Fictionasreality
Fictionasreality
by Deborah Kest
Most people assume, that if you can touch an object, taste it, or hit
something with it, it must be real, and their knowledge of its reality is
based on the direct apprehension of the facts at hand. Fiction, on the
other hand, because it is made up by us, is not a fact we can apprehend
directly, and is thus either false or unreal. I am arguing that the reverse is
true: that our access to reality is based on fiction rather than fact, that we
understand something only insofar as we tell ourselves a story about it.
By this I mean that fiction is inherently more 'true' than fact, and that
what we call facts are actually nothing more than good fictions- ones
which we deem most reasonable to accept.
Many people might say 'I am sitting on a chair. I know it is a chair because
it IS a chair- it is objectively real. I know it because I can feel it, and if I
could I would throw it at you.' First, our knowledge of this as a chair is
available because a long time ago some adult pointed and said 'chair,'
and when later we asked what's a chair, he/she said 'something made for
you to sit in or on.' We understand this as a chair because we have a story
about what a chair is and we tell ourselves that this fits our story. Its
objective reality doesn't tell us that it is a chair; we recognize it is as a
chair because of our concept of chair. It is through the concepts, not the
external facts, that we know objects to be the kinds of things which they
are.
'Fine', you might say, 'but what about the object itself, without the name. I
still know it exists and is hard even before I can speak or understand
words.' Kant answered this by arguing that you only see through the
instruments of your eyes. Things could appear very differently if we could
see them directly, without any limitations. But just as we can't see
anything without our eyes, so too can we not apprehend anything without
categories of understanding. As an example, we say that striking a match
causes it to flame. But how do we know that? Perhaps through
experience: I notice that every time I strike a match, it then flames. David
Hume pointed out that all this shows is that in the past we have a
constant conjunction of two events: the strike, and the flame. There is
nothing in this constant conjunction which gives evidence of necessity, or
that it will continue in the future. We don't have evidence of cause, but of
co-incidence. He concluded that since our belief in necessity can't derive
from perception of events in the world, it is no more than a fiction - a bad
habit, in fact. Kant responded that necessity can't come from the external
world, but it can come from us. It is because we order things as cause and
effect that we have any concept of cause, or of necessity. In our chair
example, it is because we have a category of understanding of 'substance'
which enables us to process a sensation into a something, an object.
The second response I have, following directly from the first, is that
though there may be an objective world, we have no direct access to it,
only a mediated one. That mediation is subjective, or based in the subject.
Our perception, our very concept of reality is at heart subjective. What is
most real to us is not 'raw reality' but the assumptions which underlie any
judgment we can make, including the assumption that things exist, that
there is an external world, etc.
My claim that fiction is more basic than fact in no way implies that every
fiction is worthy of acceptance. We have many criteria to distinguish good
fiction from bad. In science, for example, in order to be accepted it must
be testable, it must be the best explanation, and meet all of the other
criteria scientists have for good theories. Or, if it is a claim about the
physical world rather than a theory, then in order for the story to be good
it must be consistent with the best theories available. (It is extremely bad
fiction, evaluated by the criteria of science, to think that if you just believe
a bullet call do you no harm, then it won't.)
In the subject of history, for example, some of the criteria of good fiction
is how well our story fits with the evidence we have, with the goal being to
determine what really happened. Since we have no direct access to
history, but only tile accounts under evaluation, historians ask a variety of
questions to determine what was most likely: which sources were least
motivated to lie, which were most thorough, which were closest to the
event bring described, what is the consensus on ally given event, etc.
I am not claiming that the issue of whether or not the gods are real is
irrelevant, but that their reality is based not on existence, but on
attributes. The verb 'to be' has three uses: the existential, predicative and
veridical. According to the existential, 'to be' means to exist; in the
predicative, to be some property; and in the veridical, to be the case, or to
be true. The gods are real if they 'are.' But though they are, that doesn't
mean they must exist. Instead the gods are real in the predicative sense,
or insofar as they have properties we accept as real. I, for example, don't
believe that omnipotence makes any sense whatsoever. Because I don't
accept omnipotence as meaningful, or exemplifiable, the Hebrew God is
less real to me.
You might argue that if something has a property, it must also exist. But
many people are willing to grant that Pegasus has wings without also
agreeing that Pegasus must therefore exist. I'm not suggesting that the
gods don't exist, but that religion doesn't provide the answer to that
question, nor should it. That is a personal choice, while religion is
providing a public basis for action, a consensus about values, etc. We can
all have access to what the gods represent, and have that be meaningful
in our thoughts, actions, decisions, etc., without taking the added step of
affirming that the gods exist in some particular form. Since religion is
about the practices the gods demand, we can follow the religion just by
following the demands.
But how can we follow the demands unless we believe that there are gods
out there making those demands, and that we can perceive them in some
way? This question religion must answer. While we may not have direct
access to metaphysical entities, we must have some kind of epistemic
basis on which we all agree if we are to practice the same religion. So one
criterion for good religious fiction will be how well its epistemic basis
transmits the demands of its gods to its adherents. Religions of the book
have the advantage of a very clear common basis of rules, but the
disadvantage of less responsiveness to particular circumstances. Religions
based on divination may be very responsive to particular questions and
problems, while providing less of a common base of agreed-upon norms.
Regardless of the nature of the epistemic basis, however, each religion
will have to provide an answer to that question, and how well it answers
that question will partly determine how good that religious fiction is.
One advantage in the shift in criteria from claims about which gods truly
exist to what values they represent, what practices they demand, etc. is
that it better fits our intuitions about how to judge religion. If the criterion
is about existence, whichever religion best answers the question about
which gods exist would be objectively true, and everyone should follow it.
Because the criteria of values must satisfy us each individually, no one
religion could possibly be right for everyone. Religions whose fictions are
richer are likely to satisfy more people, but just as long as we have
different views of the world, different values, etc. no one path can claim
objective truth.
In conclusion, the concepts which make reality real are in us rather than
out there. And what makes them real has to do with the web of beliefs
which allows us to interpret our experiences, so we in fact experience
them rather than numbly undergo a barrage of sensations. It is that web
of beliefs which constitutes our reality. Because the beliefs are in us, they
are subjective. Since they are more true of us and the way we must see
the world than they are of the world itself they more closely resemble
what we call fiction than what we think of as fact. This is really only to say
that what is meaningful does not derive from what is true, but the other
way around. Truth is a subcategory of meaning, the fictions which
constitute all of what we call reality.