Aristotle On Tragedy
Aristotle On Tragedy
Aristotle On Tragedy
Aristotle on Tragedy
In the Poetics, Aristotle's famous study of Greek dramatic art, Aristotle
(384-322 B.C.) compares tragedy to such other metrical forms as comedy
and epic. He determines that tragedy, like all poetry, is a kind of
imitation (mimesis), but adds that it has a serious purpose and uses
direct action rather than narrative to achieve its ends. He says that poetic
mimesis is imitation of things as they could be, not as they are — for
example, of universals and ideals — thus poetry is a more philosophical
and exalted medium than history, which merely records what has
actually happened.
Aristotle goes on to discuss the structure of the ideal tragic plot and
spends several chapters on its requirements. He says that the plot must
be a complete whole — with a definite beginning, middle, and end — and
its length should be such that the spectators can comprehend without
difficulty both its separate parts and its overall unity. Moreover, the plot
requires a single central theme in which all the elements are logically
related to demonstrate the change in the protagonist's fortunes, with
emphasis on the dramatic causation and probability of the events.
Aristotle has relatively less to say about the tragic hero because the
incidents of tragedy are often beyond the hero's control or not closely
related to his personality. The plot is intended to illustrate matters of
cosmic rather than individual significance, and the protagonist is viewed
primarily as the character who experiences the changes that take place.
This stress placed by the Greek tragedians on the development of plot
and action at the expense of character, and their general lack of interest
in exploring psychological motivation, is one of the major differences
between ancient and modern drama.
. . . a man who is highly renowned and prosperous, but one who is not
pre-eminently virtuous and just, whose misfortune, however, is brought
upon him not by vice or depravity but by some error of judgment or
frailty; a personage like Oedipus.
In addition, the hero should not offend the moral sensibilities of the
spectators, and as a character he must be true to type, true to life, and
consistent.
It is worth noting that some scholars believe the "flaw" was intended by
Aristotle as a necessary corollary of his requirement that the hero should
not be a completely admirable man. Harmartia would thus be the factor
that delimits the protagonist's imperfection and keeps him on a human
plane, making it possible for the audience to sympathize with him. This
view tends to give the "flaw" an ethical definition but relates it only to the
4
spectators' reactions to the hero and does not increase its importance for
interpreting the tragedies.
Aristotle wrote the Poetics nearly a century after the greatest Greek
tragedians had already died, in a period when there had been radical
transformations in nearly all aspects of Athenian society and culture. The
tragic drama of his day was not the same as that of the fifth century, and
to a certain extent his work must be construed as a historical study of a
genre that no longer existed rather than as a description of a living art
form.
In the Poetics, Aristotle used the same analytical methods that he had
successfully applied in studies of politics, ethics, and the natural sciences
in order to determine tragedy's fundamental principles of composition
and content. This approach is not completely suited to a literary study
and is sometimes too artificial or formula-prone in its conclusions.
Nonetheless, the Poetics is the only critical study of Greek drama to have
been made by a near-contemporary. It contains much valuable
information about the origins, methods, and purposes of tragedy, and to
a degree shows us how the Greeks themselves reacted to their theater. In
5
addition, Aristotle's work had an overwhelming influence on the
development of drama long after it was compiled. The ideas and
principles of the Poetics are reflected in the drama of the Roman Empire
and dominated the composition of tragedy in western Europe during the
seventeenth, eighteenth, and nineteenth centuries.
6
ARISTOTELIAN TRAGEDY*
●
*Key terms regarding Aristotelian tragedy, as discussed in his Poetics:
*6 BASIC ELEMENTS*
1. Plot 4. Thought
5. Song
2. Character 6. Spectacle
3. Diction
7
● CHARACTER:
○ The tragic character, secondary to plot, should possess a
moral quality, for who should pity the fall of an evil man?
○ The tragic heroes should also be realistic and true to
their type (gender), to themselves (consistency of
character), and to the laws of necessity and probability.
○ While the characters should be realistic, Aristotle
suggests that they should also be “more beautiful,”
idealized, elevated, or ennobled.
TRAGIC HERO
● SPECTACLE:
○ last in importance
■ tragedy does not need to be performed to be
effective
■ tragedy can be read for the same effect
○ (sensory effects)
○ costuming
○ scenery
○ gestures
○ voice
○ "stagecraft"
10
● PERIPETEIA:
○ A sudden reversal of fortune, or circumstances, leading to the
protagonist’s downfall.
○ The peripeteia should be closely related to the anagnorisis
(recognition).
● ANAGNORISIS:
○ It means “recognition” or “discovery,” and Aristotle uses these
to denote the turning point in a drama at which the protagonist
recognizes the true state of affairs, having previously been in error
or ignorance.
○ We might say this is the moment in which the “tragic hero”
recognizes his “tragic error” or “tragic mistake.”
○ Perhaps, too, we can call this a “moment of clarity.” For example,
Oedipus recognizes that he killed his father, married his mother,
and brought a plague upon his people.
● DEUS EX MACHINA:
○ A weakness in a tragedy or a writer who relies upon this artifice
to resolve the Plot, rather than the action resolving itself according
to the laws of probability and necessity.
○ Literally, it means “god in/from the machine,” and it involved
the lowering of a god onto the stage via machinery in order to
resolve the entanglements of the situation/plot.
● CATHARSIS:
○ The “purging” of pity and fear in the tragic audience.
○ These emotions, feelings are aroused by the action and assuaged
by its resolution.
■ PITY = eleos: compassion for Pathos bearer
■ TERROR - FEAR = identification with Pathos bearer
■ PATHOS = Passion, key/religious suffering
11
References
https://www.cliffsnotes.com
https://academic.luzerne.edu/shousenick/ENG104_ELEMENTS_DRA
MA_Aristotle.htm