Discursive Analytical Strategies: Understanding Foucault, Koselleck, Laclau, Luhmann
Discursive Analytical Strategies: Understanding Foucault, Koselleck, Laclau, Luhmann
Discursive Analytical Strategies: Understanding Foucault, Koselleck, Laclau, Luhmann
The creation of knowledge and discourse is integral to modern society and is no longer
More than ever, therefore, we need to be able to step back and question the production
of meaning. This exciting and innovative book fills a gap in the growing area of discourse
analysis within the social sciences. It provides the analytical tools with which students
and their teachers can understand the complex and often conflicting discourses across
a range of social science disciplines.
Examining the theories of Foucault, Koselleck, Laclau and Luhmann, the book:
A bestseller in Denmark, this English edition is vital reading for anyone with an interest
in discourse analysis. It will also be invaluable to anyone looking at the analytical works
of Foucault, Koselleck, Laclau and Luhmann. Students will find the clear exposition of
the theories and strategies, supported by an easy-to-digest, easy-to-read layout, which
includes summaries and boxed examples highlighting the relevance of analytical
DISCURSIVE
strategies to social and policy research.
ANALYTICAL
STRATEGIES
Understanding Foucault,
Andersen
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
The right of Niels Åkerstrøm Andersen to be identified as author of this work has been asserted by
him in accordance with the 1988 Copyright, Designs and Patents Act.
All rights reserved: no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise
without the prior permission of The Policy Press.
The statements and opinions contained within this publication are solely those of the author and
contributors and not of The University of Bristol or The Policy Press. The University of Bristol and The
Policy Press disclaim responsibility for any injury to persons or property resulting from any material
published in this publication.
The Policy Press works to counter discrimination on grounds of gender, race, disability, age and sexuality.
Contents
List of tables and figures IV
Acknowledgements V
Glossary VI
Introduction IX
References 119
Index 131
III
Discursive analytical strategies
Tables
0.1 Method versus analytical strategy XIII
1.1 Foucault’s analytical strategies 31
2.1 Koselleck’s analytical strategies 48
3.1 Laclau’s analytical strategies 62
4.1 First- versus second-order observation 71
4.2 The differentiation of society 83
4.3 Luhmann’s analytical strategies 92
5.1 Analytical strategies compared 97
5.2 Problems of conditioning related to the analytical strategies 114
Figures
1.1 The genealogy of psychoanalysis 21
1.2 The elements of self-technology 25
1.3 Dispositive analysis 28
1.4 The double movement of dispositive analysis 29
2.1 Synchronous versus diachronic 47
3.1 Chains of difference and equivalence 55
3.2 The relationship between deconstruction and discourse analysis 58
4.1 The sign of difference 65
4.2 The marked difference 65
4.3 A difference observed through a difference 66
4.4 The distinction system/environment re-entered as a part of itself 67
4.5 The sign of re-entry 68
4.6 Re-entry of the distinction system/environment 81
4.7 The calculus of form 84
4.8 Media/form staircase 86
4.9 The relationship between form analysis and semantic analysis 89
4.10 The relationship between differentiation and semantics 90
4.11 The relationship between systems analysis and media analysis 91
5.1 Analytical strategy 117
IV
Acknowledgements
This book presents Michel Foucault, Reinhart Koselleck, Ernesto Laclau and
Niklas Luhmann as analytical strategists. There is a reason for this. I have for
some years been studying the more fundamental changes in European societies.
Trying to capture these fundamental changes, it is easy to become a victim of
current self-descriptions and future images in society. Instead of grasping the
changes you become a prisoner of the discourse producers of the day and
their strategically constructed future images. It is easy to confuse the actual
changes with the images and, in so doing, one may become an instrument in
confirming the discourse producers’ political predictions of trends: globalisation,
the knowledge society, the network society and the dream society. Studying
change, it is essentially difficult to maintain the necessary distance to the object;
to the society that should be studied.
In my terminology, this problem is one of analytical strategy: how can you
critically analyse a coherence of meaning of which you are a part? Foucault,
Koselleck, Laclau and Luhmann explored this problem and it is the four very
different strategies of handling it that form the theme of this book.
The book has been written in a very inspiring environment at the
Department of Management, Politics and Philosophy at Copenhagen Business
School. I would like to thank my colleagues for their challenging discussions
and fruitful comments. In particular I would like to thank Christina Thyssen,
Asmund Born and Hanne Knudsen.
V
Discursive analytical strategies
Glossary
An analytical strategy is a second-order strategy for the observation of how
‘the social’ emerges in observations (or enunciations and articulations). The
elaboration of an analytical strategy involves shaping a specific gaze that allows
the environment to appear as consisting of the observations of other people or
systems.
A guiding distinction is the distinction that can define the frame for second-
order observations. For the second-order observer, the guiding distinction
divides the world and dictates how the world can be observed.
VI
Glossary
Nodal points are privileged discursive points, which serve to arrest the flow of
relationships without ever becoming a real centre of the discourse. The
discursive struggle about the construction of nodal points is, so to speak, a
struggle about the conditions of conflicts within a specific discourse.
VII
Discursive analytical strategies
Subject positions are the spaces from which one speaks and observes in a
discursive formation. Subject positions have rules for the acceptance of certain
individuals into the spaces, rules for acceptance regarding in what situation
the subject position can be used as a platform for speaking and observing, and
rules for the formation of statements once one has assumed a specific position.
Subjectivation happens when the individual or the collective is not only formed
as a subject but also wishes to be the subject. Subjectivation signifies the space
in which the individual gives itself to itself.
VIII
Introduction
IX
Discursive analytical strategies
the question of social hygiene dating back to the social reforms of the 1920s
and 1930s?
At the same time, knowledge has become an intrinsic part of the organisation
of society in a much more strategic way than before. Today sociologists speak
of the knowledge society, the corporate community talks about knowledge
management. Generating knowledge is no longer exclusive to independent
scientific institutions such as universities. In the corporate community,
knowledge-intensive businesses have been established, such as the big
international consulting firms PLS Consult, Deloitte & Touche and McKinsey.
They do not simply operate and utilise organisation theories developed by
the universities. They are themselves generators of theories and concepts, and
their concept development not only serves the purpose of scientific knowledge,
it also aims to seduce and sell.
Within government, similar discursive institutions have been established in
order to develop scientific discourses and to diagnose the condition of society,
with the intention of controlling the political agenda, defining the framework
for negotiation and installing a sense of responsibility in organisations, political
parties and individuals. One European example is the European Environment
Agency, which was established in order to collect data and make objective
decisions, and to function as a creator of environmental knowledge or discourses
and as a campaigning organisation. Other European examples are the Group
of Policy Advisers and the Joint Research Centre, both of which were created
under the auspices of the European Commission, and the European Monitoring
Centre on Racism and Xenophobia.
In relation to this, some people speak of knowledge politics. Today’s researcher
faces numerous investigations, concepts, problems, solutions, theories,
descriptions and explanations, embedded in the spirit of science, but also with
a scientific standing and political, strategic and administrative function that
remains obscure. Once again, this calls for research that takes a step back and
questions these investigations, concepts, problems, solutions, theories,
descriptions and explanations:
For example...
X
Introduction
Also, it appears that the subdivision of the social sciences into branches of
knowledge related to particular functions in society has become increasingly
problematic. Economic science applies to economy; jurisprudence applies to
the courts; media studies to the mass media, and so on. Today, more than ever,
it is evident that the different fields are helping to invalidate each other. Each
field has its own discourse and its own concepts, its own limited resonance;
each field can only communicate with itself without regard for the other
fields. It becomes difficult to identify one’s research with one area of research
exclusively, knowing that what looks like progress in one field might very well
be detrimental to others. For example, the development within the media of
the combination of ‘hidden cameras’ with ‘political journalism’ may have created
a ‘new genre’, but this development fundamentally disturbs the political process.
Methods have been developed to put a price on ‘care’ and ‘unhealthy lifestyles’,
but this produces totally unpredictable events within other fields – both positive
and negative – possibly without anyone realising it and consequently without
the possibility for self-correction. Once again, it therefore seems obvious that
we need to take a step back and to question the evolution of the different
fields, their communicative closure on their own functions, the limited reflective
ability of the individual fields, and their attachment with and detachment
from other fields.
Thus, we see the outlines of a new form of questioning appear, which does
not merely question actions within a field but which also questions the way
questions are asked in the field; questions the emergence of the categories, the
problems, the arguments, the themes and the interests. This form of questioning
entails a theoretical shift from the primacy of ontology to the primacy of
epistemology (Pedersen, 1983), from first-order observations of ‘what is out
there’ to second-order observations of the point that we are watching from
when we observe ‘what is out there’. From being to becoming.
XI
Discursive analytical strategies
For example...
• In which forms and under which conditions has a certain system of meaning
(such as a discourse, a semantics or a system of communication) come into
being?
• What are the obstacles to understanding the possibilities of thinking within
– but also critically in relation to – an already established system of meaning?
• How and by which analytical strategies can we obtain knowledge critically
different from the already established system of meaning? (Pedersen, 1983)
XII
Introduction
ontology that is restricted in its approach to reality, to only saying ‘reality is’.
The object, however, is not presupposed. In this way, epistemology is concerned
with the observation of how the world comes into being as a direct result of
the specific perspectives held by individuals, organisations, or systems. It also
asks how this causes the world – in the broadest sense – to emerge in specific
ways (while the observers themselves also emerge as individuals or
organisations). Therefore, an epistemological starting point poses not a question
of method, but a question of analytical strategies.
Analytical strategy
Analytical strategy does not consist of methodological rules but rather of a
strategy that addresses how the epistemologist will construct the observations
of others – organisations or systems – to be the object of his own observations
in order to describe the space from which he describes. From an epistemological
point of view the perspective constructs both the observer and the observed.
Hence analytical strategy as a way to stress the deliberate choice and its
implications, and to highlight that this choice could be made differently with
different implications in respect of the emerging object. The problem of the
epistemological restriction to ‘how’ questions and not ‘what’ or ‘why’ questions,
is that it constructs the researcher as a ‘purist’ (that is, as one who does not
assume anything in advance about the object to be studied). However, one
needs to assume something in order to recognise and observe the object. This
is the basic condition of working with analytical strategies.
Simply put, the difference between method and analytical strategy can be
viewed as follows:
This shift from method to analytical strategy raises a number of questions that
still have not been answered, and possibly not even conceived of in a satisfactory
manner. Within analytical strategy, the question of scientific knowledge poses
itself in a different way. Other questions appear and become essential, while
certain methodological questions become irrelevant. It is a problem that many
constructivist studies do not realise this. The stringent methodological question
often fades or disappears because it is not compatible with second-order
observations, but far too often it is not superseded by analytical-strategic self-
discipline. Instead of method, we often see a pragmatic examination of
XIII
Discursive analytical strategies
procedures; the result is often sloppy and inept. Many constructivist studies
lack scientific meticulousness in the shape of thorough accounts of their
analytical strategies. Often, it is extremely difficult to identify the basis of
scientific studies and, unfortunately more often than not, the criticism raised
by more mainstream-positivist positions is well justified.
Let me provide just two examples of analytical-strategic difficulties raised
by the epistemological turn.
Studies of change within epistemology, on the other hand, formulate the question
of when change can be considered a change. From an epistemological
perspective one immediately stumbles across the analytical-strategic difficulty
that any formulation of change is based on the observer’s construction. Change
can only be characterised within the framework of specific differences: a
change must have a beginning and an end. Prior to a beginning one must
assume an end – whether or not the end provides actual closure. Thus, the
nature of any formulation of change is teleological, and the analytical strategy
of the epistemological observer must reflect this fact through inquiries and
analytical-strategic decisions about the position from which one describes
change and, consequently, the distinctions that determine what appears as
change to the observer.
XIV
Introduction
This book also juxtaposes four different theor ies about society as
communication or discourse in regard to their analytical strategies. The four
theories are Michel Foucault’s discourse analysis, Reinhart Koselleck’s concept
analysis, Ernesto Laclau’s discourse theory and Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory.
This book is not a broad introduction to the four writers. Rather, it
presupposes a certain familiarity with or interest in some form of discourse
analysis. Neither does the book aim to weigh the writers’ powers of explanation
against each other, or to provide some kind of theoretical synthesis. Rather, it
attempts to to invoke an analytical-strategic discussion of different ways of
defining society as communication. It also aims to see what possibilities for
observation unfold when the concern is no longer given objects but, instead,
the question of how problems, individuals, interests – all kinds of social identities
– come into existence as and within communication. Which analytical
difficulties do we encounter when the innocence of the empirical collapses –
when we can no longer pretend that ‘the object out there’ discloses how it
wants to be observed, when we know that it is our ‘eye’ that makes the object
appear in a particular way?
Once again, I wish to stress the fact that this book is a contribution to the
development of an analytical-strategic discourse. I am not certain that my
way of presenting the problem is the ultimate one – my argument that the
analytical-strategic problem is different from the methodological problem might
be incorrect. I do not wish to give the answers to all possible analytical-
strategic problems. Neither do I wish to present a manual for discourse analysts.
XV
Discursive analytical strategies
XVI
Introduction
To elaborate the final point, Luhmann’s criticism of critical theory is first and
foremost a critique of the notion that there could be a place from which the
critic can describe society as a whole. According to Luhmann, there are only
systems-relative descriptions of society, and these can never be absolute.
Furthermore, Luhmann denounces critical theory for focusing more on how
the world is not (that is, how the world disappoints the norms of the critic),
than on how the world is (Luhmann, 1991). Instead, Luhmann’s ideal is the
unsentimental gaze. Laclau rejects the notion of criticism through a
deconstruction of the figure of emancipation as the domicile of the critic, that
is, the notion of freedom without power (Laclau, 1996a). Koselleck rejects the
notion of criticism through a conceptual-historical analysis of the concept of
criticism (Koselleck, 1988). He examines the conditions of its origin and its
decline as hypocrisy. Finally, Foucault insists that any truth is always founded
on an injustice, which also pertains to his own discursive analyses. Foucault’s
alternative to the critical researcher is:
This book contains four chapters about Foucault’s discourse analysis, Koselleck’s
history of ideas, Laclau’s discourse theory and Luhmann’s systems theory
respectively. The four chapters inquire about the enquiry of these four
epistemologists:
The output of each of the four epistemologists is very different. Some have
produced reasonably few, but concentrated, theoretical studies, others have
primarily conducted concrete analyses and their analytical-strategic
contributions stem from these works, others have an output that is vast in size,
theoretically as well as analytically. Although I ask the same questions in
regard to the different epistemologists, the approach is necessarily different
with each one, hence the different representations of the four epistemologists
both in size and style. The benefit of this is that it consolidates the width of
the analytical-strategic problems that emerge. In the concluding chapter I
offer a more explicit formulation of what I mean by analytical strategy.
Moreover, in the conclusion I conduct a more direct comparison of the four
analytical strategies, although knowing that this is an impossible venture, I
attempt to line them up and let them reflect each other.
XVII
Discursive analytical strategies
Delimiting marks
It is obvious to ask, why not four other writers? Why not include, for example,
Habermas, Bourdieu and Fairclough? It could be argued that Jürgen Habermas
really ought to be considered in a book that is founded on the notion of
society as communication, as, since the 1960s, Habermas has observed the
linguistic turn of the social sciences. In my view, however, Habermas represents
a transitional figure between ideological criticism and discourse analysis. He
sees the unavoidable centrality of language and communication, but he does
not fully live out the consequences.
As early as 1965, in his book Knowledge and human interests (Habermas,
1972), Habermas realises that it is necessary to settle with ideological criticism
and the distinction it creates between true and false consciousness. However,
he refuses to give up the universal status of the concept of criticism; rather, he
aimed to find a new way to base criticism. His first proposal for this can be
found in an article about universal pragmatism (that is, dialogue without
hegemony directed at understanding) (Habermas, 1991). Later, he displaces
and reformulates his universalistic concept of criticism several times, for example
in his ethics of discourse (Habermas, 1992) and, most recently, in the weighty
tome Between facts and norms (Habermas, 1996). But, the fact remains that he
never establishes a programme for second-order observation, which
simultaneously admits to its status as first-order observation. His insistence on
a universalistic foundation implies that, when observing communication
through his theoretical programme, it is always by means of an ideal about
communication. This means that Habermas cannot observe observations as
observations but always has to observe them as deviations from a universal
regularity. Habermas has committed himself to observing the way the world
is not rather than the way it is. Thus, Habermas’s programme remains in the
quagmire of ideological criticism, even if it is a very advanced version.
I could also have included Pierre Bourdieu in this book and, indeed,
contemplated it for a long time. Many of Bourdieu’s works contain reflections
of analytical strategy. In my own empirical discourse analysis I have, on several
occasions, employed elements from Bourdieu’s analytics. When comparing
Bourdieu and Habermas, they very often read the same texts but from
completely different perspectives. They both read the works of Searl and
Austin, for example, about different types of speech actions. But while Habermas
inquires about the universal conditions of speech actions directed at
understanding, Bourdieu inquires about the historical institutional conditions
that authorise a specific person as the generator of specific speech actions
(Bourdieu, 1992). It is my understanding that Bourdieu pursues a double
strategy. On one hand, he is without doubt an epistemologist and thinks,
therefore, in terms of analytical strategy – he always inquires about the origins
of problems, fields and speech actions. On the other hand, he appears to have
trouble accepting the cool gaze of epistemology and often resorts, therefore,
to metaphysics of suppression as if the distinction between over and under
were universally designed. He seems to be in constant oscillation between a
XVIII
Introduction
The first question was initiated by the rapid modernisation of the public
sector and by the fact that administrative policies appeared to establish a new
discursive regime. I wanted to describe this regime and its shaping, but I was
not interested in criticising it from a normative position, such as, for instance,
‘the defence of the welfare state’. The first question addresses how something
XIX
Discursive analytical strategies
XX
Introduction
private corporations that orient themselves towards public markets are forced
to subscribe to the discursive codes of the political system, that is, they are
forced to constitute themselves anew. Thus, the boundary between politics
and economy is no longer more or less identical to the difference between
public organisations and private corporations. Within public markets the
boundary between politics and economy penetrates the internal communication
of private corporations. Here, the question focuses on the relationship between
organisation and function system and on how private organisations can associate
themselves with different function systems, including the political and the
economic systems. The analytical-strategic question is concerned with how
to study the emergence of a private corporation whose identity is not necessarily
consistent but is relative to the association with either the political code or the
economic code. This required the formulation of an entirely new analytical
strategy in regard to institutional history – an analytical strategy capable of
pertaining to the organisational level, separating organisational communication
from other forms of communication.
In a book analysing the history of the outsourcing debate (Andersen, 1997),
again, I required a new analytical strategy. Unlike the study of the origin of
administrative politics, there is no single discourse on outsourcing. Rather
than being an autonomous discourse, outsourcing is and has been a drifting
concept whose meaning is interjected simultaneously in numerous mutually
conflicting discourses. Hence the predicament was not (as in the question of
administrative politics) the examination of the constr uction and
institutionalisation of one discourse, but rather the unfolding of interdiscursive
relationships within time and space surrounding the concept of outsourcing.
The analytical-strategic task involved defining the criteria for when and how
a relationship exists, which also means when and how a discursive separation
exists. For this purpose, I developed a genealogical analytical strategy based
on the works of Michel Foucault.
My latest book, Kærlighed og omstilling – italesættelsen af den offentligt ansatte
(Love and reorganisation – the articulation of the public employee), makes inquiries
into the boundary between public administration and employee (Andersen
and Born, 2001). The book examines the articulation of ‘the employee’ over
the past 150 years in Denmark. In the past, the relationship between employee
and organisation was discussed in an impersonal fashion, in which duties and
rights were the focus. Today, however, the employee is also required to ‘love’
the employing organisation and to share its outlook, otherwise he or she ought
to leave before being racked by feelings of guilt. In the language of employment
policies, this is termed ‘involvement’, ‘initiative’ and the ‘responsible employee’.
The analytical strategy used in this book is inspired by the work of Luhmann
and Koselleck, with a Foucauldian slant. The book combines three analytical
strategies: a semantic historical-analytical strategy, a differentiation analysis and
a form/medium analysis of the coding of employee communication. The
semantic analysis examines the conceptual history of the employee – we look
at how the employee is created in different semantic regimes. The differentiation
analysis relates the semantic development to the development in the ‘unity of
XXI
Discursive analytical strategies
the administration’ over 100 years during which the public institution changes
from the ‘innocent institution’ via the ‘professionally responsible institution’
into the ‘strategic organisation’. In the strategic organisation, the codes of the
conversation become fleeting. Subsequently, the form/medium analysis pertains
to the codes that become available to the communication about the relationship
between employee and organisation. The focus is on three codes: the legal
code (right/wrong), the educational code (better/worse learning competencies)
and the code of love (loved/not loved). The code chosen for the specific
communication determines who can communicate about what, including what
can be considered as a good argument. Finally, the focus shifts to the way in
which inclusion and exclusion takes place. With love’s codification of the
communication it becomes the responsibility of the employee to be included
in the workplace. Exclusion becomes self-exclusion.
In the encounter with empirical studies, I have, over time, been able to
locate different analytical-strategic problems. I have defined various analytical
strategies pertaining to certain epistemological research questions. But one of
the difficulties I have encountered, which this book addresses, is the lack of a
general, well-defined concept of analytical strategy capable of describing what
an analytical strategy consists of. I have always been of the opinion that there
is not, and cannot, be one analytical strategy capable of answering all the
questions that a creative epistemologist could possibly ask. I have always
encouraged students and others to define their own analytical strategy in
respect to their field of interest and their questions. In many ways, this seems
like an unfair request when one is not able to clearly explicate what an analytical
strategy is or when an analytical strategy is a good strategy; when there is not
even a single book or article that addresses the question in detail.
Since there is not one true analytical strategy, it makes no sense to grant
priority to any theoretical trend (for example that of Foucault or Luhmann).
I have always skipped between different epistemological schools and have
been happy to combine elements if they fit the specific analytical strategy.
Hence, this book should be regarded as an attempt to speak of analytical
strategy in general terms, and to create a field that enables analytical-strategic
discussions across the boundaries of different epistemological trends. The
book may make difficult reading to some people; the ambition, nevertheless,
is not theory for the sake of theory but rather the improvement of empirical
analyses within the epistemological realm. What is the purpose of professing
to discourse analysis if one does not conduct actual, empirically founded
discourse analyses?
Note
1
The distinction should not be understood as a normative regulation against the
use of methods for discourse analysts. The central question is whether a
methodological or a discourse-analytical perspective is primary in the research
design. Naturally, within one analytical strategy different methods can be
introduced which the analytical strategy must then question.
XXII
1
The discourse analysis of
Michel Foucault
ore than anyone, Michel Foucault has developed and created an agenda
1
Discursive analytical strategies
Foucault as a structuralist
Foucault is often called structuralist or poststructuralist. That makes sense
given the fact that he developed his discourse analysis in an environment of
structuralists, especially his teacher, the Marxist and ideology theorist Louis
Althusser. However, he has, on several occasions, rejected both those labels.
In this book Foucault will be read as a phenomenologist, without consciousness
as the origin of meaning – a subjectless phenomenology.
Structuralists work from a distinction between the manifest surface and the
latent structure. Structuralist analysis reconstructs the hidden and latent structure
based on logical breaches on the manifest level. In other words, structuralists
work from the idea that, underneath the visible, directly accessible text, lays a
slightly displaced invisible text that controls the questions and answers posed
by the visible text. The invisible text amounts to a regime that condemns
specific questions. By directing attention toward those moments in the manifest
text when meaning breaks down – when answers are given without questions
and when questions are posed without answers – structuralism can raise
questions regarding the underlying text, which must exist so that the apparently
illogical and meaningless makes sense after all. In Althusser, it is called
symptomatic reading, that is, a reading of the logical breaches of the visible
text as symptoms of an underlying and controlling structure (Althusser and
Balibar, 1970). Poststructuralists maintain the notion of structure but see the
structure as much more loose and undecided. Foucault rejects both positions.
To Foucault there is only one level, which is that of appearance. Foucault
focuses on the statements as they emerge, as they come into being. It is crucial
to him never to reduce them to something else. Consequently, discourse is
not a structure to Foucault; a point to which we will return later in this
chapter.
However, if we were nevertheless to associate Foucault with structuralism
(which does in some respects seems fair, since his entire position is developed
2
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
3
Discursive analytical strategies
Foucault intends to sound the limits of what we can recognize as our history.
At the interior of this history of ours, as of all history, identity presides;
within it, a single culture enables a number of human beings to articulate a
collective ‘we’. This identity – here is what must now be demonstrated – is
constituted through a series of exclusions. [...] Foucault goes further and
asserts that the history of madness is the history of the possibility of history.
‘History’, as we understand it, implies in effect the accomplishment of works
4
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
In Mental illness and psychology, Foucault (1976) examines the conditions within
psychology of speaking of illness. How is the notion of illness construed?
Where does psychology find its concepts of illness? And how do these concepts
of illness place psychology in a particular relationship with the patient? Foucault
defines four questions:
1. Under what conditions can one speak of illness in the psychological domain?
2. What relations can one define between the facts of mental pathology and
those of organic pathology?
3. How did our culture come to give mental illness the meaning of deviancy
and, to the patient, a status that excludes him?
4. And how, despite that fact, does our society express itself in those morbid
forms in which it refuses to recognise itself? (Foucault, 1976)
The first two questions address the way in which the question of illness operates
within the pathological discourse. Foucault explores the shaping of the psyche
through the creation of various forms of analysis in psychology, primarily
historical and phenomenological analysis. He observes the way psychology
and psychoanalysis observe their patients. He observes, for example, how
mental illnesses occur when psychoanalysis views its patients through the
concept of the individual story. He thus inquires about the discursive figures
that cause particular individual behaviour to emerge as illness. By answering
the first two questions, Foucault has presented the forms of appearance of
illness, but not yet the conditions of its appearance. He seeks to uncover the
latter through the last two questions, which address the construction of madness
outside psychology. Once again, the boundary between reason and folly
becomes central to the analysis. Foucault’s thesis is that those psychological
analyses that define the ill person as an outsider are projections of specific
cultural and discursive themes. Foucault shows how man has become “a
‘psychologizable species’ only when his relation to madness made a psychology
possible, that is to say, when his relation to madness was defined by the external
dimensions of exclusion and punishment and by the internal dimensions of
moral assignment and guilt” (Foucault, 1976, p 73). Foucault concludes:
Psychology can never tell the truth about madness because it is madness
that holds the truth of psychology. [...] There is a very good reason why
psychology can never master madness; it is because psychology became
5
Discursive analytical strategies
possible in our world only when madness had already been mastered and
excluded from the drama. (Foucault, 1976, pp 74, 87)
In The order of things, Foucault (1974) shifts the focus onto his own scientific
discourse and its historical conditions. He sets out to examine the historical
conditions of structuralism1. He raises the question of why structuralism
becomes a dominant societal phenomenon, manifesting itself in a large number
of humanist sciences: in structuralist psychoanalysis with Lacan as the main
figure (for example, Lacan, 2001), in structuralist ethnology and anthropology
with Lévi-Strauss (for example, Lévi-Strauss, 1996) and in a structuralist literary
criticism with writers like Barthes and Kristeva (Kristeva, 1989; Barthes, 1990).
In all three cases, Foucault particularly subscribes to structuralist linguistics
with Fernando de Saussure as the primary point of reference (de Saussure,
1990). Foucault investigates how language replaces man as the object of
knowledge. Foucault simultaneously studies the origin and disappearance of
the humanities as a result of the repression of human beings by language. In
Classicism, ‘man’ is considered the centre of the world – man is defined as the
subject in an double extension of, on one hand, a transcendental being charged
with will and reason, and, on the other hand, an empirical being (as specific
people that can be observed). This defines the potential conditions of the
humanities as humans observing humans. However, through structuralism,
language becomes subject by a similar division into both a transcendent and
an empirical being. It is no longer humans but structures that speak – ‘it’
speaks as Lacan formulates it; the conditions of the humanities recede. Instead,
we are faced with language, speaking of itself through itself. Foucault says,
“where there is a sign, there man cannot be, and where one makes signs speak,
there man must fall silent” (Foucault, 1998a, p 266). In other words, discourse
analysis becomes central.
With The order of things, Foucault makes structuralism the object of discourse
analysis and seeks to distance himself from it by analysing structuralism and its
genealogy. He begins in structuralism and writes his way out of it through
discourse analysis. In Discipline and punish, Foucault (1977) asks:
Where does this strange practice and the peculiar project of locking someone
up in order to rediscipline them, which is implied by the criminal law of the
modern age, stem from? [...] Behind the insight into people and behind the
humanity of the punishments we rediscover a particular disciplinary
investment in the human bodies, a mixture of submission and objectification,
one and the same relation between ‘knowledge–power’. Is it possible to
define the genealogy of modern morality based on a political history of the
bodies? (Krause-Jensen, 1978, author’s translation)
6
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
Discipline and punish traces the history of prison and describes how the types
of surveillance and punishment change fundamentally from the beginning of
the 19th century. The change is outlined as a shift from the torment and
absolute monarchy of the Middle Ages, to the modern prisons, in which the
apprehension of punishment, rather than the appalling theatre of torment and
torture, is supposed to deter people from criminal acts. In the modern prison,
“the convicted body is no longer displayed, now it is hidden. It is no longer
destroyed, but instead detained and isolated because it carries something, which
can be tamed and trained” (Krause-Jensen, 1978, p 124, author’s translation).
This is not a simple movement from barbarism to humanism, but rather a
movement defined by the rise of disciplining as a new and effective form of
power. An expression of this displacement is Bentham’s famous Panopticon –
a prison in which prisoners do not know if or when they are being observed;
in which the observer cannot himself be observed, forcing the prisoners to
discipline themselves based on the notion of constant surveillance: “The
Panopticon is a machine for dissociating the see/being seen dyad: in the
peripheric ring, one is totally seen, without ever seeing; in the central tower,
one sees everything without ever being seen” (Foucault, 1977). The movement
is from public torment to hidden surveillance, where the soul, not the body, is
to be punished.
However, Discipline and punish is not only a book about prisons. It is a book
about how a particular power of normalisation – disciplining and surveillance
– is shaped in conjunction with the rise of the prison but is later propagated
and generalised in society. In Foucault’s understanding, the prison is not
simply an institution subordinate to the courts of justice. Conversely, prison
is a form that subjects itself to the courts and also prevails in a large number of
relationships in society at large. Foucault speaks of the relative carceral
continuity as the many connections that exist between, on the one hand, the
surveillance and disciplining forms and, on the other hand, institutions such
as education, social services and workplaces with organised hierarchy:
Foucault’s analytical strategy develops parallel with this shift in his questioning.
In this chapter, I make a distinction between four analytical strategies: the
archaeology of knowledge, genealogy, self-technology analysis and dispositive
analysis. In certain readings of Foucault, the analytical strategies successively
7
Discursive analytical strategies
replace each other. In my reading, they are constructed on top of one another.
My outlines of Foucault’s analytical strategies are not complete, however; it is
possible to trace other strategies in his work, for example an aesthetic analysis.
However, discourse is not a structure and does not exist on a level different
from statements. Statements do not manifest themselves as a discursive structure.
Discursive formation simply consists of the regularity of the irregular
distribution of statements. In other words, the fundamental guiding difference
in Foucault’s knowledge archaeology is regularity/dispersion of statements.
This is the basic difference in Foucault’s analyses of discourse:
8
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
The outlines of a book are never clearly and stringently defined: no book
can exist by its own powers; it always exists due to its conditioning and
conditional relations to other books; it is a point in a network; it carries a
system of references – explicitly or not – to other books, other texts, or
other sentences; and the structure of reference, and thereby the entire complex
system of autonomy and heteronomy, depends on whether we are dealing
with a dissertation on physics, a collection of political speeches, or a science
fiction novel. It is true that the book presents itself as a tangible object; it
clings to the tiny parallelepiped surrounding it: but its unity is variable and
relative, does not let itself be constructed or stated and therefore cannot be
described outside a discursive field. (Foucault, 1970, p 152, author’s
translation)
Like texts, the works of authors are not bound wholes: “Apparently it indicates
the sum of texts that can be denoted by a proper name” (Foucault, 1970,
p 153). However, says Foucault, how about texts that are signed under a
pseudonym? How about hasty notes or sketches that are discovered
posthumously? What, for example, should be considered as belonging to the
works of Nietzsche? Only the books? Or also letters and postcards and texts
signed Kaiser Nietzsche? The fundamental problem, however, consists in the
general tendency to perceive works, as heterogeneous as they might be, as the
embodiment of one writer’s thoughts, experiences or unconscious. In other
words, to view texts as the indication of a whole, which is not visible in the
textual fragments but must be ascribed through interpretation. Consequently,
9
Discursive analytical strategies
Foucault delivers a critique not only of actual literary analysis but of any
textual analysis, which professes to refer the statements of the text back to the
author and his intentions, concerns, unconscious, circumstances and so on.
Every discursive moment (that is, every statement) must be observed in its
positive suddenness, in this punctuality which it enters and in this temporal
dispersion which makes it possible to repeat it, realise, forget, transform,
efface it until the last traces, hide it, far from all eyes, in the dust of books.
(Foucault, 1970, p 155, author’s translation)
Analysis of statements
In short, a statement needs to be analysed in its appearance, as it emerges, and
cannot be reduced to expressing anything other than itself, such as, for example,
the intention of the statement, the context, the concern or the meaning of the
statement. Foucault rejects any reductive or interpretative statement
descriptions. He consistently avoids questions of what or why in relation to
statements but only asks how. The question ‘What is the meaning of the
statement?’ instantly ontologises the statement – it is reduced to a given,
containing a secret. The question ‘Why this statement?’ reduces the statement
to its cause. Only questions of how the statement appears grant full attention
to the statement, only how does not immediately shift the attention away from
10
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
the statement itself to that which could possibly provide the statement with a
meaning or an explanation.
Discursive objects
Subjects
Again, subjects do not stand outside of the statement; conversely, the statement
articulates the space and possibility of subjects.
Conceptual network
11
Discursive analytical strategies
in some way. Linguistic elements such as signs and sentences are only statements
if they are immersed in an associated field, in which they simultaneously
appear as unique elements. Foucault summarises it thus:
This should not only be understood retrospectively as the fact that the statement
becomes a statement by relating to prior statements, but also understood
progressively as the way in which the statement paves the way for potential
future statements. Hence, a statement becomes a statement only if it both re-
actualises and extends other statements. This enunciative function, by the way,
has a striking resemblance to Luhmann’s notion of meaning, which is discussed
in Chapter Four.
According to Luhmann, meaning is merely the unity of actualisation and
potentialisation. Conversely, the enunciative function differs significantly from
Laclau’s more poststructuralist theory of signification, which is concerned
with structural relations between elements. I propose that perhaps Foucault’s
discourse analysis and Luhmann’s systems theory are closer to one another
than Foucault’s discourse analysis and Laclau’s discourse theory because of
their phenomenological kinship.
Strategy
For example...
Regardless of the attempted analogies, the readaptation for the screen of the
books of Morten Korck is not an identical transcription of the ‘original’ statements.
The statements are repeated, but their materiality and strategic standing is different.
The fact that Lars von Trier is responsible for the screen version is an enunciative
event, which exceeds the film itself.
12
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
• First, it means that, since it is not possible to define the discursive formation
beforehand, one cannot limit one’s reading to a theme such as, for example,
madness. Themes can relate to each other in unpredictable ways, which,
moreover, can change over time and between spaces. We therefore have to
follow the references of the statement and the references of the references
in time and space in the broadest sense, until they appear to form a completed
whole. There is no shortcut without consequences, as with the fate of the
discourse commentator.
• Second, Foucault maintains that it does not suffice to read the canonical
works pointed out by the history of ideas. It is crucial that the reading also
includes the statements of the institutions, statements that demonstrate
practice. Unravelling the history of madness includes readings of
philosophical works as well as scientific dissertations and the statements,
regulations and accounts of the institutions themselves.
• Third, and finally, we must be careful not to install a preconceived distinction
between official and more private and individual sources, as if the private
and personal sources exist outside the discourse.
13
Discursive analytical strategies
For example...
In the studies by Foucault of the self-relation of the self, diaries and personal
notes from Rome in the 1st and 2nd centuries play an important role in the
analysis. Likewise, novels, paintings and personal documents appear as frequently
used material. And, understandably, we cannot weigh up the types of statement
against each other in advance, as if a text by Voltaire is of greater importance
than documents written by an historically anonymous person, which, in turn, are
more important than the diaries of a doctor, and so on.
Not until the archive has been established is it possible to inquire about the
discursive formations. Not until the entire body of statements has been pieced
together can we start to ask questions about the way one or more regularities
appear in the irregular dispersion of statements, in other words, how the
dispersion of statements over time seems to be regulated by different discursive
formations. For Foucault it is about “seizing the statement in its momentary
conciseness and total singularity, determining its exact boundaries, establishing
the connections to other statements to which it can be linked, and showing
which other categories of statements are thus excluded” (Foucault, 1970,
p 156, author’s translation). The fundamental question to the statements posed
by discourse analysis in the attempt to create discursive formations is: ‘Why
did this and no other statement happen here?’ (Foucault, 1970, p 156, author’s
translation). The aim is to detect the rules that govern the way different
statements come into being in discursive formations. Rules in this context
mean rules of acceptability, that is, rules about when a statement is accepted as
a reasonable statement.
The question here is why statements shape their objects the way they do.
14
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
• From which subject positions do the objects appear the way they do in the
discourse?
This pertains to the rules of acceptability for the shaping of the spaces from
which one can speak and observe in the discursive formation, but it also
pertains to the existing rules for the acceptance of entering certain individuals
into the spaces that are being created, and when this can happen. That is:
The enunciation of the subject positions and the discursive objects furthermore
implies the connection to concepts. The questions are:
• Why does the statement actualise particular concepts and not others?
• How do concepts organise and connect statements?
• What are the rules for conceptualisation and how do specific discursive
formations draw on concepts from other formations, including the rules of
transcription, which seem to exist between different discursive formations?
15
Discursive analytical strategies
Conclusion
16
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
Genealogy
Genealogical analysis cannot be separated from archaeological analysis. The
relation between archaeology and genealogy is frequently portrayed, in Foucault,
as two periods in his writings in which the genealogical breakthrough is
summoned with the article ‘Nietzsche – genealogy and history’ (Foucault,
1991). However, before this publication Foucault had already used the term
‘genealogy’, at times together with the word ‘archaeology’. Moreover, the
majority of the questions addressed in the Neitzsche article had already been
discussed before in The archaeology of knowledge (Foucault, 1986a), in the chapter
‘Discourse and discontinuity’, and in different introductory problem
formulations in his historical works. In this section, I will construe the
genealogical analytical strategy as the historical dimension of the knowledge
archaeology. Consequently it is impossible, in my understanding, to conduct
a knowledge-archaeological analysis without combining it with a genealogical
analysis. In my exposition, the following is chosen as my starting point.
Whereas the framework for the eye of knowledge archaeology is the difference
regularity/dispersion of statements, the framework for the eye of genealogy is
the difference continuity/discontinuity.
17
Discursive analytical strategies
Antiquarian historiography cultivates the past for the sake of the past. It
becomes a blinded collection mania and a restless amassing of things of the
past. Such a historiography mummifies life; it is incapable of breeding life and
always underestimates the future (Nietzsche, 1988).
18
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
19
Discursive analytical strategies
Rather, the aim is to query the discourses and practices of the present by
referring them back to the hegemonic conditions under which they have
been established, which also includes pointing out ruptures in the grounds on
which strategies, institutions and practices are shaped. The presuppositions of
the present are to be dissolved by means of history2. Mats Beronius sums up
the main task of genealogy:
20
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
object of our examination, we need to investigate how our object has been
construed historically in different ways and in different settings. We are not
only to look for those events that stand out clearly as seen from the present,
but also for those constructions, strategies and practices that, for some reason,
never distinguished themselves, disintegrated or changed into something else.
Hence, we should not just trace that which became history, but also very
much that which has been defined as mistakes, antiquated, unrealistic and so
on. In this respect, the approach needs to be wide rather than deep. The way
of seeing that the difference continuity/discontinuity constitutes is a glance of
dissociation,
Confession
a, b, i
Treatment Psychology of the 18th century
ø, å
c, d, k
Mental institution
a, c, æ,
e, w,
c, æ, o, å
e, z Psychoanalysis
æ, q
The hospital
Internment
e, w, x
Source: This figure is a slightly altered version of a figure from Noujain, 1987.
21
Discursive analytical strategies
renews a control issue pertaining to the handling of deviants, but which has
obtained a specific definition and elaboration within the individual formations
and practices.
For example...
One example of these specific definitions and elaborations of the control issue
is the Poor Law internment institution, in which poor people, criminals and
people with mental illness were locked up together and excluded from ordinary
life and from the rest of society, to hide these examples of unwanted, non-
industrious laziness. Later examples are the mental institutions, in which mad
people were distinguished as a particular group and notions of societal dependency
were impressed on them in their treatment, as discussed above. Finally, there is
psychoanalysis, which introduces the distinction between the body and the
consciousness of the ‘madman’ and aims to restore his communication with the
outside world (Foucault, 1971).
This does not mean, however, that discursive histories are fictional in the sense
that it is entirely open which stories can be told. Rather, it means that no
history can be described without being rooted in problem and perspective.
History is a constructed reality of a perspective and is real and observable as
such. This question is unfolded frequently in Foucault’s work, for example in
relation to periodisation:
22
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
This, of course, has implications for the reading and analysis of the different
monuments of history, such as texts, images, legal reports and so on. The
displacement of one’s perspective and problem changes not only what one
sees, but also the way of seeing employed when reading and analysing. It
changes the statements to which one’s attention is drawn as well as the
connections one sees between statements:
The texts that I spoke of could easily be taken up again, along with the
very material that I treated, in a description that would have a different
periodization and would be situated at a different level. For example, when
the archaeology of historical knowledge is done, obviously it will be necessary
to again use the texts on language, and it will be necessary to relate them to
the techniques of exegesis, of the criticism of sources, and to all the knowledge
concerning sacred scripture and the historical tradition. Their description
will be different then. But if they are exact, these descriptions should be
such that one can define the transformations that make it possible to go
from one to the other. (Foucault, 1998a, p 284)
Again, as Foucault points out, this does not lead to relativism but rather perspectivism.
Given a specific perspective and problem, genealogy becomes sensitive to its
material in a specific way. However, genealogical descriptions can be criticised
for their perspective. Naturally, it is always possible to take a step back and
investigate the relevance and probability of a particular perspective and problem,
thus questioning all criteria of selection and the validity of the examination.
In the same way that archaeology is concerned with statements as they
appear, avoiding any form of discourse commentary, a similar phenomenological
antireductionism is stressed in genealogy. Foucault maintains that genealogy
must be unobtrusive and:
23
Discursive analytical strategies
Self-technology analysis
Knowledge archaeology and genealogy are among the most clearly described
analytical strategies in the writings of Foucault, but there are a number of
others. Self-technology analysis concerns the analysis of the technologies
available to an individual’s manifestation of itself as subject. Whereas knowledge-
archaeological discourse analysis allows for studies of the way in which subject
positions are created, the analysis of self-technologies permits studies of the
practical staging of the relationship between individual and subject position.
At an early stage in his writings, Foucault spoke of practice as something
that does not unambiguously coincide with discourse. His understandings of
practice, however, remain unclear, although he seems to border on directions
for practice. In relation to the history of sexuality, the concept of practice
appears to be replaced by the concept of technology, although this replacement
is not unambiguous. What is unambiguous, in turn, is the question posed by
means of the concept of technology – it pertains to the self-relation of the
subject to its self-care.
In his sociology, Simmel defines a distinction between position and vocation
as two different ways in which a person can become an individual. Similarly,
Foucault distinguishes between subjection and subjectivation (for example,
Foucault, 1997, 1998b; and Balibar, 1994). To Foucault, subjection means that
an individual or collective is proclaimed subject within a specific discourse.
The individual or collective is offered a specific position in the discourse from
which one can speak and act meaningfully in a specific way. Foucault speaks
of subjectivation when the individual or collective has not only been made the
subject but also wishes to be so. Subjection, thus, signifies the space where one
receives oneself, whereas subjectivation signifies the space where one gives oneself
to oneself (Schmidt, 1990).
This distinction is not merely theoretical. It is also a distinction between
two forms of discursive demands on the person who is to become the subject:
a distinction between two modes of subjection. The appropriation by the
individual of a subject position is not observable in terms of discourse analysis.
It is, however, observable whether and how the discourse demands active self-
appropriation of a subject position. This is exactly what Foucault discovered
in the history of sexuality – the fact that the individual is not only required to
fill out a particular subject position but also to care for her/himself
independently. The interesting point is that the discourse itself, through the
subjecting of the individual, makes a distinction between subjecting and
subjectivation in which the former forms a counter-concept in relation to the
latter. As it is, demands are made on the individual not to simply receive
oneself passively but actively to give oneself to oneself. In that sense, the
aforementioned mode of subjecting is a mode of transformation – it invokes the
passively receiving and subjected so that s/he may cross the line from subjection
to subjectivation, thereby making her/himself actively sovereign in her/his
own self-creation. It is an invocation to the individual to invoke her/himself.
24
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
These criteria also define the basic question through which we will examine
the technologies (see also, Davidson, 1986; Hacking, 1986).
25
Discursive analytical strategies
The second criterion is the objectification of the self, which concerns the
form of knowledge that the individual can establish about itself as self. The
question is:
• As what is the self to master itself? Is the self to master itself as feeling, as
desire, as will, or as culture?
3. Self-activating activity
The third criterion is the stipulations for self-activating activities, for example,
the diary as self-activity that emerged in the 2nd century in the Roman Empire
(Foucault, 1997), or the confessional practice of the Catholic Church. Examples
of modern technologies could be the ‘time manager’ of the 1980s or competence
interviews in the workplace.
4. Telos
Finally, the fourth criterion is the fact that the self-activity needs to have a
direction or an aim that extends beyond the mere activity. The question is:
• In what way does the self-technology provide the individual with a particular
telos for life?
Conclusion
26
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
Dispositive analysis
The final analytical strategy of Foucault, which I will briefly discuss, is dispositive
analysis. Dispositive analysis is quite difficult to describe and Foucault’s
systematic descriptions of the analysis are very limited. Nevertheless, it is a
central analytical strategy, particularly in Discipline and punish (1977) and History
of sexuality (1978). Most works on Foucault have disregarded dispositive analysis
and have focused on archaeology and genealogy; those who have addressed
dispositive analysis have described it very differently. Gilles Deleuze describes
dispositive as a structuring of light composed by lines of different nature
(Deleuze, 1992), Neil Brenner as a functional imperative (Brenner, 1994), and
Mitchell Dean as a regime of practices (Dean, 1999, p 21).
What makes dispositive analysis difficult to grasp is the fact that it can only
be perceived as a complementary analytical strategy, which succeeds the
archaeology, genealogy and self-technology analyses. These analytical strategies
are preconditions of dispositive analysis because the focus of dispositive analysis
is precisely the interconnections between different discourses, institutions,
practices, self-technologies, tactics and so on, within a particular period.
Foucault defines dispositive as:
Whereas archaeology divides the world into the regulation and dispersion of
statements, geneaology into continuity and discontinuity, and self-technology
analysis into subjection and subjectivation, dispositive analysis divides the world
into apparatus on one hand and strategic logic on the other hand. The distinction
between apparatus and strategic logic is the ‘eye’ of dispositive analysis.
The apparatus is the ‘heterogeneous ensemble’; it is a system of elements
between which there exists a functional connection. The strategic imperative
or logic is a generalised schematic that brings about a particular logic. These
are always relative in relation to one another. There is no apparatus without
the apparatus acting as an apparatisation and, thus, a function of a strategic
logic. In turn, there is no strategic logic except through the effects it defines
through an apparatus. I have attempted to outline dispositive analysis in Figure
1.3.
Generalisation
27
Discursive analytical strategies
Dispositive
........ confession/perversion
For example...
Foucault speaks of the ‘prisonisation’ of society, thus pointing to how the logic
of discipline, which is born out of a context of surveillance and punishment, is
generalised so that it can subsequently obtain meaning in educational systems,
workplaces, and so on.
Apparatisation
On the other hand, when indicating the side of the apparatus in the guiding
distinction, the question is how a particular strategic logic is brought about
through apparatisation, in which forms, such as discourses, technologies and
architectures, are linked as functional elements in a system.
28
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
For example...
We have schools that divide students according to age, divide space into classrooms
and divide time into lessons. We have architectural forms that construct classrooms
with peepholes so that the class does not know if or when it is being observed by
the principal.
29
Discursive analytical strategies
Conclusion
30
The discourse analysis of Michel Foucault
capture the particular way of inquiring of each strategy; the right-hand column
provides a concrete example of how a specific social issue can be discussed,
based on Foucault, and what the differences are depending on which of
Foucault’s analytical strategies is employed.
The example used here pertains to the development of the relationship
between employee and organisation. Over the past 20 years, the construction
and definition of the employee has been put on the agenda. The relationships
between individual and role has been addressed. Employees’ personal lives
have been integrated into the workplace. Staff policies have become life policies
with management speak including terms such as ‘lifelong learning’,‘flexibility’,
‘personal competencies’, the ‘complete human being’. New practices, such as
performance and competence reviews, have come to prevail.
Archaeological discourse analysis Why did this and not another In what way has a new discourse
statement occur in this place? been established that articulates the
employee as a complete and
responsible human being with
responsibility for his or her own
development?
Genealogy How are different discursive In what way does the new discourse
formations and discursive about the complete employee not
strategies shaped and transformed? simply express a humanisation of the
workplace, but also an
internationalization of previous forms
of discipline
Self-technology analysis How have self-technologies been How are performance and
created and how do they prescribe competence reviews developed and
the way an individual can give itself carried out as self-technologies,
to itself? through which the employee can learn
to master himself as strategic resource
in the workplace?
Dispositive analysis How are forms linked together as In what way does the educational way
functional elements of an apparatus? of seeing become a general schematic
How are discursive or technological and strategy for organising, and how is
elements generalised in a schematic the educational scheme propagated
that develops a strategic logic? and apparatised in employee
discourses, self-technologies, office
architecture, and so on?
31
Discursive analytical strategies
As it is hopefully clear from Table 1.1, the choice of analytical strategy makes
an important difference to one’s empirical and problem-related sensitivity:
Notes
1
My exposition of The order of things draws on Raffnsøe, 1999.
2
For a further discussion of Foucault’s genealogy, see for example, Megill, 1979;
Roth, 1981; Shiner, 1982; Kent, 1986; Mahon, 1992.
32
2
Reinhart Koselleck’s history
of concepts
33
Discursive analytical strategies
administrative texts) and without regard for those semantic or discursive fields
of which the canonical works form a part (Ifversen and Østergård, 1996,
p 25).
The relevance of the history of concepts can be summed up in three
characteristics:
The fundamental premise for the history of concepts is the idea that concepts
are central to the constitution of society, including the constitution of action
as well as agents of action. The shaping of concepts is hence not a simple
surface phenomenon. If historical science is indeed seeking to raise critical
constitutional questions, it must do so by defining the shaping of concepts as
the central issue. Without concepts, notes Koselleck, there is no society and
no political fields of action (Koselleck, 1982, p 410). This does not imply that
everything can be reduced to concepts. According to Koselleck, the history of
concepts must include linguistic as well as sociohistorical data – any semantics
entail non-linguistic content (Koselleck, 1982, p 414). (We will return to this
point in connection with the notion of concept later in this chapter.)
The constitution of society can therefore be examined as a semantic battle
about the political and social; a battle about the definition, defence and
occupation of conceptually composed positions. Concepts must be perceived
of as reaching into the future: “Concepts no longer merely serve to define
given states of affairs, they reach into the future. Increasingly concepts of the
future were created, positions that were to be won had to be first linguistically
formulated before it was possible to even enter or permanently occupy them”
(Koselleck, 1982, pp 413-14).
Included in this proposition is the notion that semantics change at a slower
pace than the events themselves. There are several factors related to this point:
34
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
• Second, the fact that the possible ways of semantic expression are limited
gives it a more enduring stability. The semantic units (concepts) outlive
the occasions comprised by the history of events:
When new experience becomes, as it were, a part of language’s inventory,
as in the case of the centuries-old but ever more nuanced debate about
the constitutions, or in the perennially recurring conflict between different
notions of might and right, then the semantics has a slower rate of
change than the events themselves. (Koselleck, 1989, p 657)
• Third, precisely because the concepts possess a different inner time structure
than the events they participate in inciting or conceiving of, they are marked
by perseverance in respect to their epoch, which turns semantics into an
obvious historical object.
Knowledge interests
The purpose of the history of concepts is not merely to add yet another
object to the historical sciences. The purpose is to examine the way in which
the shaping of concepts and the transformation of the semantic fields move
history and reach into our future. Koselleck criticises the kind of historical
science that devotes itself exclusively to the study of individual incidents on
the assumption that detailed studies of incidents are less problematic than
studies of the structural history of longitudinal lines. Koselleck demonstrates
how the narrative content of structures and events is fundamentally the same.
Incidents are always construed narratively as events and, moreover, any event-
oriented historical science is too meagre and is unable to contribute to a
historical diagnosis of potential futures (Koselleck, 1985, pp 105-15).
The history of concepts also distinguishes between diachronic and
synchronous analysis. Diachronic analysis consists of an analysis of the historical
origins and transformation of individual concepts, and thus suggests a notion
of concept. Synchronous analysis consists of an analysis of the semantic field
in which concepts appear and connect with other concepts. Synchronous
analysis frequently refers to concepts such as the ‘semantic field’, ‘semantic
structure’ and ‘counter-concepts’. I will further address these two conceptual
sets below; however, initially I wish to stress that, to Koselleck, there can be no
qualified history of concepts without both of them. The concept-historical
analysis must continually move back and forth between the diachronic and
the synchronous in order neither to fall back on a barren history of words nor
forwards onto the pitiless social history of concepts.
35
Discursive analytical strategies
alone, and this indicates one of the main differences between the notion of
concept and many other discursive traditions such as those of Foucault and
Laclau, for example.
Accordingly, concepts provide the portal to studies of the historical space of
signification. But,
Each concept is associated with a word, but not every word is a social and
political concept. Social and political concepts possess a substantial claim of
generality and always have many meanings. (Koselleck, 1982, p 418)
For example...
There are several meanings to the word ‘tramp’, but when used it is unambiguous.
If someone gives advice to a potential boyfriend – “Stay clear of Sheila. She is a
tramp” – the meaning is clear.
For example...
One example is the concept of ‘equality’, which is never completely defined and
can signify many things, from equal pay, minority issues and ethnic equality, to the
struggle against the patriarch or the concept of ‘the state’ (which involves a
range of elements such as territory, power, tax collection, jurisdiction). Or it
may signify the concept of ‘ecological sustainability’ (which may include eco-
balance or the relationship between economic growth and the environment).
This concept functions as a point of reference to environmental bureaucrats as
well as a utopia to dedicated environmentalists; it signifies both the good life and
a pragmatic balancing of ecology and economy.
36
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
Koselleck specifies the construction in this way: “The meaning of a word can
be determined exactly through definition, concepts can only be interpreted”
(Koselleck, 1972, p XXIII, author’s translation).
According to Koselleck, words become concepts through the condensation
of a wide range of social and political meanings. Thus, concepts comprise an
undecided abundance of meaning, a concentration of meaning, which makes
them ambiguous. Without this ambiguity, concepts would not be capable of
reaching into the future but, precisely because of its ambiguity, the concept
reveals a space of signification that is open to interpretation and can become
a semantic battlefield. Precisely through its ambiguity, the concept can create
positions for later occupation and conquest, create time and space and so on.
Without the ambiguity of concepts, there are simply no conditions of
conceptual disagreement. If we were able to define ‘equality’, ‘ecological
sustainability’, ‘freedom’, ‘responsibility’, ‘representation’, there would be no
politics, no semantic battle and, consequently, no history. It is the concept of
equality that organises the fight for equality as a struggle about reducing
ambiguity and establishing positions from which equality can be represented.
Historically, we can observe how various meanings have been condensed into
the concept of equality and, thus, have organised the struggle for equality.
Equality initially was taken to mean equality between the sexes. Gradually, it
became identified with equality in the job market and eventually the conceptual
field was extended to society more broadly so that, today, the conflict is about
the equalisation of equality between the sexes with equality among ethnic
minorities or between disabled and able-bodied people. Slowly, the concept
of the politics of equality is taken over by politics of multiplicity. We are no
longer able to define employment policies only in respect of equality between
the sexes, but must also have regard to a flexibility and multiplicity that includes
a variety of people: men, women, young people, old people, Muslims, Christians,
weak people, strong people and so on. In this way, the concepts reach into the
future: they define a space of signification and they define the meaning of the
struggle for meaning.
Conclusion
The history of concepts thereby suggests an analytical strategy, which analyses
history as a semantic struggle about turning words into concepts through the
condensing a wide range of meaning into the concepts. Of course, this is not
a linear history. A word can remain the same even though its meaning changes.
A concept can remain the same even though its linguistic designation changes.
A concept can survive even though its content changes and so on.
This raises a question that is parallel with (but probably not identical to)
Laclau’s question of hegemony and floating signifiers. According to Laclau, a
hegemonic struggle can only take place if the structure is open – if the signifiers
float above the signified – and the hegemonic struggle is therefore about
arresting the floating. The concept of the floating signifier appears to function
in a similar way to Koselleck’s notion of concept. The ambiguity of the
37
Discursive analytical strategies
concept indicates that the concept does not possess a fixed relation to the fact
to which it refers, in the same way that Koselleck’s definition implies that the
concept moves into the fact by adding meaning to it. Both characteristics of
the concept (its floating and creative qualities) form the conditions for a semantic
battle.
Counter-concepts
Koselleck links the notion of counter-concept with the question of the
construction of collective identities, in particular the construction of political
subjects. He asserts that the construction of identities always involves asymmetric
classification – identities are always shaped in asymmetric relations between ‘us’
and ‘them’. The simple identification of the ‘us’ offers far from adequate
conditions of giving ‘us’ the capacity to act:
But a ‘we’ group can become a politically effective and active unity only
through concepts which are more than just names or typifications. A political
or social agency is first constituted through concepts by means of which it
38
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
Singularity/generality
Still, the creation of identity through counter-concepts cannot occur without
tension in the relationship between, in Koselleck’s terms, singularity and generality.
In many ways, this separation coincides with Laclau’s distinction between
particular and universal (a point to which I return in Chapter Three). On the
one hand, we can ascertain that concepts such as ‘movement’, ‘party’ and
‘interest group’ can be exercised on equal terms in the self-construction of a
range of different identities. The concepts of ‘movement’, ‘party’ and ‘interest
group’ are transferable in the sense that they can be subsumed, applied and
transcribed by many different groups in a large number of contexts. Similarly,
the identities that are constructed in association with the concepts of
39
Discursive analytical strategies
‘movement’, ‘party’ and ‘interest group’ are reciprocal, in the sense that they do
not exclude and incapacitate each other.
For example...
In the current Danish Parliament there are 10 parties that all shape their identities
by referring to the concept of ‘party’, which, in itself, does not present a problem.
The Social Democrats and Venstre (Liberal Party) are different, but reciprocal,
identities that do not incapacitate each other.
On the other hand, Koselleck notes that there tends to be singularisation, that
is, for the general to be subjected to the singular: “Historical agencies tend to
establish their singularity by means of general concepts, claiming them as
their own” (Koselleck, 1985, p 160). This is the case when a religious community
lays claim to the Church, or when a political party claims to the represent the
people. The Communist Party in the Soviet Union was an extreme example
of the singularisation of the general designation of ‘people’ and ‘party’. However,
the same thing is true when generality is being restricted, for example through
prohibiting certain political parties (such as the Communist Party or the
National Socialist Party), or not allowing a religious community to be
recognised as such. Generally, this applies whenever specific, that is, singular,
requirements exist for affiliating oneself with the general. These requirements
are always present, and hence the general is never truly general. There is
always a limit to transferability, and reciprocal identities are therefore only
reciprocal in relation to the identities they collectively exclude. The singular
and the general never appear as pure differences, they always contaminate
each other.
The problem of the singularisation of the general requires an analysis of
how identities are constructed in relation to the shaping of concepts to focus
always on how the tension between singularity and generality is defined.
For example...
40
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
Christianity introduced the next phase. Rather than maintaining the distinction
between Hellenes and barbarians, Christians recruited members from both sides.
They did not define themselves in opposition to Romans, Jews, Hellenes and so
on; the concept ‘Christian’ was created potentially to encompass all human beings,
regardless of race, class and so on. However, the distinction between Hellenic and
barbarian was gradually superseded by the distinction between Christian and
heathen, as a separation of religious and non-religious people. The distinction was
41
Discursive analytical strategies
construed temporarily, according to the prevailing notion that all heathens would
eventually become Christians. This temporality installed a dynamics in Christianity.
Gradually, however, through the crusades, for example, becoming a Christian
was not just an option. Exclusion and expulsion became the other side of
Christianity.
The third phase is represented by humanisation. Until this point, beginning with
the renaisance, ‘man’ signified the unity of differences. Humankind was the sum
of the Hellenes and the barbarians, and, later, the sum of the Christians and the
heathens. Today, however, humankind and humanity have developed into an all-
encompassing counter-concept that outdoes the opposition between Christians
and heathens. This has happened in conjunction with the discovery of America
and general globalisation, which means it is no longer possible to discover and
annex new land ad infinitum; and the dispersal of the Christians into different
religious communities, which means that the concept of ‘Christian’ in itself is no
longer singular. Humanity thus emerges as a concept that produces a minimum
definition uniting the divided Christians.
42
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
• before/after;
• inside/outside;
• up/down.
(They are sometimes portrayed as five couples: before/after; birth/death; inside/
outside; friend/enemy; up/down.)
43
Discursive analytical strategies
Before/after
Any history is, by its nature, poised between a before and an after, and this
distinction is prelinguistic insofar as we are always living in the space between
birth and death. This means not only that the lifespan is limited, but also that
we live with death as the horizon and know that murder as well as suicide is
possible. The distinction is furthermore prelinguistic in the sense that
generations succeed generations, which results in a range of overlapping fields
of experience that exclude each other in layers. Here, Koselleck speaks of
diachronic conflicts (Koselleck, 1987, pp 11-14, 1989).
Koselleck extended the difference before/after in his distinction between
space of experience and horizon of expectation (Koselleck, 1985, pp 226-88). ‘Space
of experience’ and ‘horizon of expectation’ should be understood as
epistemological categories. There can be no time–space relationship and thus
no history without a conceptual formation of a space of experience and a
horizon of expectation. The present does not exist in itself but only in the
tension between a space of experience and a horizon of expectation, and all
forms of political and social action must therefore ascribe to this tension. It is
of great significance that it is a couple of opposition, that is, a two-sided difference:
there is no experience without expectation and vice versa. The space of
experience and the horizon of expectation thus corrupt one another; no side
of the difference holds a preliminary status of privilege. The space of experience
is seen as present past (that is, as the events that have been incorporated and
remembered), while expectations designate present future (which directs itself
towards the forthcoming, towards that which has not yet been experienced,
towards that which will be prompted later). The horizon of experience is the
line behind which new experience will emerge that cannot yet be seen
(Koselleck, 1985, p 273).
To Koselleck, historical time is created, in continuously changing patterns
and relations, by the mere tension between expectation and experience.
Concept–historical analysis should uncover that which applies over time as
expectation and experience, but also the tensions and relationships between
expectation and experience, which are historical and must be exposed by the
semantic analysis (Koselleck, 1985, p 275).
Inside/outside
No society or human action exists without a distinction between inside and
outside. The distinction inside/outside is constitutive for the spaciousness of
history:
In this formal opposition, too, lie the seeds of varies potential histories.
Whether it be the embattled retreat into a cave, or the forcible enclosure of
a house, whether it be the drawing of a border that occasions, or concludes,
a conflict, or rites of initiation, whether we are talking about grants of
44
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
Up/down
There are also different positions within a community. On the inside, we are
joined against the things or people on the outside, but inside this community
one can be up or down. The distinction between up and down can therefore
define the internal pecking order. Nevertheless, the distinction can be
articulated in countless ways, for example as a master/slave relationship, as in
Greek and old-European terminology, or as the democratic political system of
modern times that provides the standards for a continuous exchange of up/
down positions (Koselleck, 1989, p 651). In politics, for example, the ruling
party might be in opposition after the elections; new parties are established
and voted into Parliament while other parties lose their support and dissolve.
There can be no political self-organisation, no distribution of relationships of
dependency and hence no history without the broadest definition of the
distinction up/down.
Collectively, the three (or five) couples of opposition form the metahistorical
conditions of the constitution of history: “According to Heidegger, we are
dealing with existential definitions, that is, a particular kind of transcendental
categories which indicate the possibility of histories without, however,
describing specific histories” (Koselleck, 1987, p 20). In my opinion, Koselleck
wishes to introduce three points.
45
Discursive analytical strategies
The same applies to the language that precedes the events and contributes, in
spoken or written form, to triggering the events. Moreover, the articulation is
a process of selection (my choice of words!). Not all occurrences become
articulated as events and those that do become events could equally have been
articulated as different events. Finally, some occurrences simply do not allow
for articulation; language fails and takes the form of a boisterous silence:
When the fluctuating distinction between ‘inner’ and ‘outer’ hardens into
passionate conflict between friend and foe, when the inevitability of death
is pre-empted by killing or by self-sacrifice, when the relation between ‘above’
and ‘below’ leads to enslavement and permanent subjugation or to
exploitation and class struggle, or when the tension between the sexes leads
to degradation – in all these cases there will occur events, or chains of
events, or even cataracts of events, which are beyond the pale of language,
and to which words, all sentences, all speech can only react. There are
events for which words fail us, which leave us dumb, and to which, perhaps,
we can only react with silence. (Koselleck, 1989, p 652)
• because it disregards the fact that historical reality only exists in shapes of
language;
46
Reinhart Koselleck’s history of concepts
• because it disregards the fact that a selection of that which has been deemed
worthy of reminiscence has already taken place;
• because it disregards that it is always the linguistically-fixed events that
imbue unique events with their meaning of relative duration or specific
signification;
• most importantly, because it fails to explain why formerly reliable and, for
that reason, abandoned histories have to be rewritten at all (Koselleck,
1989, pp 661-6).
Conclusion
Koselleck’s history of concepts consists of a combination of two analytics,
between which one is continuously going back and forth. One is the diachronic
analysis that focuses on single objects and their origins and transformation.
These studies concern the shaping and consolidation of meaning into words,
which are thereby transformed into objects that reach into the future by means
of the constituent effect they have on, for example, the shaping of political
agents, their identity and their ability to act. The study of the history of
concepts is simultaneously a study of the semantic battle about concepts,
including a battle about occupying concepts, about generalising concepts and
about singularising the general.
On the other hand, synchronous analysis studies the way concepts always
come into being in relation to other concepts in a semantic field. A semantic
field is organised as the relationship between concepts and their counter-
concepts. Prelinguistic couples of opposition provide guiding differences for
the analysis of counter-concepts.
Koselleck’s concept-historical analytical strategy is summarised in Figure
2.1.
Synchronous analysis
Concept/meaning
Singularisation/generalisation
Concept/counter-concept
Before/after
Inside/outside
Us/them
Up/down
47
Discursive analytical strategies
48
3
The discourse theory of
Ernesto Laclau
49
Discursive analytical strategies
Discourse
Let us begin with the concept of discourse. This, of course, is taken from
Foucault, but in this context it embodies a more unambiguous and general
definition. Laclau defines discourse as a structural totality of differences (Laclau
and Mouffe, 1985, pp 105-14): “When, as a result of an articulatory practice,
one has become capable of configuring a system of exact different locations,
this system of different locations is called discourse” (Laclau, 1985, p 113).
50
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
51
Discursive analytical strategies
The political
The first detail pertains to the political. Politics happen precisely because
structures are never complete. If a structure were able to reach full closure, it
would exclude the political. Because of the eternal undecidability of the
discursive structures, however, politics acquire a central role within all structures
as that moment when undecidable structures, demanding a conclusion or
closure, become partially fixed. Discourse analysis is a political analysis of the
way contingent relations become fixed in one way, but could have been fixed
in many others.
S/subjects
Furthermore, this is the most substantial critique of Althusser’s ideology theory.
In Althusser, there is no room for the political because the structures are seen
as complete. This is illustrated by the problem of the subject. Althusser makes a
distinction between the small subject and the big Subject. The big Subject is
the model for the creation of all smaller subjects. When an individual or
collective is defined as subject it is granted a steady position in relation to the
big Subject (or the master subject); a steady position in the structure of the
ideology. The individual becomes subject to the Court, to God, to the Economy,
or whatever the big Subject happens to be in the proclaiming ideology in
question. In relation to the declaration, the individual faces a simple choice
between reason and madness, between accepting her/his place and becoming
a ‘sensible’ subject, or being excluded from reason without the possibility of
defining oneself as a subject outside the ideology. If, on the other hand, the
structure is seen as incomplete, the need for politics emerges. The individual
cannot fully identify with the subject position provided by the discourse but
is forced into filling in the structural gaps through identification, and this
identification process is precisely political because it requires a choice that
cannot be explained away – a choice about the subject’s self-constitution.
52
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
what happens if that structure is seen as incomplete? That would mean that
signifiers and their signified were not irrefutably tied to each other. Instead
they would be partially free floating layers on top of each other; the signifiers
would be floating signifiers.
The expression ‘floating signifier’ was first used by Claude Lévi-Strauss,
although it was the psychoanalyst Jaques Lacan who unfolded the concept
theoretically (Macey, 1988, p 137; Lacan, 2001, pp 146-78). Lacan demonstrates
how the sliding of the signifier across the signified forces the signifier to step
into, or down onto, the level of the signified. Hence, the signifiers influence
that which they signify. This means that signifiers receive a particular status in
relation to signification and to the signified.
For example...
Lacan’s favourite example is that of two identical doors next to each other. The
doors (the signified) are not signified in the same way, however – one door is
signified ‘Gentlemen’ and the other door is signified ‘Ladies’. The effect is obvious:
the exchange of signifiers cuts through the bar (/) and into the signified. The
incomplete structure thus appears, not only in the sliding relationships between
the signs, but also insofar as the bar that separates signifier from signified proves
to be less watertight than assumed by de Saussure.
• how signifiers and the signified do not relate to each other in a predetermined
relationship;
• how discursive signification happens precisely in relation to displacements
in the signification of the signified;
• how which signifier is fixed above a given signified is very much a political
issue.
For example...
A dead seal lands on the beach. How should we signify this event? There are still
seals off the shore of xville; pollution takes new victims; the ruthless over-fishing of
herring is starving the seal population; or another flu epidemic ravages the seals
off the sound? The signifier steps down into the signified and transforms the seal
(the signified) into a signifier of its own – the dead seal signifies the diversity of
nature, pollution, a flu epidemic, and so on. The signifier is also obviously political:
should we take measures against fishing or pollution, or simply wonder about
the whim of nature?
53
Discursive analytical strategies
This battle over fixing sliding signifiers is, as I have noted before, a battle over
the definition of nodal points (or, to use Lacan’s term, privileged signifiers),
which can arrest the sliding of the many signifiers across the signified.
Besides the application of these concepts, Laclau introduces yet another
concept – the notion of the empty signifier. (I believe this is Laclau’s invention,
although, here too, he is heavily indebted to Lacan.) The question of the
signifier that signifies nothing emerges in Lacan’s famous article on the non-
existence of the woman: “This the is a signifier characterized by being the only
signifier which cannot signify anything” (Lacan, 1982, p 144). Such a signifier
is the only signifier capable of ending and defining a limit for the chain of
signification. The analogue question in Laclau addresses the partial finality of
the discursive game. The empty signifier is used to signify that which does
not allow for signification, that is, the limit of the discursive signification: “An
empty signifier can consequently only emerge if there is a structural impossibility
in signification as such, and only if this impossibility can signify itself as an
interruption of the structure of sign” (Laclau, 1996a, p 37).
Summary
A discourse consists of different elements of signification, which only obtain
identity through their mutual differences in the discourse. The condition of
mutual differences, however, is that the elements are identical or equivalent in
respect to belonging to the discourse and existing within the boundaries of
the discourse. On other words, on the one hand, elements can only form an
identity through their mutual differences, while on the other hand, the
differences are cancelled out by the equivalent relation provided by the elements’
attachment to the discursive structure. This is only possible if there are different
types of differences; if a difference exists that is radically constituent for the
differences of the system. Laclau identifies this difference as the excluding
boundary. Within the boundary exists a system of relational elements; outside
the boundary exists only pure, indifferent being in relation to which every
element of the system is equally different. Thus, outside the boundary only
radical indifference exists (which is why the distinction inside/outside the
system should not be confused with Luhmann’s distinction between
surroundings/system).
The empty signifier occurs, in effect, as a possibility for the signification of
“the pure cancellation of all difference” (Laclau, 1996a, p 38). Laclau summarises
the argument thus:
There can be empty signifiers within the field of signification because any
system of signification is structured around an empty place resulting from
the impossibility of producing an object which, nonetheless, is required to
be the systematicity of the system. (Laclau, 1996a, p 40)
An empty signifier is that which signifies the indifferent and the cancellation
of difference. All differences must be equally different in relation to it, while
54
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
also being different from each other. Locating and analysing the empty signifier
entails a signification of the ultimate limit of the discourse but, since such a
signifier will always be inside the discourse, it will never be possible to represent
it fully.
Laclau illustrates the relationship between equivalence and difference as
portrayed in Figure 3.1.
...X/X/X/X/X/X/X/X/... X
X equals an element
55
Discursive analytical strategies
that can be accomplished” (Laclau, 1985, p 107). Hegemony creates the space
for “a politics of signifiers” (Laclau, 1983).
Hegemonisation subsequently consists in the imposition onto elements of a
certain way of relating to each other. This also means that hegemonisation
brings elements together that have not previously been brought together (Laclau
and Mouffe, 1985, pp 134-45). The economic hegemonisation in society
appears in elements that were not earlier considered socioeconomic being
suddenly recognised as such, and, furthermore, in these elements now relating
to themselves as social economy. One example could be the emergence of
policies for older people from the mid-1980s.
For example...
Until the mid-1980s the elements of residential homes, older people, home care,
and older people’s housing in Denmark were not associated with elements such
as social–economic balance, inflation, finance and so on. From the mid-1980s,
however, policies for older people became a central socioeconomic and political
issue. Subsequently, a number of policy works are commissioned. This results in
two things. First, residential homes, older people’s housing, home care and other
issues are brought together under the same policy umbrella through the joint
formulation of policies for older people (which has never happened before).
Second, policies for older people establish themselves through the formulation
of a political expenditure issue about the social–economic coordination of public
services for older people. Hence, the hegemonisation of policies for older people
within the socioeconomic conception appears not as a hierarchy of relations of
superiority and inferiority, but as the investment of a particular logic in the
construction and shaping of policies for older people.
56
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
Deconstructing difference
The deconstruction of a difference does not end, however, once it has been
shown that the difference is not valid. The illustration of the non-difference
of the difference (so to speak) is simultaneously an illustration of those
57
Discursive analytical strategies
Opening of the
political
through the Demonstration
deconstruction discourse analysis
illustration of hegemony
of the
undecidability
of a difference
dualities
58
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
Logics
Logic of signification
Logic of representation
59
Discursive analytical strategies
Logic of tolerance
The logic of tolerance indicates the mechanism that is present in the difference
tolerance/intolerance. Here, too, the difference is reversed through
deconstruction which shows that tolerance cannot be explained in itself without
turning into its opposite. Consequently, intolerance is simultaneously the
condition of the possibility and the impossibility of tolerance; the undecidability
of the distinction extends the possibility of both poles. With the logic of
tolerance we are able to study the hegemonic battle over what should be
tolerated and what should not be tolerated (Laclau, 1996b, pp 50-2).
Logic of power
The logic of power indicates the mechanism present in the difference power/
liberation. Once again, the difference is reversed. Jurisprudence assumes that
freedom is the condition of power; power is the restriction of freedom and
therefore earns its potential through freedom. Laclau reverses the difference
and points out that what restricts freedom is also what makes it possible – a
society free from power is an impossibility. Once again, this provides the basis
for a discourse-analytical study of the continued negotiation and displacement
of the power/freedom boundary (Laclau, 1993b, 1996b, pp 52-3).
60
The discourse theory of Ernesto Laclau
Conversely, the logic of difference signifies the logic through which the
political sphere is widened and increases its internal complexity. The elements
do not become particularly interchangeable, but the number of subject positions
(that is, the positions from which one can be political) is increased (Laclau and
Mouffe, 1985, p 130).
Logic of universalisation
Conclusion
Laclau also configures a few other logics that are usually presented as aspects
of almost all logics, including the logic of supplement and the logic of impossibility.
The concept of logic does not therefore appear to be exercised completely
consistently. The logic of supplement and the logic of impossibility involve a
metalogic that might also apply to the logic of difference and the logic
equivalence, but not to the logic of representation, which, one must assume, is
bound by a particular historicity. We can therefore observe a division of
duties between deconstruction and discourse analysis, but also a lack of
theorisation of their mutual relationships, which appears as an inconsequent
and insufficiently defined concept of logic. This raises a number of questions,
particularly about universality:
However, these questions do not change the fact that, analytically, the linking
of deconstruction and discourse analysis is exceedingly powerful.
61
Discursive analytical strategies
Conclusion
Laclau’s two analytical strategies and the way they pose questions have been
summarised in Table 3.1. In the right-hand column I have attempted to
provide an example of a possible concrete analysis. The example used in this
table is the issue of animal ethics that has taken place in most EU countries, in
particular in the UK. A deconstructive analysis could address the discursive
infinity of the debate about animal ethics. Ethics always claims to be universal,
to be unavoidable, and to not let itself be deflected by pragmatic and specific
circumstances. Ethics are only ethics if they raise themselves above concrete
circumstances. A deconstructive analytical strategy, therefore, could address
the duality of universal/particular in order to demonstrate that any claim for
universality is always particular, and that the two sides of the duality must
incessantly pollute and contaminate one another. Deconstruction could point
to the conditions of impossibility of animal ethics. Subsequently, a hegemonic
analysis would be able to analyse how the conditions of impossibility of ethics
are unfolded in specific discursive battles about trying nevertheless to fixate
animal ethics. Hegemonic analysis could point out different discursive attempts
to fixate and how different attempts must exclude something from their
discoursing in order to form a coherent discourse. The more militant discourses
define production and financial prioritising as antagonistic opposites to ethics.
These discourses would not be able to maintain their strong sense of unity
without rejecting any kind of pragmatism, which, in turn, prevents them from
ever gaining any form of hegemony. By contrast, production and economically
oriented discourses of agriculture might involve ethics, but on behalf of the
purity of ethics as precisely universal ethics. Ethics become temporalised. It
is something that should be achieved in the long term and a consideration
that, because of its temporal distance, must be weighed against other
considerations in the present, such as the economy and production.
Note
1
In the article ‘Discourse’, Laclau even distinguishes between two fundamental
notions of discourse analysis – his own poststructuralist discourse analysis and
Foucault’s second-order phenomenology (Laclau, 1993b).
62
4
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
O and in many ways, the most comprehensive. He has written more than
50 books and over 400 articles. One of his goals has been to test
the general stating power of systems theory by writing at least one book
about each of the function systems of modern society. Hence, he has conducted
extensive historical analyses of the scientific system, the political system, the
system of arts, the educational system, the system of justice, the system of
regions, love and family as a system, the system of mass media, and the system
of economics. But his work is also the most comprehensive in another respect.
Of the authors in this volume, Luhmann’s work probably involves the highest
number of different theoretical questions, provides the widest scope of
theoretical approaches and possesses the highest degree of flexibility for the
elaboration of projects within theory. However, in this book, we are not
concerned with the many analyses of different social systems but only with
the Luhmanian ‘eye’ for social systems as communication.
Luhmann’s path towards the ‘communication-theoretical turn’ is completely
different from that of Laclau and Foucault. The communication-theoretical
turn did not appear until around 1980. Prior to this, Luhmann had suggested
that meaning was the fundamental concept of sociology (Luhmann, 1990b,
pp 21-79), but it was not until the beginning of the 1980s that he changed his
notion of social systems as systems of action to an understanding of these
systems as autopoietic systems of communication, consisting in and by
communication. To a certain extent, Luhmann’s systems theory can be viewed
as a communication-theoretical rewriting of the systems theory of Talcot
Parsons. In Parsons’ work, the communication-theoretical inspiration stems
not from French structuralism, but from a unique patchwork of the calculus
of form from the mathematician Spencer-Brown, the theory of life as a system
of autopoiesis from the biologist Maturana, the theory of information as
differences that make a difference from the autodidact Bateson, and the theory
of meaning from the phenomenologist Husserl.
Luhmann’s theoretical architecture has often been compared to a labyrinth.
This is not only because it is difficult to get in and even more difficult to get
out, but particularly because it is not construed deductively. It is inductive in
a very particular way and always allows for the observer to step back and ask:
‘Why this particular concept?’, through which all concepts suddenly appear
in a new light. I will return to this point later in this chapter.
63
Discursive analytical strategies
For example...
We might, for example, fasten upon something artistic. ‘Art’ is then indicated.
But art can only be indicated within the boundaries of a distinction. The opposite
side could be ugliness, unsightliness, disharmony and so on, and this other side of
the distinction makes a difference to the way art appears as an object to the
observer. Therefore, what we observe is above all dependent on the distinction
that defines the framework for what is indicated in the world at large.
64
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Indication/distinction
Second-order observations
65
Discursive analytical strategies
Obviously, all second-order observations are also, at the same time, first-
order observations, since they indicate first-order observation within a
distinction. There exists, therefore, no privileged position for observation.
This is illustrated in Figure 4.3.
{ m
Reference
66
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Distinctions
Observations of the first as well as the second order are observations within a
distinction, but not all ways of distinguishing allow for second-order
observation. Luhmann distinguishes between three ways of making a
distinction:
A system is only able to observe itself if it indicates itself within the framework
of a second-order concept. If a system is to observe itself as observer, the
system is required to divide itself in two: the observer and the observed. Hence,
Luhmann proposes that a system, constituted as the unity of the distinction
system/environment, is only able to observe itself as observer if it can copy its
guiding distinction and re-enter it into itself, that is, its ability to divide itself
by entering the distinction system/environment into the system itself (Luhmann,
1995a, pp 37-55). This process of re-entry is illustrated in Figure 4.4.
system/environment
re-entry copying
system/environment
67
Discursive analytical strategies
Paradox
Perspective
Even though an observer of the second order is simultaneously an observer of
the first order, the outlook is nevertheless different:
• On the level of the first order, the outlook is mono-contextual. The observer
sees what he sees. He makes use of a distinction without being able to
distinguish.
• On the level of the second order, the outlook is poly-contextual. Although
the observer still observes within the framework of a distinction, the observer
of observers knows that she cannot see that which she cannot see. She
knows that reality depends on the observer – that the observed is contingent
with the difference that defines the boundaries of the observation. She
uses a distinction but she is also able to distinguish.
68
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
69
Discursive analytical strategies
Point out, substantiate and account for the implications of the exact
observation point
Operating as an observer of the second order with distinctions that can re-
enter themselves, it is not self-evident what is defined as object. Even when
observing observers through, for example, the distinction system/environment,
it remains for the observer to decide which system is defined as the observation
point, since all systems simultaneously constitute the environment of other
systems. The moment one system has been selected as the observation point,
all other systems can only be seen as environment, and only then to the extent
that they are constructed as such by the particular system. In the words of
Luhmann, any theory about observed systems must designate its systems reference:
which it uses as its starting point in order to designate which system which
things exist as the environment of. [...] However, if one wants to know the
systems reference upon which an observer is based [...] one must observe
the observer. The world does not disclose the way it wants it. With the
choice of systems reference, one has simultaneously designated the system
which draws its own boundaries and thus divides the world into system and
environment. (Luhmann, 1995b, p 46)
For example...
70
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
71
Discursive analytical strategies
Conclusion
Meaning
When focusing on social systems, meaning thus becomes the first inevitable
concept. In part, the concept of meaning plays the same part in Luhmann’s
systems theory as the concept of discoursivity plays in Laclau’s discourse theory:
• While all social identities in Laclau are embedded in a discoursivity and are
unable to go beyond this discoursivity, psychic and social systems in
Luhmann are similarly unable to operate outside of meaning.
• In the same way that discoursivity in Laclau is constituted by differences
and relations, meaning in Luhmann is also a concept of difference.
• Finally, while discoursivity in Laclau is characterised by floating and unfixable
relationships between discursive elements, meaning in Luhmann is similarly
unfixable, and is always unstable and indefinable.
72
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
For example...
Psychic and social systems are tied to meaning. They possess no relationship
with the environment, let alone themselves, except through meaning. Meaning
is the shape of the world and overrules the distinction between system and
environment. On the other hand, there are no limits to meaning as such – in
principle, anything can be understood by psychic and social systems but only
within the shape of meaning. Meaning can never extend itself into something
else (Luhmann, 1995c, pp 59-63). Hence, meaning is open-ended in the sense
73
Discursive analytical strategies
that everything can be understood through meaning, but it is closed and self-
referential in the sense that meaning refers only to meaning.
Like discursive identity in Laclau, meaning can never be fixed. However,
Luhmann’s argument for this is not that a structure is not complete but that
the core of the actualised disintegrates from the moment something has been
indicated. Meaning can never be fixed or maintained; it is fundamentally
unstable. This is in part due to the fact that meaning is always shaped by a
thought or by communication, which disappears the very moment it occurs.
Meaning is always reproduced (or changed) recursively, like decisions within
an organisation.
For example...
It is always decided at the following meeting, when the minutes are being approved,
which decisions are not to be considered decisions after all but simply talk, and
which decisions are to be included in the minutes and should therefore be followed
up and put on the agenda in terms of new decisions. However, the decisions
included in the minutes can never be identical to the decisions as they emerged at
the previous meeting. They now appear in a new situation, in a new specification
in relation to a new horizon of possibilities: for example, the possibility of the
minutes not being approved, or of the decisions not really being decided upon.
The core of actuality thus disintegrates from the moment it appears and,
consequently, meaning provokes change.
74
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Autopoietic systems
75
Discursive analytical strategies
Nevertheless, social and psychic systems are structurally linked: first, they
both shape meaning as a medium (but in different forms); second, they make
their own complexity available to each other. Although psychic systems are
unable to communicate with each other, communication is also unable to
communicate unless at least two psychic systems partake in the communication.
Social systems, in turn, make their complexity available to psychic systems,
primarily through language and through disappointment/fulfilment of the
expectations of psychic systems.
Communication
It should be noted that the three selections noted above all shape meaning as
a medium. The selection of information shapes the distinction of actualised
information/possible information; the selection of message shapes the
76
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Preliminary summary
As we have seen, Luhmann’s systems theory is a theory about society as
communication. It assumes that society consists of autopoietic systems of
communication, which produce and reproduce themselves through
communication alone. The different systems of communication are closed
around themselves; they are self-referring. And this closure constitutes the
condition of their openness, that is, of their sensitivity to their environment.
All communication is observation, either in the shape of self-description or
external descriptions. The closure of systems of communication both in regard
to meaning and to communication implies that systems of communication
always observe from a blind spot.
Systems theory attempts to establish itself as observation of the second order
– as an observation of how systems of communication observe. It is about the
description of the limits and blind spots (in the broadest sense) of
communication. It is not only a question of describing how a system of
communication sees something and not something else. It is also not only a
question of localising the moment when silence takes over. But it is concerned
with the relationship between the different systems of communication, the
way they are connected, the way they interrupt each other productively and
destructively, including the existing limits, not only of the individual system of
communication, but also of the overall communication structure of society.
As a second-order observer, systems theory must recognise that it is itself
communication within society. In that sense, systems theory is about
contributing to the self-description of society but, as part of society, systems
theory is faced with a classical sociological problem: self-reference. Within
systems theory, autology provides the solution to this problem of self-reference.
Through the concept of autology, systems theory can describe itself as a form
of self-description describing itself. An autological sociological description of
society in society thus describes the description of society by adapting it to
itself. This means, for one thing, that systems theory explores its own origins,
but it also means that it has to define explicitly those guiding differences on
which it bases its second-order observations, and account for the way they
construct the object of systems theory.
The next section presents some of the central guiding distinctions to
observation of the second order in Luhmann’s systems theory.
77
Discursive analytical strategies
Form analysis
When taking the concept of observation as the point of departure, it is important
to grant priority to Luhmann’s form analysis. It appears that all choices and
accounts of choices in Luhmann begin with a form analysis of the guiding
distinction itself. The role of form analysis in relation to systems analysis in a
broader sense is highly comparable to the role of deconstruction in the analysis
of hegemony in Laclau.
While deconstruction in Laclau focuses on specific central dualities around
which a discursive game is played out, form analysis similarly focuses on specific
distinctions in connection to which communication plays itself out. The
deconstruction of central dualities produces particular logicities, which
necessarily emerge in certain discourses. Likewise, form analysis analyses the
boundaries of communication and the paradoxes that communication unfolds
when it connects with one particular distinction.
Luhmann defines form as the unity of a difference. This brings us back to
the theory of observation but now we have specified the systems reference to
social, meaning-shaping systems of communication.
For example...
We observe the observations of an observer and note that the observer focuses
on, for example, the risks of nuclear power. We might also note that other observers
focus on different risks – the risk of prenatal diagnosis, of share investments, of
work and so on. We notice a certain recursivity in the communication, when
questions of risk appear. We now need to ask whether a particular form of
communication appears to define itself within societal communication, which
we can call ‘risk communication’.
If we pose this question in terms of form analysis, the objective is at first to localise
the difference, which defines the scope of the indication of risks.
78
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Luhmann himself uses the example of risk (Luhmann, 1990d) and asks if the
other side of the difference might be security. Security/risk is a distinction
that is often related to risk communication; however, Luhmann rejects this
proposal, since security cannot be conditioned and cannot therefore operate
as counter-concept to risk. In other words, it is not able to describe the blind
spot of risk communication. Instead, Luhmann suggests ‘danger’ is the other
side of risk. Risk communication is subsequently defined as communication
that connects with the distinction risk/danger. If communication connecting
with risk shapes the distinction risk/danger, then risk is always only risk in
relation to a danger. Risk and danger cannot be separated but only exist in
relation to each other. Now the distinction has been identified. The subsequent
form analysis asks which kind of communication can develop within the
scope of this distinction.
For example...
One driver’s decision to assign himself the risk of passing another car on a curve
at high speed on the assumption that he can just make it simultaneously implies
the assignment of danger to others. Danger exists in being exposed to the risk
decisions of others (Luhmann, 1990d).
In accordance with Derrida and deconstruction, one might say that form
analysis points to a particular ‘logicity’ given a specific guiding difference in
the communication. Where deconstruction tries to convert the hierarchy of
differences, form analysis begins by inquiring about the other side of the side
indicated. Form analysis tries to locate the distinction that constitutes the
framework of a particular observation. Subsequently, form analysis inquires
about the unity of the distinction and hence about the communication that
the distinction both enables and excludes. Luhmann has conducted a great
number of form analyses, for example on the form of writing, the form of the
distinction system/environment, the form of knowledge and the form of
causality.
It is important to note that form analysis rarely represents the end of the
involvement with a particular problem but often represents the beginning of
the formulation of a problem, which is then followed up in other analytics, for
example in a systems and differentiation analysis. Luhmann himself defines
79
Discursive analytical strategies
the difference between form analysis and deconstruction by saying that, where
deconstruction often contents itself with uncovering the logicity and
paradoxical basis of a duality, form analysis simply constitutes the incipient
inquiry about the unfolding of a paradox within communication. Given the
fact that, for example, the concept of risk is paradoxical by nature (since
communication on risk is itself risky, whoever runs a risk and inflicts danger
on others runs the risk of becoming visible), how and within which systems
of communication is this paradox handled? In this respect, we can trace a
certain parallel to Laclau to whom deconstruction is merely the beginning of
an analysis of hegemony.
Systems analysis
The most central guiding distinction in Luhmann is the distinction system/
environment. It is not only the difference most often used by Luhmann in his
second-order observations, it is also the difference he uses to regulate the use
of other guiding distinctions and, more generally, to steer his development of
theories.
In systems analysis, the basic notion is that all communication takes place
within a social system, and that all social systems are constituted by a boundary
of system and environment. As indicated in relation to the theory of observation,
it is the very observation that divides the world into system and environment.
The same pertains to social systems in which observations consist in
communicative descriptions. A social system can observe itself or the
environment through descriptions of self-reference or external reference. One
example of self-referential communication in an organisation is financial
accounting in the same way that surveys of waste sites are examples of
communication of external reference in environmental administrations.
The very construction of the distinction system/environment as a guiding
distinction for second-order observation begins with a form analysis of the
distinction, that is, with an analysis of the capacity of communication to shape
the distinction system/environment. For one thing, form analysis demonstrates
that the environment always works as an environment of a particular system
and, conversely, that a system is always a system only in relation to a specific
environment. A social system is simply the unity of the distinction system/environment.
When communication recursively connects with communication, social systems
emerge because of the distinction by the communication between self-reference
and external reference – between that which constitutes the system itself and
that which makes up the environment of the system.
Both system and environment are internal structures of communication.
Environment is not ‘reality’ as such: environment consists of that which is
defined by the communication as its relevant surroundings. The system, in
turn, is only a system in relation to this internal construction of the environment.
System is that which environment is not. Any system therefore is identical
with itself in its difference (and only in the difference) from the internal
environment construction.
80
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Differentiation analysis
As we have already seen, the distinction system/environment is not merely a
difference, but one that has the capacity for re-entry into itself. A social
system comes into being through a communicative installation of a boundary
between system and environment. However, this is a formation within society
as a social system of communication. Any formation of a social system consists,
therefore, of a transcription of the difference system/environment and its re-
entry into the system itself. Hence, social systems come into being as
differentiations of communication (see Figure 4.6).
System Environment
System Environment
System Environment
81
Discursive analytical strategies
82
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
For example, Luhmann points out that the closure brought about by the
communicative focus on functions blinds society to the destruction of the
ecological precondition of society by the function systems. Each individual
form of differentiation only allows for particular perspectives of observation,
which is the same as saying that each form of differentiation installs its blind
spot within the communication of society. One example of a perspective of
observation that can exist in the stratified society but not in functional society
is the male-dominated perspective of observation. Formerly, the distinction
between man and woman made up a guiding difference in respect of social
stratification. Within the functionally differentiated society, the asymmetric
indication of the male side and the use of the distinction man/woman as a
principle of differentiation for social systems are no longer useful in the same
way.
Points of observation
Media analysis
A fourth analytics of Luhmann draws on the guiding difference form/medium.
Any observation is an observation by a system in which observation exists in
an indication within the scope of a distinction. Subsequently, any observation
forms differences or, rather, any observation establishes a relationship between
observation as form and its difference as medium. In order for an observation
to be brought about in the first place, difference as difference has to offer itself
up as medium for a form that can condense differences into specific forms
such as horse/not horse, right/wrong, car/not car. Differences as loose elements,
83
Discursive analytical strategies
without preferences one way or the other and open to any consolidation,
make up the medium of observation, which can precisely only take place by
isolating a single form in the medium of difference. If we look at Spencer-
Brown’s form calculus reproduced in Figure 4.7, we can see that the very line
or gibbet is the medium of form as the unity of the specific separation of m
from not m.
Figure 4.7: The calculus of form
Forms, on the contrary, reduce size to that which they can order. No
medium creates only one form since it would then be absorbed and
disappear. The combinatory possibilities of a medium can never be exhausted
and the only reason for restrictions to evolve is the fact that the creations of
forms mutually disrupt each other. (Luhmann, 1986b, p 101)
The relationship between form and medium is itself a form, meaning that any
speech on form is only form in relation to a medium and vice versa. Forms
are only shaped when a medium makes itself available but, on the other hand,
form prevails in relation to the medium, without any resistance on the part of
the medium in regard to the rigidity of form. The difference between form
and medium, however, is relative in the sense that form can be more or less
rigid.
For example...
be offered as random notes, because one payment does not depend on the
significance and purpose of another payment, because the medium is
incredibly forgetful (since it does not have to remember in order to maintain
the paid amount), and because the solvency determines whether payment
is possible. (Luhmann, 1986b, p 101)
84
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Decisions are an example of form; they constitute a form because they impress
themselves in a medium and condense its elements into one decision, which is
only a decision in relation to previous decisions and decisions not taken. The
decision to print the company’s logo on paper forms the medium of money by
requiring expenditure. This decision is not interchangeable with other decisions
– its meaning is tied to time and space, and can only be understood in relation to
the company’s other decisions. Moreover, the decision has been made possible
by previous decisions, for example the decision to have a company logo.
How language, how writing, how alphabetical writing, and how symbolically
generalised media appear. They provide a potential for the creation of forms
which would not exist without them, and we can take advantage of this
potential as soon as the social conditions permit it. (Luhmann, 1986b,
p 104)
85
Discursive analytical strategies
Media of distribution
Language
Meaning
Distinction
• language;
• media of distribution, such as writing and television;
• general symbolic media, such as, for example, money.
Semantic analysis
Finally, Luhmann employs semantic analysis, which forms the guiding
distinction condensation/meaning, to examine how meaning is condensed in
semantic forms that produce a conceptual pool for communication.
Luhmann makes a distinction between system and semantics in which
semantics are defined as particular structures linking communication to
communication by offer ing up for ms of meaning that systems of
communication treat as worth preserving (Luhmann, 1995c, p 282).
If we were to invoke the concept of discourse anywhere in Luhmann’s
theoretical architecture, this would be the place. In the same way that we can
talk about different discourses in Foucault that enable the enunciation of
particular discursive objects, Luhmann speaks of different semantics (the
semantics of love, of organisational theory, of money and so on) that invoke
specific communication. However, the distinction between system and
semantics is considerably different to Foucault’s concept of discourse. In
Foucault, a discourse can contain characteristics of system; a discourse can
constitute a regime and a discourse can conflict with other discourses; discourses
possess qualities of reality. Semantics do not in the same way posseses these
86
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
qualities. They do not have a self; they cannot make up a regime; they cannot
conflict with each other. Only systems hold the characteristics of system;
systems decide whether or not they wish to employ specific semantics.
Consequently, semantics do not exist by themselves outside the systems of
communication. An observer can choose to make a semantic distinction
between system and structure but they cannot actually be separated. The
semantic structures are used and reproduced in the selection of communication
that is linked to communication, and can only exist in the constriction of
choices.
The concept of semantics is based on a distinction between meaning and
condensed meaning. As noted above, meaning comprises a constant rearranging
of the distinction actuality/potentiality. Meaning disintegrates immediately
on its actualisation. Thus, meaning is tied to the momentary condition of
actualisation. Communication, on the other hand, is capable of developing
structures that condense meaning into forms, which are set free from the
momentary condition of actualisation. Condensation means that a multitude
of meaning is captured in a single form, which subsequently makes itself
available to an undefined communication. Consequently, semantics are
characterised as the accumulated amount of generalised forms of differences (for example,
concepts, ideas, images, and symbols) available for the selection of meaning within the
systems of communication. In other words, semantics are condensed and repeatable
forms of meaning, which are at our disposal for communication. These
generalised forms are relatively independent of situations and obtain their
specific content from the communication by which they are selected (Luhmann,
1993c, pp 9-72). This definition of semantics largely derives from Koselleck’s
history of concepts.
Objects and concepts are among the forms that semantics can take. As
noted previously, objects constitute a form that has an undefined outer side
(for example, horse/not horse). The concept, in turn, is a form of meaning in
which the indicated inner side delineates restrictions for the outer side (for
example, man/woman), and hence concepts are inextricably bound up with
counter-concepts. There exist no concepts without counter-concepts and
thus no unambiguous concepts (Luhmann, 1988b, pp 47-117).
Luhmann distinguishes between three dimensions of meaning (Luhmann,
1995c, pp 74-82), which enables him to distinguish accordingly between three
forms of semantics. We will not go into this distinction in depth but merely
give a brief précis:
• The fact dimension pertains to the selection of themes and objects for
communication and consciousness. Themes and objects are all designed
according to the distinction this/something else in the same way as ‘object’
as a form of meaning. Similarly, we can speak of semantics of facts as
generalised forms of ‘being-one-thing-and-not-another’.
• The social dimension is based on non-identity in the relationship between
communicators and constitutes the horizon of possibility in the tension
between ‘alter’ and ‘ego’. It thus concerns that which cannot be regarded
87
Discursive analytical strategies
88
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
semantics: the semantics of love, the semantics of law and so on. Subsequently,
semantic history acts as a history of the de-paradoxification of a particular
paradox, for example the history of how the paradox of the justice of justice
has historically sought de-paradoxification through different judicial semantics:
natural law, judicial positivism, Scandinavian judicial realism and so on.
Historical semantic analysis can, in turn, point out new concepts for form
analysis. The relationship between form analysis and historical semantic analysis
is illustrated in Figure 4.9.
Points to the
blind spot of the Analyses the semantic
concept by conditions of the formation
illustrating how form analysis semantic analysis
and de-paradoxification of
it is based on a the paradox
paradox
concepts
89
Discursive analytical strategies
Complexity
Semantics
Differentiation
90
Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory
Figure 4.11: The relationship between systems analysis and media analysis
Evolution of media
Conclusion
This chapter has examined the most central analytical strategies in Luhmann’s
systems theory. I have attempted to summarise these strategies in Table 4.3,
and have supplemented them with a specific example. The left-hand column
indicates the analytical strategy; the centre column the general inquiry of the
analytical strategies; and the right-hand column an example of a potential
systems theoretical analysis. The example used in this table concerns the
politicisation of businesses. Today, private businesses have become central
political players in a number of fields and are expected to take on social
responsibility that exceeds purely economic concerns. Today, corporations
are expected to consider issues beyond those that are economic; for example,
many businesses have developed extensively into areas including ethics, the
environment and human rights. Many businesses also take an active role in
political decision-making processes; for example, thousands of businesses take
part in standardisation committees and commissions, and are involved in
decision making about the rules for the European market. These decisions
concern consumer interests, the environment, working conditions, industrial
policies and much more.
91
Discursive analytical strategies
Form analysis What is the unity of the In what way are organisations
distinction? And which systems that communicate
paradox does it establish? through the form ‘decision’? And
which paradoxes does this form
establish?
Systems analysis How does a system of In what way does the politicisation
communication come into being of the organisations become
in a distinction between system apparent in the internal
and environment? How is the construction by the organisations
system’s boundary of meaning of their environment so that
and autopoiesis defined? they not only construct the
environment as market but also as
political public?
Differentiation How are systems differentiated? In what way does the politicisation
analysis What is the similarity in the of the organisations challenge
dissimilarities of the systems? their internal form of
What are the conditions, differentiation and force them to
therefore, of the formation of institutionalise internal
new systems of communication? reflections of themselves as closed
communication (for example,
through the establishment of so-
called ‘ethics officers’)?
Semantic analysis How is meaning condensed? And How is meaning condensed with
how does it create a pool of respect to environment, human
forms, that is, stable and partially rights, ethics, animal welfare,
general distinctions available to health and prevention, into the
the systems of communication? concept of ‘the socially responsible
corporation’, and bring about new
conditions for corporate
communication?
Media analysis How are media shaped? How do In what way does the politicisation
they suggest a specific potential of the organisation mean that the
for formation? organisation is no longer only
supposed to form the medium of
money, but is also expected to
form a number of other
communicative media such as
power, information and morals? In
what way does this change the
conditions of the organisation from
homophony to polyphony?
Note
1
However, it is debatable whether Luhmann consistently maintains this strategy,
since he, on several occasions, ascribes to semantics a more constitutive role in
relation to systems formation (see Stahäli, 1998).
92
5
A hall of mirrors or a pool of
analytical strategies
n this concluding chapter, I will seek to let the different analytics and
93
Discursive analytical strategies
Precondition 1
Precondition 2
Systems theory, conceptual history and discourse analyses are all, in some
sense, analyses of the second order: observations of observation, descriptions of
description, conceptualisations of concepts or designations of signs. Only
while this condition is maintained is the comparison productive.
Precondition 3
The third precondition is the realisation that, on this second-order level, it
does not make much sense to let one’s research be guided by rules of method.
This is simply because a definition of methodological rules leads to an
ontologisation of the social phenomena, when the aim is precisely de-
ontologisation. The equivalent of methodological rules in second-order
observation is analytical strategy. Second-order observation is aware that the
world is not asking to be observed in any particular way. Second-order observers
perceive of the world as poly-contextual, as dependent on the distinction
shaped by observation. Consequently, second-order observers can choose
how the world should appear by deciding on a particular way of seeing, by
connecting with a particular distinction. This is what analytical strategy is
about: choosing a way of seeing and accounting for its implications regarding
the way the world appears and does not appear. Observations of observations
as observations are contingent in relation to the chosen way of seeing. It is
always possible to observe the second order in a different way. A decision has
to be made, therefore, and the decision calls for an explanation.
Precondition 4
The elaboration of an analytical strategy consists of four choices:
94
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Precondition 5
One also needs a guiding distinction, by which I mean the distinction that
can define the frame for observations of the second order. The guiding
distinction divides the world to the second-order observer and dictates how
the world can be observed. The guiding distinction creates the necessary
distance between the object and the observer, but also defines which questions
can be posed in relation to the object. The guiding distinction is not predefined
but must be decided. Whether the distinction system/environment, regularity/
dispersion of statements, or discourse/discoursivity is defined as the guiding
distinction is an essential analytical-strategic choice. The guiding distinction
steers the observation and frames the choice of different supporting distinctions.
For example, if the choice is system/environment, the world is divided into
systems and their environment; if one decides on regularity/dispersion, the
world is divided into the dispersion of statements and the regularity of this
dispersion. And one sees only that, which is precisely the purpose of the
guiding distinction: to discipline our way of seeing so that we do not
involuntarily fall back on first-order observation. This is why Foucault expends
so much energy on sharpening his discourse-analytical focus. He knows that
he is only able to observe the discourse as it appears if his way of seeing is
refined enough to keep him from reducing his discourse analysis to discourse
commentary.
Precondition 6
The conditioning of the guiding distinction is the specification of those
conditions by which one and not the other side of a distinction can be indicated
in a second-order observation. It does not suffice to distinguish between
system and environment. One must also define when a system can be perceived
as a system, when a system can historically be said still to be the same system,
when the system has evolved into a different system and when the system has
ceased to be a system. Otherwise the guiding distinction can only obtain the
status of a loose metaphor in relation to which an observer’s indication of
system and environment respectively becomes completely arbitrary. This, of
course, applies to all guiding distinctions. We could thus ask:
95
Discursive analytical strategies
to criticism. The clearer and more unambiguous the conditioning, the greater
the sensitivity of the analytical strategy to the empirical, which amounts to
saying that the clearer the conditioning of the guiding distinction, the more
evident the falsification criteria of the second-order observation. A discourse
analysis without well-defined criteria for the indication of discursive formations
immunises itself to tangible empirical criticism, thereby dooming any critical
discussion of the analysis to a meta-discussion. (Unfortunately, there are many
of these types of discourse analyses.)
Precondition 7
I understand point of observation to be maintained through external reference
in a second-order observation. It is not enough to decide on a guiding
distinction and to condition it in order to adhere to the analytical eye. As
Foucault points out, different statements can be read very differently depending
on the discursive regularity one employs. In relation to discourse analysis, the
point of observation implies a choice of discursive reference, that is, a definition
of the question whose genealogy one wishes to unravel and the implications
this has for fixing the point of observation. It is my view that this is, as already
mentioned, what Foucault discusses when he, for example, dwells on the criteria
for periodisation. Similarly, in systems theory the analysis depends entirely on
the systems reference of the second-order observer. Do we perceive of the
communication as a system of interaction, an as organisational system or as a
social system? Each communication can appear as an event in several systems
simultaneously. Thus, the appearance of the communication to the second-
order observer relies on the observer’s choice of systems reference (that is,
which system he decides to observe). Again, communication does not itself
call for a particular point of observation; a choice is required, and the choice
must be followed by an explanation.
Precondition 8
Finally, analytical strategies can be combined, as, for example, when Laclau
combines deconstruction and hegemonic analysis. Here, a thorough account
of the complementation of the analytical strategies is critical.
• What are the rules for joining the different guiding distinctions?
Various discourse and systems theories are comparable on the level of their
analytical-strategic potential, that is, on the level of their pool of guiding
distinctions, conditionings and points of observation.
96
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
97
Discursive analytical strategies
Foucault
In Foucault I have isolated four analytics:
Geneaology
98
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Self-technology analysis
Dispositive analysis
Koselleck
In the works of Koselleck we seem to find a distinction between two analytical
strategies:
History of concepts
The concept-historical analytical strategy is, like Foucault’s archaeology, of
the second order. It is a strategy for the study of the origins of the linguistic
space of possibilities. But the guiding distinction and hence the opening
question is different. Therefore, although they both work with linguistic units,
they are objectified in different ways. Koselleck’s diachronic guiding distinction
is meaning/meaning condensed into concepts. Koselleck studies the way the
creation of meaning is concentrated and contained in concepts that then
become carriers of a multitude of meaning, which can organise the shaping of
identities and fields of conflict, and thereby extend into the future. The focus
is on concepts, which creates different analytical material to that of Foucault’s.
Whereas Foucault ideally reads everything, Koselleck focuses on what he calls
nurtured semantics, that is, writings that have been worked through linguistically
and thus employ concepts prudently.
99
Discursive analytical strategies
Laclau
In Laclau we are able to distinguish:
• hegemonic analysis;
• deconstructivist analysis.
Hegemonic analysis
Deconstructivist analysis
Luhmann
For Luhmann it becomes difficult to maintain a comprehensive view of the
pool of guiding distinctions and the potential combinations. I believe I can
define five different analytical strategies in Luhmann:
100
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
• form analysis;
• systems analysis;
• differentiation analysis;
• semantic analysis;
• media analysis.
Form analysis
Systems analysis
• How is the boundary of meaning defined in the system and what are the
implications for the continuance of the communication in the system?
• In what way is it closed around itself?
• How does it develop a sensitivity to the environment, that is, how does the
system define the relevance of the environment?
101
Discursive analytical strategies
Differentation analysis
Sematic analysis
102
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Media analysis
Luhmann’s fifth and final analytical strategy uses the guiding distinction form/
medium, where form can only be regarded as such in relation to a medium
and vice versa, with form the operative side. Media analysis only finds its
equivalent in Foucault’s dispositive analysis, in which apparatus corresponds
to form and strategic logic corresponds to medium. The strategic logics that
Foucault pursued largely resemble Luhmann’s symbolically generalised media
in their characterisation. Foucault speaks about legal/illegal, Luhmann about
right/wrong; Foucault speaks about security preparedness/insecurity and
Luhmann speaks about risk/danger. Both medium and strategic logic can
only be brought about through something else; that something else is apparatus
in Foucault and form in Luhmann. However, Luhmann never ascribes a
strategic function to media. The concepts of form and apparatus both constitute
the context in which logic and media are inscribed. However, having
highlighted the similarities, the big difference is that Foucault’s apparatus is a
system of relations between forms, whereas Luhmann appears not to have
unfolded the potential in the concept of form with respect to the relations of
the forms to other forms. (Although he does point to a guiding difference,
which he terms element/relation, and one could argue its potential for
perspectives similar to those that Foucault opens with his concept of apparatus.)
Finally, like dispositive analysis, media analysis constitutes a double movement.
It can be approached from the side of the form as well as the side of the
medium. We can inquire into the generalisation of a form into a medium,
which I call media analysis. But we can also ask which medium is formed by
a specific form and with what effects, which I call formation analysis.
Media analysis asks the questions:
• How are media shaped and how do they suggest a particular potential for
formation?
• How do media render certain forms of communication probable?
• How are, for example, language – spoken and written – and media of
distribution such as the Internet shaped?
• How do they substantiate entirely new forms of communication?
103
Discursive analytical strategies
104
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Foucault
Archaeological discourse analysis
Let us, once again, begin with Foucault’s archaeological discourse analysis.
Here, the fundamental question is the conditioning of the discursive formation.
When are we able to identify a discursive formation? The guiding distinction
regularity/dispersion of statements is not sensitive to empiricism until it has
been established when a regularity in the dispersion of statements constitutes
a discursive formation. Without exact criteria for when we can identify
regularity and hence discursive formation, our designation of discourses is
based solely on intuition (Hebrew for revelation).
In fact, Foucault answers this question thoroughly in his work on knowledge
archaeology, but the entire answer depends on which particular form of discourse
we are dealing with. There is no guarantee that regularity can signify the same
thing at all times and in all discursive contexts. Foucault knows this. As it is,
knowledge archaeology precisely designates knowledge as a point of reference.
It extends itself into very different areas of knowledge but always in the shape
of knowledge. This is evident even down to the level of the specifications by
the analytical strategy of the levels of formation, including the emphasis on the
object level and the questions of how objects are shaped, placed in hierarchies
and classified. We can conceive of numerous other forms of discourses that
would not have in common the form of knowledge and would also not, therefore,
share the same form of regularity. Hence, knowledge-archaeological analytical
strategy possesses an inherent notion of the characteristics of knowledge
discourses, but these characteristics themselves become the object of the analysis
and discussion of their origins. Accordingly, The birth of the clinic (Foucault,
1986b) does not merely concern the history of medical discourse but also the
origins of the scientific way of seeing. The conditioning of the guiding
distinction is not therefore a question of deciding on a set of premises once and
for all. In a discourse analysis, conditioning the concept of discourse is itself an
object of analysis. The way a discursive formation is a discursive formation is
an intricate part of the discourse analysis. The discursive formation does not,
therefore, precede the study of it, since the discursive formation as the subject
of discourse analysis can only be demarcated after the completion of the analysis.
In practice, this means that the discourse analyst constantly questions the
discourse’s own criteria for discourse.
Genealogy
105
Discursive analytical strategies
Self-technology analysis
Dispositive analysis
106
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Point of observation
For example...
The question might be the birth of the complete employee, but the specification
of this question implies a definition of whether the point of observation is a scientific
discourse and, if so, which one (for example, psychology or organisational theory).
It might also be a political discourse, for example that of administrational politics.
Depending on the discourse one chooses as point of observation, different criteria
for discourse exist and different articulations and notions of the ‘complete
employee’ appear.
Koselleck
Concept-historical analysis
107
Discursive analytical strategies
the fact that the creation of meaning possesses exactly these conceptual qualities.
This includes the existence of a nurtured semantics in which the concepts can
appear as object to the history of concepts. Conceptual history is not able to
capture creation of meaning that does not obtain the form of concept (for
example, symbols or images).
Point of observation
Laclau
In Laclau we see the emergence of a number of problems of conditioning,
which, in some cases, take on more serious dimensions than in the analyses of
Foucault and Koselleck. Generally, we might regret that Laclau has abstained
from empirical work, since this kind of experience might have influenced his
theoretical architecture. However, no efforts have been made towards the
conditioning of the apparatus for observation, which means that what appears
coherent and consistent within the theory is transformed into rather feeble
metaphors on confrontation with an actual object. This applies to the concepts
of discourse, and floating and empty signifier. The concept of empty signifier
is particularly anti-empirical.
Hegemonic analysis
108
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
109
Discursive analytical strategies
Deconstructivist analysis
Point of observation
Luhmann
Form analysis
The problem of conditioning in Luhmann’s form analysis has the same qualities
as the problem of conditioning in relation to deconstruction in Laclau. As we
have seen, form analysis concerns the unity of the distinction, hence, the
primary task is to recognise which distinction is the object of the form analysis.
The first difficulty is therefore in a motivation of the other side of the distinction
in relation to the indication one seeks to observe.
110
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
For example...
As was the case with deconstruction, the question cannot be answered until
form analysis functions as input for another analysis, for example a semantic
analysis or a systems analysis, in which the unfolding of the paradoxical character
of form can be studied. Only in studies of the de-paradoxification of paradoxes
will it become evident to what degree and with what implications a form
manifests itself. Only through de-paradoxification can we follow form in its
chains of distinctions and only then can we determine to what extent
communication follows a specific form.
Systems analysis
Differentiation analysis
Evidently, all social systems do not adhere to the same form of differentiation.
Luhmann claims that functional differentiation is presently the primary form
of differentiation, but this does not mean that systems adhering to a different
form of differentiation are not continually formed (for example, biker gangs
111
Discursive analytical strategies
Media analysis
• language;
• media of distribution;
• general symbolic media.
Evidently, each of the types holds definitional measures but, at the same time,
each medium typically exceeds the general definition. The media never
completely function as media in exactly the same way, and it is therefore
critical to the empirical sensitivity of the analysis that the conditioning possesses
an inductive rather than a deductive character. Parallel to Foucault’s discourse
analyses, we cannot predefine a final conditioning of the point at which a
medium can be regarded as a medium. The conditioning happens as part of
the analysis in which the demands on the chosen medium are gradually
intensified, and in which this evolution makes the object appear increasingly
clear and causes the analysis to heighten its sensitivity to empirical details.
The analysis can be seen as completed once one has reached a delimitation of
the characteristics of the medium as medium. As with archaeological discourse
analysis, the object (that is, the specific discursive formation) cannot therefore
be presupposed. On the contrary, the object is the result of the analysis,
including the measures for the assertion of the object.
Semantic analysis
112
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Point of observation
113
Discursive analytical strategies
Foucault
Archaeological discourse When can we speak of ‘regularity’? Which discursive problem is pursued?
analysis
When can a statement be What is the discursive reference?
regarded as a statement?
Genealogy What are the measures for the What is the discursive reference?
identification of continuity and
discontinuity respectively?
Self-technology analysis When can we speak of What is the discursive reference?
subjectivation?
When can something be regarded What is the discursive reference?
as technology?
Dispositive analysis When are the elements sufficiently What is the discursive reference?
connected for them to be called
an apparatus?
When is a schematic a general and What is the discursive reference?
strategic logic?
Koselleck
History of concepts When is meaning condensed? Which semantic field is referred to?
Semantic field analysis When does a semantic field possess What is the discursive reference?
the qualities of a field?
Laclau
Hegemonic analysis Which conditions must be met for What is the discursive reference?
someone to speak of discourse?
Which logic is defined as guiding principle?
Deconstructivist analysis Why this particular distinction? Which discursive problem is pursued?
Luhmann
Form analysis Why this particular distinction? What is the systems reference?
Why this particular ‘other side’ Which form is defined as the guiding principle?
of the distinction?
Differentiation analysis What are the measures for a Which form is defined as the guiding principle?
similarity in a distinction to be
designated as a form of differentiation?
Semantic analysis When is meaning condensed? Which form is defined as the guiding principle?
When does a semantic rupture exist?
Media analysis What are the measures for the Which form is defined as the guiding principle?
recognition of a medium?
114
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
115
Discursive analytical strategies
For example...
Future questions
116
A hall of mirrors or a pool of analytical strategies
Choice of conditioning
117
Discursive analytical strategies
For example...
118
References
119
Discursive analytical strategies
120
References
121
Discursive analytical strategies
122
References
Luhmann, N. (1994b) ‘Speaking and silence’, New German Critique, vol 61,
pp 25-37.
Luhmann, N. (1995a) ‘The paradoxy of observing system’, Cultural Critique,
no 31, pp 37-55.
Luhmann, N. (1995b) ‘Subjektets nykker og spørgsmålet om mennesket’, in
J.C. Jacobsen (ed) Autopoiesis II, Copenhagen: Politisk Revy, p 46.
Luhmann, N. (1995c) Social systems, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Luhmann, N. (1996) ‘On the scientific context of the concept of
communication’, Social Science Information.
Macey, D. (1988) Lacan in context, London: Verso.
Mahon, M. (1992) Foucault’s Nietzschean genealogy, Albany, NY: State University
of New York Press.
Megill, A. (1979) ‘Foucault, structuralism, and the end of history’, Journal of
Modern History, vol 51, no 3, pp 451-503.
Nietzsche, F. (1988) On the advantage and disadvantage of history for life, Indianapolis,
IL: Hackett Publishing.
Nietzsche, F. (1998) On the genealogy of morality, Indianapolis, IL: Hackett
Publishing.
Noujain, E.G. (1987) ‘History as genealogy: an exploration of Foucault’s
approach to history’, in A.P. Griffiths (ed) Contemporary French philosophy,
New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, pp 157-74.
Pedersen, O.K. (1983) Videnskabsproblemet, Copenhagen: Aurora.
Pocock, J.G.A. (1987) ‘The concepts of a language and the métier d’historien:
some considerations on practice’, in A. Pagden (ed) The languages of political
theory in early-modern Europe, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Raffnsøe, S. (1999) ‘Historie- eller diskursanalyse? En introduction til Foucault
Les mots et les choses og L’archéologie du savoir’, COS-report 4/99, Copenhagen:
Copenhagen Business School.
Raffnsøe, S. (2000) ‘Michel Foucault’s dispositionelle magtanalytik’, Grus.
Regnault, F. (1983) ‘Hvad er et epistemologisk brud?’, in S.G. Olesen (ed)
Epistemologi, Copenhagen: Rhodos.
Richter, M. (1990) ‘Reconstructing the history of political languages: Pocock,
Skinner, and the geschichtliche Grundbegriffe’, History and Theory, vol 29,
pp 38-70.
Richter, M. (1995) The history of political and social concepts, New York, NY:
Oxford University Press.
Rose, N. (1996) Intenting ourselves: Psychology, power and personhood, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Roth, M.S. (1981) ‘Foucault’s “History of the present”’, History and Theory, vol
20, pp 32-46.
Röttgers, K. (1982) ‘Kritik’, in O. Brunner, W. Conze and R. Kosseleck (eds)
Geschichtiche Grundbegriffe, Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in
Deutschland, Vol III, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.
Scharff, R. (1974) ‘Nietzsche and the “use” of history’, Man and World, An
International Philosophical Review, vol 7, p 74.
Schmidt, L.H. (1990) Det sociale selv, Århus: Århus Universitetsforlag.
123
Discursive analytical strategies
Schmidt, L.H. and Kristensen J.E. (eds) (1985) Foucaults Blik, Århus: Modtryk.
Shiner, L. (1982) ‘Reading Foucault: anti-method and the genealogy of power–
knowledge’, History and Theory, vol 21, pp 382-98.
Skinner, Q. (1987) Machiavelli, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Spencer-Brown, G. (1969) Laws of gorm, London: George Allen & Unwin.
Stahäli, U. (1998) ‘Die Nachträglichkeit der Semantik zum Verhältnis von
Sozialstruktur und Semantik’, Soziale Systeme, Zeitschrift für soziologische Theorie,
no 2, pp 315-40.
Stråht, B. (ed) (1990) Language and the construction of class identity, Göteborg:
Department of History, Göteborg University.
Tully, J. (1988) Meaning and context: Quentin Skinner and his critics, London:
Polity Press.
von Foerster, J. (1981) Observing systems, Seaside, CA: Intersystems Publication.
124
Appendix A: Examples of other
analytical strategies
Analytical strategy Guiding distinction Question Goal of the analysis
Pierre Bourdieu
Field analysis Community/disagreement How are fields created as To demonstrate the
communities of disagreement correlation between
and how do they distribute a history, practice and
network of relative subject power
positions?
Analysis of Authorising/speech How are individuals authorised
communicative position by institutions so that they not
competence only speak from a position of
meaning but also with weight?
How can individuals collect social
and cultural capital that they can
actualise communicatively in
specific fields?
Jürgen Habermas
Discourse analysis Discursive practice/ethics In what way does practice Emancipation and
of discourse deviate from the ethics discourse-ethical
of discourse? communication
Bruno Latour
Translation analysis Translation/association How are ideas, technologies, To demonstrate the
and practices propagated by growth of power
being associated with other ideas, through distribution
technologies, and practices etc, and practice in a
so that they form a network? network
In what way does propagation
through association simultaneously
mean a translation of the
propagated phenomena so that
phenomena constantly change
character and value through
their propagation?
Louis Althusser
Symptomatic reading The invisible in the visible Which questions are posed To analyse the imaginary
by the text? order which regulates
people’s relationship to
Which answers does the text their condition of
offer to the questions it poses? existence with a view
to politicisation
Which questions does the text
pose without answering them?
Which answers does the text offer
to questions it does not pose?
In sum, what is the prohibited and
displaced question that guides and
regulates the text and its visibility?
125
Appendix B: Further reading
127
Discursive analytical strategies
Cornell, D., Rosenfeld, M. and Carlson, D.G. (eds) (1992) Deconstruction and
the possibility of justice, New York, NY: Routledge.
Dalton, C. (1985) ‘An essay in the deconstruction of contract doctrine’, The
Yale Law Journal, vol 94, no 5, pp 999-1113.
Daly, G. (1991) ‘The discursive construction of economic space: logics of
organization and disorganization’, Economy & Society, vol 20, no 1, pp 79-
102.
128
Appendix B
129
Discursive analytical strategies
Ball, T. and Pocock, J.G.A. (eds) (1988) Conceptual change and the constitution,
Lawrence, KA: University Press of Kansas.
Ball, T. (1988) Transforming political discourse: Political theory and critical conceptual
history, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Knemeyer, F.-L. (1980) ‘Polizei’, Economy & Society, vol 9, no 2, pp 173-96.
Koselleck, R. and Presner, T.S. (2002) Practice of conceptual history:Timing history
spacint concepts, Cultural Memory in the Present, Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Koselleck, R. (1985) Futures past, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Koselleck, R. (1988) Critique and crisis, Oxford: Berg.
Walther, R. (1989) ‘Economic liberalism’, Economy & Society, vol 13, pp 178-
207.
130
Index
INDEX
A ‘concepts and counter-concepts’
‘actuality and potentiality’ (Koselleck) VI, 33-48, 47fig,
(Luhmann) 12, 73 48tab, 99-100
Althusser, L. 2, 3, 49, 52, 125 ‘condensed meaning’ (Luhmann) see
analytical strategies ‘meaning and condensed
Anderson’s views 93-118, 117fig meaning’
definition XIII, 93-6 counter-concepts (Koselleck) see
methodological issues XIII-XV ‘concepts and counter concepts’
ee also strategy types under Foucault;
Koselleck; Laclau; Luhmann D
Anderson, N. A. XIX-XXII, 93-118 Davidson, A.I. 25
apparatus (dispositif) (Foucault) de Saussure, F. 3, 6, 52
27-30, 28fig, 29fig, 31tab, 97tab, Dean, M. 27
99, 106-7, 114tab deconstructivist analysis (Laclau)
see also archaeology; genealogy; 56-61, 62tab, 97tab, 100, 110,
technologies of the self 114tab
archaeology (Foucault) 8-16, 31tab, relationship with discourse analysis
97tab, 98, 105 58-9, 58fig
ee also apparatus; genealogy; see also hegemonic analysis
technologies of the self Deleuze, G. 27
Archaeology of knowledge (Foucault) 8, Derrida, J. 49-50, 51
17 Of grammatology 57
‘articulation’ (Laclau) 50, 51 Descombes, V. 4-5
diachronic and synchronous analysis
B (Koselleck) 35, 43, 47fig
Balibar, E. 2, 24 ‘difference’ (Laclau) see ‘equivalence
Barthes, R. 6 and difference’
‘before and after’ (Koselleck) 44 ‘difference’ (Luhmann) see ‘form and
Beronius, M. 20 difference’, ‘unity and difference’
Between facts and norms (Habermas) differentiation analysis (Luhmann)
XVIII 81-3, 83tab, 89-90, 90fig, 92tab,
Birth of the clinic (Foucault) 105 97tab, 102, 111, 114tab
Born, A. XXI, 115 see also form analysis; formation
Bourdieu, P. XVIII, 125 analysis; media analysis; semantic
Brenner, N. 27, 30 analysis; systems analysis
Brunner, J. 33 Discipline and punish (Foucault) 6-7,
19, 27
C discourse and discoursivity
Chouliaraki, L. XIX Foucault VI
‘communication’ (Luhmann) 74-7 Laclau VI, 50-4, 72, 100
discourse analysis
(Foucault) 1-32, 114tab
131
Discursive analytical strategies
132
Index
133
Discursive analytical strategies
‘form and difference’ VI, 64, 65fig mental illness see ‘madness and
‘form and medium’ 97tab, 114tab reason’
formation analysis 97tab, 114tab Mental illness and psychology
‘indication and distinction’ 65-7 (Foucault) 5-6
‘meaning and condensed meaning’ Mouffe, C. 49, 50, 51, 56, 61
12, 72-4, 86, 87, 102
media analysis 83-6, 84fig, 86fig, N
90-1, 91fig, 92tab, 97tab, 103, 112 Nassehi, A. 75
‘media and form’ 83-6, 84fig, 86fig, Nietzsche, F. 17-18
97tab, 103, 112 ‘nodal points’ (Laclau) VII, 51
observation VII, 64-71, 71tab,
77-8, 93-5 O
semantic analysis 86-90, 89fig, observation (Luhmann) VII, 64-71,
90fig, 92tab, 97tab, 102, 112-3, 71tab, 77-8, 93-5
114tab Of grammatology (Derrida) 57
‘similarity and dissimilarity’ 82, On the genealogy of morality
92tab, 97tab, 102 (Nietzsche) 17
‘system and environment’ 66, 67fig, Order of things (Foucault) 6
69, 80-1, 81fig, 101 Østergård, U. 34
systems analysis 82-3, 90-1, 91fig,
92tab, 97tab, 101, 111
P
systems theory 12, 63-92
Panopticon (Foucault) 7
‘unity and difference’ 78-9, 101
Parsons, T. 63
Pedersen, O.K. XI, XII
M Pocock, J.G.A. 33
Macey, D. 53 poststructuralism see structuralism
Madness and civilization (Foucault) 3, ‘potentiality’ (Luhmann) see
4, 19 ‘actuality and potentiality’
‘madness and reason’ (Foucault) 3-6 prison as punishment/cure
Mahon, M. 32 (Foucault) 6-7
‘meaning and condensed punishment (Foucault) 6-7, 19
meaning’(Luhmann) 12, 72-4,
86, 87, 102
R
media analysis (Luhmann) 83-6,
Raffnsøe, S. 28, 32
84fig, 86fig, 90-1, 91fig, 92tab,
‘reason’ (Foucault) see ‘madness and
97tab, 103, 112
reason’
see also differentiation analysis;
Regnault, F. XV
form analysis; formation analysis;
Richter, M. 33
semantic analysis; systems analysis
Roth, M.S. 32
‘media and form’ (Luhmann) 83-6,
84fig, 86fig, 97tab, 103, 112
‘medium’ (Luhmann) see ‘form and S
medium’ Scharff, R. 18
Megill, A. 19, 32 Schmidt, L.H. XVII, 2, 24
second order observation
(Luhmann) see observation
134
Index
135