerging landscape of digital media for music education”
may seem intimidating, it is an accessible introduction to the terminology
and cultural concepts currently associated with the relentlessly expanding
arena of music technology. Evan Tobias offers a road map of newly emerg-
ing technologies and examples of how these technologies are beginning to
allow music educators to reconceptualize music pedagogy and curriculum.
More importantly, he urges music educators to move beyond concentrating
on the medium and instead to examine the “larger contexts and systems in
which media, musicking, and education exist.” Tobias does this by “focus-
ing on cultural contexts and overarching frameworks of which digital media
are a part.”
Music education exists in multiple cultural contexts and the chapter pro-
vides examples of how music learning might be enhanced and mediated by
innovative use of new media. The opening description of audience members
interacting via digital media with one another during an actual performance
immediately captures our attention. The very thought of being in a concert
hall in which the glow of numerous digital screens is allowed to infringe
on the darkness that usually enforces singular concentration on the aes-
thetic products emanating from the stage is antithetical to the indoctrina-
tion regarding concert etiquette most people receive in the course of their
musical education. Does encouraging individuals to communicate during a
concert suggest that the importance of performance is becoming less valued,
or might such interaction instead actually nurture reflective engagement
with music as the sound and multiple conceptual ideas about a performance
158 Frank Heuser
unfold in real time? Questions of this nature challenge commonly held for-
malistic ideals of music as an aesthetic object.
The types of online tools available for interacting with music, analyzing
music, and understanding music challenge traditional notions of how music
should be learned. Traditionally, music education has compartmentalized
musical elementals and placed overt importance on pitch and rhythm. At
least one critic of this approach (Pratt, 1998) maintains that the focus on
pitch and rhythm, which are the most prominent aspects of standard western
notation, results from the ease with which those elements might be assessed
and points to difficulties in evaluating understandings of musical elements
such as timbre and texture. Tobias suggests that this type of analysis might
be facilitated through the use of multimedia spectrograms (Thibeault, 2011)
and provides descriptions of other digital tools and apps that might allow
music educators to move beyond a “mono-media focus on music.” How-
ever, the author repeatedly warns that particular technologies and applica-
tions must not be the focal point of instruction. New media should instead
be used to inform instruction and develop curricula that expand musical
thinking as well as enable creativity.
Using new media in the service of music learning requires the capacity to
reflect on and theorize about how this might be accomplished. Just as the abil-
ity to hear and identify musical structures is refined as one learns to apply
specific labels acquired through the study of music theory, the capacity for
understanding effective uses of digital media will be enhanced as our profes-
sion cultivates a sophisticated vocabulary for describing and discussing this
emerging field. The first part of the chapter’s title, “Inter/trans/multi/cross/
new media(ting),” suggests that we are entering an educational landscape
that will require music teachers to develop proficiency in using very specific
terminology for the purposes of understanding how these media are being
used as well as how meaningful learning experiences can be constructed and
implemented. The author provides several frameworks for understanding
and theorizing about the multiple roles new or digital media might play in
music education. Understanding the frameworks presented in the chapter,
including the concepts of convergence culture(s) and participatory culture(s)
as well as those specific to media including multimedia, intermedia, and
transmedia, will become essential for interpreting and meaning making when
working and teaching with new media. Fluency with these terms will allow
teachers to clarify basic concepts by identifying both broad and specific
categories of practice thereby facilitating analysis and theory building. This
in turn should permit music educators to relate the design of instructional
activities using new media to the foundational premises of music education.
From my perspective, Tobias has done a masterful job of collecting and
codifying the currently available vocabulary that is central to understand-
ing new media from a variety of disparate sources. More importantly, he
provides an example of how to think about digital media so that discussions
might become nuanced in ways that allow for multiple understandings and
outcomes rather than reduced to discrete characteristics or technologies.
Understanding the Tools 159
The clearly articulated message that using new media requires critical
awareness of how these tools must purposefully contribute to music learning
rather than become a means of amusement is a perfect prelude to the chapter
“Is It the Technology? Challenging Technological Determinism in Music
Education.” The essays in this chapter provide three distinct and ultimately
hopeful perspectives on technological determinism. Collectively, they can be
seen as a call to examine critically the ways new technologies are impacting
music, music consumption, and music learning. They also serve as an appeal
to apply a critical lens to traditional practices in music education so that we
can develop increasingly nuanced understandings of the possibilities and
limitations inherent in all instructional practices.
The concepts of affordances and constraints developed by Tobias offers
a framework for examining technology critically and thereby avoiding the
pitfalls that might be experienced when incorporating digital technologies
in well-established educational processes. One example of the necessity to
look at the affordances and constraints of technological solutions to edu-
cational issues is in the realm of piano instruction. Traditionally students
have needed to practice on an excellent acoustic piano in order to acquire
the touch and motor skills necessary to develop beautiful tone production.
Unfortunately, the financial burden of purchasing a high quality piano
precludes many learners from being able to practice regularly on such an
instrument thereby placing a major constraint on their ability to develop
performance skills. For learners hoping for an affordable alternative, the
relatively new Yamaha DGX-650 portable grand promises the touch of an
acoustic piano and the tone quality of a Yamaha concert grand. With a street
price of less than one thousand dollars and advertised to build “the proper
finger technique for when the time comes to perform on an acoustic piano”
(Yamaha Corporation of America, 2014), this digital instrument seems like
the perfect substitute for a far more expensive grand piano. However, the
development of proper keyboard technique depends on learning to listen for
subtle gradations and improvements in tone quality that occur as a result
of increasingly effective playing mechanics. Because the tone quality of an
acoustic piano varies depending on the way the fingers press the keys, the
aural feedback a student receives while practicing enables refinements in
finger technique. This important but somewhat unrecognized characteristic
of acoustic pianos is not present in the synthesized sounds generated from
digital instruments that produce a consistent tone quality regardless of play-
ing mechanics. Without aural feedback from an instrument that allows for
both good and poor tone quality, proper piano finger technique may not
emerge. This suggests that although a digital piano might make excellent
economic sense, it might not be the ideal instrument for a student at certain
stages of the learning process.
The limitations of a specific digital instrument depicted in the forego-
ing discussion provide one small example of the subtle and nuanced issues
that must be considered when incorporating new media and digital music
making into music education. Both the affordances and constraints must be
160 Frank Heuser
known, acknowledged, and examined with regards to how each contributes
to or limits music learning. An understanding of the strengths and shortcom-
ings of digital music making allows thoughtful teachers to guide students
and their parents in a direction that will provide a meaningful musical edu-
cation to each learner. All must realize that constraints may be outweighed
by the affordances offered by any given pathway. Continuing with the piano
example, the affordances of a digital keyboard such as the ability to record
audio files or practice with recordings of popular songs may prove more
valuable than the constraints synthesized tone places on the development of
proper finger technique. Some learners, especially those who never plan to
play on an acoustic piano, may prefer practicing on a synthesizer that has
multiple built in recording and playback options even though developing the
sensitivity to subtle changes that are a result of proper finger technique on
an acoustic piano might nurture better playing mechanics. This comparison
of synthesized and acoustically produced piano tone implies that decisions
about affordances and constraints must be made in regards to all instruc-
tional tools, not just digital instruments and new media.
The degree to which the technological resources of any era influence
cultural understandings and determine educational practices often remain
unexamined. Just as digital natives may have little insight about how the
technologies they so fluently use impact their understanding of the world,
those of us who practice established forms of music education can be some-
what naive about the ways that the non-digital technologies which enable
traditional music practices also can determine how music is taught, what
students learn, and what becomes valued in music education. As discussed
earlier in this chapter, technology has always played a vital role in music
and music learning. Without the mass production of woodwind, brass and
percussion instruments, the school band movement could not have become
a defining feature of music education in the United States. The universal
presence of large performing groups in communities throughout the country
might lead to the assumption that participating in school ensembles auto-
matically develops musical concepts and literacy. Yet the technology through
which instruction is delivered, usually in the form of printed method books
and sheet music, may often constrain learning to the narrow range of skills
needed to decode Western notation and assume a predefined position within
a school ensemble. The materials included in method books tend to develop
and reinforce a very specific set of performing skills rather than nurture the
broad range of musical concepts, aural skills, and creative abilities needed for
informed musical citizenship (Heuser, 2007). The constraints described here
are not “inherent or embedded in the technology” of instrumental method
books but are instead the result of an instructional vision that values ensemble
membership over the development of individual musicianship. Even traditional
educational technologies can be deterministic when used unreflectively.
We have seen how the seemingly straightforward process of choosing a
keyboard or using an instrumental method book may determine the nature
Understanding the Tools 161
of the musical skills a learner eventually develops. As emerging technologies
find their way into instructional settings, we must critically assess what it is
we want students to learn and remain cautious so that technology does not
dictate how we teach or become more important than the musical values that
we seek to instill. Perhaps both the best and worst aspects of technological
determinism can be found in iPads as they are brought into music-learning
settings. The elegant design of these tablets allows even novice musicians to
easily manipulate sounds through programs like GarageBand. When used
reflectively, the applications available on the iPad can become a catalyst for
developing musical concepts. The kinds of discussions about aesthetic values
that are rarely possible in school ensemble settings are readily facilitated
by asking students to justify the stylistic or timbre choices they make when
creating an arrangement in GarageBand. Understanding the rhythmic skills
needed for ensemble performance can be nurtured as students compare a
recording they make in real time to a quantized version of their own work.
Asking the right questions changes an iPad ensemble from just a perform-
ing group into a forum for exploring musical thought processes. However,
without carefully guided reflective questions, the musical escapades of iPad
users might provide no deeper levels of musical knowledge than that a group
of teens acquires from playing “Heart & Soul” on a camp piano. The avail-
ability of predetermined tracks in GarageBand can be used simply to create
musical products that are immediately satisfying to the user but provide no
basic understanding of underlying musical concepts or values. The same dan-
gers will be present when using iPads in ensemble settings.
Presumably, tablets offer unlimited possibilities for use in music-learning
settings. A quick review of the Apple App Store reveals incredible numbers
of products including music-learning games for children, practice aids such
as iReal, a wide variety of virtual instruments, to sophisticated recording and
music-creation applications. When thoughtfully used for music instruction,
students can form ensembles via wireless networks, practice aural skills, and
compose without needing to know music notation. As enticing as these pos-
sibilities seem, music educators must, as with all technology, be critical and
reflective so as to avoid using tablets and applications in deterministic ways.
We must be aware that, as Jaron Lanier (2013) suggests, tablets “enforce
a new power structure . . . by running . . . only programs and applications
approved by a central commercial authority.” Because many of the programs
running on tablets are extremely enticing to young people, we must avoid
succumbing to their flashiness and make sure that we use them in a way that
empowers students rather than nurtures intellectual laziness. John Naughton
(2013), a professor of the public understanding of technology at the Open
University, critically warns that technologies such as the Macintosh computer
frees users “from the need to make decisions,” suggesting that the “hard
determinism” described by Randles may be unavoidable when using Apple
products. It is difficult to imagine music technology without the contribu-
tions that have been developed as a result of the elegant Apple operating
162 Frank Heuser
system. However, Naughton’s advice implores us to be as analytical about
this family of hi-tech products as we are of all the technology creeping into
the music education arena. By juxtaposing the concepts of “hard” and “soft
determinism,” Randles suggests that what might be viewed as a constraint on
creativity can instead become “a mechanism that assists individuals in devel-
oping their own capacities for self-expression.” Although his contribution to
this chapter could be read as a Festschrift for Steve Jobs, his insights regard-
ing technological determinism along with the imaginative views of Matthew
Thibeault, who explores ways determinism can make sense, provide our pro-
fession with a hopeful view of how new media and music technology might
be used for the betterment of music education.
The three chapters in Making Sense of our Tools explore different aspects
of how music is viewed, the ways technology and digital media mediate under-
standings of music, and how music educators must become critically reflective
of technology in order to avoid potential negative possibilities. An essential
step for any emerging new discipline is the creation of its own vocabulary, to
which these chapters have made a substantial contribution. The terms intro-
duced by these authors will facilitate reflection and critical assessment of the
multiple roles new media will play in music education. As we moved from an
era of acoustic music making to one of digital media musicking, the writers
reminded us that what it once meant to be a musician and what it once meant
to listen to music has and will continue to change. This suggests that our pro-
fession has an obligation to maintain critical awareness about the ways the
persistent evolution of music and technology will transform the ways people
will want to learn music. While reading these chapters, it is clear that the
authors hope the new media we are beginning to embrace might result in
greater reflection about what it means to teach music. It is my hope that such
reflection will extend to all approaches toward music education, traditional
as well as digital. A profession that is constantly asking questions about the
nature of music, the nature of musical understanding, and the nature of music
learning will, to paraphrase Matthew Thibeault, lead to more profound under-
standings, improved questions, and more nuanced instructional approaches
that will advance our work in music education.
REFERENCES
Chadabe, J. (2000). Part IV: The seeds of the future. Electronic Musician, XVI(5).
Retrieved November 13, 2013, from www.emusician.com/gear/0769/the-electronic-
century-part-iv-the-seeds-of-the-future/145415.
Erlich, C. (1990). The piano: A history. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Ervin, (n.d.). “The Tourte model bow.” Retrieved November 5, 2013, from www.
ervinviolins.com/tourte_bows.shtml.
Grymes, J. A. (1998). Dispelling the myths: The opening bassoon solo to the Rite
of Spring. The Journal of the International Double Reed Society, 26. Retrieved
July 14, 2014, from www.idrs.org/publications/PublicationsIndex/recordlist.php?-
skip=1238&-max=25
Understanding the Tools 163
Hess, A. G. (1953). The transition from harpsichord to piano. The Galpin Society
Journal, 6, 75–94. Retrieved September 12, 2013, from www.jstor.org/stable/
841719.
Heuser, F. (2007). A theoretical framework for examining foundational instructional
materials supporting the acquisition of performance skills. In A. Williamson &
D. Coimbra (Eds.), Proceedings of the International Symposium on Performance
Science 2007. Utrecht, Netherlands: The European Association of Conservatoires
(AEC).
Holmes, T. (2003). Electronic and experimental music: Pioneers in technology and
composition. New York, NY: Routledge.
Lanier, J. (2013). Digital Passivity. The New York Times. Retrieved November 30,
2013, from www.nytimes.com/2013/11/28/opinion/digital-passivity.html?ref=
turningpoints2014&_r=0
Manning, P. (2013). Electronic and computer music. New York, NY: Oxford University
Press.
Masters, T. (2009). Rock stars cool over video games. Retrieved November 30,
2013, from http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/entertainment/8242749.stm
Naughton, J. (2013). The church of Apple tests the faith of its flock. Retrieved
November 30, 2013, from www.theguardian.com/technology/2013/nov/17/apple-
mavericks-upgrade-naughton
Pratt, G. (1998). Aural awareness: Principles and practice. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Rosen, C. (1971). The classical style. New York, NY: Norton.
Thibeault, M. D. (2011). Learning from looking at sound: Using multimedia spectro-
grams to explore world music. General Music Today, 25, 50. (Originally published
online July 27, 2011). doi: 10.1177/1048371311414050
Yamaha Corporation of America, (2014). Portable Grand DGX-650 Digital Piano.
Retrieved November 14, 2013, from http://usa.yamaha.com/products/musical-
instruments/keyboards/digitalkeyboards/dgx_series/dgx-650/
This page intentionally left blank
Part III
Visualizing Expansion
This page intentionally left blank
11 Liminal or Lifelong
Leisure, Recreation, and the Future
of Music Education
Roger Mantie
Clearly, in the first half of the 20th century the learning and teaching of
music was connected with an appreciation of leisure and recreation, aspects
viewed as central to “the good life” and the “art of living.” Leisure was
not necessarily conceptualized by these early music educators in its purest
Aristotelian sense, of course, but, consistent with Progressive Era ideals that
considered education as a developmental process aimed at both vocation
and avocation, the learning of music in schools was very much rational-
ized on the basis of its potential for leisure time use. One learned music in
schools, in other words, in order to use it (i.e., play or sing it recreationally)
beyond the school years.
By the late 1950s, however, one no longer finds many references to leisure
and/or recreation in the scholarly discourses relating to the rationalization
or justification for teaching music. Max Kaplan’s (1955) Music in Recre-
ation: Social Foundations and Practices and Charles Leonhard’s (1952) Rec-
reation through Music appear to mark the end of scholarly concern with
leisure and recreation among most music education academics. The found-
ing of the International Society for Music Education (1955) and Journal of
Research in Music Education (1953), and the publication of Basic Concepts
in Music Education (Henry, 1958) and Foundations and Principles of Music
Education (Leonhard & House, 1959), all represent a shift in emphasis,
whereby music education was to be treated as a serious academic subject
170 Roger Mantie
concerned primarily with—at least until the 1990s—“aesthetic education,”
not the “nice but not necessary” interests of leisure and recreation. Notably,
the words leisure and recreation* (* here signifying a wildcard to account
for recreational) do not appear in the index of Foundations and Principles
of Music Education. In Basic Concepts in Music Education the word leisure
(but not recreation, which appears only twice in the entire book) shows up
in the index under music, listed “as an activity of leisure.” The eight appear-
ances of the word leisure occur over the space of three chapters, although
only once is it discussed seriously, when John Mueller (1958), in his chapter,
“Music and Education: A Sociological Approach,” presciently writes, “There
are many who do not quite feel comfortable in the thought that music is an
activity for leisure. Such a function is not quite substantial enough and still
reflects a squeamish affinity with the frill” (p. 110). Although his discussion
makes clear he does not necessarily agree with this, he seems to have accu-
rately summarized prevailing thought with his appraisal.
Leisure and recreation do not currently register as the proper concerns of
music educators—or many other educators for that matter. Educational dis-
courses in the United States, especially those reflected in the popular media,
emphasize such things as accountability, parental choice, and standards.4 A
JSTOR search of music education journals reveals a marked decline in the
presence of the words leisure and recreation* from the 1960s onwards, with
almost no appearances from the year 2000 onwards. The words leisure and
recreation do not appear in the Handbook of Research on Music Teaching
and Learning (1992), The New Handbook of Research on Music Teach-
ing and Learning (2002), or the two-volume Oxford Handbook of Music
Education (2012).5 Nor do they appear in the indices of Bennett Reimer’s
A Philosophy of Music Education (1970, 1989, 2003) or David Elliott’s
Music Matters: A New Philosophy of Music Education (1995).6 What was
once such a fundamental part of thinking about music and education up
until the early1950s has almost completely disappeared from the profes-
sion’s vocabulary.
It could be, of course, that societal endorsement of education for leisure
and recreation growing out of the Progressive Education period was simply
a product of its time, and that the rise of the Cold War and the launch of
Sputnik resulted in wholesale changes in attitudes regarding schooling and
education, ones where leisure was relegated to the province of private, not
public, concerns. Strangely, however, the profession seems to have forgotten
its own history. Many music teachers of the 1920s through the 1960s clearly
understood their work as helping students prepare for a life worth living by
premising their own teaching of bands, orchestras, and choirs (in the case
of music educators in the United States and Canada) on at least the pos-
sibility of active music making outside of schooling.7 Today’s concerns, as
evidenced in the pages of Music Educators Journal and Journal of Research
in Music Education, show little sympathy for such a view. As I argue via my
presentation of empirical analysis in the next part of the chapter, thinking
Liminal or Lifelong 171
of music as something used by people beyond K-12 graduation, rather than
as simply a quasi-academic subject to be learned during the school years,
provides insights into the possibilities for reviving leisure as a viable aim for
music education.
In previous research (Mantie, 2013) I have argued that the college years pro-
vide what should be a temporal frame of great interest for music education
researchers, given that the college years are, in a sense, “liminal” (Turner,
1967). For many students the college years represent the first period of sus-
tained living apart from direct parental care; students are no longer children
but they are not quite adults, at least in the practical sense of the word
(see Arnett, 2000, Blatterer, 2010). It is during these years that students
exercise greater choice over their leisure, or discretionary, time. Thus, for
those who believe that school music should “make a difference” (Regelski,
2005), both immediately and, more importantly, later in life, how people
choose to spend their time when not influenced by authority figures (e.g.,
parents, teachers) provides a good measure of how successful music educa-
tion has been in its mission—assuming of course that making music beyond
the school years matters to the music education profession. This is not to
imply that making music is the only, or necessarily the best, way to experi-
ence music, nor is it to dismiss the value of the experiences had by students
in primary or secondary school music programs. Rather, it is to suggest that
the extent to which people engage in music making beyond the school years
is a significant indicator of how such an activity is regarded. What does it
communicate about the effectiveness of music education if people stop mak-
ing music at their first opportunity to do so?
The phenomenon of collegiate a cappella provides a fascinating case
study of recreational music making during this “liminal” stage in life. An
online directory of collegiate a cappella (Collegiate A Cappella Group Direc-
tory, www.collegiate-acappella.com) lists over a thousand groups at colleges
and universities throughout the United States and Canada. Thanks to televi-
sion shows like Glee and The Sing Off, and more recently the movie Pitch
Perfect,8 this form of musical activity has become more widely known in
172 Roger Mantie
recent years.9 Significantly—and not always evident from The Sing Off—
these groups are most often populated by non-music majors. While the spe-
cifics vary from institution to institution, in my own research I found that
most students were heavily involved in academics, with many sustaining full
course loads in “serious” degrees of study, such as environmental analysis,
aerospace engineering, neuroscience, bio-medical engineering, communica-
tions, human physiology, chemistry, business, international relations, and
so on. It also bears mention that the phenomenon of collegiate a cappella is
not limited to so-called second- or third-tier academic institutions. On the
contrary, prestigious institutions like Harvard and the Massachusetts Insti-
tute of Technology boast over two-dozen groups between them. That seri-
ous students at so many colleges throughout the United States volitionally
involve themselves with an intensive, time-consuming recreational activity is
intriguing. Why do these students choose to participate in this leisure activ-
ity when it takes time away from their academic studies? It is one thing to
enjoy singing and making music, it is quite another to do so while spending
substantial money to attend college in pursuit of an academic qualification
not enhanced by one’s leisure time pursuits (students typically do not receive
academic credit).
The majority (approximately 70–75%) of individuals I interviewed sang
with their high school chorus, with a minority of these “singers” also hav-
ing previously participated in high school a cappella, but only about half of
these participated in a form of a cappella analogous to the collegiate pop
style.10 Interestingly, however, other members had no previous singing back-
ground, with many identifying as instrumentalists (e.g., from a saxophonist:
“I’m more of a musician, less of a singer”). Surprisingly (or perhaps not), in
my research I found that the Music Director, or MD—an individual elected
from within and by the group, and who performs with, not in front of,
the group—was often someone who identified more as an instrumentalist
than as a singer. Although collegiate a cappella is a somewhat diverse musi-
cal practice,11 most groups are student-run, comprise 12–16 members, and
rehearse 4–6 hours per week (or more), 2–3 times per week. Groups usu-
ally perform two or more times per semester, with intense activity groups
sometimes performing almost weekly.
Collegiate a cappella can be viewed as exemplifying many of the val-
ues and characteristics hopefully desired of an education in music. Groups
are self-run, self-directed, and perform self-arranged music. As a musical
performance practice, collegiate a cappella demands a level of musician-
ship that we might hopefully desire for all people: a good sense of pitch,
part independence, rhythmic embodiment, and not least, a strong sense of
musical expression. One cannot succeed as an a cappella musician without
these four vital components. Indicative of previous musical training perhaps,
many of the groups I observed used sheet music during at least part of the
learning phase (the arrangements were generally notated), but it should be
noted that reading was not necessarily a prerequisite for participation (there
Liminal or Lifelong 173
were some non-readers and even the occasional person with little prior for-
mal music training or involvement).12
In my observations I was consistently impressed with the level of musician-
ship evident in rehearsals. Moreover, as a student-run and student-directed
group, a cappella requires a level of social interaction and cooperation that
Randall Allsup (2003) might describe as democratic. During part of each
rehearsal there was some form of business meeting where function and logis-
tics were discussed. Groups employ some form of executive, but I repeat-
edly witnessed a lot of cooperative decision making among all members.
Musically, I was continually impressed by the level of group involvement in
the process and product in rehearsals. Every single member demonstrated a
vested interest in “getting it right” and making the music better.
For this study I was particularly interested in learning about the partici-
pants’ perceptions of the balance between effort, excellence, and enjoyment,
aspects that speak to the heart of recreational involvement in music. I would
frequently challenge my interviewees: “If six hours per week gets you this
good [visualizing with my hands] and you wish to be better than that, why
not rehearse eight hours? Why not ten? Why not twenty?” In other words, I
wanted people to express the importance of musical excellence in relation to
their own enjoyment and the time and effort involved. Just how serious were
they about what Stebbins (1992, 1998) terms “serious leisure”? Although a
few participants expressed the desire for additional rehearsal time (e.g., “I
wanted to do ICCAs [International Championship of Collegiate A Cappella]
but the other girls aren’t as committed”), the vast majority felt the current
amount about right. Despite institutional variation vis-a-vis exact rehearsal
format (e.g., 2 three-hour vs. 3 two-hour rehearsals), I found it interesting
that six hours per week appeared to be the norm for all groups in spite of
the absence of formalized communications between colleges regarding such
matters. Six just seems to be the magic number that represents the maximum
regularly scheduled time that most students are prepared to commit.
Some groups do spend more than six hours in rehearsal and related activi-
ties, however. In addition to extra time devoted to preparation for concerts,
many groups record CDs.13 The single biggest factor determining whether or
not a group spends additional hours in rehearsal preparation appears to be if
they decide to participate in the International Championship of Collegiate A
Cappella—a national singing tournament, organized by Varsity Vocals, that
occurs over a period of months with regional quarter and semifinals leading
up to (at time of writing) the final competition at New York City’s Lincoln
Center. From what I could gather, everyone involved with collegiate a cap-
pella knows about the “ICCAs,” and the decision to enter the competition is
a major determinant of group identity. Some groups enter every year, some
never enter, and some consider it on a year-by-year basis.
What I found intriguing in my conversations was how various par-
ticipants understood the very obvious pecking order that existed among
groups, a reputation and performance hierarchy with serious implications
174 Roger Mantie
for auditions and, subsequently, for how students’ tenure with collegiate a
cappella would play out. To explain, groups almost always stay intact. For
schools with multiple groups, there is usually an unwritten (or even writ-
ten) rule that stipulates that people cannot switch between groups. Thus,
acceptance into a group in freshman year dictates one’s fate as a participant
from freshman through senior year. That is, acceptance into a competitive
group means one’s collegiate a cappella experience will be competitive and
vice versa. Next, consider that groups are usually 12–16 in size. This usu-
ally breaks down to 3–4 people per academic year (freshman, sophomore,
junior, senior). Although the number of people auditioning for the open
3–4 spots per group (i.e., replacing the graduated seniors) is a reflection
of the size of the institution and number of groups at that institution, I
heard numbers as high as 150 auditioning for two open spots in a group. At
larger institutions, students usually audition for multiple (or all) groups to
increase their chances. The goal for most students is to get into the “best”
groups on campus.14 These “best” groups usually compete in the ICCAs.
Most students, however, seemed to understand that just getting into a group
is an achievement, as most who audition do not make any group. In addi-
tion, while those in the lower tier groups I interviewed expressed their initial
disappointment of not making it into the group(s) of their choice (e.g., “I
wish we were more competitive”), they also, explicitly or implicitly, seemed
to understand the outcome as reflective of their own abilities. Moreover,
almost all admitted that the outcome was a blessing in disguise and that they
loved their a cappella group. (Without exception, everyone loved his or her
group.) This admission could be considered a defense mechanism of “sour
grapes,” but I sensed instead that it was, rather, reflective of their own satis-
faction of coming to a better understanding of who they were in the world.
Listening to the “best” collegiate a cappella groups live (rehearsal and per-
formance) can be quite exhilarating. A group at one university, for example,
regularly drew an audience of a thousand screaming fans reminiscent of a
rock or pop concert experience. In attending rehearsals, experiencing, in close
proximity, the power of good a cappella singing frequently gave me goose
bumps and sent shivers down my spine. As evident in my field notes above,
however, not all groups are at this refined level. Not infrequently I experi-
enced, according to Western performance norms, issues of pitch, balance, or
expression, which, for me, raised issues of public performance and associated
expectations. Just as one’s listening expectations for the elementary school
band or chorus are not the same as they are for the professional symphony
orchestra or chorus, I was left to ponder where this left the performance
efforts of recreational music making like collegiate a cappella. While I did not
personally observe any groups I would consider musically unacceptable, the
majority were, as public performing groups, just good or okay.
My own discomfort sitting through one of the quarterfinal competitions
of the ICCAs stemmed from what I perceived as a disconnection between the
purpose of the event and the raison d’être of collegiate a cappella. Attending
Liminal or Lifelong 175
this particular competition brought into stark relief the difference between
what Thomas Turino (2008) describes as participatory and presentational
music making. While collegiate a cappella does derive from a Western pre-
sentational aesthetic normed to “professional” performance standards, as a
form of amateur, recreational music making utilizing pop and rock reper-
toire it is fundamentally participatory. Although the groups do perform in
public, observing any rehearsal makes clear that the goods of the activity
reside in the joy of singing together each week. The musical embodiment I
witnessed in rehearsals was a reminder to me of what I would want for any
of my own music students. Each and every member of each group exhibited
an overt love of what they were doing irrespective of what more refined
Western trained ears might describe as flaws detractive from listening plea-
sure. However, when placed on the stage of an elegant concert hall designed
for presentational music, especially that of the high art music tradition, the
efforts of the “weaker” groups suddenly seemed unfortunate. The musick-
ing (Small, 1998) event of the rehearsal space—so intimate, personal, mean-
ingful, and amateur in the best sense—suddenly took on what I considered
to be the mean-spiritedness of the American Idol audition episodes that, for
the perverse amusement of the viewer, mock the efforts of hopefuls who are
apparently oblivious to the inadequacy of their amateur (in the worst sense)
efforts. What seemed to me as an admirable get-together of people with a
shared love of music in their rehearsal environment became, in the context
of a formal performance space, a spectacle highlighting their shortcomings
as performers (although not necessarily as musicians; it was their inexperi-
ence as performers that was glaring).
LIMINAL OR LIFELONG?
The thing about collegiate a cappella is, no one wants the party to end.
—Mickey Rapkin, Pitch Perfect
Commentators (e.g., Booth, 1999; Regelski, 2007) have lamented how the
expectation for professional level performance norms has been detrimental
for amateur music making—“amateuring” here meant in its sense of amare,
or “to love.” What is intriguing about collegiate a cappella is that the level
of passion exhibited by the students was uncorrelated with the performing
level of their group. While most students interested in collegiate a cappella
desire at the outset of their college experience to be in the high-level com-
petitive groups, the reality is that only a handful of available spots exist;
the majority end up in groups that vary from pretty good to just okay.
This, however, did not seem to affect their level of interest or commitment,
which appeared to me relatively consistent from group to group. Everyone
involved with collegiate a cappella, it seems, enthusiastically participates, as
Wayne Booth (1999) might put it, “for the love of it.”
176 Roger Mantie
And yet, this apparent love for what they do seems to blur an issue that
I believe speaks to a vitally important issue in recreational music making. I
discerned in my interviews a lot of what Isbell and Stanley (2011) describe
as “the competition paradox.” Participants generally were not willing to
sacrifice the hours necessary for the pursuit of a higher level of performance,
and were content with their group’s present level (e.g., “I don’t want to suck,
but I don’t want to put in a ton of hours to be just a little bit better”). As
the majority of participants pointed out to me, however, competition was
a regarded as a good thing and competitive performance events such as the
ICCAs serve as a necessary goal toward which groups can orient their efforts
(e.g., “you can only get so good without competition”). The paradoxical
nature of this rang through repeatedly, however. Not infrequently did people
tell me that the ICCAs were a necessary goal but that they participated for
fun, not because of the competition. As one person phrased it, “I like to be
good, but not at the expense of happiness.” The issue this raises, however, is
why a competitive goal is necessary in the first place. Is recreational partici-
pation alone—in this case, regular rehearsing and presenting the occasional
performance—considered insufficient? Are competitive events really neces-
sary for improvement and effort? Is recreational participation for its own
sake—doing something for the love of it—just a fictive notion masking a
deep-seated desire to be number one? Or, to put it in rather grand terms, is
the desire for competition driven by a conditioned, capitalistic ethic perva-
sive in Western society—one that, in its pursuit of besting others, stands in
the way of enjoying activities for their own sake?
In part, I believe the answer to this question is addressed by consid-
ering whether individuals as their participation regarded part of a life-
long involvement with music or merely as a transitional college activity.
A defining moment for me in almost every interview was the answer to
my question, “What happens after you graduate?” When coupled with
the participants’ responses to my earlier question, “Why do this?” their
description of future plans inevitably laid bare whether participants
viewed music making as a lifelong activity or merely something one did
during the college years. That is, when I asked people why they auditioned
for a cappella, most responded by saying how much they loved music or
loved singing (e.g., “I just want to be able to sing out loud and have it not
be weird”), or that they had always been part of music groups and could
not imagine not continuing to be in a music group. Others said that they
thought joining a cappella would be a good way to transition to college,
as they were likely to meet people with similar interests.
When asked about the prospect of collegiate a cappella coming to an
end, however, slightly over half of those I interviewed responded by saying
that they were scared or terrified (their words), although one or two of the
freshmen and sophomores feigned ignorance of the time-bound nature of
the activity: e.g., “I haven’t thought about it; I’ve concentrated on this last-
ing forever.”15 Clearly, however, most had thought about it to some degree.
Liminal or Lifelong 177
Some pointed out that current collegiate a cappella members are more for-
tunate than those of 5–10 years ago thanks to the rise in what participants
referred to as “post-collegiate a cappella.” One person mentioned that she
would eventually become like several of her friends, who “are now trolling
for post-collegiate a cappella.” And while some people expressed possibili-
ties for future involvement (e.g., musical theatre, starting a band, songwrit-
ing) and emphasized their passion for music making (“I can’t live without
singing; if I can’t be part of a cappella I’ll take singing lessons”), what dis-
turbed me, as a music educator, were the number of people who saw their
music making lives ending (e.g., “I think singing ends for me”) and the
number who had virtually no clue about the ways they might continue to be
musically active post-graduation. One interviewee, confessing her frustra-
tion at the thought of not being able to continue with something she loved
so much, commented, “it would be awesome if there was some after college
group out there.”
A minority, about one in three, felt that collegiate a cappella was an
activity intended for and bounded by the college years. As a member of a
highly competitive group remarked, “Last year the thought [of this end-
ing] would have destroyed me, but now I’m okay with it. I’ve had my
run.” Or as another person put it, “You have your time and then you
should move on,” a comment that serves as a reminder that, in the minds
of some, collegiate a cappella is indeed a college activity akin to student
government, the student newspaper, other student clubs, or college rituals
such as Greek life or attending sporting events on campus. Graduation,
like the Jewish bar and bat mitzvah, marks the end of this liminal period
in one’s life;16 the time for frivolous playful activities, like recreational
singing, is over.
IMPLICATIONS
CONCLUSION
We cannot undo the present state of the music education profession, but we
can make choices with the potential to change the future. We can choose
to resurrect leisure and recreation, long a fundamental rationale for school
music, as a legitimate aim and purpose for music education. Rather than
viewing “leisure” negatively, associating the word with privilege or frivolity,
we can restore its noble origins as the very definition of “the good life.” Fur-
thermore, we can restore recreational participation as a legitimate goal for
school music instruction. Appreciating music is fine; doing music, however,
holds greater potential for realizing more of music’s goodness as a healthy
and worthy use of leisure time.
Collegiate a cappella is but one example of how music is currently
engaged with recreationally for the purpose of leisure. It provides an inter-
esting case study because it occurs at a stage in life when young adults have
the autonomy to make individual choices over their use of time. That so
many choose to continue making music rather than stop at their first oppor-
tunity is encouraging. Whether or not they continue to do so after they
graduate from college will be the real litmus test of their commitment to
lifelong recreational music making, however. By continuing to study those
who remain musically active we can hopefully generate better understand-
ings that can help to orient our curricular and instructional efforts so as to
ensure that more people are able to make music a meaningful and desirable
part of their life throughout the lifespan.
180 Roger Mantie
NOTES
1. See, for example, Foucault’s essays “On the Ways of Writing History,”
“Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” and “Return to History” in Aesthetics,
Method, and Epistemology, edited by James D. Faubion (New York: New Press,
1998). Foucault’s entire oeuvre, however, tends to emphasize this message.
2. The Greek word uses chi, hence the variations in Anglicized spellings (k vs. ch
vs. kh). Moreover, in contemporary Greek the meaning of skholē depends on
the accent: stressing the first syllable means school, stressing the second means
leisure.
3. The first three of these are taken from Diana Brault’s (1977) dissertation, “A
History Of The Ontario Music Educators’ Association (1919–1974)” (The
University of Rochester). The first is from Roy Fenwick’s 1935 address to
music teachers (p. 167), the second from the 1935 Canadian School Journal
(p. 171), and the third from the Ontario government’s Chief Inspector’s Report
for 1930 (p. 505). The fourth example is from Alice Rogers’, “The Junior High
School Music Program and Some of Its Problems,” Music Supervisors’ Journal,
no. 13(1) (1926): 27. The fifth is from Joseph Leeder and William Haynie,
Music Education in the High School (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall,
1958), 100–101. The last is from a 1952 MENC publication, The Function of
Music in the Secondary-School Curriculum, 6.
4. These types of neoliberal discourses are not unique to the United States; it is
simply a context with which I am more familiar.
5. There are two very incidental references to leisure sociology (pp. 203 and 573)
in The New Handbook of Music Teaching and Learning. One, in passing, men-
tions Max Kaplan and his interest in leisure; the other simply mentions leisure
sociology as a field of study.
6. On page 7 of the first edition of Reimer’s A Philosophy of Music Education
there is a very brief mention of leisure in connection to the Progressive
Education movement.
7. As I have documented elsewhere (Mantie, 2013), this was often referred to in
the literature as “carry over.”
8. Pitch Perfect is based on a book of the same name by Mickey Rapkin, a jour-
nalist who studied three collegiate a cappella groups in the early to mid-2000s.
A similar project, but more academic in tone, is Duchan’s (2012) Powerful
Voices: The Musical and Social World of Collegiate A Cappella.
9. Contemporary interest in collegiate a cappella dates to the 1990s. Thus, it is
likely that in this case popular culture capitalized on existing social practices
before (arguably) fueling them.
10. Collegiate a cappella is technically over one hundred years old, dating back
to such groups as the Yale Whiffenpoofs. The current resurgence of interest
from the 1990s onwards, however, differs in that groups began to focus on
“popular” music (i.e., of the Billboard charts and the like) rather than, as had
been the tradition up to that point, singing published choral arrangements or
emulating barbershop or doo-wop styles. The term “collegiate a cappella”
is usually reserved for groups performing today’s “popular” music (although
many groups show great latitude in what they consider popular).
11. As per my previous note, I investigated mainstream collegiate a cappella. Many
specialized varieties, for example religious or culturally based, exist and provide
yet another potential layer of interest for researchers. My own concern was
restricted to mainstream groups without special motivators or agendas at play.
It should be noted that other forms of a cappella, such as barbershop based or
“glee” style, also exist, but represent more of a subcultural involvement com-
pared to the broadly based participation of mainstream collegiate a cappella.
Liminal or Lifelong 181
12. Clearly, however, people with no formal training must possess the requisite
musicianship: they must, in their auditions, exhibit a good sense of pitch,
rhythm, and musical expression.
13. There are websites devoted to collegiate a cappella recordings, such as www.
acatunes.com.
14. The gendered aspects of this are fascinating, insofar as the best group on cam-
pus is often all male. The all-female groups tend to lie at the bottom of the
pecking order. Alas, this aspect of collegiate a cappella requires an article of its
own and cannot be discussed here.
15. One needs to be an enrolled student to be a member. Although there are excep-
tions, collegiate a cappella is generally considered an undergraduate activity.
16. I am alluding here to the sense of liminality as a threshold, especially in rela-
tion to ceremonial markers (a la Arnold van Gennep’s “rites of passage”). The
Jewish mitzvahs, for example, ceremoniously mark the end of childhood.
17. Space does not allow for elaboration, but I have based my discussion on
Patricia Stokowski, Leisure in Society: A Network Structural Perspective (New
York: Mansell Publishers, 1994).
18. I am thinking here especially of possible variations on sites like Facebook or
meetup.com.
REFERENCES
INTRODUCTION
This chapter was written in response to the call-for-papers for the 2013 Sun-
coast Music Education Research Symposium (SMERS IX), which had the
theme of “navigating the future”—an inherently unknowable domain. In
order to negotiate the unpredictable, it seems prudent to take time to reflect
critically upon the present. To do this, I discuss three interrelated areas in
which I work as a practitioner—popular music performance, popular music
education, and scholarship in these related areas. This paper reflects my
own perspective on, and experiences in, the fields about which I write and
the issues that I discuss. It is a truism that an “invisible” authorial voice is
present in most scholarly writing; by foregrounding my own voice I wish
to highlight its centrality to my work. I could not write this paper without
my discrete positionality, so I invite readers to critique this in concert with
the other subject matter. Any assumptions that I make in this text are, there-
fore, included as part of a consciously reflective autoethnographic approach
(Chang, 2008). To exclude my subjective voice “would have been dishon-
est” (de Rond, 2008, p. xii).
I have been a drummer for 25 years, and have been self-employed as such
part-time since 1999. I have mostly performed and recorded in musical the-
atre “pit” bands, punk, rock, folk, blues, and jazz bands, and with singer/
songwriters of many a hue. I also began teaching in 1999. I taught mostly
drum set, guitar, clarinet, and general music in elementary and secondary
schools for a decade before I began working at a college of further and
higher music education—the Institute of Contemporary Music Performance
(hereafter, the Institute) in London, England. At the Institute I teach drum
set performance to undergraduates in a range of styles such as blues, rock,
and jazz; I teach ensemble classes including Creative Ensemble, Rhythm
Section Workshop, and Advanced Performance Workshop; I taught Har-
mony and Theory for two years, and increasingly I teach popular music
studies courses including Music in Context, Music and Society, Cultural and
Philosophical Studies, and History of Popular Music. I also teach Research
Skills and supervise around fifteen students annually through undergraduate
184 Gareth Dylan Smith
Dissertation courses, one of which I also lead. My work as a performer con-
tinues to inform my work as an educator, and vice versa, in a symbiosis that
breathed life to this chapter.
The Institute where I work could arguably be seen as an example of an
extension of the northern European “fait accompli,” in which popular music
is included and valued in the U.K.’s music education system (Hebert, 2011,
p. 13; Mantie, 2013, p. 342). However, the Institute is a post-compulsory,
higher education institution, broadly modeled, since its inception almost 30
years ago, on U.S. (Los Angeles) college, Musicians Institute. The pedagogi-
cal model has tended, perhaps out of a perceived need, to overtly and rig-
orously systemize and legitimize its provision, to “formalize the informal”
learning practices (Smith & Shafighian 2013, p. 257) that are typically iden-
tified as being native to popular music (Green, 2002). As the Institute’s full
name implies, the primary focus for student activity is performance of popu-
lar music (I critique the conflation of terms “popular,” “contemporary,”
and others in Smith, in press). Given that education programs in popular
music are considered (even assumed) in this context to be worthwhile—they
are the school’s raison d’être—I turn my attention to assumptions that may
underlie and inform educational practice, and the potential implications of
these assumptions in and beyond higher popular music performance educa-
tion (hereafter, HPMPE).
My emic perspective is a limiting factor in this paper, and also a strength.
Bresler and Stake (2006) advise that “in music education, we have a need
for . . . experiential understandings of particular situations” (p. 278).
Muncey (2010) adds that “subjectivity doesn’t infect your work, it enhances
it. Making links between your own experience and your [scholarly] work
is healthy” (p. 8). Muncey’s work comes from the field of health care stud-
ies, but it is clear that her observations regarding the value of reflexive,
autoethnograhpic writing speak also to the ongoing experiences of those
working in music education, and perhaps especially in the emerging, less
well-established domain of popular music education. I stand at the inter-
section of current directions in scholarly practice and music education and
find, as Muncey affirms, “there is no distinction between doing research and
living a life” (2010, p. 3).
Jorgensen (2009) advises us that “the field [of music education] is in need
of robust conceptual theories of music education” derived from research
that includes “systematically describing the field” (p. 415). I offer nothing
here so bold as a conceptual theory of this broad field. Instead, this paper
may be viewed as the type of descriptive work sought by Jorgensen, and as
a response to Mantie’s invitation in his remark that, “Researchers may wish
to document practices . . . outside of the United States to more adequately
Seeking “Success” in Popular Music 185
determine the actual extent and forms of engagement with popular musics”
in music education (Mantie, 2013, p. 347). Hopefully this paper may thus
contribute to the valuable work of colleagues attempting to construct much-
needed theories of our profession.
Williamson, Cloonan, and Frith (2011) describe a lack of trust between
professional academics who value scholarly knowledge in or from aca-
demia, and professional musicians and others in the music business who
value music knowledge in or from the popular music industry. They state
that “academics have a vital role to play in keeping the public informed in
ways that are not processed by PR companies or designed to serve corporate
ends” (Williamson, Cloonan, & Frith, 2010, p. 470). Equally important, of
course, is that scholars in music and education are able to accommodate the
knowledge of those “on the ground” in popular music performance. As I
hope to illustrate, in order to navigate the future, scholars, performers, and
educators need to share expertise in a broad dialogue that embraces the over-
lapping boundaries of music performance, scholarship, and education. As is
indicated by the literature on learning in popular music (e.g., Green, 2002,
2008; Smith, 2013a), there is often little or no distinction between musician,
educator, and learner—between music practices and music education—in
popular music. Few writers appear to be directly involved with knowledge
from these three domains; the world of HPMPE is at the crossroads. In such
a broad and under-researched field as popular music education (Mantie,
2013; Smith, 2013a), it is especially vital that all proceed with open ears,
eyes, and minds.
I seek in the following pages to describe and explore two related prob-
lems. The first of these is that HPMPE programs, courses, and institutions
may be in danger of de-valuing many popular musicians (including the over-
whelming majority of their own students, faculty, and alumni) and those
musicians’ work through adherence to a tacit and under-interrogated epis-
temology of “success.” Bennett explains how this situation exists across
higher music education: “The learning cultures within music are unlikely . . .
to encourage broad purviews of career or broad definitions of what it is to
be a successful musician” (Bennett, 2013, p. 236). As HPMPE programs
proliferate, this situation is becoming untenable, and serves our students
poorly, since “building a successful career depends on entrepreneurial activi-
ties and carving out a niche market” (Bennett, 2013, p. 235). The second
problem is that this potential epistemological deficit is accompanied and
exacerbated by the adherence to similar prohibitively exclusive assumptions
regarding success in popular music, both by scholars in the field of popu-
lar music studies, and by commentators in the wider public consciousness
and the mainstream media. The overall aim of this paper is, thus, to chal-
lenge, broaden, or recontextualize perspectives of colleagues in HPMPE and
beyond, by exploring what appear from my perspective and context to be
salient issues regarding how the HPMPE community and others construe
success in popular music.
186 Gareth Dylan Smith
POPULAR MUSIC IN EDUCATION
The fields of popular music performance and popular music studies have
infrequently collided in the extant literature. In discussing “popular music
studies,” I refer to that wide branch of scholarship championed by the Inter-
national Association for the Study of Popular Music (IASPM) that investigates
popular music textually, contextually, historically, culturally, and sociologi-
cally, having no explicit concern with music education. Popular music stud-
ies (as it is thus defined for this paper) also tends largely to exclude popular
music performance as an area of interest. Indeed, when I have, at various
IASPM conferences over the last five years, presented papers on learning and
identity in popular music education, and on the embodied experience of per-
forming popular music, I have found my studies to be somewhat anomalous
(although of sufficient interest to be accepted for presentation).
In late summer 2012, I received a call-for-papers from @IASPM, IASPM’s
online peer-reviewed journal, for a special edition that would explore popu-
lar music performance. Isolating performance in this way underlined for me
the “orthodox” assumption that when one studies popular music one is not
studying performance. A week later, as if to underscore this dichotomy, an
editorial piece in the newly reinstated IASPM U.K. and Ireland newsletter
declared that “every issue now we intend to let the other side of the fence have
their say—in each edition we will be asking a practicing musician for their
perspective and opinion on popular music studies” (McLaughlin, 2012, p.
12). In that edition of the newsletter, Rod Jones of Scottish rock band Idlewild
gives a 245-word response to this invitation, in which he talks only about the
pros and cons of popular music performance programs in the U.K.; he clearly
appears to misunderstand the question, believing “popular music studies” to
refer to the study of popular music performance, in the sense of working hard
at being a performer. This is quite an understandable error, and underlines the
centrality of performance in popular music to those who perform it—this does
look like the most obvious way to study popular music. However, to bifurcate
the two fields of “performance” and “studies” creates a false duality that is
misleading because it is at odds with the experiences of popular musicians.
I have always found difficulty in conceptually separating “popular music”
from “popular music performance,” since to me the former implies the lat-
ter. Without the performance there would be very little popular music (and
188 Gareth Dylan Smith
historically, most popular music has been performed). While this is a gross
over-simplification and could engender volumes of discussion, it is from
this perspective that I write; being a professional drummer, I have always
approached the teaching of music and writing about music and musicians as
a drummer, first and foremost. I have not, as it were, left my musicianship
at the door when entering the office to write or the performance classroom
to teach.
Attending the inaugural meeting of the U.K. Punk Scholars Network in
late 2012, it struck me that those of us who straddle McLaughlin’s “fence”
are growing in number. We are reaching a point where it is no longer healthy
or tenable—if it ever was—to maintain the epistemological barrier between
performers and scholars. This is not to say that scholars need to be perform-
ers; but rather that academia could consider using a less divisive lens. Berger
(2002) observes “a huge gap between the experience of living a normal life
at this moment on the planet and the public narratives being offered to give
a sense to that life” (p. 176). Musicians increasingly lead protean or portfo-
lio careers (Bennett, 2008, 2013; Hallam & Gaunt 2012; Partti, 2012) that
Burnard (2013) identifies as “boundary-less careers”; those of us working
in HPMPE need to recognize this as soon as possible, or else risk holding
the frame up quite a long way from the picture. Our institutions need to rec-
ognize diverse manifestations of success for musicians, and to reflect these
back, through curriculum and pedagogy, to our students so that they are
all the better prepared for navigating the future. Bennett (2013) asserts that
students across higher music education “need to form themselves for entre-
preneurship even while they are studying. This requires a future-oriented
epistemology developed within a safe study environment that rewards lead-
ing as well as learning, such that the ‘future self’ is self-defined as one who
combines knowledge and action in the creation of the new” (p. 238).
Rodriguez (2004) observes that popular music benefits from “a rich history
that is tied to our social, political, cultural, and economic history. What it
lacks, in comparison to, say, Western European music, is the passage of suf-
ficient time to determine which practices, structures, persons, and places have
most influenced the genre” (p. 17). Rodriguez’s denial of a canon in popular
music, however, runs contrary to my experience as an educator and scholar
working in HPMPE. Students at the Institute are required to take a course in
the history of popular music, part of “popular music studies” misunderstood
above by Rod Jones (McLaughlin, 2012). Literature in popular music studies
has tended to focus on the work of famous and commercially successful musi-
cians, with few exceptions. This is not unreasonable, as bands or artists that
have sold millions of albums and become recognized internationally are, by
definition, very popular. Popular music scholars have thus arguably (although
perhaps inadvertently) established a canon of Great Works and Great Mas-
ters in popular music to parallel those of the Western Classical and (more
recently) Jazz traditions (e.g., Frith, 1996; Gracyk, 1996, 2007; McLaughlin
& McLoone, 2012; Moore, 2001, 2012). Those of us in popular music educa-
tion risk embedding this view as an orthodoxy which ignores the 21st-century
“reemergence of grassroots creativity” that continues increasingly to charac-
terize artists’ and musicians’ modes of production and distribution of their
Seeking “Success” in Popular Music 193
creative products (Jenkins, 2006, p. 136). Indeed, Reynolds (2011) argues
compellingly that the obsession with its past threatens popular music’s very
survival as a paradigm; this threat is perhaps nowhere in more urgent need of
consideration than at institutions such as the Institute, whose students, alumni,
and faculty can only ever hope to have careers in the present and the future.
One of the key foci in creation and distribution of popular music has
always been the “new,” the current, music that has changed sometimes by
revolution, at others by evolution, with artists and craftspeople striving to
be novel and exciting by assimilating, synthesizing, replacing, and displac-
ing various gestures—musical, corporeal, attitudinal, social—of preceding
styles or movements that have spawned today’s plethora of musics in the
“popular” realm. Those creating and producing the music may wish for
high-profile commercial longevity, but that is not the prevalent model in
popular music, although the media have a habit of wheeling out and reify-
ing, even deifying, popular music iconic heritage acts of a former age such
as Paul McCartney and the Rolling Stones; the mind boggles at the thought
of what fate might today have befallen a withering Elvis Presley, had he
survived to the present day. There is not much room on the tiny pedestal
at the top of the media industry “tree” for musicians and bands. However,
in the “creative revolution” taking place around us and amongst us, the
dialogue and boundaries between “participatory culture and commercial
culture” (Jenkins, 2006, pp. 136–37) are becoming ever more blurred. The
tacit overarching epistemology in popular music studies needs to change and
to acknowledge this or else, as Hoskyns (2012) warns, “the most authentic
scenes will be those we know nothing about.”
Messages from mainstream media are often reductive and sometimes wholly
misleading, such as when the New Musical Express in 2002 announced the
“New Rock Revolution” (New Musical Express/Ignite!, 2002). I recall my dis-
belief at the allegation that a handful of bands selected for coverage by a high-
profile publication were suddenly rediscovering and re-inventing a genre that
had been alive and well since its inception. As far as I (along with the scores of
people I frequently encountered on London’s less well-publicized rock scene)
was concerned, there was no revolution, just a shift in the attention of main-
stream media to a style that had been ignored for a season while indie bands,
divas, and (in the U.K.) Welsh musicians were the flavor of the day. Similarly,
“the most important acts who are shaping music today” (Q, 2011)2 include hip-
hop and alternative rock artists, with a particularly high level of attention paid
to folk music musicians Laura Marling and Mumford & Sons. These artists are
not unworthy of attention, but then neither are dozens, scores, or hundreds of
comparably “good” acts. I and many of my peers have been playing folk music
for over twenty years, and will continue to do so after the cameras have turned
elsewhere for the next “new” style that will likely have long preexisted and will
long outlast the fickle media hype. Instances such as these are typical of what
Hoskyns (2012) describes as the mainstream media’s propensity for “deification
and demolition—build ’em up and knock ’em down.”
194 Gareth Dylan Smith
When I teach undergraduate popular music history I begin by telling
the students that I will not be giving them an accurate or complete his-
tory. Notions of “popular,” “music,” and “history” are so complex that
to attempt to fool students that I could comprehensively fill them in on all
the details would be arrogant, at best. I am always very nervous to canon-
ize and to reify the songs, albums, artists, genres, movements, and events
that we discuss, although I realize that by discussing them I risk canonizing
them all the more, in the minds of one class of undergraduate students at a
time. At best, I can aim to augment students’ existing—usually substantial—
knowledge of music that has gone before, and, my main task, perhaps to
encourage them to question the histories and messages that they encounter. I
discuss with the class our inevitable ignorance of the majority of music being
made in the world or even just in London at present, and, by extension, the
futility of trying to identify a definitive history of popular music.
I like to try the following exercise with my classes: I ask how many of the
students in the class are in bands making original popular music, and every
hand in the room goes up. I then ask students to keep their hands up if their
band is “any good.” Most hands remain up. Finally I ask who is in a band of
which I would have heard. Hands then all go down (apart from the occasional
hand belonging to someone who sings backup vocals or plays drums for a
high-profile pop artist on tour). These young musicians are just beginning to
find their niches in the “long tail” of the music business (Anderson, 2006),
where the traditional music industry model of selling as much as possible
of as little as possible (Cartwright & Smith, in press) is incompatible with
a now-normative, more flexible, portfolio career model. As Cartwright and
Smith (in press) point out, “Whereas once upon time such an existence would
have been construed as a paying one’s dues en route to success, for a consider-
able majority of excellent, professional musicians in the contemporary socio-
musical business environment, this is success. It is just not widely recognized
and valued as such.” Popular music studies’ prevailing focus on musicians
who have been afforded (and in the very rarest of cases may themselves have
achieved) significant mainstream and commercial success risks miss-construal
by educators, students, and the public as reflective of popular music in the
present, when it is distinctly at odds with the perspectives of musicians making
the vast majority of the world’s popular music today, that is, the very ways in
which popular music is popular in a 21st-century paradigm.
My fellow tutors and I at the Institute play music that, although in similar
styles, and using virtually all of the same gestures as more commercially suc-
cessful artists, is (if we take traditional indicators like album sales and fame
as the yardsticks of success) wholly unpopular. However, the ways that it
Seeking “Success” in Popular Music 195
sounds and is created are entirely consistent with notions of popular music
(e.g., Frith, 1996; Green, 2002; Hoskyns, 2012). We all have portfolio
careers, pieced together from a mixture of high-profile performances, low-
profile gigs, teaching, journalism, composition, and all manner of music-
related and non-music-related work. Similar work patterns are described in
detail in the work of Cottrell (2004), who studies the working lives of musi-
cians in London, Bennett (2008), who explores the practices of musicians in
Australia, and Smith (2013a), where I describe the identities and practices
of drummers in and around London. This is the modus operandi of many a
successful musician.
I consider myself to be a successful musician. I have accomplished things
of which I am proud and for which I have received praise from respected
peers; I have a secure job in HPMPE, and many “irons in the fire” for cur-
rent and future projects. This being said, I am not famous, and my income
derives largely from things other than performing. Most of the music that
I make and that I would consider truly successful in artistic and technical
terms, pays me very little. Indeed, the music that I have been paid the most
to play has frequently (although not always) been what I consider to have
been some of the least successful music, musically. In terms of the aspirations
of ISME and NAfME, my life would probably be judged to be an ongoing
story of success. In the tacit, unwritten terms of the discussion in the House
of Commons, I would probably be barely recognized as a “musician.” My
performance and recording career to date will certainly be ignored by the
overwhelming majority of IASPM-ites (as the Association’s popular music
scholars affectionately refer to ourselves).
Successful musicians today occupy unique niches as multifaceted entre-
preneurs, operating in numerous intra- and inter-disciplinary networks of
contacts with artists, writers, and colleagues from all over the world—what
Gloor (2006) in his book Swarm Creativity terms “COINs . . . collabora-
tive innovation networks” (p. 3). Work patterns like this are increasingly
common and increasingly encouraged across creative industries and other
domains—including the academia—with members of COINs collaborating
for individual as well as mutual benefit toward outcomes only achievable
with collaborative, group efforts. Gloor (2006) writes that, “In a COIN,
knowledge workers collaborate and share in internal transparency. They
communicate directly rather than through hierarchies. And they innovate
and work toward common goals in self-organization instead of being ordered
to do so” (p. 4). While this type of career is not new, the literature indicates
a general shift toward a significantly higher level of people’s experiences of
work happening in these ways (Gloor, 2006; Partti, 2012; Sennett, 2012;
Netto, 2012; Smith & Shafighian, 2013). It is in collaborative networks that
most musicians in popular and other musics construct their continued suc-
cess, through a process that Cartwright, Gillett, and Smith (in press) identify
as “orchestration . . . defined in terms of efforts to achieve success by finding
and managing creative combinations for value.”
196 Gareth Dylan Smith
Many in higher music education are tuning in to the changing shape of
success in music (e.g., Hallam & Gaunt 2012). Partti (2012) advocates inte-
gration of networks akin to Gloor’s COINs into the music education experi-
ence at and across every level, to the mutual benefit of all stakeholders:
Some people say, “You’re the future of music education.” We’re not the
future—we’re just now, but, because of our relentless critical interroga-
tion of our culture, our practices, and the needs of our students, the
present actually looks like the future.
NOTES
1. The Houses of Parliament (often referred to as just “Parliament”) are the two
debating houses of the U.K. government. In the House of Commons, dem-
ocratically elected representatives, “Members of Parliament” (or “MPs”),
debate and pass laws on behalf of the populace. The House of Commons
functions in conjunction with the House of Lords, whose members (“Peers”)
are not democratically elected. MPs in the House of Commons refer to one
another in the third person as “the Right Honourable Member.”
2. Q is a monthly U.K.-based journalistic publication advertising and discussing
current “popular” music.
REFERENCES
Oh no! My eggs are burning! I bet- The buzzer rings again, and I’m
ter pay attention. I stir the eggs and startled out of the past. I glance
add some salt. at my watch: 13 more minutes.
Because I’m prepared for music
Why didn’t Teacher Catie ask me playtime when the children enter.
to sing my song at meeting today?
Maybe she didn’t hear my song. I leave the music space.
Alison: I listen to Nate’s song, smiling as I enjoy seeing his sparkling eyes
and expressive face and the way he moves as he sings. “Wow, Nate, what
a beautiful song!”
Nate: [singing]
“Pssst . . . Over Here!” 205
Alison: [singing]
Nate: [singing]
I like that ending. So your song sounds like this?” I sing Nate’s song. “Is
that right?”
Nate: I smile a big smile. You know, the kind where you show all your
teeth. “Uh uh, Teacher Alison. That’s my song!”
Alison: “Yes, he’s letting me share it with him. It’s a shared tune.”
Alison: Nate plays his song on his recorder as Noura sings and I move.
Other kids are running over to join in. Max grabs a drum and joins in
on the fun. Andrea finds some maracas and adds another rhythmic layer.
Pretty soon all of the children have joined in our band. Some are playing
instruments, some are dancing, some are singing, and some are listening.
Soon, teachers Catie and Amy also join in.
Alison: I wonder if this is like what the child in the Pillsbury Foundation
School had experienced when he said, “Everybody stand up and raise
your hands to the sky. That means you’re all members of this music; we’re
all members of that tune we were playing.”1
I thought I was ready for music playtime! But, children’s music making
began long before I rang that doorbell.
When the noise of the past settles into relative stillness within the present,
articulate your current view of young children, and how young children—
particularly very young children—fit in your descriptions and definitions of
“the study and making of music by all.”2
Next, we ask you to reflect on music moments that were also transforma-
tive moments in your lives as musicians, parents, teachers, researchers, or
policy makers.
Indeed, all nations and communities should listen to the voices of their
youngest citizens. Children can offer critical insights that support myr-
iad societal developments. We must ask the question: What do the chil-
dren say they need in order to lead successful and fulfilled lives?
(“Children Investing in Childhood,” 2013, para. 2)
The affiliates offer five statements that can frame broad perspectives for
the music education profession’s views of young children as music makers:
1. Safe and secure places for living and learning, with access to health
care, clothing, and nutritious food
2. Strong families and loving, consistent caregivers
3. Social interactions and friendships
“Pssst . . . Over Here!” 209
4.Creative play and physical activity
5.Appreciation and stewardship of the natural environment
6.Creative expression through music, dance, drama, and the other arts
7.Education that develops the full capacities of the child—cognitive,
physical, social, emotional, and ethical
8. Supportive, nurturing, child-friendly communities
9. Growing independence and decision making
10. Children and youth participating in community life.
Every child in every nation deserves a childhood full of hope, joy, free-
dom, and promise for the future.
(“Embracing the Human Future,” 2013, para. 3)
Within the United States, federal and state initiatives, credentialing agen-
cies for education certification, curricula in higher education, and organi-
zations in education and music education from national to local levels
make policy that eventually affect young children and their music capaci-
ties. Specifically within our profession, early childhood music educators
have documented steadily increasing attention to early childhood music
education research, practice, and policy. Officially, the National Associa-
tion for Music Education (NAfME) wraps its arms around all young chil-
dren, advocating for music interactions from birth. In The School Music
Program: A New Vision (NAfME, 2013), the profession states:
The years before children enter kindergarten are critical for their musi-
cal development. Young children need a rich musical environment in
which to grow. The increasing number of day-care centers, nursery
schools, and early-intervention programs for children with disabili-
ties and children at risk suggests that information should be available
about the musical needs of infants and young children and that stan-
dards for music should be established for these learning environments
as well as for K–12 settings.
The standards outlined in this section reflect the following beliefs con-
cerning the musical learning of young children:
NAfME’s current standards offer guidelines for music with infants and
toddlers, and standards for interacting with children from two to four years
old. Music standards for children K–4 encompass the remaining ages that
we advocate for in this chapter.
Early childhood music educators, no doubt, applaud the profession’s
advocacy efforts to date. Yet, the need for increased dialogue and integrated
play among stakeholders within and beyond the profession and academies
persists. Prioritizing the role the future of early childhood music education
plays relative to the future of all of music education seems critical to our
profession’s next steps.
NOTES
REFERENCES
One problem with the title “musician” is that people are afraid to use
it. They fear that other people will disagree with this term. They com-
pare themselves to other musicians that they feel are more talented.
Just because you aren’t the master of your craft does not mean you
aren’t considered part of that craft. I am a student. I may not go to
Harvard, 4.0 every assignment, and study tirelessly, but I am a student
nonetheless. . . .
For two semesters during graduate school, I taught Music for the Classroom
Teacher,1 a 4-credit, 400-level course for elementary education majors.
Most students in the course had participated in school music programs, at
least in elementary general music. Many students had taken band or choir
in middle school, and some continued in school music (instrumental and/or
vocal) throughout high school. Several students participated in music out-
side of school, through private lessons, camps, or additional performance
ensembles such as church choirs or garage bands. All of the students inter-
acted with music socially (e.g., going to clubs or concerts, sharing music
with friends) and individually (nearly omnipresent iPods). However, very
few students would say they were “musical” or “a musician.”
In class, we debated possible definitions of the word “musician” and briefly
discussed musician identity development in early childhood through adoles-
cence. We had this discussion for three reasons: (1) to advance my assertions
from earlier in the course regarding the inherent musicality of young children,
(2) to further position music integration in the elementary classroom as natural
and likely to be beneficial for students, and (3) to help students think about
216 Karen Salvador
the effect their own music identity (often a negative one) could have on their
students. This discussion took place in week 12 of the 14-week semester. As the
culmination of this discussion, each student wrote a description of his or her
current music identity and its development over time. As I graded these essays,
I found them poignant and powerful as a music teacher and music teacher
educator. I wanted to analyze and share the insights they contained.
Purpose
The purpose of this qualitative study was to explore essays on music identity
development written by undergraduate students who were not music majors
or minors. Further, my intent was to analyze findings specifically with
regard to their implications for school music instruction and music teacher
218 Karen Salvador
education. My guiding questions were: How did the students describe their
musical identity from childhood through their lifespan? What experiences
did students describe as having positive or negative influences on their musi-
cian identity?
DESIGN
Data Analysis
For this qualitative content study, I used deductive analysis related to my
guiding questions as well as general inductive data analysis as described by
Thomas (2003). This analysis involved cleaning the data (removing identi-
fiers and empty space, unifying fonts, etc.), close reading of the text, creation
of categories, and continually revising and refining these categories through
multiple sets of coding, allowing overlapping coding and uncoded text. The
trustworthiness of the data was established through triangulation within the
project (among the 35 essays), comparison with other findings in the literature,
and peer review (Creswell, 2012). In this deductive and inductive analysis,
my assumptions and experiences inevitably informed both how I conducted
the research and how I analyzed the data (Peshkin, 1994). Therefore, my
thoughts with regard to musician identity and “non-musicians” become the
lens through which the data is viewed, and it is important to the trustworthi-
ness of this study that I describe my biases with regard to musician identity.
Researcher Lens
Although I am now an assistant professor who specializes in music teacher
education, my views are informed by my previous identity as an elementary
general music teacher, and by my continued practice as an early childhood
music teacher. I acknowledge that my background as a classically trained
musician means that I see music and musicianship differently than the general
Identity and Transformation 219
population who do not have that background. Therefore, as I read these
essays, I was an “Other” or outsider. Moreover, I believe that every person has
the potential to be musical: music is the birthright of every human. I believe
that participatory musicianship is good for individuals of all ages, communi-
ties, and society, and that musicking2 can take a variety of forms. My idea of a
musician is not limited to people who engage regularly in music performance,
and I do not think that the label “musician” is limited to those with “talent” or
who have high levels of expertise. These beliefs were likely evident as I taught
the classes, designed this study, analyzed the data, and wrote this paper.
FINDINGS
Music at School
Several students related positive experiences with secondary school music
ensembles and teachers, and cited these as reasons that they viewed themselves
as musicians. These school music experiences were rarely mentioned sepa-
rately from how they interrelated with music experiences outside of school.
Using my formal knowledge from playing the trombone in band class for
3 or 4 years, I began to teach myself drums. Eventually, I started playing
with bands and even began playing gigs in high school. My band played
at local venues and in venues around the state and the country. . . . During
this time I became on avid blues fan, eventually giving way to my love of
jazz music. Also around this time, I had the opportunity to take a music
history class . . . at my high school. This class opened my ears to music
that I had never really given much time. I began listening to Chopin, Viv-
aldi, Beethoven and others. . . . Music has become a driving force in my
life. I am an avid player, listener, and researcher of music.
(Essay 19)
The choir was about to sing at church and my ten-year-old self was the
only soprano there. I was absolutely terrified but I knew that I knew
the song. . . . The director got to the bridge and had each part sing the
part alone. It gets to be my turn and I’m singing and crying at the same
Identity and Transformation 221
time but it sounded really good. After that, singing and music became
the thing that made everything else OK.
(Essay 2)
Family Influence
The influence of family members also sometimes supported a persistently
positive musician identity. The author who described being ten and the only
soprano in choir one day (Essay 2, see above) mentioned elsewhere in her
essay that her grandfather was minister for music at the church, and her dad
played drums for the choir. Many students mentioned parents who played
instruments (especially guitar and piano), and siblings who preceded them
in school music programs as supporting their musician identity.
While the influence of family is clear, the author of Essay 12 seemed also
to indicate that her musician identity was strengthened by competition.
Competition/Talent
For some students, it was competition (in school and/or out) or a perception
that they had a special talent, which led them to see themselves as musical.
I think that in high school I was a Musician [sic5] as I was very serious
about learning music and improving my instrument. By my sophomore
222 Karen Salvador
year, I was a part of the chamber choir, and I competed in both Choral
and Solo & Ensemble Festivals, singing with the choir and as a soloist,
reaching the state level in both areas. I also auditioned for and per-
formed with the MSVMA regional, state, and all-state Honors Choirs.
(Essay 3)
Music at School
Some participants indicated secondary school music instruction as a main
reason they stopped seeing themselves as musicians. Sometimes, it seemed
that the band/choir director either would not or could not teach them how
to succeed in school music:
Joining choir was a lot of fun for me. I got to sing every day and I
even mustered the courage to try out for a solo. However . . . my choir
teacher said that I did not have a voice that was “special” enough. This
comment made me reconsider singing out loud in front of people and
for the next few years I only sang to myself.
(Essay 13)
Identity and Transformation 223
I was pushed around to many different instruments [because] I was not
performing the way they wanted me to. So I decided I was done with
band. . . . I was so devastated by my experience that I decided I wanted
to stay away from anything that would identify me as a musician.
(Essay 27)
In other essays, it seemed that some teachers were willing to sacrifice the
needs of one student for the needs of the group:
I was in the boys’ section of the choir for a while and I liked to tell myself
that I didn’t mind, but sometimes looking back I think I did. . . . I wish
that someone, such as my choir teacher, would have told me why she
put me in the boy’s section of the choir. I look back now and I know it is
because my voice could reach lower pitches and I showed a confidence
that a lot of other girls didn’t necessarily show at that age. By the time
eighth grade was over, that confidence in choir was pretty much gone.
(Essay 7)
Competing Identities
Some students linked a weak or negative musician identity to a stronger identity
in some other pursuit. “I grew up as an athlete and never wanted anything to
do with music” (Essay 8). However, other students—who enjoyed music, felt
musical as young children, and may have maintained a positive identity if they
continued to play and/or sing—quit because of time constraints. “[At age ten] I
started to play the flute. I played for three years and I really loved it. However,
in high school I had to choose between music class and visual arts” (Essay 30).
Overall, there seemed to be an impression among the students that they should
focus on one role: “I was more of an athlete than a musician” (Essay 15).
Talent Attribution/Competition
Just as being identified as “talented” and doing well in comparison to oth-
ers helped some participants to develop and maintain a positive musician
identity, competition and the perception of lacking “talent” contributed to
negative musician identity in other students. Sometimes, music teachers con-
tributed directly to these feelings:
[M]y director used the chair system and had quizzes where we played in
front of the entire class. . . . I cried a lot in band on those days because
I knew how bad I would be.
(Essay 2)
224 Karen Salvador
Other times, the student’s sense of needing to be the best, or to be perfect,
came from within:
Influence of Family
Similar to competition and talent attributions functioning as factors that both
supported musician identity and also contributed to a negative musician iden-
tity, family influences could be positive or negative. One student recalled being
“heckled” by siblings as she tried to practice saxophone at home and explained
further, “I was in the school choir for three years, and loved to sing quite a bit,
but was always encouraged to quit and stop singing by my three older sisters
who thought that my singing voice was pretty bad” (Essay 34). Another par-
ticipant mentioned that part of the reason she did not view herself as a musi-
cian was that her older brother was always so much more accomplished (Essay
23). Parental influences also sometimes factored into negative identity: “My
parents were never heavily involved in music, but they had a lot of involvement
in sports. . . . My childhood did not have much music in it at all” (Essay 18).
Self-Efficacy Beliefs
Although the essays were ostensibly focused on musician identity, many
essays revolved around the related concept of self-efficacy beliefs. Self-effi-
cacy is a person’s judgments of her ability to achieve a particular task—not
simply an assessment of skill level, but rather an individual’s judgments of
what she can do with the skills she possesses (Bandura, 1986).
Transformation/(Re)Claiming
Many of these students had loved music and musicking throughout their
lives, but had denied themselves an identity of “musician” because their def-
initions of the term were limited. When they redefined the word, it seemed
to allow some of them to (re)claim an identity they had yearned for: that of
“musician.” Taking up this mantle seems to have been transformative for
some students.
Some of the students seemed to relate their new identity directly to teach-
ing, creating an “identity for” integrating music in their future classroom,
or in essence stating they could be “musician enough” for their students.
DISCUSSION
(Re)Defining of “Musician”
Many respondents stated that they had not considered what defined a musi-
cian until they were asked. Perhaps music teachers could ask this question,
and propose inclusive and flexible definitions of “musician” to help stu-
dents see the myriad of ways that someone might musick. The redefinitions
of “musician” that contributed to some students (re)claiming a musician
identity reflected my core beliefs, which must have been consistently appar-
ent in Music for the Classroom Teacher. I positioned singing as a valid form
of musicianship alongside playing instruments. I stated that musicianship
Identity and Transformation 229
can exist at a variety of levels of proficiency. I explicitly valued other musics
alongside “classical” music and other forms of musicking along with per-
forming. With regard to children’s musical development, I taught that no
one is completely lacking in music aptitude. Finally, I reinforced that many
components of musicking that students seemed to think required “talent”
(playing, singing, moving, having a “good ear”) are skills that can be learned
with effort and practice.
Although none of this is likely to be viewed as revolutionary to music
education researchers, some student “non musicians” responded to these
messages with apparent surprise and pleasure. Essentially, students seemed
loath to own their musician identity because they were not “good enough”
or “talented enough” in comparison to others. This negative musician iden-
tity was constraining some students from pursuing music activities they
wanted to engage in, such as learning to play guitar. It was as though they
needed permission to be “musician enough” to use music to teach, to learn
instruments, to dance and to sing. Roberts (2006) found that music majors
worked to create the proficiencies they needed to support their identity.
However, these students were already accepted as music majors, and had
the support of the academy in claiming a musician identity. Perhaps one
way to extrapolate Roberts’s findings could be that once “non musicians”
realize that they may (re)claim an identity as a musician, they will feel freer
to behave in the ways a musician does. An unintended consequence of this
identity reflection essay assignment may have been that, in asking students
to consider their current beliefs, giving information, and allowing for redefi-
nition, I essentially engaged students in “reframing,” a technique therapists
use to change thoughts and behavior (Beck, 1997). Furthermore, the act of
constructing a narrative of musician identity may have been a powerful act,
as writing is thought to provide a space for the formation and reformation
of thought (Menary, 2007).
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
Abril, C. (2007). I have a voice but I just can’t sing: A narrative investiga-
tion of singing and social anxiety. Music Education Research, 9(1), 1–15.
doi:10.1080/14613800601127494
Bandura, A. (1986). The explanatory and predictive scope of self-efficacy theory.
Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 4, 359–73.
Beck, A. (1997). The past and the future of cognitive therapy. Journal of Psychotherapy
Practice and Research, 6, 276–84.
Borthwick, S. J., & Davidson, J. W. (2002). Developing a child’s identity as a musi-
cian: A family script perspective. In R. A. MacDonald, D. J. Hargreaves, & D.
Miell (Eds.), Musical identities (pp. 60–78). New York, NY: Oxford University
Press.
Campbell, P. S., Connell, C., & Beegle, A. (2007). Adolescents’ expressed mean-
ings of music in and out of school. Journal of Research in Music Education, 55,
220–36. doi: 10.1177/002242940705500304
Creswell, J. W. (2012). Qualitative inquiry and research design: Choosing among five
approaches 3rd Ed.). Los Angeles, CA: Sage Publications.
Elpus, K., & Abril, C. R. (2011). High school music ensemble students in the United
States: A demographic profile. Journal of Research in Music Education, 59(2),
128–45. doi: 10.1177/0022429411405207
Gracyk, T. (2003). Does everyone have a musical identity? Reflections on Musical
Identities. Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education, 3(1). Retrieved
from http://act.maydaygroup.org/php/archives_v3.php#3_1
Gustafson, R. I. (2009). Race and curriculum: Music in childhood education. New
York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Heyning, L. (2011). “I can’t sing!” The concept of teacher confidence in singing and
the use within their classroom. International Journal of Education & the Arts,
12(13). Retrieved February 2, 2013, from www.ijea.org/v12n13/
Lamb, R. (2003). Talkin’ musical identities blues. Action, Criticism, and Theory for
Music Education, 3(1). Retrieved from http://mas.siue.edu/ACT/v3/Lamb04.pdf
Lamont, A. (2002). Musical identities and the school environment. In R. A.
MacDonald, D. J. Hargreaves, & D. Miell (Eds.), Musical identities (pp. 41–59).
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Lee, K. (2003). Nothing new: Lots of gel? Action, Criticism, and Theory for
Music Education, 3(1). Retrieved from http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles//
Lee3_1.pdf
232 Karen Salvador
MacDonald, R. A., Hargreaves, D. J., & Miell, D. (2003). Editors’ response: The
sound of ideologies clashing. Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education,
3(1). Retrieved from http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/EditorResponse3_1.pdf
MacDonald, R. A., Hargreaves, D. J., & Miell, D. (Eds.) (2002). Musical identities.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Marsh, H., Debus, R., & Barnholt, L. (2006). Validating young children’s self-concept
responses. In D. Teti (Ed.), Handbook of research methods in developmental sci-
ence (pp. 138–60). New York, NY: Wiley Blackwell.
McPherson, G. E. (2009). The role of parents in children’s musical development.
Psychology of Music 37(1), 91–110. doi: 10.1177/0305735607086049
Menary, R. (2007). Writing as thinking. Language Sciences 29(1), 621–32.
National Association for the Education of Young Children (NAEYC). (2012).
NAEYC Accreditation: All Criteria Document. Downloaded January 26, 2013,
from www.naeyc.org/files/academy/file/AllCriteriaDocument.pdf
North, A. C., Hargreaves, D. J., & O’Neill, S. A. (2000). The importance of music to
adolescents. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 70(2), 255–72.
O’Neill, S. A. (2002). The self-identity of young musicians. In R. A. MacDonald,
D. J. Hargreaves, & D. Miell (Eds.), Musical identities. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Peshkin, A. (1994). The presence of self: Subjectivity in the conduct of qualitative
research. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education, 122, 45–56.
Randles, C. (2010). What is a “good musician”? An analysis of student beliefs. Arts
Education Policy Review 112(1), 1–8. doi: 10.1080/10632913.2010.490774
Roberts, B. (2006) Music making, making selves, making it might: A counter-
point to Rhoda Bernard. Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education,
6(2). Retrieved January 13, 2013, from http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/
Roberts6_2.pdf
Scheib, J. W., Albert, K., Haston, W., Hellman, D., Hourigan, R., Miksza, P., Moore,
M. W. (2007). Roles, identity, socialization, and conflict: The transition from music
student to music teacher (a literature review). Society for Music Teacher Education.
Retrieved January 26, 2013, from http://smte.us/wp-content/uploads/2007/02/
rolesidentitysocializationconflict.pdf
Small, C. (1998). Musicking: The meanings of performing and listening. Middletown,
CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Thomas, D. R. (2003). A general inductive approach for qualitative data analy-
sis. Retrieved January 26, 2013, from www.fmhs.auckland.ac.nz/soph/centres/
hrmas/_docs/Inductive2003.pdf
Trehub, S. E., Unyk, A. M., & Trainor, L. J. (1993). Adults identify infant-directed
music across cultures. Infant Behavior and Development, 16, 285–95.
Trevarthan, C. (2002). Origins of musical identity: Evidence from infancy for musi-
cal social awareness. In R. A. MacDonald, D. J. Hargreaves, & D. Miell (Eds.),
Musical identities. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Vanatta-Hall, J. E. (2010). Music education in early childhood teacher education:
The impact of a music methods course on pre-service teachers’ perceived con-
fidence and competence to teach music. (Unpublished doctoral dissertation).
University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign.
Part IV
Guiding Researchers
This page intentionally left blank
15 Methodological Trends in
Music Education Research
Michael S. Zelenak
METHOD
a form of inquiry in which (1) key concepts and procedures are care-
fully defined in such a way that the inquiry can be replicated and
possibly refuted, (2) controls are in place to minimize error and bias,
(3) the generalizability limits of the study’s results are made explicit,
and (4) the results of the study are interpreted in terms of what they
contribute to the cumulative body of knowledge about the object of
inquiry.
(p. 35)
I included only those articles that met these criteria. Articles such as
essays, position papers, letters, rebuttals, speeches, symposium abstracts,
book reviews, and dissertation critiques, were excluded.
238 Michael S. Zelenak
Methodological Elements
Gall, Gall, and Borg described the investigative process used by educational
researchers and provided definitions of each aspect of that process. From
their description and definitions, I extracted five primary methodological
elements: (a) form of inquiry, (b) design, (c) sampling technique, (d) data
collection, and (e) data analysis (Figure 15.1). The specific type or variation
of each element was then considered a subcategory. As I read each article, I
tallied the subcategories and these tallies became the data used for compari-
son and statistical analysis.
I. Form of inquiry
Qualitative Quantitative
II. Design
Probability Non
Probability
V. Data analysis
Qualitative Quantitative
Element 2: Design
To accommodate diverse forms of qualitative designs, Gall, Gall, and Borg
recommended differentiating qualitative research based on research tradi-
tions (p. 490). They identified three traditions of investigation in qualita-
tive : (a) lived experience, (b) society and culture, and (c) language and
communication. Studies in the lived experience tradition included those per-
taining to cognitive psychology and phenomenology; studies in the society
and culture tradition included action research and ethnography; and studies
in the language and communication tradition included narratives, herme-
neutics and semiotics (p. 491). Along with these three traditions, historical
240 Michael S. Zelenak
research was included as a fourth category of qualitative design. Gall, Gall,
and Borg devoted an entire chapter (Chapter 16, p. 528) to this topic assert-
ing the importance of historical research as a unique form of qualitative
investigation.
In studies following a quantitative form of inquiry, the design element
was divided into experimental and non-experimental subcategories. In an
experimental design, the researcher introduced an intervention and studied
the impact of that intervention on treatment and control groups. Common
experimental designs included pretest-posttest control-group design and
quasi-experimental design. In a non-experimental design, the researcher
does not introduce an intervention but rather examines and describes
phenomena. Typical non-experimental designs include descriptive, causal-
comparative, and correlational designs.
Unlike research design and data analysis, data collection methods were
not linked to the form of inquiry. Questionnaires, for example, can be used
in studies based on quantitative or qualitative forms of inquiry. There were
many types of data collection techniques used throughout the articles and
it is important to note that I used the definitions stated above to determine
the categorization. Some techniques, however, did not fall neatly into any
of the subcategories. In these cases, I based my categorization on the intent
of the authors and their use of the data.
Data Analysis
I read all articles and coded for each of the methodological elements. The
resulting data were then entered into the Statistical Analysis Software (SAS)
program for analysis. Since the articles were analyzed ten different ways,
two times (time and journal) for each of the five methodological perspec-
tives, a Bonferroni adjusted p value of .005 was used to determine signifi-
cance. To provide evidence of reliability in coding, a colleague holding a
PhD in music education coded 10% (n = 32) of the articles. The proportion
of agreement, Cohen’s kappa, was calculated for each category. According
to descriptive interpretations provided by Landis and Koch (1977), results
indicated almost perfect agreement in coding forms of inquiry (κ = .81
[0.63, 0.98]), substantial agreement in research design (κ = .80 [0.63, 0.98]),
perfect agreement in sampling technique (κ = 1.00 [1.00, 1.00]), substantial
Methodological Trends in Music Education Research 243
agreement in data collection (κ = 0.70 [0.55, 0.86]), substantial agreement
in quantitative data analysis (κ = 0.76 [0.60, 0.92]), and poor agreement in
qualitative data analysis (κ = -0.03 [-0.51, 0.45]). The poor level of agree-
ment in coding the qualitative analysis techniques (50% agreement) may be
attributed to incongruent definitions of the terms inductive, deductive, and
other. Although most of the coding was highly reliable, the reader should
approach conclusions related to qualitative data analysis methodologies
with caution.
RESULTS
Frequency
Percent
Row Pct
Column Pct 1988–89 1998–99 2008–09 Total
Bulletin 14 40 47 101
4.35 12.42 14.60 31.37
13.86 39.60 46.53
21.54 31.50 36.15
JRME 35 66 40 141
10.87 20.50 12.42 43.79
24.82 46.81 28.37
53.85 51.97 30.77
POM 16 21 43 80
4.97 6.52 13.35 24.84
20.00 26.25 53.75
24.62 16.54 33.08
Total 65 127 130 322
20.19 39.44 40.37 100.00
* Significant difference among proportions of journal by time period, χ² (4, N = 322) = 18.50,
p < .001.
Frequency(Column Percentage)
Perspective
Category 1988–89 1998–99 2008–09 Total
Forms of inquiry
Qualitative 19(29.23) 34(27.20) 35(28.23) 88(28.03)
Quantitative 46(70.77) 91(72.80) 89(71.77) 226(71.97)
Design (Qualitative)
Lived Experiences 6(9.23) 10(8.00) 12(9.68) 28(8.92)
Society & Culture 1(1.54) 7(5.60) 14(11.29) 22(7.01)
Language & 2(3.08) 3(2.40) 4(3.23) 9(2.87)
Communication
Historical 10(15.38) 14(11.20) 5(4.03) 29(9.24)
(Quantitative)
Experimental 14(21.54) 16(12.80) 18(14.52) 48(15.29)
Non Experimental 32(49.23) 75(60.00) 71(57.26) 178(56.69)
Sampling Technique
Non-Probability 49(75.38) 112(89.60) 112(90.23) 273(86.94)
Probability 16(24.62) 13(10.40) 12(9.68) 41(13.06)
Data Collection*
Test 26(31.71) 40(22.86) 29(14.08) 95(20.52)
Self-Report 14(17.07) 20(11.43) 33(16.02) 67(14.47)
Questionnaire 7(8.54) 28(16.00) 50(24.27) 85(18.36)
Interview 3(3.66) 20(11.43) 26(12.62) 49(10.58)
Observation 7(8.54) 16(9.14) 21(10.19) 44(9.50)
Product 25(30.49) 51(29.14) 47(22.82) 123(26.57)
Data Analysis (Qualitative)a
Inductive 2(1.34) 10(3.61) 19(6.60) 31(4.34)
Deductive 1(0.67) 3(1.08) 3(1.04) 7(0.98)
Other-Qualitative 16(10.74) 21(7.58) 13(4.51) 50(7.00)
(Quantitative)
Descriptive 41(27.52) 86(31.05) 85(29.51) 212(29.69)
2 Group Comparisons 21(14.09) 31(11.19) 38(13.19) 90(12.61)
Regression/Correlation 19(12.75) 38(13.72) 43(14.93) 100(14.01)
Chi-Square 15(10.07) 16(5.78) 19(6.60) 50(7.00)
Multiple Group 31(20.81) 59(21.30) 51(17.71) 141(19.75)
Factor Analysis 0 (0.00) 8(2.89) 14(4.86) 22(3.08)
Other-Quantitative 3(2.01) 5(1.81) 3(1.04) 11(1.54)
a. Many studies used more than one data collection and analysis technique. Frequency totals for
data collection and analysis techniques were greater than total number of studies investigated.
* Significant difference in methodology used by time periods, χ² (10, N = 314) = 27.09, p < .005.
Table 15.4 Frequencies and Percentages of Methodologies Used by Journals
Frequency(Column Percentage)
Perspective
Category Bulletin JRME POM Total
Forms of inquiry*
Qualitative 50(51.02) 22(15.60) 16(21.33) 88(28.03)
Quantitative 48(48.98) 119(84.40) 59(78.67) 226(71.97)
Design* (Qualitative)
Lived Experiences 14(14.29) 6(4.26) 8(10.67) 28(8.92)
Society & Culture 15(15.31) 5(3.55) 2(2.67) 22(7.01)
Language & 7(7.14) 0(0.00) 2(2.67) 9(2.87)
Communication
Historical 14(14.29) 11(7.80) 4(5.33) 29(9.24)
(Quantitative)
Experimental 5(5.10) 25(17.73) 18(24.00) 48(15.29)
Non Experimental 43(43.88) 94(66.67) 41(54.67) 178(56.69)
Sampling Technique*
Non-Probability 91(92.86) 110(78.01) 72(96.00) 273(86.94)
Probability 7(7.14) 31(21.99) 3(4.00) 41(13.06)
Data Collection*
Test 19(13.67) 51(25.12) 25(20.66) 95(20.52)
Self-Report 14(10.07) 31(15.27) 22(18.18) 67(14.47)
Questionnaire 16(11.51) 36(17.73) 33(27.27) 85(18.36)
Interview 26(18.71) 15(7.39) 8(6.61) 49(10.58)
Observation 17(12.23) 17(8.37) 10(8.26) 44(9.50)
Product 47(33.81) 53(26.11) 23(19.01) 123(26.57)
Data Analysis*
(Qualitative)
Inductive 20(11.98) 4(1.11) 7(3.72) 31(4.34)
Deductive 3(1.80) 3(0.84) 1(0.53) 7(0.98)
Other 27(16.17) 15(4.18) 8(4.26) 50(7.00)
(Quantitative)
Descriptive 41(24.55) 114(31.75) 57(30.32) 212(29.69)
2 Group Comparisons 12(7.19) 51(14.21) 27(14.36) 90(12.61)
Regression/Correlation 20(11.98) 56(15.60) 24(12.77) 100(14.01)
Chi-Square 11(6.59) 26(7.24) 13(6.91) 50(7.00)
Multiple Group 25(14.97) 74(20.61) 42(22.34) 141(19.75)
Factor Analysis 6(3.59) 11(3.06) 5(2.66) 22(3.08)
Other-Quan 2(1.20) 5(1.39) 4(2.13) 11(1.54)
Limitations
The findings of this study must be approached with caution. Since I exam-
ined only a small proportion of the published articles in these journals,
the findings do not represent all published articles in these journals for the
21-year time period. In addition, the articles reviewed in this study may
not be representative of all work done in music education research. Some
researchers may have sought publication in other journals specializing in
particular types of research such as historical journals. Finally, the catego-
rization process in this study was ultimately based on the interpretation of
the methodological elements by this researcher. Although I used Gall, Gall,
and Borg’s (2007) definitions and Glass and Hopkins’s (1996) explanations
as objective measures, the categorical decisions were subject to my personal
interpretations.
DISCUSSION
This study uncovered several trends in music education research. First, the
number of research studies published in eminent journals increased from
1988 to 2009. This increase may be attributed to several factors. Psychol-
ogy of Music was published semiannually in 1988–89 and 1998–99, and
248 Michael S. Zelenak
then quarterly in 2008–09. This change doubled the number of articles
published per year by POM. The Bulletin also increased its publication of
research articles in 2008–09 by removing book reviews and dissertation
critiques from its pages. As for JRME, the total increase in article publica-
tion would have been even greater had JRME continued with its pre-2008
publishing schedule. JRME shifted the publication of its December 2008
issue to January 2009, resulting in a calendar year (2008) with only three
issues instead of four.
The second trend was a significant change in the data collection tech-
niques used from 1988 to 2009. Although there were minor changes in all
of the methodological elements over the 21-year period, only the element
data collection exhibited a significant difference among its subcategories.
This difference was brought about by a decrease in the use of tests and an
increased use of questionnaires and interviews. The increase in the number of
qualitative studies conducted from 1988–89 (n = 19) and in 2008–09 (n = 35)
may have been responsible for this change. Questionnaires and interviews
are common data collection methods in qualitative studies.
Although each journal published research articles in music education,
there were significant differences in the methodologies published in the jour-
nals. Comparisons of the subcategories of all five methodological elements
revealed significant differences among the journals. In most cases, the dif-
ference in the last four elements can be linked to the form of inquiry in each
article. It did not appear unusual to find differences in the design, sampling
technique, data collection, and data analysis methodologies since JRME
and POM published a greater proportion of quantitative articles (84.40%
and 78.67%, respectively) than the Bulletin (48.98%). Although the form
of inquiry does not prescribe specific methodologies, there are certain prac-
tices that are consistent with the positivist epistemology and its investigative
processes.
Although the number of qualitative studies increased, it is important
to note that the proportion of qualitative to quantitative studies remained
consistent across the years. Researchers have recognized the advantages
of qualitative inquiry (Flinders & Richardson, 2002) but there remains a
strong quantitative orientation as exemplified by the data from the journals
JRME and POM. In addition, I was unable to find any articles in the time
periods examined based on the qualitative language and communication
tradition in JRME. Although JRME publishes qualitative articles, this study
has documented its inclination to publish quantitative research. This incli-
nation may have resulted from JRME being the oldest publication among
the journals. Historically, research in music education has been built on
quantitative traditions.
The results of this study were consistent with findings from other stud-
ies. Yarbrough (2002) reported a decrease in the publication of historical
research from 1953–2002 in JRME. She also noted a small increase in the
use of qualitative methodologies. In this study, the publication of historical
Methodological Trends in Music Education Research 249
research declined from 10 articles in 1988–89 to 5 articles in 2008–09. One
possible explanation may be that authors of historical articles have found
other publications in which to publish their work. In a separate review of the
literature, Bartel and Radocy (2002) identified seven trends in music educa-
tion research. Four of the seven trends were within the scope of this study:
(a) methodological complexity, (b) data complexity, (c) analytical complex-
ity, and (d) representation complexity. The significant change in data collec-
tion methodologies provided the most direct support of Bartel and Radocy’s
(2002) trend of increased data complexity. Questionnaires and interviews
can provide more complex data than numeric tests.
CONCLUSION
The results of this study offer valuable insights for navigating the future
of research in music education. In 1988, the digital age was in its infancy.
By 2009, improvements in personal computers and the Internet brought
profound changes to the collection and processing of information. Research
in music education has benefited from these changes. Benefits include the
increased accessibility of articles and the development of sophisticated
analytical tools. Researchers are now able to collect larger data sets and
examine them with increased levels of complexity. In many ways, digital
processing has facilitated the escalation of research activities.
Research in music education has reached new levels of prominence. The
findings of this study have demonstrated that eminent journals in the field
have increased their publication of research articles. This shift indicates that
research has become more highly valued by others in the profession and
considered an important contributor to improvements in music education.
Along with these journals, new technology-based venues are being devel-
oped to provide even greater access to research information. These new
venues include online journals, websites, and social media. Music education
is making progress toward becoming a research-based profession.
Although there has been progress, traditional investigative processes dom-
inated the research examined in this study. More quantitative studies were
published than qualitative. This finding may not have negative repercussions
for the field, but it is worthy of closer scrutiny. Questions may arise such as
(a) Do we conduct more quantitative research simply because that is what
we were trained to do?, or (b) Are more quantitative studies being conducted
because more quantitative studies are being published? In either question,
the tail is wagging the dog (cliché). I recommend that future researchers dig
deeper and closely examine the questions being asked in research studies.
The driving force behind research must be the questions and not the method-
ologies. Methodologies are tools to answer questions. We should be asking
ourselves, are we asking the right questions? In the 322 articles reviewed
for this study, no researcher investigated research questions. Future research
250 Michael S. Zelenak
must begin examining research questions and the relationship between those
questions and the needs of the profession.
The significant change in data collection methodologies signifies trends
on two levels. On one level, it suggests that researchers investigated different
topics in 2009 than in 1988. Topics such as music achievement and aptitude
can be collected with tests using numeric responses. Thoughts and opinions,
however, are most authentically represented through the language of the
individuals. Consequently, researchers must use questionnaires or interviews
to collect the data. The shift away from tests and toward questionnaires
found in this study provided evidence that researchers investigated topics in
which data collection methods such as tests were not appropriate. The data
consisted of language that could only be collected using other means. On a
second level, I would speculate that researchers have become more adept at
analyzing language. Coding responses from questionnaires is difficult and
time-consuming work. The increased use of questionnaires may suggest that
researchers are using new technologies to make their work faster and less
burdensome. Future research on methodologies should examine the impact
of software tools on researchers’ methodological choices.
This investigation has raised questions not only about research methodolo-
gies, but also about the context of research in a field such as music education.
For example, the increase in non-probability sampling may not necessarily
indicate a lack of interest among researchers in probability sampling, but
rather reflect the increasing difficulties researchers encounter as they attempt to
include K–12 students as participants in their studies. In most cases, research-
ers have little choice but to accept convenience samples as participants. Most
schools’ reaction to violence in society has been to limit outsiders’ access to
students. Researchers would benefit from increasing their knowledge of con-
venience samples and understanding effective means to incorporate them into
their studies. Probability sampling may not be an option.
In closing, I would like to acknowledge the overall improvement in quality
of the research articles over time. More articles followed strict publication
guidelines resulting in greater organizational consistency and clarity. Recent
articles included information such as effect sizes and confidence intervals to
assist in the interpretation of results. To better navigate the future, research-
ers can learn from the past. Cronbach and Meehl (1955) recommended con-
structing nomological networks that interrelate hypotheses based on theory.
Although rigorous studies have been conducted in music education, the top-
ics have been divergent. Researchers should consider connecting these top-
ics by filling the knowledge gaps. This process may involve measuring and
analyzing multiple constructs concurrently. The development of multivari-
ate analyses and the availability of high quality software programs make
this challenge a realistic goal. Finally, the lesson learned in this study may
not be in what is observed, but in what is missing. There is much work left
to be done. My hope is that this study will provide an impetus for future
investigations into research methodologies.
Methodological Trends in Music Education Research 251
REFERENCES
Abeles, H. F., & Conway, C. (2010). The inquiring music teacher. In H. F. Abeles &
L. A. Custodero (Eds.), Critical issues in music education: Contemporary theory
and practice (pp. 276–302). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Bartel, L. R., & Radocy, R. E. (2002). Trends in data acquisition and knowledge
development. In R. Colwell & C. Richardson (Eds.), The new handbook of
research on music teaching and learning (pp. 1108–27). New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Choate, R. A. (1965). Research in music education. Journal of Research in Music
Education, 13(2), 67–86.
Cronbach, L. J., & Meehl, P. E. (1955). Construct validity in psychological tests.
Psychological Bulletin, 52, 281–302.
Draves, T. J., Cruse, C. S., Mills, M. M., & Sweet, B. M. (2008). Subjects in music
education research 1991–2005. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music
Education, 176, 19–30.
Ebie, B. D. (2002). Characteristics of 50 years of research samples found in the
“Journal of Research in Music Education,” 1953–2002. Journal of Research in
Music Education, 50(4), 280–91.
Flinders, D. J., & Richardson, C. P. (2002). Contemporary issues in qualitative
research and music education. In R. Colwell & C. Richardson (Eds.), The new
handbook of research on music teaching and learning (pp. 1159–76). New York,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Gall, M. D., Gall, J. P., & Borg, W. R. (2007). Educational research: An introduction.
New York, NY: Pearson Education.
Glass, G. V., & Hopkins, K. D. (1996). Statistical methods in education and psychol-
ogy. Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Hamann, D. L., & Lucas, K. V. (1998). Establishing journal eminence in music edu-
cation research. Journal of Research in Music Education, 46(3), 405–13.
Heller, G. N. (1985). On the meaning and value of historical research in music educa-
tion. Journal of Research in Music Education, 33(1), 4–6.
Humphreys, J. T. (2006). 2006 senior researcher award acceptance address:
Observations about music education. Journal of Research in Music Education,
54(3), 183–202.
Internet World Stats. (2013). Retrieved June 13, 2013, from www.internetworldstats.
com/stats.htm
Jones, R. S. (1957). Current trends and new directions in educational research.
Journal of Research in Music Education, 5(1), 16–22.
Kratus, J. (1993). Eminence in music education research as measured in the
Handbook of Research on Music Teaching and Learning. Bulletin of the Council
for Research in Music Education, 118, 21–32.
Krueger, P. J. (1987). Ethnographic research methodology in music education.
Journal of Research in Music Education, 35(2), 69–77.
Landis, J. R., & Koch, G. G. (1977). The measurement of observer agreement for
categorical data. Biometrics, 33, 159–74.
Mark, M. L. (1992). A history of music education research. In R. Colwell (Ed.),
Handbook of research on music teaching and learning (pp. 48–59). New York,
NY: Macmillan.
Patton, M. Q. (2002). Qualitative research & evaluation methods. Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage Publications.
Randles, C., Hagen, J., Gottlieb, B., & Salvador, K. (2010). Eminence in music
education research as measured in the New Handbook of Research on Music
Teaching and Learning. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education,
183, 165–76.
252 Michael S. Zelenak
Sample, D. (1992). Frequently cited studies as indicators of music education research
interests, 1963–1989. Journal of Research in Music Education, 40(2), 153–7.
Schmidt, C. P., & Zdzinski, S. F. (1993). Cited quantitative research articles in music
education research journals, 1975–1990: A content analysis of selected studies.
Journal of Research in Music Education, 41(1), 5–18.
Yarbrough, C. (1984). A content analysis of the “Journal of Research in Music
Education,” 1953–1983. Journal of Research in Music Education, 32(4), 213–22.
Yarbrough, C. (2002). The first 50 years of the “Journal of Research in Music
Education”: A content analysis. Journal of Research in Music Education, 50(4),
276–9.
16 Critical Ethnography
as/for Praxis
A Pathway for Music Education
Marissa Silverman
INTRODUCTION
PROBLEM
Many researchers (e.g., Jaffurs, 2004; Jones, 2007; Randles, 2012; Veblen,
Messenger, Silverman, & Elliott, 2013) have alerted us to various types of
disconnection between school, community, and homemade music making
around the world. Reasons for this pattern of disconnection include the
vast and growing expansion of community-based alternatives to school
music and the ever-expanding range of accessible music technologies that
facilitate young people’s high quality home-based music production (Bell,
2012). Indeed, research suggests that, on average, traditional school music
ensembles serve approximately 20% of most school populations (Elpus &
Abril, 2011; Kuzmich & Dammers, 2013). Furthermore, school music
ensembles tend to exclude members of marginalized groups (DeLorenzo,
2012a; DeLorenzo, 2012b; Elpus & Abril, 2011).
To alleviate school-community disconnections, some researchers sug-
gest that students, especially minority students, need broader exposure to
music mentors and role models, who have backgrounds similar to students
(Lucas & Robinson, 2003; Quiocho & Rios, 2000). Others have suggested
and/or operationalized various programs and pedagogical strategies that
emphasize different ways of knowing (see the U.K. “Musical Futures Proj-
ect”1; Green 2002, 2006; Myers, 2007). Other researchers focus on cul-
turally relevant pedagogies that assist in making music classrooms more
diverse in content and curriculum (Ladson-Billings, 1995; Volk, 2004;
Prier, 2012).
While these solutions may be effective to various degrees (further research
is necessary), I believe there are other possibilities for reconnecting today’s
youth with the musical and educational potentials of reconstructed pub-
lic school music programs. Indeed, we should not be too quick to give up
the fight to make public school music more relevant and effective (in every
respect) for today’s and tomorrow’s youth. As the educational philosopher
Chris Higgins (2011b) emphasizes: “Schools should be central to public life:
key locations for the regeneration of values, the cultivation of judgment, and
the creation of the conditions for positive freedom” (p. 451). He continues:
“Schools can only revitalize public life if they return to . . . something very
close to the heart of their mission: to provide a model of how to be together”
(p. 466).
Indeed, and as other researchers note, unless students and teachers trans-
form what is to what can be, and until we “challenge institutions, regimes
Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis 255
of knowledge, and social practices that limit choices, constrain meaning,
and denigrate identities and communities” (Madison, 2012, p. 6), we will
not and cannot create pathways for more meaningful musical, interpersonal,
and intersubjective transactions and transformations among students, teach-
ers, and classrooms. How can we challenge educational practices and create
new pathways? This chapter offers one suggestion in the form of a research
praxis that allows us to get inside and under the skin of the problems and
potentials of schools as sites of personal and musical empowerment and
transformation.
PURPOSE
The purpose of this chapter is to explain the nature and strategies of criti-
cal ethnography as these apply to “intersections between theory, fieldwork
methods, performance, critical practice, and social justice” (Madison, 2012,
p. ix). Critical ethnography examines the interdependence between theory
and practice and how, when united with an ethical stance, it creates spaces
for ethical praxis (as explained by Marx, Freire, Arendt, and others—see
below). At the conclusion of this chapter, I will explain the implications that
this type of research holds for music education by focusing on teaching and
learning in music-listening classes (e.g., secondary school “music apprecia-
tion” classes). I choose to focus on music-listening classes because, in my
experience as an observer and evaluator of secondary school music pro-
grams, general music situations are especially prone to “banking-method”2
procedures (Freire, 1970).
By way of background, critical ethnographies utilize qualitative data
collection methods for sociopolitical and ethical purposes. That is, criti-
cal ethnographies are “critical” in two senses: (a) they are framed and
carried out with a social-ethical sense of responsibility to critique, and,
if necessary, to change the specific contexts they investigate; and (b) they
are grounded in “a self-referential form of reflexivity that aims to cri-
ticize the ethnographer’s own production of an account” (Schwandt,
2007, p. 51).
From a philosophical perspective, critical ethnography exemplifies the
central themes of praxis while highlighting the priorities of critical theory
and critical pedagogy (e.g., McLaren, 1995; Freire, 1970). D. Soyini Madi-
son (2012) explains that critical ethnography is “the ‘doing’—or better
the ‘performance’—of critical theory” (p. 14). Joe L. Kinchloe and Peter
McLaren (2002) describe critical ethnography as critical theory in action.
According to Madison (2012) and others (Denzin, 2003; Noblit, Flores, &
Murillo, 2004; Thomas, 1993; Carspecken, 1996), the critical ethnogra-
pher “disrupts the status quo, and unsettles both neutrality and taken-for-
granted assumptions by bringing to light underlying and obscure operations
of power and control. Therefore, the critical ethnographer . . . moves from
256 Marissa Silverman
‘what is’ to ‘what could be’ ” (Madison, 2012, p. 5). S/he aims to break
through unjust social barriers “in defense of . . . the voices and experiences
of subjects whose stories are otherwise restrained and out of reach” (p. 6)
and to contribute to emancipatory knowledge and social justice.
1. How claims to valid findings are acts of power in themselves and thus
whose interests are being served by the research;
2. How values influence what is seen in facts; and
3. How we choose to represent reality is also an act of power and alters
the interpretation of reality (quoted in Noblit, 2004, p. 185).
How does the above relate to music education? First, I want to discuss
music history/music theory courses taught primarily as music-listening
courses. On too many occasions, I have observed secondary school class-
rooms where actual music making and creating are entirely absent. By way
of comparison, other classes were focused on action. I observed physical
education classes where students were actively moving, running, and jump-
ing, depending on the context of the sport being explored. I spent time in
art history classes where students were using Picasso paintings as models for
their own “cubist” works. In every other discipline, students were engaged
in the hands-on actions at the heart of the subject’s “knowledge” base.
However, more often than not, music history classes/music theory classes
devolved into music-listening classes where students were passive recipients
of auditory patterns. When I asked a music teacher of a music-listening class
if his students would ever engage in actual music making, he said: “These
students aren’t interested in making music. If they were, they’d join the band
or choir.” But when I talked with three students after their class, I found
out quickly that they were deeply interested in making music (recall the
epigraphs to this chapter).
Indeed, the music “listening” classes I just referred to fell into the “music
appreciation” trap. Why trap? As conceived and practiced in North Amer-
ica, teaching and learning music education as “music appreciation” assumes
that student listeners should be prepared to become passive consumers. Stu-
dents in music appreciation classrooms are most often expected to “sit and
listen” quietly to pieces, and learn to identify the formal elements (i.e., mel-
ody, harmony, rhythm, timbre, texture, and form) of musical sound struc-
tures. Another assumption of this approach is that musical-structural acuity
and verbal information about music prepares students for deep “aesthetic
Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis 263
experiences” and greater respect for masterpieces. Regelski (2006) articu-
lates the reasons I reject this concept of music-listening instruction:
This is where critical ethnography can help pave the way for improved peda-
gogies of music history and music theory classes that are transformative. I have
written elsewhere about how critical ethnography can be utilized to transform
music classrooms for praxis (Silverman, 2013). I explored how teachers and
students can marshal strategies to create a space that contributes to personal/
group empowerment and positive transformation. Indeed, music students tend
to be marginalized and/or “silenced” (if not oppressed) during their schooling
by (a) the large school bureaucracies that characterize contemporary Ameri-
can public education and (b) the exclusionary, “top-down” teaching methods
driven by the priorities of American “marketplace education” and its corollar-
ies, namely high-stakes testing and business-accounting procedures. Further
marginalization can be found in urban schools located in low socioeconomic
areas, because students in these contexts often experience inequitable condi-
tions of all kinds (see Noguera, Ginwright, & Cammarota, 2006). These char-
acteristics of American education and their deleterious effects on students and
teachers have been thoroughly studied and supported by leading American
educational scholars (e.g. Anyon, 1997; Apple, 2001, 2003; Bell, Joshi, &
Zuniga, 2007; Cochran-Smith, 2004, 2005; Darling-Hammond, 2004).
Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis 265
A music classroom, regardless of its title or orientation (whether, say, music
history, music theory, or music appreciation; band, choir, or orchestra; laptop
ensemble, or chamber ensemble) and location (rural, suburban, urban) should
be a space that functions as communitas—a space in which students and
teachers are free to clarify their individual and collective powers of sharing,
each gaining a greater sense of their own and other’s personhood in a context
of social equality, solidarity, and togetherness. Critical ethnographies of music
classrooms can help to create places where teachers and students can acti-
vate their music learning activities as social acts of becoming; where, through
music, teachers and students can go beyond what is to what can be. This must
happen with and for students and teachers together. As a community, students
and teachers can decide ways of musically experiencing the world.
Critical ethnographies can support the above aims and activities because
critical ethnographies do not “act on” teachers and students. Critical eth-
nography is a participatory pedagogy for transformative action. McLaren
(1995) explains: “Critical ethnography must be organic to and not admin-
istered upon the plight of struggling peoples” (italics in original, p. 291).
Critical ethnography breaks from traditional qualitative research traditions
where the researcher engages in research “on” something or someone (bank-
ing concepts of teacher-student relationships function this way, too). Instead,
critical ethnography is an emancipatory stance; it is research “with,” as
in a reflexive engagement where researcher and researched are part of the
dialogical process together (recall Freire’s “problem-posing” concept of
education mentioned earlier). The researcher is as much a “subject” of the
research as are the participants of the study; the participants of the study
are afforded opportunities to help conceive the aims, focus, and purpose
of the research, including the questions and design. Through the research
process, the boundaries between researcher and researched are blurred. Both
the researcher and the researched consider the problematics that need to be
challenged. Critical ethnography empowers teachers and students to prob-
lematize the assumptions that often constitute what students and teachers
conceive as music, personhood, and research (Madison, 2012).
CONSIDERATIONS
All these questions, I suggest, are open to, and opened by, the deep analyses
and the personally and socially transformative powers of critical ethnography.
NOTES
1. See www.musicalfutures.org
2. For those unfamiliar with Freire’s (1970) banking concept of education, it
maintains that some educators “turn [students] into ‘containers,’ into ‘recep-
tacles’ to be ‘filled’ by the teacher. The more completely she fills the receptacles,
the better a teacher she is. The more meekly the receptacles permit themselves
to be filled, the better the students they are. Education like this becomes an
act of depositing, in which the students are depositories and the teacher is the
depositor” (p. 72).
3. While one could claim that many teachers are advocates for the oppressed, we
must be careful to note distinctions between taking action, doing research, and
engaging in “action research” projects that utilize critical ethnography as a tool
for investigation.
4. Discussions of praxis in music education are found in the following: Elliott,
1995, 2012; Bowman, 2000; Allsup, 2003; Regelski, 2005; Jorgensen, 2005;
Silverman, 2013; Elliott & Silverman, 2014..
REFERENCES
Allsup, R. (2003). Praxis and the possible: Thoughts in the writings of Maxine
Greene and Paulo Freire. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 11(2), 157–69.
Anderson, G. (1989). Critical ethnography in education: Origins, current status, and
new directions. Review of Educational Research, 59(3), 249–70.
Anyon, J. (1997). Ghetto schooling: A political economy of urban educational
reform. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis 267
Appiah, K. A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Apple, M. (2001). Educating the right way: Markets, standards, god, and inequality.
New York, NY: Routledge/Falmer.
Apple, M. (2003, Spring). Competition, knowledge, and the loss of educational
vision. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 3–22.
Arendt, H. (1998). The human condition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
(Original work published 1958)
Aristotle. (1985). Nichomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Bell, A. (2012). Homemade records: A multiple case study of the role of record-
ing technology in the music-making processes of informally trained musicians.
(Unpublished dissertation) New York University.
Bell, L. A., Joshi, K. Y., & Zuniga, X. (2007). Racism, immigration, and globaliza-
tion curriculum design. In M. Adams, L. A. Bell, & P. Griffin (Eds.), Teaching for
diversity and social justice (pp. 145–66). New York, NY: Routledge.
Bernstein, R. (2011). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics, and
praxis. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Bowman, W. (2000). Discernment, respons/ability, and the goods of philosophical
praxis. Action, Criticism and Theory for Music Education, 1(1). Retrieved from
http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Bowman1_1a.pdf
Bowman, W. (2012). Practices, virtue ethics, and music education. Action, Criticism,
and Theory for Music Education, 11(2). Retrieved from http://act.maydaygroup.
org/articles/Bowman11_2.pdf
Bradley, D. (2007). The sounds of silence: Talking race in music education. Action,
Criticism, and Theory for Music Education, 6(4), 132–62. Retrieved from http://
act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Bradley6_4.pdf
Brown, S. G. & Dobrin, S. I. (2004). Introduction. New writers of the cultural sage:
From postmodern theory shock to critical praxis. In S. G. Brown & S. I. Dobrin
(Eds.), Ethnography unbound (pp. 1–12). Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press.
Carspecken, P. F. (1996). Critical ethnography in educational research: A theoretical
and practical guide. New York, NY: Routledge.
Cochran-Smith, M. (2004). Walking the road: Race, diversity, and social justice in
teacher education. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
Cochran-Smith, M. (2005). The new teacher education: For better or worse?
Educational Researcher, 34(7), 3–17.
Cook, K. (2008). Critical ethnography. In The SAGE encyclopedia of qualitative
research methods. Retrieved from www.credoreference.com/entry/sagequalrm/
critical_ethnography
Cox, R. (2002). The political economy of a plural world: Critical reflection on
power, morals, and civilization. New York, NY: Routledge.
Dardar, A. (2002). Reinventing Paolo Freire: A pedagogy of love. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Darling-Hammond, L. (2004). From “separate but equal” to “No Child Left
Behind”: The collision of new standards and old inequalities. In D. Meier &
G. Wood (Eds.), Many children left behind (pp. 3–32). Boston, MA: Beacon
Press.
DeLorenzo, L. (2012a). Sketches in democracy: Notes from an urban classroom.
New York, NY: Rowman & Littlefield Publishing.
DeLorenzo, L. (2012b). Missing faces from the orchestra: An issue of social justice?
Music Educators Journal, 98(4), 39–46.
Denzin, N. K. (2003). Performance ethnography: Critical pedagogy and the politics
of culture. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Elliott, D. J. (1995). Music matters: A new philosophy of music education. New
York, NY: Oxford University Press.
268 Marissa Silverman
Elliott, D. J. (2012). Music education as/for artistic citizenship. Music Educators
Journal, 99(1), 21–7.
Elliott, D. J., & Silverman, M. (2012). Rethinking philosophy, re-viewing musical-
emotional experiences. In W. Bowman & A. L. Frega (Eds.), The Oxford hand-
book of philosophy in music education (pp. 37–62). New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Elliott, D. J., & Silverman, M. (2014). Music matters: A philosophy of music educa-
tion. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Elpus, K., & Abril, C. (2011). High school music ensemble students in the United States:
A demographic profile. Journal of Research in Music Education, 59(2), 128–45.
Everhart, R. (1983). Reading, writing, and resistance: Adolescence and labor in a
junior high school. New York, NY: Routledge.
Ford, P. (2006). Appreciation without apologies. College Music Symposium, 46, 31–44.
Foucault, M. (2000). Essential works, Vol. 1: Ethics. London, UK: Penguin Books.
Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed [Pedagogía del oprimido.]. New York,
NY: Herder and Herder.
Freire, P. (1998). Teachers as cultural workers: Letters to those who dare to teach.
Boulder, CO: Westview.
Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of culture. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Green, L. (2002). How popular musicians learn: A way ahead for music education.
London, United Kingdom: Ashgate.
Green, L. (2006). Popular music education in and for itself, and for “other” music:
Current research in the classroom. International Journal of Music Education,
24(2), 101–18.
Habermas, J. (1971). Knowledge and human interests (J. Shapiro, Trans.). Boston,
MA: Beacon Press.
Habermas, J. (1974). Theory and practice [Theorie und Praxis]. London, United
Kingdom: Heinemann.
Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory
of law and democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Higgins, C. (2011a). The good life of teaching: An ethics of professional practice.
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.
Higgins, C. (2011b). The possibility of public education in an instrumental age.
Educational Theory, 61(4), 451–66.
Jaffurs, S. (2004). The impact of informal music learning practices in the classroom,
or how I learned how to teach from a garage band. International Journal of Music
Education, 22(3), 189–200.
Jones, P. (2007). Returning music education to the mainstream: Reconnecting with
the community. Visions of Research in Music Education. 7(1). Retrieved from
www.usr.rider.edu/˜vrme/v7n1/visions/Jones%20Returning%20Music%20
Education%20to%20the%20Mainstream.pdf
Jorgensen, E. (2005). Four philosophical models of the relation between theory and
practice. Philosophy of Music Education Review, 13(1), 21–6.
Juslin, P. N., & Sloboda, J. (2001). Music and emotion: Theory and research. New
York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Kinchloe, J., & McLaren, P. (2002). Rethinking critical theory and qualitative
research. In Y. Zou & E. T. Trueba (Eds.), Ethnography and schools: Qualitative
approaches to the study of education (pp. 87–138). New York, NY: Rowman &
Littlefield Publishing.
Kuzmich, J., & Dammers, R. (2013). Alternative music. SBO: School Band and
Orchestra. Retrieved from www.sbomagazine.com/431228/technology/alterna-
tive-music/
Ladson-Billings, G. (1995). But that’s just good teaching! The case for culturally
relevant pedagogy. Theory Into Practice, 34(3), 159–65.
Critical Ethnography as/for Praxis 269
Lucas, T., & Robinson, J. (2003). Reaching them early: Identifying and supporting
prospective teachers. Journal of Education for Teaching, 29(2), 159–75.
Madison, D. S. (2012). Critical ethnography: Method, ethics, and performance.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Malinowski, B. (1947). Dynamics of culture change: An inquiry into race relations
in Africa. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Marx, K. (1857/1973). Grundrisse (M. Nicolaus, Trans.). London, United Kingdom:
Penguin. (Original work published 1857)
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1978). The Marx-Engels reader (2nd edition; R. Tucker,
Ed.). New York, NY: W. W. Norton.
McLaren, P. (1995). Collisions with otherness: “Traveling” theory, postcolonial criti-
cism, and the politics of ethnographic practice—the missions of the wounded eth-
nographer. In P. McLaren and J. Giarelli (Eds.), Critical theory and educational
research (pp. 271–300). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, society. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Myers, D. (2007). Freeing music education from schooling: Toward a lifespan per-
spective on music learning and teaching. International Journal of Community
Music, 1(1), 49–61.
Noblit, G. W. (2004). Reinscribing critique in educational ethnography: Critical and
postcritical ethnography. In K. DeMarrais & S. D. Lapan (Eds.), Foundations for
research: Method of inquiry in education and the social sciences. Mahwah, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Noblit, G. W., Flores, S. Y., & Murillo, E. G. (2004). Postcritical ethnography:
Reinscribing critique. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press.
Noddings, N. (2002). Starting at home: Caring and social policy. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Noddings, N. (2005). The challenge to care in schools: An alternative approach to
education. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
Noguera, P., Ginwright, S. A., & Cammarota, J. (2006). Beyond resistance! Youth
activism and community change: New democratic possibilities for practice and
policy for America’s youth. New York, NY: Routledge.
Park, R. (1932). The university and the community of races. Honolulu, HA:
University of Hawaii Press.
Prier, P. (2012). Culturally relevant teaching. New York, NY: Peter Lang.
Quantz, R A (1992). On Critical Ethnography with some Postmodern Considerations.
In M.D. LeCompte, W.L. Millroy, & J. Preissle, The Handbook of Qualitative
Research in Education (pp. 447–505). San Diego: Academic Press, Incorporated.
Quiocho, A., & Rios, F. (2000). The power of their presence: Minority group teach-
ers and schooling. Review of Educational Research, 70(4), 485–528.
Radcliff-Brown, A. R. (1952). Structure and function in primitive society, essays and
addresses. London, United Kingdom: Cohen & West.
Radigan, J. (2002). The class clown: A school laminar. In Y. Zou & E. T. Trueba
(Eds.), Ethnography and schools: Qualitative approaches to the study of educa-
tion (pp. 257–80). New York, NY: Rowman & Littlefield Publishing.
Randles, C. (2012). Music teacher as writer and producer. Journal of Aesthetic
Education, 46(3), 36–52.
Regelski, T. (2005). Music and music education: Theory and praxis for “making a
difference.” Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(1), 7–27.
Regelski, T. (2006). Music appreciation as praxis. Music Education Research, 8(2),
281–310.
Schwandt, T. A. (2007). The Sage dictionary of qualitative inquiry. Los Angeles, CA:
Sage.
Silverman, M. (2013). A critical ethnography of democratic music listening. British
Journal of Music Education, 30(1), 7–25.
270 Marissa Silverman
Thomas, J. (1993). Doing critical ethnography. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Veblen, K., Messenger, S., Silverman, M., & Elliott, D. J. (2013). Community music
today. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Volk, T. (2004). Music, education, and multiculturalism: Foundations and princi-
ples. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Willis, P. E. (1977). Learning to labour: How working class kids get working class
jobs. Farnborough, United Kingdom: Saxon House.
Wolcott, H. F. (2002). Ethnography? Or educational travel writing? In Y. Zou & E. T.
Trueba (Eds.), Ethnography and schools: Qualitative approaches to the study of
education (pp. 27–48). New York, NY: Rowman & Littlefield Publishing.
17 Application of Sound Studies
to Qualitative Research in
Music Education
Joseph Michael Abramo
Sounds matter. Think of the din of the music classroom and an array of
sounds may come of mind:
What can sounds reveal about how students and teachers communicate,
gather meaning, and learn? How can researchers incorporate sound into the
frameworks, fieldworks, and presentations of empirical research?
These questions may be answered by looking to the growing field com-
monly referred to as “sound studies.” As Sterne (2012) notes, “Sound stud-
ies is a name for the interdisciplinary ferment in the human sciences that
takes sound as its analytical point of departure or arrival” (p. 2). Sometimes
known as “aurality” (Erlmann, 2010) or “auditory culture” (Bull & Back,
2004), sound studies:
can begin from obviously sonic phenomena like speech, hearing, sound
technologies, architecture, art, or music. But it does not have to. It may
think sonically as it moves underwater, through the laboratory or into
the halls of government; considers religion or nationalisms old and new;
explores cities; tarries with the history of philosophy, literature or ideas;
or critiques relations of power, property or intersubjectivity.
(Sterne, 2012, p. 2)
The field of sound studies encompasses more than merely studying sound;
it is to “think sonically.” Sound studies “challenge us to think across sounds,
272 Joseph Michael Abramo
to consider sonic phenomena in relationship to one another—as types of
sonic phenomena rather than as things-in-themselves—whether they be
music, voices, listening, media, buildings, performances, or another path
into sonic life” (Sterne, 2012, p. 3, italics in original).
Investigating some of these themes and questions addressed in sound
studies provides music education researchers new avenues of inquiry. In this
paper, I explore how the epistemology, nature, and history of sound and
listening’s conception may provide new theoretical frameworks, including
what I am calling here “individual” and “critical-historical” phenomenolo-
gies. Second, I suggest how these frameworks of sound and listening may
provide new ways for researchers to conceive fieldwork, including consid-
ering ethnographic sites as found soundscapes (Schafer, 1994; Thompson,
2002) and what sound and listening may reveal about the collection and
interpretation of “data,” including the dilemmas of verbal and musical tran-
scription. Third, I explore how researchers may incorporate sounds and
listening into their presentations of research through researcher-created
compositional soundscapes (Drever, 2002; Samuels et al., 2010; Truax,
2000). Throughout this paper, I hold the individual and critical-historical
phenomenologies in tension with one another, exploring what each of them
says about the stages of the research process I outline here. Because each of
these topics are complicated, producing many articles and books on each
facet, this paper serves as a starting point of dialogue on the role of sound
in qualitative empirical research in music education.
Noise
Perhaps the best way of finding the political and sociological aspects of a
soundscape is by attending to noise. Although there are a variety of defini-
tions of noise (Thompson, 2002)—as a neutral synonym with sound, as
unintelligible or unimportant sounds, or as irritating sounds—Schafer’s
definitions serve as a starting point: “Noise is any undesired . . . [or] unde-
sirable sound” (1986, p. 110) and “Noises are the sounds we have learned
to ignore” (1994, p. 4). But these definitions leave the question, how does
a sound become undesirable? The line between noise and music and other
desirable sounds is thin and porous, and its placement is political. As Attali
(1986) notes, “Any theory of power today must include a theory of the
localization of noise and its endowment with form. . . . Noise is inscribed
from the start within the panoply of power” (p. 6).
Prima facie, noises are unavoidable intrusions in fieldwork. They dis-
tract the researcher, making it difficult to concentrate. They interrupt and
mask important sounds, rendering them inaudible and unintelligible. But
280 Joseph Michael Abramo
attending to noise as artifacts of politics, rather than as commonsensical
annoyances, reveals research sites in new ways. As Attali (1986) notes, “Our
science has always desired to monitor, measure, abstract, and castrate mean-
ing, forgetting that life is full of noise. . . . [But] nothing essential happens
in the absence of noise” (p. 3). Noise is not senseless; it is data. “Noise may
well interrupt or disturb; but we do not see that this need be a problem for
the qualitative researcher—it may even be an opportunity” (Hall, Lashua,
& Coffey, 2008, p. 1036). Thus, listening to the noise that one either con-
sciously or unconsciously filters out of her aural experiences is valuable.
From this viewpoint, music classrooms are spaces of noise. And if, as
Schafer (1994) notes, “the ear demands that insouciant and distracting
sounds would be stopped in order that it may concentrate on those which
truly matter” (p. 12), then attention to the processes people go through to
learn what to attune to and what to ignore in classrooms could provide
interesting avenues of research. Practicing teachers are required to ignore
many sounds they hear. This includes extraneous sounds in performance,
like the clicking of keys, string sounds on guitars, and exhalation during
singing. But noisealso resides in classroom management including which
sounds from students are ignored or addressed either positively or negatively.
Teachers are required to distinguish students’ “distracting” talk and sounds
from positive contributions to class. This ability to distinguish amongst and
to control the sounds in the classroom is one of authority: “Eavesdrop-
ping, censorship, recording, and surveillance are weapons of power” (Attali,
1986, p. 7). And “power reduces the noise made by others and adds sound
prevention to its arsenal” (Attali, 1986, p. 122). Thus, what teachers label
as noise is not a trivial, commonsensical decision; it is an act of authority
and its use is a question of ethics. These ethics are a concern for researchers,
too. I will return to this at the end of the chapter.
As an example, elsewhere (Abramo, 2011) I have suggested that in pop-
ular music settings boys often choose to rehearse in a constant wash of
sound. Educators unfamiliar with the practices of rock musicians and their
rehearsal techniques might find this “distracting”—as noise. But for the
boys, this dizzying sonic environment was integral to their musical thought
processes as well as how they communicated. What is noise to the teacher
is the residue of musical learning and communication for the students. A
teacher’s well-intentioned attempt to silence this communication because
it does not reflect the order typically found in classrooms, and because she
deems it distracting, would be a disservice to her students and is a reflection
of her power in the classroom.
While teachers are required to ignore or accept sounds and this is a politi-
cal act, music teacher education has no formalized or theoretical way of
addressing what teachers should “tune out.” NASM accreditation requires
preservice music education curricula to include courses in music theory,
history, sight singing, ear training, and conducting in order to “sharpen
the ear.” They guide and focus the ear for what to listen to: to hear chord
Application of Sound Studies to Qualitative Research 281
progressions, melodies, formal structures, stylistic nuances, and detection of
errors. But this specificity is not lent to the ways educators ignore sounds.
Asking students to reflect on what and how they define and then filter out
noise and its political and sociological causes and effects can be another
avenue towards informed practice.
Attention to noise, then, serves at least two purposes: it allows teacher
educators ways of conceptualizing how to guide music education students
through the noisy terrain of classrooms, allowing them not only to be con-
scious of what and how they attune their ears, but also to be cognizant to
what they label as “noise” and choose to ignore or correct. With this, how-
ever, is the acknowledgement that noise is not objective, but is, instead, a
political act that is based on historical and material conditions. Thus, what
teachers label as “noise”—students’ “excessive” talking, “playing out of
turn,” and “extraneous” and “irksome” sounds—may be a mechanism for
control and silencing of students. Second, it allows those who do partici-
pant “observation” a more comprehensive way of attending to soundscapes.
“Noise,” rather than being intrusions upon hearing important information,
is data in itself, and perhaps as an irony, by attending to noises in this way,
they cease to be noise; they become wanted sounds.
(RE)PRESENTATION
Arts-based Research
Traditionally, research is exclusively represented in prose. Written as reports,
research is rendered in concise unambiguous language, on paper, or the sim-
ulation of paper on computers and other media. But, starting in the 1990s,
some researchers questioned this positivistic and prosaic representation of
research and turned their attention to arts-based research. As Eisner (2003)
notes, research in general has moved from the assumptions of quantifica-
tion, experimental paradigms, research as the discovery of “true” knowl-
edge, objectivity, statistical generalization, scientific inquiry, and simplistic
and proscriptive application of research results to practice (pp. 210–15).
Instead, arts-based researchers borrow from the arts to proliferate new and
artistic forms of research; “Narratives, films, video, theater, even poems and
collages can be used to deepen one’s understanding of aspects of educational
284 Joseph Michael Abramo
practice and its consequence” (Eisner, 2003, p. 210). Researchers can even
add plays (Denzin, 2013; Saldaña, 2008) and cartoons (Bartlett, 2013) to
this list.
How researchers present data is important because, as Eisner (2003)
comments:
form and meaning interact because the form in which ideas appear
affects the kind of experience people will have. Hence, the use of forms
of representation that previously had little or no place in research have
been recognized as providing new meanings, something needed if under-
standing is to be enlarged.
(p. 211, italics added)
Because of this, researchers need not make a false distinction between sci-
entific research—which renders a “truth”—and the arts—which are merely
aesthetic without truth claims. Instead, researcher can consider research
methodologies on a continuum—a point I will return to shortly.
But we can extend Eisner’s ideas by asking, “Why does research need to
‘appear’”? If sound never appears, perhaps its research should not be visible
as well. The form of audio recordings—ranging from raw field recordings,
to soundscapes, to even musical compositions—enrich and change the ways
researchers represent and gain meaning from data. These renderings are
intended to display the ambiguity and polysemy of interpreting data and to
make the material accessible to audiences beyond academics.
Some arts-education researchers have applied arts-based methodologies
to their work. The International Journal of Education and the Arts has
presented some of the visual arts data pictorially (Mans, 2000) and embed-
ded audio into research reports (Bell, 2008). Gould (2010) has presented
music and sound in new and interesting ways at conferences. How can music
education researchers implement methodologies like these and others that
implement sound? How can music educators present data so that it will stop
appearing and start resonating with their audiences?
Researcher-Created Soundscapes
Again, soundscapes may provide avenues to reconceptualize representa-
tion of research and incorporate sound and music. Differing from Schafer
(1994) and Thompson’s (2002) description of soundscape as a found and
studied auditory landscape, composers also use “soundscapes” to denote
audio created from audio-recorded source material derived from environ-
ments to produce musical works. For purposes of clarity, I will refer to
these as “researcher-created soundscapes” or “soundscape compositions”
to distinguish them from “found soundscapes.” As ethnomusicologist Feld
(1994) notes, “Soundscape research really should be presented in the form
of a musical composition. That is the one way to bend the loop back so that
Application of Sound Studies to Qualitative Research 285
Radio-like Musical
Aural paper presentation composition
Positivistic Arts-based
paradigm paradigm
research and the artistry come together and we can auditorally cross those
rivers and those creeks and climb those trees and walk those paths without
the academic literalism, the print mediation” (p. 328). While soundscape
compositions are intended as extracting sounds from an (usually natural)
environment to create a musical composition, with some modifications,
soundscapes can be useful to music education researchers (Drever, 2002).
As the figure displays, conceptualizing sound in research in continuum
serves as a starting place to situate sounds and soundscapes. Researchers can
vary their incorporation of sounds from embedding audio into traditional
reports to musical compositions.
On one side, one closer to traditional and positivistic reports of research,
a researcher could read a paper, perhaps inserting audio clips of field record-
ings and interviews, rather than transcribing them into text. On the other
arts-based side, there could be strictly musical compositions, used to (re)pres-
ent the environment without making explicit, language-based statements or
theories about that environment. Somewhere in the middle could be some-
thing more akin to radio broadcasts like Radiolab and This American Life,
which mix explanation and analysis with field and interview recordings.
The positivistic, radio-like, and artistic examples sit on a continuum and
should not be conceived of as separate. Instead, researchers may blend and
use them in the same study. There could be a study that is somewhere in
between the radio-like and musical composition that combines field record-
ings, interview data, explanation, and interpretation of that data in prose
as well as a researcher-generated musical composition comprised of data.
Further, researchers may begin to think past the continuum by combining
the poles. It may be possible to represent both a traditional aural report and
an artistic composition of the same study side by side, using both sides of the
continuum to polysemically (re)present the same phenomenon.
286 Joseph Michael Abramo
Rigor and Sound in Research
Whatever approaches researchers choose, ultimately, they have to answer to
questions of academic rigor when producing these soundscapes. As Drever
(2002) notes, “The challenge to soundscape composition artists is whether
they can balance musical with representational concerns” (p. 26). To address
this, Truax (2000) suggests four qualities of compositional soundscapes that
may facilitate this rigor:
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
METHODOLOGICAL TRENDS
SOUND STUDIES
REFERENCES
Biswas, A. (2011). The music of what happens: Mind, meditation, and music as move-
ment. In D. Clark & E. Clarke (Eds.), Music and consciousness: Philosophical,
psychological, and cultural perspectives (pp. 95–110). New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Campbell, E. (2013). A moral critique of contemporary education. In H. Sockett
& R. Boostrom (Eds.), NSSE Yearbook, 112(1) (pp. 216–37). New York, NY:
Teachers College Press.
Chochran-Smith, M., & Dudley-Marling, C. (2012). Diversity in teacher educa-
tion and special education: The issues that divide. Journal of Teacher Education,
63(4), 237–244.
Jorgensen, E., & Yob, I. (2013). Deconstructing Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand
Plateaus for music education. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 47(3), 36–55.
Juslin, P., & Sloboda, J. (2010). Handbook of music and emotion: Theory, research,
applications. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Mertens, M., & Hesse-Biber, S. (2013). Mixed methods and credibility of evidence
in evaluation. New Directions for Evaluation, 138, 5–13.
MET. (2013). Ensuring fair and reliable measures of effective teaching. Seattle, WA:
The Bill & Melinda Gates Foundation.
19 Structural Equation Modeling
and Multilevel Modeling in
Music Education
Advancing Quantitative Research
Data Analysis
Nicholas Stefanic
The primary and eventual goal of all research is to better inform our actions,
which we do by gathering information, considering the information, and
making decisions based on the information we have. We can gather informa-
tion that describes (questions of who, what, where, when, to what degree)
or information that explains (questions of why or how). The most crucial
component of any type of research is asking critical, substantive questions
of great consequence (Fung, 2008; Kemp, 1992). Research questions should
be critical in that they are skeptical about assumptions and seek to illu-
minate rival arguments. Additionally, a good research question should be
substantive in that it seeks an abundance of relevant information regard-
ing an issue or phenomena, thus seeking well-supported answers, even if
that involves contradictory information. Lastly, a research question is of
great consequence if it has substantial value to one or more fields. Because
research requires much time and resources, research questions of great con-
sequence also represent a responsible use of those resources.
In quantitative research, and possibly in qualitative research as well, there
is sometimes a tendency to develop research questions in relation to the
techniques and tools one has at one’s disposal for collecting relevant data,
and more importantly, analyzing those data. In particular, there is a set of
statistical procedures that most researchers learn, often in their graduate
studies, all of which are essentially variations on a theme of linear regres-
sion (e.g., t-test, ANOVA, multiple regression). Because these statistical
techniques require data to be structured in certain ways, research questions
may be formed to match these structures. For example, if a researcher wishes
to investigate how a group of individuals changes over time (e.g., change
in a student’s musical self-efficacy over four years), he/she is likely familiar
with repeated-measures ANOVA as a means for dealing with time series
data. In repeated-measures ANOVA, the categorical grouping variable is
time (e.g., year 1, year 2, year 3, year 4) and there is a continuous dependent
variable (e.g., musical self-efficacy). The research question that can be asked
with this data structure is something like the following: Do these students
(as a group) differ in their self-efficacy over four years? However, other
300 Nicholas Stefanic
questions that might be considered include the following: To what extent
do individuals vary in their individual growth; how much is growth related
to other predictor variables (e.g., IQ, musical aptitude, hours of practice);
or how much is an individual’s initial self-efficacy related to his/her change
in self-efficacy? Each of these questions seek a deeper, more substantive pic-
ture of the change in a student’s self-efficacy over time in comparison to the
initial research question stated with the repeated-measures ANOVA frame-
work. Unfortunately, some of these questions (and others like them, to be
discussed later) either cannot be asked in a traditional ANOVA repeated-
measures framework or cannot be handled in a very straightforward man-
ner. These questions can be considered with other, possibly less well-known,
data analysis techniques such as Structural Equation Modeling and Multi-
level Modeling.
Logic of SEM
For someone unfamiliar with SEM, it is perhaps beneficial to conceive of it
as a combination of path analysis and Confirmatory Factor Analysis (CFA).
With path analysis, a researcher hypothesizes a series of causal relationships
(often mediating and moderating relationships) between a set of measured
variables. Those relationships are displayed as a path diagram with single-
headed arrows indicating direction of causality. Using a series of multiple
regression equations the researcher then calculates coefficients (β), which
are interpreted as the amount of change in an outcome variable with a given
change in the predictor variable.
In CFA, a researcher hypothesizes a factor structure for a set of mea-
sured variables a priori. The latent variables (not actually directly measured)
are believed to cause the responses seen on the respective items (the actual
measured variables). The measured variables are called manifest variables
because they are believed to be manifestations of the underlying, unobserv-
able latent variable.1 CFA is different than Exploratory Factor Analysis
(often referred to simply as factor analysis) in that CFA attempts to deter-
mine if the hypothesized factor structure fits the observed data, whereas
Structural Equation Modeling 301
EFA attempts to discover the factor structure for the observed data. Con-
ceptually, a structural equation model combines the structural aspect (causal
relationships) of path analysis with the measurement aspect (hypothesized
factor structure of latent variables) of CFA. SEM simultaneously evaluates a
structural and a measurement model in relation to the observed data.
There is also another important distinction between SEM procedures and
traditional GLM procedures. Typically, with inferential statistics we attempt
to estimate the population parameter(s) from our sample data, and then
use a statistical significance test to determine the probability of observing a
parameter of that size (or greater) if in fact the parameter was something else
(e.g., the mean is zero; there is no relationship between two variables). The
observed sample data is treated as a known, and the parameter is treated
as an unknown. With MLE (Maximum Likelihood Estimation), the logic is
flipped, and we treat the parameter as a known, and the observed sample
data as an unknown. Using an iterative process (i.e., an algorithm), MLE
finds the parameter estimate(s) that would make the sample data the most
likely to have been observed.
There is also another important distinction between SEM procedures and
traditional GLM procedures. Since we rarely can study every individual in
a population, we conduct research on samples of populations. The goal of
inferential statistics is to estimate the parameters of these populations (e.g.,
mean, variance, covariance) from the sample statistics. There are many ways
to go about estimating these parameters. Traditional GLM procedures often
utilize the Ordinary Least Squares (OLS) method to estimate the population
parameters. Most SEM software offer a wide variety of estimation methods,
of which MLE is the most common. A full explanation of MLE is beyond
the scope of this chapter, but an explanation can be found in virtually any
SEM textbook.
Example of SEM
The following example will help to illustrate the potential uses of SEM
by relating to an actual study in the music education literature (although
this study did not use SEM). Brand (1986) investigated the relationship
between the home musical environments of second graders and musical
attributes (tonal perception, rhythmic perception, and musical achieve-
ment). Using EFA, Brand developed a 15-item Home Musical Environment
Scale (HOMES), which measures four dimensions (factors): “(a) parents’
attitude toward music and musical involvement with child; (b) parental con-
cert attendance; (c) parent-child ownership and use of record/tape player,
records, tapes; and (d) parent plays a musical instrument” (p. 115). Brand
used setwise2 multiple regression analysis to explore relationships between
the four dimensions of HOMES and the musical attributes. With multiple
regression analysis all items for a given factor have to be summed or aver-
aged to produce a single number to use as the independent variable. So while
302 Nicholas Stefanic
a measurement instrument might be developed in a reflective latent variable
framework (e.g., using EFA), it is actually analyzed as a composite vari-
able (assumed to be measured without error), not as a true reflective latent
variable, in traditional regression analyses. In essence, all item variance is
treated as common factor variance and each variable contributes equally to
the composite variable (i.e., has the same factor loading). In a SEM frame-
work, the hypothesized factor structure can remain intact for any variable
that assumes a latent variable measurement model, which means all infor-
mation from each item is included in the model, and subsequently in the
hypothesis testing and model evaluation.
To return to the Brand (1986) example, musical achievement was mea-
sured with a 12-item Musical Achievement Assessment Form (MAAF),
which measures four areas: “musical knowledge (e.g., music symbols, terms,
and instruments), skill in (instrumental and vocal) performance, music read-
ing, and musical initiative (e.g., degree of interest and motivation” (p. 115).
Gordon’s Primary Measure of Music Audiation was used to measure tonal
and rhythmic aptitude, an oft-used measure in music education. There are
several options for how to handle this particular measure in a SEM frame-
work. A latent musical aptitude variable could be modeled as being indicated
by two items,3 the rhythmic and tonal sub-scores. Another option would be
to construct two latent variables, one for rhythmic and one for tonal, with
their respective test items as effect indicators of the latent variable.
For didactic purposes, one potential (hypothetical) model for addressing
questions about the relationships between home environment and musical
attributes is shown in Figure 19.1. This particular model also illustrates the
strength of SEM to test mediation in a straightforward manner. In this model,
tonal and rhythmic aptitude mediates the relationship between home environ-
ment and musical achievement. This model also illustrates how SEM allows
the researcher to make explicit the structure of the errors (random and mea-
surement). All endogenous latent variables (variables with arrows pointing
toward them) also have a disturbance pointed toward them, which represents
the remaining variance not explainable by the variables that point to them.
In addition, each manifest/measured variable also has a symbol similar to
the disturbance, which represents unique variance for each item (variance
that is not part of the common factor). This is but one potential model for
investigating the relationships between these variables. Once the model has
been specified, the parameters for the model would be estimated using the
iterative procedure described above. Assuming convergence is reached (i.e., a
solution is found), the model is then evaluated for overall fit. In addition to
calculating various fit statistics, a chi-square test provides a formal inferential
test of model fit. All of the various evaluation techniques (see Hu & Bentler,
1998, for a discussion of fit indices) are different ways of testing how well
the data fit the specified model. If the model appears to have acceptable fit,
then the model can be interpreted by examining the parameter estimates and
R2 values (i.e., explained variance). Hypothesis tests can be conducted on the
various path coefficients and/or on the variance/covariance estimates.
Structural Equation Modeling 303
Figure 19.1 Hypothetical SEM model for Brand (1986). Item numbers are also
hypothetical and do not relate to actual MAAF and HOMES measures. Circles are
latent variables, rectangles are manifest/measured variables, straight arrows repre-
sent causal relationships, and curved arrows show covariance/correlation of exog-
enous variables.
Advantages of SEM
There are several advantages of SEM in comparison to other traditional
GLM procedures, as explained by Bagozzi and Yi (2012) and Lei and Wu
(2007), and described below. First, SEM allows the investigation of the
relationships between latent variables. In path analysis, causal relationships
can only be modeled with measured (observed) variables. With CFA, latent
variables can only be modeled to affect measured (observed) variables. SEM
overcomes these two limitations because latent variables can be modeled to
impact other latent variables. CFA is actually a special case of SEM.
Second, from a measurement perspective, using latent variables in model-
ing causal relationships between constructs is ideal because latent variables
have no measurement error. Multiple regression and ANOVA techniques, all
of which use single indicators for each variable (often an average of multiple
items), do not take measurement error into account when testing hypotheses
because they have the assumption that variables were measured without
error, which is rarely the case in social sciences. With SEM, the reliability of
individual measures is taken into account in hypothesis tests.
304 Nicholas Stefanic
Third, the specification process involved with SEM can help research-
ers to be more particular in how they operationalize constructs and how
they specify their hypotheses. Fourth, from a practical standpoint, the visual
nature of SEM path diagrams not only helps the researcher think more glob-
ally or holistically, but also can help to convey theories more easily through
visual depiction of variable relationships. Fifth, the SEM framework works
equally well for exploratory research, which involves model building, as for
confirmatory research, which involves model testing. When done appropri-
ately and with good reason, the combination of exploratory and confirma-
tory research can advance theory development quite substantially.
While the SEM framework is most often used to examine covariances, it
can also be used to examine means. Therefore, the sixth advantage of SEM
is that it is possible to compare the means of groups on latent variables (e.g.,
using multiple group CFA). A traditional ANOVA can only compare means
of observed/measured variables. Therefore, in addition to examining covari-
ance structure, mean differences between groups can also be incorporated
into a SEM analysis.
There are several caveats that should also be mentioned in regards to
SEM. First and foremost, SEM is undoubtedly a large-sample technique.
Although “rule-of-thumb” statements about sample size are difficult to
make with SEM because models can vary in complexity, Jackson (2003) has
provided some evidence for considering the ratio of sample size to the num-
ber of parameters being estimated, suggesting 20:1 is ideal but certainly not
less than 10:1. Second, SEM research tends to place less emphasis on indi-
vidual tests of statistical significance and more emphasis on evaluation of
entire models. Kline (2011) explains that this is because “there is a sense in
SEM that the view of the entire landscape (the whole model) has precedence
over that of specific details (individual effects)” (p. 13). In addition, because
SEM is a large-sample technique, and because hypothesis tests are sensitive
to sample size, it becomes more likely that null hypotheses are rejected sim-
ply because of a large N. Kline (2004, 2011) is also a staunch advocate of
focusing more on magnitudes of effect sizes, and thus practical significance,
as opposed to primarily focusing on statistical significance.
MULTILEVEL MODELING
Advantages of MLM
There are several reasons for using MLM, both statistical and practical. From a
statistics standpoint, MLM provides better estimates of fixed effects. For exam-
ple, if traditional techniques were used to estimate the cross-level interaction of
creative music-making experience and teaching experience, the assumption of
independence would be violated because CMME is a level-one variable (stu-
dent-level) and students are nested within classrooms, and therefore not inde-
pendent. The issue of the independence assumption for traditional regression
analyses is quite serious because violations result in severely biased estimates,
which in turn leads to untrustworthy inferences (Kenny & Judd, 1986;
Scariano & Davenport, 1987). While many analysis techniques are robust to
violations of some of the other assumptions (e.g., normality), failure to account
for non-independence in one’s data is actually harmful to the research field
because of the untrustworthiness of any conclusions drawn from such an analysis.
In addition to the ability to ask questions about cross-level variability in the data,
MLM also provides better level-one estimates. If separate regression analyses
were done for each classroom in the MCSE example, the sample size for each
classroom would be relatively small, which results in more error in the estimates.
From a practical standpoint, MLM offers an alternative to the loss of
information that occurs when dependent (non-independent) data are aggre-
gated. Information regarding differences between groups can be just as
important as the information from all of the individuals within the groups.
An MLM framework allows for all useful data to be incorporated. Finally,
MLM provides a statistical framework by which cross-institution collabo-
ration can be accomplished. Larger samples can be achieved when multiple
institutions are involved and the nested nature of cross-institutional data can
be accounted for with MLM.
A few additional comments should be made regarding the advantages of
MLM specific to repeated-measures data. Repeated-measures data can also
be conceived as being nested (in addition to being non-independent). Con-
sider the previous example with musical creative self-efficacy, but this time
as a repeated-measures design, and the researcher is interested in students’
change in self-efficacy over the course of the year. The researcher has stu-
dents complete a measure of self-efficacy once a month for the entire school
Structural Equation Modeling 307
year, which results in nine measurement occasions. In this example, level one
is within-individual, the nine measurements over time per individual. We
could refer to this as the occasion level. This means that level two is actu-
ally the individual, which we would refer to as the individual level. From
this perspective, measurement occasions are nested within individuals, so a
multilevel/hierarchical analysis is logical.
In traditional repeated-measures ANOVA analysis, the amount of time
between measurements must be equal (equal intervals) and the number of
observations per individual must be equal. MLM is capable of handling obser-
vations collected at different time points and different numbers of obser-
vations per individual. The reason for this is that MLM models time as a
continuous variable as opposed to a categorical variable like in repeated-
measures ANOVA or MANOVA. This is particularly helpful because it is
fairly common in an educational setting for a student to be absent on the day
a measurement is taken. If that observation needs to be made a week later,
MLM can incorporate this difference in measurement interval. If that par-
ticular measurement is missed altogether and the student has only eight mea-
surements instead of nine, MLM can handle the missing data much better
than ANOVA. Most statistical programs will simply eliminate that individual
from the analysis, which can result in a large amount of information loss.
While the flexible nature of MLM analysis is helpful from a data collection
standpoint, it also offers several additional flexibilities from an analysis stand-
point. The term hierarchical linear modeling implies an exclusiveness to linear
growth, but MLM can also model nonlinear and even more complex growth
curves. Another advantage of MLM is the ability to incorporate covariates
(predictors) that vary over time (occasion-level) as well as covariates (predic-
tors) that are constant (individual-level). For example, in addition to measuring
MCSE, the researcher could also take a measure of motivation at each time
point, thus representing an occasion-level predictor. Similarly, the same previ-
ously discussed covariates (e.g., musical aptitude) could be included as level
two (individual-level) predictors. Lastly, in traditional repeated-measures anal-
ysis, there is an assumption that all individuals have the same growth curve.
With MLM, it is possible to have different growth curves for each individual,
something that is more likely the case in real life for many situations.
What is hopefully clear at this point is that both SEM and MLM are
extremely powerful analytic techniques, with several advantages over tra-
ditional analysis techniques in many circumstances. We now consider the
different types of questions that can be asked with these analysis techniques
in comparison to traditional techniques.
How well does this model fit the How well does the model explaining
observed data? the relationships of home musical
environment, musical aptitude, and
musical achievement fit the data?
Confirmatory Approach
the model can be made to better altering paths that might fit the data
fit the observed data? Are those better. Are these alterations plausible
modifications plausible and rational? and rational?
Does one model fit the observed data Is musical aptitude a mediator of
better for one level of a categorical home musical environment and
variable compared to other levels? musical achievement only for
Should two or more complimentary students from high SES families?
models be considered?
Structural Equation Modeling 309
differences. Those questions are slightly different depending on whether the
multilevel data is organizational (i.e., observations of individuals nested within
groups) or longitudinal (i.e., measurement occasions nested within individu-
als). Table 19.2 identifies examples of general research questions for organiza-
tional data as well as specific examples as they would relate to the hypothetical
study discussed in the MLM section of this chapter. As for longitudinal data,
Table 19.3 displays the corresponding questions for a longitudinal multilevel
design and examples specific to the hypothetical music education study dis-
cussed in the repeated-measures MLM section of this chapter.
These techniques can also be expanded beyond what has been dis-
cussed in this chapter. In short, it is possible to have multilevel SEM and
there are also latent variable MLM approaches. Each have situations in
which they are the better choice (for further discussion, see Stoel & Garre,
2011). It is also possible to create three-level models. For example, in a
What is the form of the growth curve What is the form of the growth curve
(nature of the change) between individuals (nature of the change) for students’
(linear, quadratic, cubic, etc.)? MCSE over nine months?
To what extent do individuals vary To what extent do individual students
(between each other) in their initial status vary (between each other) in their initial
(intercept) on an outcome variable? MCSE score (intercept)?
To what extent do individuals vary To what extent do individual students
(between each other) in their rate (slope) vary (between each other) in their rate
of change on an outcome variable? (slope) of change in MCSE?
What is the relationship between a given What is the relationship between
time-varying variable and individuals’ motivation and students’ initial MCSE?
intial status on an outcome variable?
What is the relationship between a given What is the relationship between
time-varying variable and individuals’ motivation and students’ rate of change
rate of change in an outcome variable? in MCSE?
What is the relationship between What is the relationship between
individuals’ intial status on an outcome students’ intial MCSE and their rate of
variable and their rate of change? change in MCSE?
When a time-varying (level-one) When motivation is added as an
covariate/predictor is added, how much occasion-level (level one) predictor,
is the proportion of within-individuals how much is the proportion of within-
variance reduced? individual variance in MCSE reduced?
When an individual-level (level-two) When musical aptitude is added as an
predictor is added, how much is the individual-level (level two) covariate/
proportion of between-individuals predictor, how much is the proportion
variance reduced? of between-individuals variance in
MCSE reduced?
NOTES
1. This is the most common type of latent variable, often referred to as a reflec-
tive latent variable. Other specifications are possible, including composite and
formative latent variables (cf. Bollen & Bauldry, 2011; Cadogan & Lee, 2013)
2. Setwise regression is a type of stepwise regression, but variables are entered
into the model in sets of variables.
3. This is possible as long as (1) there is at least one more reflective latent variable
in the model, which also has at least two effect indicator manifest variables;
(2) the factors are properly scaled; (3) each item loads on only one factor; and
(4) the errors are not correlated. Otherwise, the model is underidentified.
REFERENCES
Bagozzi, R. P., & Yi, Y. (2012). Specification, evaluation, and interpretation of struc-
tural equation models. Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science, 40, 8–34.
Bollen, K. A., & Bauldry, S. (2011). Three Cs in measurement models: Causal indica-
tors, composite indicators, and covariates. Psychological Methods, 16(3), 265–84.
Brand, M. (1986). Relationship between home musical environment and selected
musical attributes of second-grade children. Journal of Research in Music
Education, 34(2), 111–20.
Cadogan, J. W., & Lee, N. (2013). Improper use of endogenous formative variables.
Journal of Business Research, 66, 233–41.
Fung, C. V. (2008). In search of important research questions in music education:
The case of the United States. Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music
Education, 176, 31–43.
Graham, J. M. (2008). The general linear model as structural equation modeling.
Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics, 33(4), 485–506.
Hu, L.-T., & Bentler, P. M. (1998). Fit indices in covariance structure model-
ing: Sensitivity to underparameterized model misspecification. Psychological
Methods, 3(4), 424–53.
Jackson, D. L. (2003). Revisiting sample size and number of parameter estimates: Some
support for the N:q hypothesis. Structural Equation Modeling, 10(1), 128–41.
Kamata, A., & Cheong, Y. F. (2007). Multilevel Rasch models. In M. Von Davier &
C. H. Carstensen (Eds.), Multivariate and mixture distribution Rasch models:
Extensions and applications (pp. 217–32). New York, NY: Springer.
Structural Equation Modeling 313
Kamata, A., & Vaughn, B. K. (2011). Multilevel IRT modeling. In J. Hox & J. K.
Roberts (Eds.), Handbook of advanced multilevel analysis (pp. 41–57). New
York, NY: Routledge.
Kemp, A. E. (1992). Approaching research. In A. E. Kemp (Ed.), Some approaches to
research in music education (pp. 7–18). Reading, United Kingdom: International
Society for Music Education.
Kenny, D. A., & Judd, C. M. (1986). Consequences of violating the independence
assumption in analysis of variance. Psychological Bulletin, 99(3), 422–31.
Kline, R. B. (2004). What’s wrong with statistical tests—And where we go from here.
In R. B. Kline, Beyond significance testing: Reforming data analysis methods
in behavioral research (pp. 61–91). Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Kline, R. B. (2011). Principles and practice of structural equation modeling (3rd Ed.).
New York, NY: The Guilford Press.
Lee, S., & Hershberger, S. (1990). A simple rule for generating equivalent models
in structural equation modeling. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 25, 313–34.
Lei, P. W., & Wu, Q. (2007). Introduction to structural equation modeling: Issues
and practical considerations. Educational Measurement: Issues and Practice,
26(3), 33–43.
Scariano, S. M., & Davenport, J. M. (1987). The effects of violations of independence
assumptions in the one-way ANOVA. The American Statistician, 41(2), 123–9.
Stoel, R. D., & Garre, F. G. (2011). Growth curve analysis using multilevel regression
and structural equation modeling. In J. Hox & J. K. Roberts (Eds.), Handbook of
advanced multilevel analysis (pp. 97–111). New York, NY: Routledge.
20 Reflecting on Guiding
Researchers
Peter R. Webster
Abramo’s chapter on the field of sound studies and its implications for both
teaching and research represents a topic of major importance for a small but
very talented group of music education researchers and theorists. As a com-
pliment to his chapter, I recommend the work of Matthew Thibeault, Evan
Tobias, and Alex Ruthmann, among others. New teachers and researchers,
especially those interested in media and technology and their role in the
emerging social structures of youth and music consumption today, will find
this and other writings to be foundational.
For years, I have said in my classes and when giving talks to other audi-
ences that music educators are “sound educators,” with the pun intended.
My motivation for this comes from passion about thinking in sound and
its role in moving the agenda ahead for creative experiences to accompany
more teacher-centered approaches that do not give time for the student
voice. Embedded in this excellent chapter, and also in Silverman’s to come,
is this same disposition. Abramo touches on the importance of sound and
its consideration both in terms of teaching practice but also in the ways we
do and present research. His notion of “individual phenomenology” with
respect to the sonic experiences of individuals is powerful. I feel this has
major importance for the way to teach listening, something that we do not
do well in my opinion. His example of the differing perceptions surround-
ing Bach’s “C Major Prelude” of the Well Tempered Clavier is a brilliant
example of how patterns of tradition in our institutions have effected per-
sonal construction of meaning. The more open consideration of the sonic
experience of music is an important notion for music listening. I have in
mind too the questions of recorded music today. For example, as teachers of
music within the context of today’s media, we need to be aware of the issues
of sound production and reproduction. This chapter and the references
therein welcome the music teachers to be sensitive to how the live sounds
of artists of all types are processed for consumption. Yet another interest-
ing facet of this discussion is the matter of visual experiences of music in
performance as a factor in music listening.
316 Peter R. Webster
But Abramo gives us more. His speculation and observations about its
role in research might be an even more important question. His idea of more
soundscapes in our conception of data sets is worth major consideration
and invites us to be more thoughtful about the implications of sound. The
advancements now in some research publications (both online and more tra-
ditional) that allow multiple forms of media as part of the evidence presented
welcome this affordance. The use of sound in our presentations of research
too are noted, opening up a way to think more creatively about making the
findings more meaningful for audiences interested in the sonic experience.
I found the examples offered about sounds betraying the sociological and
historical record of schooling to be intriguing and potentially very useful
for researchers interested in deconstructing the educational experience. His
explanation of “noise” in this context is important.
The section on arts-based research, inspired in part by Eisner’s writing,
is also of importance, especially for those that frame the requirements for
advanced degrees. Newer forms of “research” in our field that might include
less discursive prose and more artistic products such as narratives, plays,
and musical compositions place more attention on the arts experience as
part of the research record. Perhaps it is time for us to welcome more cre-
ative approaches to terminal degree requirements and to the acceptance of
research reports with more “musical” evidence.
CONCLUDING THOUGHTS
In all four of these chapters, one senses the importance of good research
questions. This is sometimes implied in the writing and at other times is
actually highlighted as a section. It is likely that our practice of teaching and
research will only improve in coming years if professionals have a better
understanding of research itself and the tools for doing it.
In each of these chapters, too, the clear role of interdisciplinary sensibility
is present. A review of the reference lists of each chapter will demonstrate
that each author is well-read in other disciplines and they apply this knowl-
edge to their scholarship. The development of this kind of cross-disciplin-
ary understanding does not happen by accident and probably needs to be
instilled as a core value in our research education efforts. Related to this is
a need for more collaboration between researchers in other fields of music
and with those outside our field. The disposition toward research teams
and a continuing agenda of research activity continues to evade most of our
professional efforts.
Finally, a clear implication for me in reading these chapters and in con-
sidering all that they have in common (and how they are different) is that
we need to upgrade our efforts to integrate research content into our profes-
sional education programs. Each of these chapters contain advanced thinking
about research and powerful implications for practice. To lay groundwork
for this, we simply need to do better at both our undergraduate and gradu-
ate levels in preparing our music teachers professionally. In undergraduate
education, evidence-based practice should be at the forefront of “methods”
classes (if we must continue to call them that). There is nothing inherently
complicated about the basics of good research and to include some level of
understanding in undergraduate programs is not asking too much if we are
clever at what we do. Graduate school offerings in research need to build
on this and lead readers to be better able to consume and apply the content
of chapters by Abramo, Silverman, and Stefanic particularly. If we have any
hope of really effecting reform in the way music is taught, better research
questions, interdisciplinary and collaborative efforts, and advanced under-
standing of the context and techniques of research are all necessary for the
future that we all want.
This page intentionally left blank
Part V
If you are reading this chapter, there is a good chance that you are someone
with an interest in seeing music education be a valuable part of your com-
munity. It is likely that some of you are music teacher educators who would
like to see the future teachers with whom you are working be well equipped
to be successful in this the first part of the 21st century. I would like to
suggest here that change, in both variety and in degree, is a product of the
specific culture that you find yourself working within. It is possible that you
are teaching in a setting that enjoys a 60 percent student participation rate,
well above the national average in the United States (21 percent) and Florida
(8 percent), and that the scope and quality of the music making that your
students are engaged in is excellent. In your case, there might not be a need
at the moment to change much of anything in the organization of what you
do. However, there may be some who are reading this who are struggling in
their specific setting to recruit students for and sustain meaningful interest
in music. This theory might be a useful tool to assist both your thinking and
action.
The character and the role that an individual devises for himself as an
occupant of a particular social position. More intuitively, such a role-
identity is his imaginative view of himself as he likes to think of himself
being and acting as an occupant of that position.
(p. 65)
Figure 21.2 Model of identity as the foundation upon which “self” constructs rest.
Note: Identity is the most stable of the constructs, as it is the root of all of the other constructs.
Some scholars have argued that questions of identity are at the founda-
tion of a person’s belief system (Buss, 2001; Green, 2003; Roberts, 1991),
that identity beliefs mark who a person is. Perceptual worlds, on the other
hand, help to orientate a person to her surroundings, thus helping her to
know where-she-is. Cultural worlds—with a connection to history—help a
person to know who-she-is, thus helping shape her identity (Benson, 2001).
Table 21.1 shows some of the common differences between self-esteem (a
perceptual component of the self) and identity (a cultural component of the
self). Notice that both areas are generally quite stable, however, identity is
perhaps the most stable. Since identity deals with the portion of self that is
concerned with meaning, it might be viewed as essentially one’s philosophy
of self as a function of time.
The self-systems located higher in the model, being more perceptually
bound, that help answer the “where am I” locative questions, are more eas-
ily malleable. By completing a difficult task successfully, an individual can
add to her self-efficacy (perception of her ability to complete a task in the
future) of any number of musical or teacher-orientated tasks. That, in turn,
can help in the self-esteem area (her evaluation of how worthwhile she is),
and in turn, the self-concept area (the component of the self that sorts all of
the incoming information related to self enhancement). Over an extended
period of time, identity can also be affected.
One application for music education at the higher education level is
that by locating particular efficacies in music that might lead future music
Table 21.1 The Difference Between Self-Esteem Questions and Identity Questions
Self-Esteem Identity
How worthwhile am I? Who am I?
Positive: adds pride in self Positive: lends meaning to life
Lacking: self-effacement Weak: rootlessness
Amnesia has little effect Amnesia obliterates it
Romantic love adds to it Marriage adds to it
How well a role is played Commitment to a role
Group: vicarious self-esteem Group: a feeling of belonging
Note: The table is borrowed from Psychological Dimensions of the Self (Buss, 2001, p. 89).
A Theory of Change in Music Education 329
teachers to approach their jobs as music teachers in ways that could stretch
currently immovable curricular offerings, music teacher educators will be
able to feed, in a way, the future local cultural creative processes of music
teachers. Efficacies in vernacular musicianship, composition, free improvisa-
tion, and others, could be infused in teacher education programs as “tools”
of sorts for local change. Again, the model of cultural creativity presented
later in this essay will illustrate how this might work in practice.
Figure 21.3 Model of the analogy of the self-system to soil in a rain storm.
Note: Identity as a cultural world is located the deepest, as it is the most stable, and the least
directly affected by the bombardment of experience.
330 Clint Randles
self-system, while Figure 21.3 is about the idea of the structure as it re-
lates to the notion of change. Saturation is what it will take to effectually
“change” an individual at the “who am I” level (keep in mind the defini-
tion of individual presented earlier). Various efficacies are the first practical
component of the self that should be addressed in this theory of change in
music education. The idea of efficacies are explained in more detail as they
relate to the Conceptual Model of Change in Music Education, presented
later in this essay.
Another way to think about the relationship between perceptual worlds and
cultural worlds is to think of the two constructs not as one combined whole,
such as in the previous model, but rather as separate members involved in
a dynamic relationship characterized by interaction. Tuan (1977) wrote in
his thought provoking book Space and Place that “place is security,” some-
thing that we are attached to, while “space is for freedom,” something we
long for (p. 6). Space is where elements that are both novel and appropri-
ate are searched out. These elements serve as food for the cultural creative
processes that are engaged in at the individual level. Place is where these
elements are checked and tested. Place can be thought of as the location of
the cultural creative process.
Place can further represent the cultural worlds that we seek to nurture
in our lives, our sense of who we are. Tuan (1977) stated that “what begins
as undifferentiated space becomes place as we get to know it better and
endow it with value” (p. 6). So, for Tuan, we constantly are aware of place,
while we more comfortably explore the area of space. This exploration can
be likened unto a personal quest for fulfillment or a hero’s journey (Camp-
bell, 1949/2008), where identity is maintained and over time extended. The
hero’s journey in the Campbellian sense is characterized by separation-ini-
tiation-return. Tuan (1997) suggested that once we conquer areas of space,
they have the potential to become place to us (p. 6).
I shall now shift the focus of this essay to situating this theory within the
history of the study of identity, before unpacking my conceptual model of
change in music education.
SITUATING CHANGE
Work in the sociology of music education has been somewhat ongoing since
the late 1950s (Mueller, 1958) and the mid-1960s (Kaplan, 1966), and con-
tinues to be a topic today (Froehlich, 2006; Green, 2011; Wright, 2010).
Music education scholars and researchers have grappled with the realiza-
tion/belief that social/historical/political forces have and probably always
A Theory of Change in Music Education 331
will impact music education practice on multiple levels (Campbell, 1997,
1998; Green, 2002; MacDonald et al., 2002). The complex interactions
caused by these forces mean that teachers and students must work within
systems that are sometimes predetermined, sometimes out of their control,
while at the same time trying to do what they feel is best for their students.
Doing what is best for students and working within existing social struc-
tures is not always easy, particularly when the social structures are rigid.
However, I do not want to suggest here that the situation is without
hope, for music education is alive and well in many cases at the local level.
Teachers who recognize that curriculum might best be conceptualized as
a creative process are finding ways to enhance the musical experiences of
their students by working within sometimes rigid social structures. In the
United States, there is band, choir, and orchestra at the secondary level.
These ensembles have been around since the beginning of the 1900s in the
United States (Mark & Gary, 2007). These ensembles are promoted at the
state and national level by NAfME, and are a part of nearly every college
music program across the country. To be accepted into any of these pro-
grams, one must audition for a spot on one of the instruments or voices
currently being represented in these standardized ensembles. Students who
audition to get into the school have had at least thirteen years of encultura-
tion into the world of that way of making music—performing from notation
masterworks in a large ensemble under the direction of a conductor. This
is the cultural world that music education theorists/practitioners in their
specific cultures must work within and through. This is part of the reason
why identity, in this essay, is conceptualized as a somewhat rigid construct.
The “who we are” part of self has a legacy. This legacy is what we have to
acknowledge and work with and around.
Identity is not impossible to change, though. Lucy Green (2011) describes
the formation of musical identities this way:
So, going back to the Model of the Analogy of the Self-System to Soil in a
Rain Storm (Figure 21.3), new experiences bombard our perceptual worlds,
in this case the perceptual worlds of music education collectively, that cause
the profession to become aware of things that it has not been aware of, and
cause it to reevaluate its place. Over time (this is key) the profession searches
the space containing all possible ways to expand first its perceptual world,
332 Clint Randles
then its own cultural world. For example, the notion of being multi-musical,
being able to function as a reader of notation and as a vernacular music
maker, or being multi-creative (Burnard, 2011, 2012), might capture the
collective imagination of the profession. Members of the higher education
community could search out ways of engaging their respective schools of
music in the actualization of various plans to prepare the next generation
of teachers to occupy a new and improved place (stemming from the col-
lective mind of the profession). All the while, new experiences bombard the
profession, as this dynamic interaction prompts change in new and exciting
ways. It was formed over time, and so therefore, out of necessity, it must
change over time. Music education scholars and curriculum reformers must
take into consideration the rootedness of identity in terms of the individual
preservice music teacher.
Music education faculty members often desire to assist students in form-
ing a teacher identity through various observations and practicum experi-
ences, sometimes seeking to encourage new ways of thinking and doing
regarding music education theory and practice, with full knowledge that
each preservice teacher has had at least 13 years of enculturation into the
world of music learning and teaching as a student. This point complicates
the work of music education faculty who have a mind for change in the
profession. Identity is stable; it might be considered the root of our human
self-systems. By the time music education majors reach the college level, the
“who am I as a music maker” questions have been answered in the minds of
students to a large extent. These questions can certainly still be approached
by music teacher education faculty; however, given that they were developed
over time, resulting beliefs regarding these important questions must morph
over time.
not be this prescriptive, although they might be. The creativity of the teacher
is an essential ingredient to creating new practices that meet our “product
intention” expectations.
An understanding of the components of the Cultural Creative Process
provides a point of entry for how to use this model to enact change. Enabling
skills might be a teacher’s musical or teaching skills that have been devel-
oped as a result of his or her primary or secondary socialization. Teacher
education is key to expanding these enabling skills for future generations
of teachers and their students. Opportunities to arrange music by utilizing
vernacular musicianship, composing and improvising in a variety of con-
texts, and using a variety of technological tools in the performance of digital
music, are all examples of enabling skills that can have an impact on cul-
tural creative processes. Enabling conditions, that include both personal and
social/cultural factors, are the specific components of the larger model (con-
text, people, past practices, etc.) that require immediate attention during
the cultural creative process. Not all knowledge of people, context, and past
practices (among other large conceptual areas) is useful during a particular
336 Clint Randles
cultural creative process. This is the primary reason that the Conceptual
Model of Change in Music Education accounts for the various components
of change at both the macro and micro levels.
Specific practices are the end and the beginning of every cultural creative
process. So how do we gauge the success or failure of the process? What
makes a particular created practice more or less appropriate than another?
Csikszentmihalyi’s (1999) “Systems View of Creativity” (see Figure 21.6)
might provide a useful way of conceptualizing how new experiences, new
ideas, the work of practitioners, individual music education scholars, academic
institutions, and even research centers might be able to engage the imagination
of the profession. These are the outputs, the “new practices” of the “cultural
creative process,” what is created. These “new practices” then can be tested
for appropriateness, first at the local level, and then, potentially, at the
regional, state, and even national level. In Csikszentmihalyi’s (1999) model,
the individual, domain, and field work together to determine what is “novel”
and “appropriate” (p. 315). In order for new ideas and practices to be
accepted, they need to be introduced and promoted by individuals who possess
a good feel for what is acceptable to the society and the consequent culture that
he or she is working within. If the social groups and the culture that make up the
“webs of significance,” to quote Geertz (1973, p. 5) once again, that make up
those cultures are not taken into consideration, then change might not be pos-
sible. I would like to argue, with much optimism, that change is possible.
A PLACE TO START
NOTE
REFERENCES
Anderson, W. T. (1997). The future of the self: Inventing the postmodern person.
New York, NY: J. P. Tarcher.
Barrett, M. (2011). Towards a cultural psychology of music education. In M. Barrett
(Ed.), A cultural psychology of music education (pp. 1–16). New York, NY:
Oxford University Press.
338 Clint Randles
Benson, C. (2001). The cultural psychology of self: Place, morality, and art in human
worlds. New York, NY: Routledge.
Burnard, P. (2011). Rethinking “musical creativity” and the notion of multiple cre-
ativities in music. In O. Odena (Ed.), Musical creativity: Insights from music
education research (pp. 5–28). Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing.
Burnard, P. (2012). Musical creativities in practice. New York, NY: Oxford University
Press.
Burnard, P., & Younker, B. (2008). Investigating children’s musical interactions
within the activities systems of group composing and arranging: An application
of Engestrom’s activity theory. International Journal of Educational Research,
47, 60–74.
Buss, A. (2001). Psychological dimensions of the self. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
Publishing.
Campbell, J. (2008). The hero with a thousand faces (3rd Ed.). Novato, CA: New
World Library. (Original work published 1949)
Campbell, P. S. (1998). Songs in their heads: Music and its meaning in children’s lives.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, P. S. (2007). Adolescents’ expressed meanings of music in and out of
school. Journal of Research in Music Education, 55(3), 220–36.
Casey, E. (1997). The fate of place: A philosophical history. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Castro-Tejerina, J., & Rosa, A. (2007). Psychology within time: Theorizing about
the making of socio-cultural psychology. In J. Valsiner & A. Rosa (Eds.), The
Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology (pp. 62–81). New York, NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1999). Implications of a systems perspective for the study of
creativity. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), Handbook of creativity (pp. 313–35). New
York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Engestrom, Y. (1987). Learning by expanding: An activity-theoretical approach to
developmental research. Helsinki, Finland: Orienta-Konsultit.
Engestrom, Y. (2001). Expansive learning at work: Toward an activity theoretical
reconceptualization. Journal of Education and Work, 14(1), 133–56.
Froehlich, H. (2006). Sociology for music teachers: Perspectives for practice. Upper
Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.
Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Green, L. (2002). How popular musicians learn: A way ahead for music education.
Hampshire, England: Ashgate Publishing.
Green, L. (2003). Music education, cultural capital, and social group identity. In
M. Clayton, T. Herbert, & R. Middleton (Eds.), The cultural study of music: A
critical introduction (pp. 263–73). London, United Kingdom: Psychology Press.
Green, L., (Ed.) (2011). Learning, teaching and musical identity. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Kaplan, M. (1966). Foundations and frontiers of music education. New York, NY:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Kirton, M. J. (1976). Adaptors and innovators: A description and measure. Journal
of Applied Psychology, 61, 622–98.
MacDonald, R., Hargreaves, D., & Miell, D. (2002). Musical identities. New York,
NY: Oxford University Press.
Mark, M., & Gary, C. (2007). A history of American music education (3rd Ed.).
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishing.
McCall, G. J., & Simmons, J. L. (1978). Identities and interactions: An examination
of human associations in everyday life. New York: Free Press.
Merton, R. K. (1968). Social theory and social structure. New York, NY: Free Press.
A Theory of Change in Music Education 339
Mueller, J. H. (1958). Music and education: A sociological approach. In N. B.
Henry (Ed.), Basic concepts in music education: The fifty-seventh yearbook of the
national society for the study of education (pp. 88–122). Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Randles, C. (2013). Why composition in band and orchestra? In C. Randles & D.
Stringham (Eds.), Musicianship: Composing in band and orchestra (pp. 5–14).
Chicago, IL: GIA Publishing.
Randles, C., & Webster, P. (2013). Creativity in music teaching and learning. In G.
Cariyannis (Ed.), Encyclopedia of creativity, innovation, invention, and entrepre-
neurship (pp. 420–9). New York, NY: Springer Publishing.
Roberts, B. (1991). Music teacher education as identity construction. International
Journal of Music Education, 18, 30–9.
Seeger, F. (2001). The complementarity of theory and praxis in the cultural-histori-
cal approach: From self-application to self-regulation. In S. Chaiklin (Ed.), The
theory and practice of cultural-historical psychology (pp. 35–55). Oakville, CT:
Aarhus University Press.
Siegel, H. (2006). Epistemological diversity and education research: Much ado about
nothing much? Educational Researcher, 35(3), 3–12.
Sternberg, R. J. (Ed.) (1999). Handbook of creativity. New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press.
Triandis, H. C. (2007). Culture and psychology: A history of the study of their rela-
tionships. In S. Kitayama & D. Cohen (Eds.), Handbook of cultural psychology
(pp. 59–76). New York, NY: Guilford Press.
Tuan, Y. (1977). Space and place: The perspective of experience. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Webster, P. R. (2006, April). Refining a model of creative thinking in music: A basis
for encouraging students to make aesthetic decisions. Paper presented at the
National Convention, Music Educators National Conference, Salt Lake City, UT.
Welch, G. (2011). Culture and gender in a cathedral music context: An activity theory
exploration. In M. Barrett, A cultural psychology of music education (pp. 225–58).
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Wright, R. (Ed.) (2010). Sociology and music education. Burlington, VT: Ashgate
Publishing.
22 The Role of Subversion in
Changing Music Education
John Kratus
RESISTANCE TO CHANGE
Change in American music education has usually come very slowly. Randles
pointed out that the formal education of music teachers in the United States
has changed little over a long period of time. In 2009 I gave a presentation
on collegiate curricular change in music for the Society for Music Teacher
Education in Greensboro, North Carolina. One of the first slides in my pre-
sentation was an outline of Michigan State University’s degree requirements
for the Bachelor of Music in Music Education. The outline included certain
numbers of semesters for applied lessons, large ensembles, theory and ear
training, and history and literature, as well as music education requirements
including three tracks (instrumental, string, choral/general), introduction to
music education, conducting, instrument and voice classes dependent on
track, methods classes dependent on track, college of education courses, and
student teaching. I asked the audience members how many of them taught
in a college program similar to that. Nearly every hand went up. Then I
revealed that the program I described was taken from the Michigan State
University Academic Programs book from 1959. The course descriptions,
the performance repertoire, even the delivery of instruction were, for all
practical purposes, nearly unchanged in 50 years. This inertia is dangerous,
The Role of Subversion in Changing Music Education 343
because institutions that do not change to accommodate their changing con-
texts ultimately cease to exist.
The stagnation in our music teacher education programs goes back much
further than 50 years. It is not an exaggeration to say that the type of music edu-
cation provided to contemporary collegiate music majors has deep roots in the
conservatories of European capitals of the 19th century. In fact, more than its
roots are located there—21st-century collegiate music has retained the stems,
branches, leaves, flowers, seeds, and pollen of its 200-year-old predecessors.
A little history lesson is in order to uncover how we find ourselves today
in such an intractable, anachronistic curriculum for music teacher educa-
tion. Beginning in the early 1800s, the classical music business experienced
a boom across Europe, especially in the urban centers. Prior to this time,
this form of music was primarily available only to the secular and religious
aristocracy. With the creation and increase of a European middle class,
orchestral music and opera became accessible to a much broader audience.
Orchestras and opera companies were formed in all the larger European
cities and in many smaller ones as well. Opera companies and orchestras
spread through the United States in the late 19th century and early 20th
century. Classical music was a growth industry, and the demand for musi-
cians was high.
Up to this time professional classical musicians learned their craft through
an apprentice system. With the dramatic increase in orchestras and opera
companies, the one-on-one apprentice system was unable to produce a suf-
ficient number of trained musicians to fill the available positions. As a means
to supply additional qualified musicians, the first secular music conservatory
in the world, the Conservatoire National de Musique et d’Art Dramatique,
was founded in Paris in 1795. Across Europe secular conservatories soon
sprung up in Milan (1807), Naples (1808), Prague (1811), Vienna (1817),
London (1822), Leipzig (1843), and elsewhere. The conservatory boom hit
the United States later in the 19th century, with schools like Oberlin (1866),
New England (1867), Boston (1867), and Peabody (1868).
REFERENCES
Joseph Abramo
University of Connecticut
Neag School of Education
Department of Curriculum and Instruction
249 Glenbrook Road, Unit 3033
Storrs, CT 06269–3033
Wayne Bowman
Brandon University
School of Music
Queen Elizabeth II Music Building
270—18th Street
Brandon, Manitoba
Canada, R7A 6A9
Richard Colwell
University of Illinois at Urbana/Champaign
School of Music
1114 W. Nevada St.
Urbana, IL 61801
Frank Heuser
UCLA
Herb Alpert School of Music
2539 Schoenberg Hall
Los Angeles, CA 90095–7234
John Kratus
Michigan State University
College of Music
214 Music Practice Building
East Lansing, MI 48824
348 Names and Addresses
Roger Mantie
Arizona State University
Herberger Institute for Design and the Arts
PO Box 872102
Tempe, AZ 85287–2102
Michael L. Mark
Towson University
Department of Music
Center for the Arts, Room # 3095
8000 York Road
Towson, MD 21252
Clint Randles
University of South Florida
School of Music
4202 East Fowler Ave.
Tampa, FL 33620
Bennett Reimer
Northwestern University
Bienen School of Music
711 Elgin Rd
Evanston, IL 60208
Alex Ruthmann
New York University
Department of Music and Performing Arts Professions
35 W. 4th Street, Suite 1077
New York, NY 10012
Names and Addresses 349
Karen Salvador
University of Michigan-Flint
Department of Music
126 French Hall
303 East Kearsley St.
Flint, MI 48052
Marissa Silverman
Montclair State University
College of the Arts
1 Normal Ave
Montclair, NJ 07043
Nicholas Stefanic
University of South Florida
School of Music
4202 East Fowler Ave.
Tampa, FL 33620
Brent C. Talbot
Gettysburg College
Sunderman Conservatory of Music
Campus Box 403
300 North Washington Street
Gettysburg, PA 17325
Matthew Thibeault
University of Illinois at Urbana/Champaign
School of Music
1114 W. Nevada St.
Urbana, IL 61801
Evan Tobias
Arizona State University
Herberger Institute for Design and the Arts
PO Box 872102
Tempe, AZ 85287
350 Names and Addresses
Peter R. Webster
University of Southern California
Thornton School of Music
Los Angeles, CA 90089-0851
David B. Williams
Illinois State University
School of Music
College of Fine Arts
Campus Box 5660
Normal, IL 61790–5660
Michael Zelenak
Alabama State University
Department of Music
915 S. Jackson Street
Montgomery, AL 36104
Index
National Standards for Music talent 189, 191, 198, 215, 219–29,
Education 18 236, 296, 315, 336, 343
New Media 63–6 Tanglewood Symposium 3–4, 189
Index 353
technological determinism 66, 89, 120, Transmedia 94, 99, 107–18, 142, 146,
122, 124–5, 128–38 152, 158
time cone 20, 25, 163
Tobias, Evan 85, 90–8, 109, 113–22, Webster, Peter 29, 42, 91, 94, 119,
139, 141–3, 147, 152, 157–9, 315 121–2, 138–9, 143, 148, 154,
TPACK 149–50 224, 314, 333, 339, 341
transformation 5, 35, 40, 92, 132–3,
137, 215, 219, 226–31, 255–6, YouTube 64, 80–1, 95–100, 116, 120,
261, 264, 286, 316, 323, 332 137, 141, 198