(Cornell Studies in The Philosophy of Religion) ) J.L. Schellenberg - Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason-Cornell University Press (2006)
(Cornell Studies in The Philosophy of Religion) ) J.L. Schellenberg - Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason-Cornell University Press (2006)
(Cornell Studies in The Philosophy of Religion) ) J.L. Schellenberg - Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason-Cornell University Press (2006)
A full list of titles in the series appears at the end of the book.
J. L. Schellenberg
Divine Hiddenness
and Human Reason
All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book,
or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form without
permission in writing from the publisher. For information, address
Cornell University Press, 124 Roberts Place, Ithaca, New York 14850.
https://archive.org/details/divinehiddennessOOsche
Contents
Acknowledgments ix
Introduction i
Index 215
Acknowledgments
In this book I argue that there is support for such claims as these.
The weakness of evidence for theism, I maintain, is itself evidence
against it. Paving the way for my argument will be a discussion of
certain important questions raised by its central claim: What reasons
are there to suppose that God would be more clearly revealed? (It is
not obvious a priori that he would, so reasons need to be pro¬
vided.) If reasons there be, what is suggested by them as to the
degree of clarity, and of accessibility, we might expect to find?
Should we look for proof—perhaps an overwhelming manifesta¬
tion—or would something less than this serve God’s purposes?
And would the evidence be made available to all, or only to those
who satisfy certain conditions beforehand? More generally, what
explications of “weak” and “strong” ought we to give here? It
seems clear enough that these questions need answering if our
problem is to be properly developed, but they have not been ad¬
dressed in previous discussions, even by those (few) who have seen
that there may be an argument for atheism lurking here. Our dis¬
cussion will seek to remedy this neglect—to state with some preci¬
sion why we might expect stronger evidence for theism to be
available if God exists, and what sort of evidence God might be
expected to provide.
The argument that will emerge from this discussion is, in broad
outline, as follows. A perfectly loving God would desire a recipro¬
cal personal relationship always to obtain between himself and
every human being capable of it. But a logically necessary condi¬
tion of such Divine-human reciprocity is human belief in Divine
existence. Hence a perfectly loving God would have reason to en¬
sure that everyone capable of such belief (or at any rate, everyone
capable who was not disposed to resist it) was in possession of
evidence sufficient to bring it about that such belief was formed.
But the evidence actually available is not of this sort (the claim that
it is “weak” is to be read simply as the claim that it is not “strong”
in this sense). The most obvious indication that it is not is that
inculpable—or as I prefer to term it, reasonable—nonbelief actually
I have suggested (and the title of this book also suggests) that the
question here raised for discussion is connected to the idea of the
hiddenness of God. But the notion of God’s hiddenness is ambig¬
uous, and so this way of referring to our topic can be misleading.
It can mislead, first of all, by suggesting that all the ways in which
God may be said to be hidden pose problems for theology. It can
also mislead in a very different way, by suggesting that the absence
of persuasive and readily available theistic evidence is not a prob¬
lem—that since theology has always insisted on God’s hiddenness,
the question I am raising can be dismissed a priori, as displaying
theological naivete. In order to avoid being misled in these ways,
we must make some distinctions. The notion of God’s hiddenness
can be interpreted in at least three ways: as referring to the obscur¬
ing of God’s existence, the incomprehensibility of God’s nature, or
our inability to detect the exact pattern of God’s activity in the
world. To the question I am raising, only “hiddenness” in the first
sense is relevant. All I seek to show is that we might expect God’s
existence to be more obvious. I am happy to allow that the same
claim made in respect of the depths of God’s nature or the exact
pattern of his activity would have much less to recommend it.
Can it now be argued, however, that theologians have always
insisted on God’s hiddenness in all three senses? I think not. Al¬
though some writers, such as Karl Barth, seem to refer to God as
hidden not only in the second and third of the above senses, but
also in the first, it is important to note that this is largely a post-
Enlightenment phenomenon.4 The majority of patristic, medieval,
portunity to acquire belief and the benefits of belief was missed by no one (see
Schlesinger, “Availability of Evidence,” 424-425). But if only God’s justice need
be saved, the theist may always point to the possibility that everything will even
out in the end—that those who fail to benefit from belief in this life will be com¬
pensated hereafter. Or else she may claim that it is not unjust to give a gift to
someone while not giving it to others, unless everyone can be shown to be entitled
to it. Such easy “outs” are, however, not possible where Divine love is concerned.
If God is loving as well as just, he is motivated to pursue personal relationship
with each of us in this life as well as in the hereafter. In the interests of a stronger
argument, therefore, I have decided to fill out the reasoning suggested by the ques¬
tion “Why, if there is a God, is his existence not more obvious?” in terms of love
rather than in terms of justice.
4. For Barth’s view, see his Church Dogmatics, vol. 2, pt. 1 (Edinburgh: T&T
Introduction [ 5
Clark, 1957), p. 187. He writes: “That God is, lies as little in the field of our
spiritual oversight and control as what He is. We lack the capacity both to establish
His existence and to define His being.”
5. Jaroslav Pelikan, The Christian Tradition, vol. 3 (Chicago: University of Chi¬
cago Press, 1978), p. 289.
6. Martin Luther, quoted in Jaroslav Pelikan, The Christian Tradition, vol. 4
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 165-166.
7. Ibid., p. 166.
6] Introduction
action, or state of affairs need not be of this sort. ' It need only be
such that the affirmation of its existence comes into conflict with
what theists are committed to saying about the nature of God—in
particular, about the moral nature of God: it poses a problem of evil
if it seems that a morally perfect God who was also omnipotent
and omniscient could not allow it, or if it seems improbable that he
would. Hence the state of affairs discussed in this book—the rea¬
sonableness of nonbelief—though it is not a state of affairs that we
would all naturally view as negative or destructive and so as evil,
and though it is not a state of affairs the world would be much
better without even if God does not exist, may still legitimately be
viewed as posing a problem of evil if the affirmation of its exist¬
ence comes into conflict with what theists are committed to saying
about God’s moral nature. And that it does so is my claim. Hence I
seem to be in a position to claim that the problem of reasonable
nonbelief is a problem of evil. However, the “evil” to which it
refers is, as we have seen, not of the ordinary sort (for it does not
consist in pain or suffering or any other commonly recognized evil,
nor would its removal be a great good unless personal relationship
with God is possible); and so, to mark this difference, it may be
appropriate to refer to it as a special instance of the problem of evil.
It remains only to point out the sort of conflict I have in mind
here: Do I consider the problem of reasonable nonbelief to be a
special instance of the logical, or of the empirical, problem of evil?
If the former, then the claim I advance is tantamount to the claim
that
10. See Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1974), chap. 9.
Introduction
11. It may be worthwhile to point out here that there is a way of construing my
claim as a necessary truth that is equally immune to a Plantinga-style response. This
can be seen as follows. The claim that some state of affairs obtains and the claim
that it obtains in the actual world (a) are truth-functionally equivalent. (I assume
here that “the actual world” and “a” designate rigidly.) Hence we may with per¬
fect propriety rephrase (2) as follows:
But as Plantinga’s own work shows, “a-claims” like (2') are noncontingent—ei¬
ther necessarily true or necessarily false. For if a includes some state of affairs S, it
necessarily includes it. And if a does not include S, it necessarily excludes it. (See
Plantinga, Nature of Necessity, pp. 45-46, 55.) Hence if (2') is true, it is necessarily
true, which was what we wished to show. So anyone who wishes to do so may
interpret the claim for which I will be seeking to make a prima facie case as a claim
with respect to what is necessarily true: no susceptibility to Plantinga-style maneu¬
vers need thereby be incurred. But for myself, I will continue to view it simply as
the claim that if God is perfectly loving, reasonable nonbelief does not occur—a
claim which purports to be no more than true.
Introduction
12. I have taken this argument from Richard Swinburne, Responsibility and
Atonement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 165-166. See also Bernard Wil¬
liams, Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp.
147-149. There will be more on the nature of belief in Chapter 1, second section.
13. While it is impossible, as I am suggesting here, to will belief directly, it may
be possible to will it indirectly, and so belief may be said to be indirectly voluntary.
But this is a very different notion. Getting oneself to believe, for example, that
there is a God when the evidence does not seem initially to support that belief
requires deliberate self-deception, and such self-deception—since it involves view¬
ing the evidence selectively and forgetting that one has done so—requires a consid¬
erable period of time.
14. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979),
P- 153-
Introduction [
thing like a complete explication of “Divine love,” I think we can
say that what usually goes by that name—at a minimum, self-giv¬
ing, unconditionally accepting, relationship-seeking love—is such
that any being who lacked it would be a being whose greatness
could be surpassed, and therefore not God. Love of the sort in ques¬
tion is clearly one of the highest manifestations of personal being;
so if God is conceived as embodying the perfections of personal
life, he must be conceived as perfectly loving.
Now it may be said that this picture of God as perfectly loving is
a picture of God peculiarly suited to my purposes and so one I will
naturally be inclined to defend. But it should be noted that very
many who are not antecedently committed to the conclusion of
my argument would nonetheless accept this premise without hesi¬
tation. As H. H. Price puts it, “What could conceivably be better
than universal and unconditional love?”15 In the unconditional love
of a Mother Teresa, for example, we see reflected a quality of be¬
ing that most of us would intuitively say must belong to God, if
God exists. For it is something to which we are inclined to ascribe
very great value indeed. When we reflect on the nature of such
love, all the power and knowledge in the world fade by compari¬
son. Hence it would seem (and I will assume) that all who espouse
a form of theism are rationally committed to the truth of the claim
that God, if he exists, is perfectly loving.
(4) A fourth assumption is that the claim that God exists is coher¬
ent. I do not wish to suggest that there are no problems of coher¬
ence which theists must resolve, but these problems will not con¬
cern us here. That some description of God falling within the
parameters laid down above is coherent is in any case assumed by
most contemporary philosophers of religion to be in principle de¬
monstrable.16 The questions that concern philosophers of religion
writing today are more commonly questions of truth than ques¬
tions of coherence.
(5) I will further assume that the relevant evidence (exclusive of
15. H. H. Price, “Faith and Belief,” in John Hick, ed., Faith and the Philosophers
(London: Macmillan, 1964), p. 5.
16. See, for example, Richard Swinburne, The Coherence of Theism (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1977), and J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Claren¬
don Press, 1982), pp. 1-3.
] Introduction
evidence adduced in this book) does not clearly favor either the
conclusion that there is a God or its denial. This assumption seems
warranted in light of recent discussions in the philosophy of reli¬
gion, which often end in deadlock, and is accepted by many, both
inside and outside the academic study of religion.17 In the Conclu¬
sion, however, I will consider the implications of our discussion
for those who would view belief in the existence of God as having
considerably more in the way of evidential support than I here al¬
low.
(6) Finally, I will assume that it is coherent to suppose that hu¬
man beings survive their deaths. This assumption, like the assump¬
tion of libertarian free will and of the coherence of theism, is made
in full recognition of its controversial status, for the sake of argu¬
ment: it too is accepted and commonly presupposed by those to
whom this book is addressed.
My description in this Introduction of the argument to follow
may seem to suggest that it is my wish to defend atheism—to
show that God does not exist. But this is not an accurate represen¬
tation of my intent; and I would like to emphasize that it is not.
The intended contribution of this book is more correctly charac¬
terized as a demonstration that there is an argument here—an argu¬
ment of considerable force, which deserves much more attention
than it has heretofore received. It is true, as noted earlier, that I will
conclude by declaring all the available counterarguments to be
bankrupt, and by suggesting that anyone who accepts my conclu¬
sion (as well as the fifth assumption above) has good grounds for a
denial of theism. But I by no means wish to rule out the possibility
that better arguments than the ones here discussed may one day be
devised. It is indeed my hope that those who read this book may
be motivated to seek to provide such arguments. Thus although I
do believe that, where there is a prima facie case, the failure of all
the arguments one can think of to rebut that case provides good
grounds for believing its conclusion, and that no available counter-
17. The deadlock is exemplified by, for example, the opposed arguments of
Swinburne’s Existence of God, and Mackie’s Miracle of Theism.
Introduction
3. In line with earlier discussion in the Introduction, claims with respect to this
connection are defended as true, not as necessarily true. Needless to say, if they are
necessarily true as well, the argument will be none the worse for it.
4. W. H. Vanstone, Love’s Endeavour, Love’s Expense (London: Darton, Long¬
man and Todd, 1977), p. 45.
Epistemic Implications of Divine Love [
Before endorsing this claim, however, we must examine it a little
more closely. What are the benefits such a relationship would
make available? We may begin by noting the ethical benefits. It
seems clear that explicit relationship with a perfectly loving God
would have a certain moral influence and make available certain
resources for dealing with the moral weakness endemic to human¬
ity; and few would deny that, were we to become ethically stron¬
ger in this way, our well-being would be enhanced. But that is not
all. If God exists and is perfectly loving, and if the life of God is
unsurpassably good, as by definition it must be, and if, in addition,
God has created us and wills our good, then the love of which we
are in some measure capable must be seen as a significant clue to
the nature of our deepest well-being. Growth in self-giving love
must, in other words, lead to a deeper realization of well-being,
and so God as perfectly benevolent will naturally seek to facilitate
it. In helping us replace self-centered patterns of activity with
agapeistic ones, he will be allowing us to share in his own life and
thus will be facilitating the achievement of an objective quality of
being which is of great worth. Now, of course, to avoid begging
the question at issue, we must assume for the moment that the
love God seeks to facilitate is a form of benevolence not necessarily
involving the seeking of personal relationship. But, even so, the
promised additional point follows. It is that if self-giving love has
this special importance vis-a-vis our well-being, then given that we
are often morally weak, we are even more obviously in a position
to benefit from outside help—help of the sort made available by
personal relationship with God.
Few religious writers would quarrel with this view. Their posi¬
tion is represented by Brian Hebblethwaite:
ity of people need a power not themselves that makes for righteous¬
ness.5
It is, above all, the love of God which serves both as a motive and as
a reason for the love of neighbor. We should love him because he
first loved us; and we should love others because he loves them. It is
this theme preeminently which explains how it is possible for a man
to turn away from anxious self-concern and identify himself with
the interests of others, however uncongenial those others are, and
even if it runs counter to the prevailing ethos of his society.6
If one both loves God and trusts in God’s love, this will issue in an
inner peace or sense of security. And this, as many religious thinkers
have argued, will free one to take a lively interest in God’s creatures
for their own sake—to enjoy his gifts with un-self-conscious grati¬
tude and to love one’s neighbor. Here a love for God, combined
with faith in him, provides an atmosphere of gladness and security
in which a love for the creature can be encompassed.7
As Adams notes, his view apparently agrees with the biblical un¬
derstanding of Divine love:
seeking personal relations, but also the one who seeks personal re¬
lations only from benevolence, fails to achieve the fullness of love.
And so God, if he exists and is perfectly loving, must also desire
personal relationship with us for its own sake.
This is, it seems to me, an important point. For it allows us to
claim with full assurance that even if our well-being would be as
well served for a time by the existence of a state of affairs entailing
the absence of personal contact with God, God would not on that
account be deterred from seeking personal relationship with us.
His valuing of friendship for its own sake would in every case
prevent him from actualizing the state of affairs in question.12 By
reflecting on our own friendships with other human beings and on
the judgments we are inclined to make with respect to their value
as we grow in them, we can see a little of the intrinsic value God
(if he exists) might be expected to find in personal relationship
with us. But it is only a little. God, infinitely more knowledgeable
and capable of love than we, will, we may expect, see ever so
much more of value in personal relationship with us—the beings
he has (in biblical terms) fashioned in his own image—than we can
see ourselves.
I have been defending the claim that the proper explication of
“God loves human beings” must include the proposition “God
seeks to be personally related to us.” But two very important ques¬
tions about this claim have yet to be addressed: (i) What is the
extension of “us” here? Does this expression refer to all human
beings or only to some? (2) Would a perfectly loving God seek to
be personally related to us only at some future point, perhaps after
death, or already in this life? I will treat these questions in turn.
(1) Although some theologians in times past have seemed to fa¬
vor a contrary view, virtually all contemporary writers would say
that if God’s love is a perfect love, it must extend to everyone
equally—nothing less than unlimited love in this sense would be
worthy of God. Consider, for example, the following passages,
chosen at random:
12. Except, perhaps, insofar as the latter was viewed as an equally great good in
itself or as the necessary condition of such a good.
4] Framing the Argument
13. Karl Barth, God, Grace, and Gospel, J. S. McNab, trans. (Edinburgh: Oliver
and Boyd, 1966), p. 50.
14. Wolfhart Pannenberg, Theology and the Kingdom of God (Philadelphia: West¬
minster Press, 1969), p. 118.
15. Keith Ward, Rational Theology and the Creativity of God (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1982), p. 142.
16. For example, even individuals who have cognitive and affective powers that
are still developing (children) or impaired (the mentally handicapped) may surely
sometimes be said to have a capacity, however limited, for belief in God, grateful¬
ness to God, and so on. Indeed, as the New Testament writer suggests, children
are often the ones who provide our best examples of trusting, grateful, worshipful
attitudes in relation to God (Matthew 19:13-15; 21:16). Of course, there comes a
point when we would wish to say that a capacity for such attitudes does not exist.
Epistemic Implications of Divine Love [
For each created person, the primary source of meaning and satisfac¬
tion will be found in his/her intimate personal relationship with
God. This relationship will also be the context in which a created
person can be best convinced of his/her worth, because it is the
place where God’s love for the individual is most vividly and inti¬
mately experienced. Christians naturally see it as to everyone’s ad¬
vantage to enter into this relationship as deeply as one can in this
world, as soon as possible.'7
But this point is not reached as quickly as my fairly complicated description of this
capacity might seem to suggest.
17. Marilyn McCord Adams, “Forgiveness: A Christian Model,” Faith and Phi¬
losophy, 8 (1991), 291.
6] Framing the Argument
18. The fact that it is at some time a limited capacity does not imply that God
does not wish it to be exercised, for he may have—and if religious claims about
freedom are correct, has—created us this way so that we may have the opportunity
of growing in personal relationship with himself as a result of our own free choices.
19. Perhaps God will also allow some to lose the capacity for a relationship with
him or to suffer a diminished capacity because of, for example, the free actions of
others. I am thinking here of those unfortunate individuals who have been de¬
prived and/or abused in childhood and so are suspicious of everyone, incapable of
trust in man or God. (This fact may, of course, itself constitute a problem of evil,
but it is not the one that concerns us here.)
Epistemic Implications of Divine Love [ 27
20. John Macquarrie, In Search of Humanity (London: SCM Press, 1982), p. 180.
21. John Hick, Faith and Knowledge, 2d ed. (London: Macmillan, 1988), pp.
128-129.
8] Framing the Argument
sions that what was once seen was seen no longer. But if God is
perfectly loving, and treats us as persons, he will, we may suppose,
permit even this extent of freedom over against himself Hence the
clarified claim should read as follows: God will bring it about that,
unless we culpably put ourselves in a contrary position, it is at all
times possible for us to relate personally to him if we so choose.
Or to put it more formally,
22. It is important to note that “capable of’ and “in a position to” are here
understood in such a way that someone might be capable of a personal relationship
with God at a time—have the requisite cognitive and affective machinery—with¬
out being in a position to exercise her capacity at that time and so enter into the
relationship.
Epistemic Implications of Divine Love [ 29
Salvation is not (or at least not primarily) about our future destiny
but about our relationship to God and the gradual transforming ef¬
fect of that relationship in our lives. ... If religious experience is
centrally the sense of the loving presence of God, gradually helping
people to reorient and integrate their lives in accordance with their
love for him, is this not precisely what salvation is? Salvation must,
surely, be religious experience if anything ever is: not in the sense of
being a single climactic experience . . . but in the sense of a gradual
opening of all life, all of experience to the wholemaking love of
God.23
Pi, we can infer that God will seek to bring it about that I am
never in a state of nonbelief. More exactly, we can infer that
26. It might be held that belief is not just necessary but also su fficient to put one
in a position to enter into personal relationship with God, since anyone who has
the relevant emotional and intellectual capacities and believes can, just by choosing
to, contemplate God’s goodness, cultivate a loving and trusting attitude toward
God, and so on. But then, it might be concluded, P2 is in fact equivalent to Pi. I
have considerable sympathy for this claim, but it is not necessary, for our pur¬
poses, to endorse it. And the weaker claim, which is required, is quite obviously
true.
27. The view of belief as “graded” is discussed by Alvin Goldman in Epistemol¬
ogy and Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986). See esp. p.
324. Goldman rejects the graded notion of belief in favor of a categorical one, ac¬
cording to which the onset of belief marks the complete victory of one contender
over all others. My view, it will be noted, is a sort of compromise position.
32 ] Framing the Argument
28. And conversely, God might at times (as we will see) have reason to facilitate
a stronger belief.
29. What I say here is meant to apply both to the initial acquisition of belief and
(should it be retained) to its persistence.
30. This view is defended by Alvin Plantinga. See his “Reason and Belief in
God,” in Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff, eds., Faith and Rationality
(Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 78-79.
34 1 Framing the Argument
32. I do not wish to be taken as suggesting that God would ensure that his
existence was probable on the totality of the evidence that exists—whatever that
might be—or on the public evidence available—that is, on the set of propositions
that provide the premises for arguments in natural theology. All we have seen
reason to suppose (and all that the arguments immediately below suggest) is that
God would bring it about that his existence was probable on S’s evidence; and this
evidence, as we have seen, might well include not only propositions of the sort
mentioned above but certain of S’s experiences too.
33. William Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience
(Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991), p. 74.
36] Framing the Argument
Hence the claim that one could consider one’s evidence and con¬
tinue to believe while not holding it to render the proposition one
believed probable entails that S could believe a contradiction. But
this does not seem to me to be something anyone could do. Hence
that claim is false. But if it is false, we do indeed have additional
reason to suppose that the evidence God would provide would be
probabilifying evidence. For only that way could God ensure
(without deception) that anyone who examined her evidence con¬
tinued to believe.34
Perhaps it will now be objected that while probabilifying evi¬
dence is necessary, it would not be sufficient. Someone might ar¬
gue for this as follows: “For those who consider the evidence, only
the belief that the evidence renders G very probable would be suffi¬
cient to produce the belief that G. And so there could be a situation
in which God provided probabilifying evidence and S saw it as
such, but in which S did not come to believe, or in which S came to
see the evidence on which she believed as probabilifying and forth¬
with ceased to believe. To avoid this, God would have either to
deceive S into supposing the evidence to be stronger than it was or
to provide stronger evidence. But obviously, if perfectly good,
God would not choose the former route. Hence he would choose
the latter. But then we cannot rest content with the claim that God
would provide evidence that rendered his existence probable. We
must, instead, say that he would provide evidence that rendered
his existence very probable.”
In response to this objection, I would suggest that we have good
reason to reject the claim about belief on which it depends. We
might first point out, with Richard Swinburne, that it is “tidier” to
suppose that belief will exist as soon as the probability of the prop¬
osition believed is perceived as greater than o. 5 than to identify the
34. I would add here that on my view, any claim to the effect that S holds that
G is not more probable than not-G and yet (irrationally) believes that G is most
charitably interpreted as ignoring private evidence held by S to favor G, or as
confusing belief with acceptance (a commitment to act-as-if some proposition is
true which does not necessarily involve belief that the proposition is true). It is of
course also possible for S, through self-deception, to lose the belief she once held
that G and not-G are at epistemic parity and come to believe that G is true. But I
can make no sense of the suggestion that S could at one and the same time hold both
that G is not more probable than not-G and that G is true.
Epistemic Implications of Divine Love [3
What accounts for our beliefs, in the vast majority of cases anyway,
is the triggering of one or another such disposition. For example,
we are all so constituted that upon having memory experiences in
certain situations, we are disposed to have certain beliefs about the
past. We are all disposed, upon having certain sensations in certain
situations, to have certain beliefs about the external physical world.
Upon having certain other sensations in certain situations, we are all
disposed to have certain beliefs about other persons. Likewise we
are all so constituted as to be disposed in certain circumstances to
believe what we apprehend people as telling us.37
And a little farther on, he writes: “In addition to the features of our
constitution thus far mentioned, we are all so constituted that upon
judging some proposition which we already believe as being good
35. Richard Swinburne, Faith and Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 5.
36. Nicholas Wolterstorff, “Can Belief in God be Rational?’’ in Alvin Plantinga
and Nicholas Wolterstorff, eds., Faith and Rationality (Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1983), p. 149.
37. Ibid.
38] Framing the Argument
Pi' If God exists and is perfectly loving, then for any human
subject S and time t, if S is at t capable of relating person¬
ally to God, S at t believes that G on the basis of evidence
that renders G probable, except insofar as S is culpably in
a contrary position at f.40
dence, and is it not obvious that many actual believers do not? This point may be
conceded, but it does not cast into question the approach I am taking. For the
claim of the one who argues from inculpable (but poorly grounded) belief to the
nonexistence of God—who emphasizes that a loving God would provide good
evidence—depends on the claim (and arguments for the claim) that God would pro¬
vide evidence at all. The success of my argument, in other words, is a necessary
condition for the success of any argument from inculpable (but poorly grounded)
belief. To put it yet another way, the claim under consideration is really a conjunc¬
tive claim—“God will provide evidence, and the evidence God provides will be
good evidence”—the first conjunct of which must be supported by an argument of
the sort provided in this book. If this argument does not succeed, there is no
reason to suppose that the other will. And if it does succeed, the other will be
superfluous.
41. It may be objected that this conditional is not in fact equivalent to P2'. For
as we have seen, S could be fooled into believing that poor evidence was good and
so might very well find that G was beyond reasonable nonbelief for her—might
find that she could not reject it without resisting what she took to be good evi¬
dence—without it being the case that G was in fact rendered probable by her
evidence. I will simply assume, however, that what is meant by “G is beyond
reasonable nonbelief for S” is “5 can only fail to believe that G on good evidence
culpably,” in which case the equivalence holds.
40 ] Framing the Argument
Love in its truly personal sense is . . . the ceding and the unfolding
of one’s inmost self to and for the other in love. [God wishes to
enter] into unrestricted personal communion with man. [P. 134]
Opening Arguments
ing to some degree the proposition that there is a God. And surely
no one could reasonably deny that such phenomena do render the
existence of God at least somewhat more likely than it would oth¬
erwise be. The second point (which will be seen to complement
the first) is that our evidential situation is not the only one that
could have obtained. This follows from the obvious truth that ours
is not the only possible world. We can conceive of a great many
ways in which our world might have been different. But then,
surely, the evidential situation of humans vis-a-vis God’s existence could
have been different as well: every contingently existing thing in the
world is relevant to the question whether there is a Creator, and so
if the world changes, the evidence changes too.
These points, when taken in tandem, would seem to provide a
certain amount of initial support for the claim under consideration.
If we accept that the evidence actually available to individuals in
our world goes some way toward showing that there is a God, and
accept as well that there are innumerable ways in which the world
(and ipso facto the evidence) could have been different, then it
seems we have some reason to accept that there is a possible world
in which stronger evidence is available—in particular, in which indi¬
viduals are always in the presence of evidence sufficient for belief.
create a world without evil or with much less evil, but while this
might remove an important obstacle to belief, it is not clear that it
would make the required positive contribution to the epistemic cir¬
cumstances of everyone concerned. In any case, I wish to show
that a strong epistemic situation in relation to theism is compatible
with the existence of much evil. Overwhelming miracles may also
be possible, but miracles are by definition rare events, and so it is
not easy to see how the sort of evidence they might provide could
be generally and at all times available, as a strong epistemic situa¬
tion requires. Furthermore, I wish to show that God need not
overwhelm us in order to elicit belief, and to prove that the de¬
scription of a state of affairs of the sort in question need not be
theologically crude, as a description involving reference to Di¬
vinely produced spectacular events would no doubt seem to many
to be.
A more fruitful approach, I suggest, would focus on the possible
epistemic contribution of religious experience.3 Experiential evi¬
dence, as we will see, could be generally and at all times available.
It is also more likely to be religiously efficacious—to stimulate a
religiously appropriate response. I may, if I am presented with a
good argument or witness a spectacular miracle, conclude that
there is a God, but if God is present to me in experience, my re¬
sponse (if I respond positively at all) is perhaps more likely to be
the personal response a loving God would desire. Related to this is
the point that it is only religious experience that makes possible the
deepest forms of personal relationship between God and human¬
kind.4 Although perhaps not necessary for such relationship, reli¬
gious experience must obviously enrich it and contribute to its
flourishing.
Suppose, then, that the world is one in which all human beings
who evince a capacity for personal relationship with God have an
experience as of God presenting himself to them, which they take
to be caused by God and which actually is caused by God present-
3. I do not assume that this is the only line of thought it would be profitable to
pursue in this context, but, as I argue, it does seem an appropriate one.
4. On this point, see William Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Reli¬
gious Experience (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 303-304. This
impressive book is full of insights on our topic and has stimulated my thinking in a
variety of ways.
Is a Strong Epistemic Situation Possible? [ 49
6. See Maurice Wiles, God’s Action in the World (London: SCM Press, 1986) for
a statement and defense of such a view.
Is a Strong Epistemic Situation Possible? [ 5
7. Remember, we are not asking whether actual experiences of God have oc¬
curred or whether it is reasonable for persons who have actually had religious expe¬
riences to view them as providing contact with God. What we are asking is
whether it should be deemed possible for God to bring human beings to awareness
of himself.
8. Some might argue that while my points show that an apparent awareness of
God could occur early on, we have no reason to suppose that anyone could actually
recognize at this stage (or perhaps any other) the presence of a being exemplifying
the collection of properties God is said to possess. But there is considerable support
in the literature for the view that such attributes could be directly given in experi¬
ence. See, for example, Swinburne, Existence of God, pp. 267-268; Gary Gutting,
Religious Belief and Religious Skepticism (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1982), pp. 153— 155; Alston, Perceiving God, pp. 17, 59-63; and George
Mavrodes, Revelation in Religious Belief (Philadelphia: Temple University Press,
1988), pp. 104-109. Mavrodes defends the notion of “basic cognitive acts” analo¬
gous to basic physical acts. Earlier in his book (p. 94), Mavrodes makes what
seems to me to be one of the central points here: “What kinds of experience there
are [is] itself a matter of experience.”
52 ] Framing the Argument
those who did not resist it, the judgment of experients with respect
to God’s presence would (barring steps taken to remove belief)
surely be maintained indefinitely and, indeed, reinforced—even in
the face of evils such as our world contains. One’s own experience
is a very powerful stimulus to belief; only under strong pressure
from outside forces will what is suggested by it be rejected.
Suppose, however, that some experients came to view evil (or
some other apparent counterevidence) as a threat. As we have seen,
there are degrees of experiential force and of belief, and so it would
be possible for the force of the experience in such circumstances to
be increased. God might allow the individuals in question to feel
his presence more strongly—or at least strongly enough to sustain
a certain degree of belief. Furthermore, if a state of affairs of the
sort I have described were to obtain, much of the additional evi¬
dence—in particular, the public evidence concerning the distribu¬
tion and uniformity of this form of experience—would seem to
confirm the judgments of the individual with respect to her experi¬
ence and its epistemic implications. This apparent confirmation,
together with what has already been described, would, it seems to
me, prevent the problem of evil or any other objection from over¬
whelming the subject’s belief (provided, of course, that she did not
take steps to hide from herself her experience and this apparent
confirmation).9
Now even if the state of affairs I have sketched is a possible one,
it may be that its description does not entail the proposition in
question, namely (when completely spelled out), “God has
brought it about that for any subject S and time t, if S is at t
capable of relating personally to God, S at t believes that G on the
basis of evidence that renders G probable, except insofar as 5 is
culpably in a contrary position at t.” In particular, it may be that
even if S in fact believes because of her evidence, including the
evidence of religious experience, that evidence does not render G
probable.
10. Alvin Plantinga, “Reason and Belief in God,” in Alvin Plantinga and
Nicholas Wolterstorff, eds., Faith and Rationality (Notre Dame: University of No¬
tre Dame Press, 1983), p. 72.
11. Richard Swinburne, “Does Theism Need a Theodicy?” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy, 18 (1988), 292.
54 ] Framing the Argument
17. Alston, Perceiving God, p. 275. The arguments of Swinburne, Gutting, and
Alston seem to involve the claim that the justification provided for religious beliefs
(in the actual world) by religious experience is analogous to the justification pro¬
vided for sensory beliefs by sensory experience. This analogy argument is sub¬
jected to detailed criticism by Richard Gale, in On the Nature and Existence of God
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), chap. 8. But Alston has replied
to Gale by pointing out that the important analogies do hold: the belief-forming
practice in question is socially established; it has a “functioning overrider system”;
no reasons for judging the practice to be unreliable are sufficient; and the practice
enjoys “a significant degree of self-support” (Perceiving God, p. 224). Hence, Al¬
ston concludes, it is rational for persons to form beliefs on the basis of religious
experience in the absence of specific overriding considerations. It seems to me that
whatever may be true of the actual world, were individuals in the possible world I
am describing to avail themselves of Alston’s premises (as well as the many argu¬
ments he offers in their support), adding to them the important points I have been
emphasizing with respect to universality and uniformity—points unavailable to
Alston, which strengthen the analogy with sense experience—they surely would
be justified in drawing his conclusion.
Is a Strong Epistemic Situation Possible? [ 57
18. Anyone who thinks that this position is incorrect may add other evidence or
postulate further Divine action, as appropriate. (For an interesting discussion of
how religious experience may interact with other grounds of religious belief, see
Alston, Perceiving God, chap. 8.) But for myself, I do not think such additions to
the picture are necessary.
19. Note that I have not argued that God should bring to our attention every
piece of evidence normally considered relevant to the question of God’s existence.
This would entail God making philosophers of religion of us all, and then the
world would be in a sorry state! Rather, I have pictured a state of affairs in which
every human being is given at least the evidence of experience described, and have
argued that given any amount of subsequent inquiry, this would be sufficient, in
the absence of resistance, to sustain belief.
[ 3 ]
The Reasonableness
of Nonbelief
blame is laid for morally repugnant beliefs per se, it may derive
from neglect of the possibility that the individuals in question are
constitutionally defective in some way and so not really subject to
blame.11
For these reasons, I suggest we need not accept Adams’s exam¬
ples as indicative of the truth of his position.12 And therefore the
claim that we are only culpable for voluntary epistemic failures lead¬
ing up to belief—in particular, for voluntarily neglecting proper in¬
vestigative procedures—can be upheld. Applying this to the ques¬
tion of inculpable religious doubt, we obtain the following:
15. See Anthony Kenny, Faith and Reason (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1983), pp. 87-88.
16. Prominent contemporary examples include Anthony Kenny and Ronald
Hepburn. See ibid., p. 85, and Ronald Hepburn, Christianity and Paradox (London:
Watts, 1966), p. 1.
68 ] Framing the Argument
I look around in every direction and all I see is darkness. Nature has
nothing to offer me that does not give rise to doubt and anxiety. If I
saw no sign there of a Divinity I should decide on a negative solu¬
tion: if I saw signs of a creator everywhere I should peacefully settle
down in the faith. But seeing too much to deny and not enough to
affirm, I am in a pitiful state, where I have wished a hundred times
over that, if there is a God supporting nature, she should unequivo¬
cally proclaim him, and that, if the signs in nature are deceptive,
they should say all or nothing so that I could see what course I
ought to follow. Instead of that, in the state in which I am, not
knowing what I am or what I ought to do, I know neither my
condition nor my duty. My whole heart strains to know what the
true good is in order to pursue it: no price would be too high to pay
for eternity.17
18. Eberhart Jiingel, God as the Mystery of the World, Darrel L. Coden, trans.
(Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1983), p. 4.
19. Karl Rahner, “Atheism and Implicit Christianity,” in G. A. McCool, ed., A
Rahner Reader (London: Darton, Longman, and Todd, 1975), pp. 221-222. Rahner
himself, as the context indicates, was wholly in favor of this view.
70 ] Framing the Argument
20. This phrase, as far as I know, originates in John Hick’s writings. For more
on Hick and religious ambiguity, see Chapter 5.
21. John Macquarrie, Thinking about God (London: SCM Press, 1975), p. 119.
22. See Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: Chicago
University Press, 1962).
23. James W. McClendon and James M. Smith, Understanding Religious Convic¬
tions (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), p. 117.
24. George Lindbeck, The Nature of Doctrine (Philadelphia: Westminster Press,
1984), p. 11.
25. See Thomas Morris, Anselmian Explorations (Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1987), p. 203.
The Reasonableness of Nonbelief
26. See the review by Thomas Morris of Anthony O’Hear’s Experience, Expla¬
nation, and Faith, in Faith and Philosophy, 2 (1985), 316.
27. See, for example, Langdon Gilkey, Naming the Whirlwind: The Renewal of
God-Language (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1969), part 2, chaps. 3
and 4.
] Framing the Argument
and thus, all things considered, they do not consider epistemic parity
to obtain.28
That this is also the correct interpretation where the theistic be¬
liefs of many Christian philosophers of religion are concerned is
strongly suggested by their writings. Stephen Davis, who accepts
the ambiguity view, refers explicitly to the distinction between
public and private evidence and argues in favor of the rationality of
believing on the basis of the latter when the former is inconclusive.29
Some of the more recent arguments of John Hick, Alvin Plantinga,
William Alston, and others on the relations between religious ex¬
perience and the justification of religious belief also lend themselves
to this interpretation.30 The claim of these writers is that experi¬
ences apparently of God, although they may count for little when
publically reported (because they only provide a basis for weak
inductive arguments), may provide the experient with good
grounds for belief in God.31 It is argued that such experiences must
be understood by analogy with sensory experiences and the justi¬
fication of the corresponding beliefs by analogy with the justifica¬
tion of sensory beliefs. I would suggest that what this shows is that
the philosophers in question may, however implicitly, be treating
their religious experiences as relevant evidence, and may therefore
(all things considered) be believing that there is a God while con¬
tinuing to believe that the public evidence (including such proposi¬
tions as “religious experiences have been reported in various parts
of the world”) is indecisive. As George Mavrodes writes, after giv¬
ing voice to the skeptical feelings many have about accepting the
28. Indeed, we can deduce the claim that the individuals in question consider
themselves to have private evidence from the following statements, all of which
are true: (1) that anyone who investigates the support for G can only believe that G
if she believes G to be more probable than not; (2) that the individuals in question
believe that G; (3) that they believe the public evidence to support only a parity
judgment.
29. Stephen Davis, Faith, Skepticism, and Evidence (Lewisburg, Pa.: Bucknell
University Press, 1978).
30. See John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion (London: Macmillan, 1989),
chap. 13; Plantinga, “Reason and Belief’; and William Alston, Perceiving God: The
Epistemology of Religious Experience (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1991).
31. It should be noted that Swinburne, who accepts a similar view, is not as
pessimistic as many others about the value of religious experience as public evi¬
dence.
The Reasonableness of Nonbelief [ 73
available to everyone, and that where it has not brought about belief
in God’s existence, this is because of the sinful resistance of the
nonbeliever.34 We have, therefore, the following objection to the
view I am defending: doubt is never inculpable because it is always
a result of sin. It is to a discussion of this objection that I now turn.
34. This view, it will be noted, entails that a situation much like that described
in Chapter 2 in fact obtains.
35- John Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion, Lewis Battles Ford, trans.
(Philadelphia: Westminster Press, i960), book 1, chap. 3, p. 43.
36. Plantinga, “Reason and Belief,” p. 78.
The Reasonableness of Nonbelief [ 75
37. Mark R. Talbot, “Is It Natural to Believe in God?” Faith and Philosophy, 6
(1989), 166, 168, 161, 165, 168. As far as I am aware, Talbot’s is the only piece of
76 ] Framing the Argument
43. I have argued that the believer’s experience gives her no good reason to
affirm the conditional in question. If this is correct, then, a fortiori, the believer’s
80 ] Framing the Argument
experience fails to provide the nonbeliever with any appreciable reason for affirm¬
ing the conditional, and Talbot’s claim (ibid., 168) that it does provide such reason
is to be rejected.
The Reasonableness of Nonbelief [8
tion, should provoke the believer to the realization that her claim
lacks justification.
What about the second objection? This, as will be recalled, was
that the believer must factor in, as relevant evidence, the unbe¬
liever’s positive reasons for taking a contrary view. Is this question¬
begging? Talbot’s argument in defense of an affirmative answer
seems to run as follows: “By claiming that the believer is not justi¬
fied in making her claim unless she takes his reasons for accepting
its denial into account, the unbeliever assumes that his reasoning is
not unreliable. But given the truth of the believer’s claim, the un¬
believer’s reasoning in this context is unreliable.44 Hence the unbe¬
liever, in making his objection, presupposes the falsehood of the
believer’s claim and so begs the question.” Let us suppose that the
second premise here is true—that the unbeliever’s reasoning in this
context is unreliable if the believer’s claim is true. Even then, we
may show that Talbot’s conclusion need not be accepted, for his
first premise is false. (Or rather, it is false under the interpretation
required to generate the conclusion.) The unbeliever clearly must
not assume that his reasoning is “not unreliable” in the sense of “in
fact reliable” when the proposition at issue entails the unreliability
of his reasoning. Otherwise his argument is indeed question-beg¬
ging. But why should we suppose that the unbeliever needs to as¬
sume this in order to claim that the believer is not justified in
making her claim unless she takes his reasons for denying it into
account? All he need assume is that it has not been shown that his
reasoning is unreliable—that it is at the start of the investigation an
open question whether the contrary-to-fact conditional at issue is
true or not, and that his arguments are for this reason not justifia¬
bly viewed as less likely to be reliable than the believer’s, and
should therefore be taken into account.45 It is clearly compatible
with this assumption that the believer’s claim is true (for the unbe¬
liever allows that his reasoning may be unreliable). Hence the un-
44. The context suggests that what Talbot means is that given the truth of the
believer’s claim, the unbeliever’s reasoning is of an unreliable type, that is, that the
unbeliever is qua sinner unreliable in his reasoning.
45. After all, it is not as though the reliability of the unbeliever’s reasoning is
less likely than it would otherwise be just by virtue of the question of its reliability
being raised! At the beginning of investigation there is by definition no presumption
in favor of either claim.
82 ] Framing the Argument
46. An additional point is that if in the face of the evidence, believers confi¬
dently claim that all doubt is due to the sinful rejection of belief, they display the
very fault they claim to find in the nonbeliever—moral insensitivity. On the unbe¬
liever’s alleged moral insensitivity, see Talbot, “Is it Natural to Believe?” 168.
[ 4 ]
A Summation of the Case
have served as well or better here. But some of the propositions I will be consider¬
ing seem necessarily true if true at all (e.g., propositions claiming that one state of
affairs is a greater good than another), and there is some doubt as to the appli¬
cability of terms like “probable as not” to necessary propositions: such proposi¬
tions are commonly viewed as having a probability of 1. Therefore, I have chosen
to speak in terms of reasons for and against. This language, it seems to me, is
clearly applicable to inductive evidence capturable by the probability calculus but is
appropriate as well where arguments for and against the necessity of a proposition
are concerned, since we do commonly speak of having reasons for believing some
proposition to be necessary.
3. It must be a state of affairs whose existence logically necessitates the permis¬
sion of reasonable nonbelief, for otherwise an omnipotent God could (and a per¬
fectly loving God would) bring it about without permitting the occurrence of rea¬
sonable nonbelief.
86 ] Framing the Argument
4. I say that it must be logically necessary that God permit the occurrence of
reasonable nonbelief, meaning by this, not that it must be logically necessary that
God bring about reasonable nonbelief, but that it must be logically necessary that
God bring about or allow the occurrence of reasonable nonbelief. Only by confusing
the denial of (2) (viz., “It is not the case that if God exists, reasonable nonbelief
does not occur”) with the stronger claim “If God exists, reasonable nonbelief oc¬
curs” could we be led to suppose that “permit” must here be read as “bring
about.” This point is an important one, for it implies that not only goods that
require the actual existence of reasonable nonbelief (and so God’s bringing it about
that reasonable nonbelief occurs) are relevant here, but also goods that require for
their existence only that God allow the occurrence of reasonable nonbelief (by,
e.g., leaving it up to human beings to determine whether reasonable nonbelief will
occur or not). Cf. the discussion of the Responsibility Argument in Chapter 7.
5. See, for example, Bruce Russell, “The Persistent Problem of Evil,” Faith and
Philosophy, 6 (1989), 122. As Russell points out (129), “good” and “good state of
affairs” must in the context of discussions like this be construed fairly broadly.
God might permit an evil to occur “to fulfill a duty or to satisfy some other deon-
tological requirement,” or to prevent “an even worse evil from occurring.”
6. See William L. Rowe, “The Empirical Argument from Evil,” in Robert
Audi and William J. Wainwright, eds., Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Com¬
mitment (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1986), p. 229.
A Summation of the Case [87
7. I, at any rate, will assume that we may be certain of this. In making this
assumption, it will be noted, I am only making it easier for my argument to be
rebutted.
88 ] Framing the Argument
8. Correspondingly, a rebuttal attempt of this sort fails if and only if (i) there is
good reason to suppose that there is no necessary connection between the obtain¬
ing of the state of affairs in question and the reasonableness of nonbelief, and/or (ii)
there is good reason to suppose that the state of affairs does not constitute an
outweighing good and it is no more than plausible that the state of affairs consti¬
tutes an offsetting good.
9. See Stephen Wykstra, “The Humean Obstacle to Evidential Arguments
from Suffering: On Avoiding the Evils of‘Appearance’,” International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion, 16 (1984), 73-93. See also Bruce Russell and Stephen Wyk¬
stra, “The ‘Inductive’ Argument from Evil: A Dialogue,” Philosophical Topics, 16
(1988), 133-160.
A Summation of the Case [ 89
10. Bruce Russell has recently leveled just this sort of criticism against the origi¬
nal Wykstra argument. See Russell and Wykstra, “‘Inductive’ Argument from
Evil,” 147-148, 154. For the reasons given immediately below, it does not seem to
me to succeed.
90 ] Framing the Argument
there is a God, and it seems clear that it has much less in its favor
than the first. It is to be expected, perhaps, that a God would
know of kinds of goodness that are impossible for us to under¬
stand. But why should this lead us to suppose that evils like that of
the reasonableness of nonbelief, with which we are intimately ac¬
quainted, in fact serve such goods if God exists? If there is a per¬
fectly good and loving God, he has, in creating, sacrificed his own
interests and taken on ours. We can therefore infer with some con¬
fidence that the goods many evils serve, if God exists, are human
goods—goods related to our “salvation.” But if so related, it seems
unlikely that they, or their relation to evil, should be impossible
for us to grasp. Goods of the latter sort we might expect to be
totally unrelated to the vicissitudes of human life.
Applying a point made by William Rowe, we might also point
out that the goods for the sake of which God would permit evil to
occur would likely be “goods that either are or include good expe¬
riences” of the human beings in question. God, we might suppose,
would not subject anyone to evil who was not to “figure signifi¬
cantly in the good” for the sake of which it was permitted. But
then we might expect to know of the goods evils serve, for “the
conscious experiences of others are among the sorts of things we
do know.”11
We should consider, finally, the great specificity of the claim that
reasonable nonbelief will serve inscrutable goods if God exists. The
claim that there are some evils (we don’t know which) that will
appear pointless if there is a God may not be clearly false, but
when it is made on behalf of the occurrence of reasonable nonbelief
in particular, we should be much less sanguine. Suppose that it is as
likely as not (despite criticisms like those mentioned above) that if
there is a God, at any rate some evils of human experience serve
inscrutable goods. How can we know, with regard to the occur¬
rence of reasonable nonbelief, that it is a member of this class? With¬
out independent information bearing on the question, we would
have to say, “Well, it might belong to that group, but then again it
might not.” Hence the probability that reasonable nonbelief will be
apparently pointless if God exists would seem to be at most half
that of the proposition that some instances of evil will be so. But
then, given that we can surely say no more than that the latter
proposition is as probable as not, the probability of the claim that
reasonable nonbelief will be apparently pointless if God exists is
clearly too low for rational acceptance.
The Wykstra-style objection, therefore, appears not to provide
any reason to suppose that the inductive inference in question is
unjustified. Accordingly, should we turn up no consideration of
the sort required, we might indeed be justified in concluding on
that ground that none exists, and that premise (2) of A is true. It
must now be noted, however, that even if this objection were
shown to be correct, A's claim to the status of a prima facie case
would not be imperiled. For even if the evidence of our inability to
find any goods of the sort in question does not permit the inference
that there are none, and so we cannot draw this conclusion from
the failure of the arguments of Part 2 or in this way show that (2) is
true, we may still infer from the failure of these arguments that we
have no reason to deny (2); hence, given the point made earlier (from
which the Wykstra argument has momentarily diverted our atten¬
tion), should these arguments fail, we would still be in a position
to conclude that (2) (and so (5)) is true. As I have argued, there is
considerable reason to affirm (2), which establishes a presumption
in its favor. Accordingly, if the denial of (2) is not shown to be at
least plausible, we must accept the claim that (2) is true as much
better substantiated than the claim that it is false, in other words, as
more probable than not. Against this, it seems, Wykstra could
have nothing to say. His argument (even if successful) does not
provide any reason to believe that the relevant goods exist; it only
provides reason to suppose that our inability to find them is not
evidence that they do not exist, and the denial of the latter claim is
not essential to my case.
This brings me to my final point. I have been claiming that un¬
less a rebuttal for A can be provided—that is, unless it can be
shown plausible to suppose that there are countervailing considera¬
tions of the sort characterized above—its conclusion, that God
does not exist, goes through. I will be looking at various argu¬
ments that may provide such a rebuttal in Part 2. What I wish to
point out is that our discussion in this chapter has clarified both
92 ] Framing the Argument
12. This, at any rate, is the case if our assumption that neither theism nor athe¬
ism is clearly better-evidenced than its denial is accepted. There will be more on
this in the Conclusion.
Part 2
So far in the book my concern has been to show that the argu¬
ment from the reasonableness of nonbelief is a successful prima
facie argument—that in the absence of countervailing considera¬
tions, the reasonableness of nonbelief shows the nonexistence of
God. Now in Part 2 I take up the question whether any such con¬
siderations can be adduced. As was mentioned in the Introduction,
not all of the considerations in the literature that are relevant to the
answering of this question have been given a clear shape in the past
or are applicable as they stand, and so my procedure is to clarify
and adapt them as I go along. Questions of interpretation of course
inevitably arise in a project of this sort, but I wish to make clear at
the outset that my main aim is to get as many relevant arguments
out into the open as possible, and to assess their force according to
the criterion for rebuttal set out in Chapter 4. This is not to say
that I do not attempt to determine, in individual cases, what
writers have claimed, but where their intent is unclear, I move
quickly to talk of “possible” arguments. For our purposes, it does
not ultimately matter whether some argument is actually to be at¬
tributed to a writer or not. If it is an argument suggested by his
writing which can be turned into a possible rebuttal, I will consider
it. A corollary of this procedural point is that there is here no chro¬
nological ordering of arguments or detailed historical discussion.
Where there is a reason for the ordering of arguments, it has more
96 ] The Force of the Argument
very close connection between the belief that there is a God and
belief in God that he sometimes focuses on the importance of free¬
dom in respect of the former.
This interpretation, of course, requires elucidation and defense. I
will begin with the point about Hick’s notion of cognitive free¬
dom.
It is Hick’s talk (apparently in connection with the acquisition of
theistic belief) of “cognitive decisions” and “acts of interpretation”
which seems to suggest the view that belief in the existence of God
is under our direct voluntary control.10 He writes in Faith and
Knowledge that “our knowledge of God ... is not given to us as a
compulsory perception, but is achieved as a voluntary act of inter¬
pretation.”11 And in An Interpretation of Religion a similar view is
expressed: “Faith as interpretation is ... a cognitive decision in
face of an intrinsically ambiguous universe” (p. 159).
We need not look far, however, to note that there appears to be
some confusion in Hick’s account over exactly what this “act of
interpretation” or “cognitive decision” amounts to; in particular,
over whether it is truly voluntary. For example, in Faith and
Knowledge (p. 102) he defines “interpretation” as a “recognition,”
“attribution,” or “perception” of “significance” (a significance at¬
taching, in the religious case, to the world as a whole). These
terms (with the possible exception of “attribution”) suggest that
interpretation is involuntary, but, despite the apparent incongruity,
Hick refers in the same breath to interpretation as an uact of recog¬
nition” (p. 102, my emphasis).12
10. Some writers not only may be influenced by Hick’s talk of cognitive deci¬
sions and the like, but may infer from his claim that religious belief must not be
forced upon us that, on his view, such belief should be (and is) under our (direct)
voluntary control. That this would be an illicit inference is clear; the view in ques¬
tion should not be the only one to occur to someone questing about for alterna¬
tives to intellectual coercion. Hick himself, as we will see, takes a less directly
voluntarist stance, but one compatible with the claim that we are not forced into
belief.
11. John Hick, Faith and Knowledge, 2d ed. (London: Macmillan, 1988), p. 121.
Further references to this work will be made parenthetically in the text.
12. Perhaps in order to soften the incongruity, Hick suggests that recognition
may be correct or incorrect, but this seems odd, to say the least. Later in the same
work, however (e.g., p. 115), it is clear that he is vacillating between a theo¬
logically committed and an ontologically neutral account.
i oo ] The Force of the Argument
13. It may seem to some that this quotation, with its interesting distinction
between a “basic” act of interpretation which, so to speak, gets us started, and
more detailed interpretations which presuppose it, holds out a way of harmonizing
the (seemingly) incompatible emphases in Hick’s account. Perhaps the basic act of
interpretation is voluntary even if the others are not. This way of resolving the
problem is ultimately unsatisfactory, however. For Hick often recognizes no such
distinction, speaking of all our interpretive activity, both basic and nonbasic, in
involuntarist language (see, for example, Faith and Knowledge, pp. no, in, 114-
115).
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ ioi
14. In this passage, it will be noted, the “cognitive decision” is said to be uncon¬
scious, and this is added reason to suppose that on Hick’s view, the primary “act”
of interpretation is not to be identified with the formation of belief, for belief (as he
implies) is given in and along with religious experience, and “experience” is earlier
defined by him as “a modification of the content of consciousness” (Interpretation of
Religion, p. 153).
102 ] The Force of the Argument
15. In the first part of this passage, Hick is describing a possible view, but the
context clearly indicates that he endorses it.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 103
16. John Hick, Arguments for the Existence of God (London: Macmillan, 1970), p.
114.
17. One of the merits of this interpretation of Hick is that it makes sense of his
repeated endorsement of Pascal’s claim that God “so regulates the knowledge of
Himself that He has given signs of Himself, visible to those who seek Him, and
not to those who seek Him not.” (The reference to Pascal is found in, e.g., Hick,
Faith and Knowledge, p. 141.)
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 105
The infinite nature of the Deity requires him to veil himself from
us if we are to exist as autonomous persons in his presence. For to
know God is ... to know the One ... in whose will lies our final
good and blessedness . . . , whose commands come with the accent
of absolute and unconditional demand. . . .
Clearly, to become aware of the existence of such a being must
affect us in a manner to which the awareness of other human per¬
sons can offer only a remote parallel. . . . [The believer’s] life must
become consciously reorientated towards a Being infinitely superior
to himself in worth as well as in power. There is thus involved a
radical reordering of his outlook as must be undergone willingly if it
is not to crush and even destroy the personality. . . . Only when we
ourselves voluntarily recognize God, desiring to enter into relation¬
ship with him, can our knowledge of him be compatible with our
freedom, and so with our existence as personal beings. . . .
If man is to be personal, God must be deus absconditus. . . . He
desires, not a compelled obedience but our uncoerced growth to¬
wards the humanity revealed in Christ. [Pp. 133-135]
Summing it all up a few pages later, Hick writes: “The reason why
God reveals himself indirectly—meeting us in and through the
world as mediating a significance which requires an appropriate
response on our part . . .—is that only thus can the conditions exist
for a personal relationship between God and man” (p. 140).
It would seem, therefore, that Hick is primarily concerned not
with cognitive freedom but with moral freedom—freedom with re¬
spect to belief in God. Our love, trust, and obedience must be
freely given; otherwise God’s intention to relate to us as persons
cannot be fulfilled. But this should not be taken to imply that he
106 ] The Force of the Argument
18. One criticism of Hick I will not consider is that he reaches his conclusion
only by focusing too narrowly on religious experience. Hick himself has distin¬
guished between theoretical proofs and religious experience, arguing that only the
latter could remove human freedom (Arguments for God, pp. 105-107), and so
would seem clearly to be open to such an objection. But as I argued in Chapter 2,
there seems to be some reason to suppose that, were God to put his existence
beyond reasonable nonbelief, he would do so by means of religious experience.
And so it will be important to see whether Hick’s argument succeeds when stated
in those terms.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 109
20. Anthony Kenny, Faith and Reason (New York: Columbia University Press,
1983), p. 77-
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [in
21. Terence Penelhum, God and Skepticism (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983), pp. in —
112.
22. Ibid., p. no.
23. Terence Penelhum, “The Analysis of Faith in St. Thomas Aquinas,” in Ter¬
ence Penelhum, ed., Faith (New York: Macmillan, 1989), p. 132.
11 2 ] The Force of the Argument
24. On this (alleged) difference, see Hick, Arguments for God, pp. 105-107.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [in
which the physical world is disclosed to us” (p. 134). But this view
must be rejected, for it suggests that any slight change in our actual
situation with respect to the distribution and forcefulness of reli¬
gious experience would place us in the immediate presence of God,
and this is clearly false. Hick himself (at other times) recognizes
that it is false. Indeed, he argues that it is precisely to avoid this
sort of proximity to the Divine that we are created as part of a
physical universe in the first place:
This suggests that only in another life could we experience the di¬
rect presence of God (and Hick seems unsure at times whether ex¬
perience of God will be unmediated even then; see Faith and Knowl¬
edge, p. 187, and Interpretation of Religion, p. 179). In this life,
because of the physical “screen” between ourselves and God, we
cannot expect our experience to be of that kind:
29. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979),
pp. 153, 154, 157, 159.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 117
30. Hick puts so much emphasis on the need for freedom that he fails to note
that unlimited freedom would be as much a problem as no freedom at all—that it
would rule out the sort of difficult and gradual development toward personhood
that he, like Swinburne, considers to be of great value. Because of this, he is
prevented from seeing the possibility of a “prudential” argument of the kind Swin¬
burne advances. There is also an independent reason for supposing that he fails to
see this, namely, that he distinguishes between theoretical proofs and religious
experience, arguing that only the latter could remove human freedom (Arguments
for God, pp. 105-107). If he had seen the possibility of a prudential argument, he
would surely not have insisted on this distinction. For, clearly, proofs could indi¬
cate the path of prudence as well as religious experience, and (assuming that pru¬
dential reasons would have the force assigned to them by the Prudential Argu¬
ment) would therefore remove human freedom just as effectively.
31. Richard Swinburne, “Knowledge from Experience, and the Problem of
Evil,” in William J. Abraham and Steven W. Holtzer, eds., The Rationality of Reli¬
gious Belief (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).
11 8 ] The Force of the Argument
they would have the punishment of knowing that their bad actions
were known to God. They could no longer pose as respectable citi¬
zens; God would be too evident a member of the community. Fur¬
ther, in seeing God, as it were, face to face, men would see him to
be good and worshipful, and hence would have every reason for
conforming to his will. In such a world men would have little temp¬
tation to do wrong—it would be the mark of both prudence and
reason to do what was virtuous. Yet a man only has a genuine
choice of destiny if he has reasons for pursuing either good or evil
courses of action; for ... a man can only perform an action which
he has some reason to do.32
in this sense, for such knowledge would bring with it strong rea¬
sons for not doing evil—reasons stemming ultimately from desires
for our well-being, for example, the desire not to be punished.
Prudential reasons of this sort would in such a situation swing us
strongly in the direction of good action—it would require little in
the way of an act of will to master desires to do evil—and so a
genuine choice of destiny would not be open to us.34
Before I assess the force of this argument (as well as that of an¬
other, apparently independent, argument for the “no choice of des¬
tiny” conclusion to be found in the first passage quoted above),
two points should be noted. First, what Swinburne hints at in the
first passage (by saying little temptation) but does not bring out is
that, even in the state of affairs he has described, desires to perform
actions seen to be wrong would not simply vanish’, although such
desires would, if he is right, be rendered inefficacious by all the
reasons available for not doing evil (reasons stemming from strong
prudential desires), they might be expected to persist. As Swin¬
burne himself writes in The Evolution of the Soul, “the agent still
finds himself ready geared to do the action, even when he believes
it immoral,” and “it is the fate of humans that the inclinations to
act needed for enjoyment still move towards action (make the ac¬
tion easier, more natural to do) when the agent believes the action
overall bad.”35
Examples bring this out. If I strongly desire to go to the univer¬
sity bookstore to buy a volume that has just come out on the
shelves but recognize that in so doing I will fail to prepare ade¬
quately for an important lecture, my desire for the lesser good will
not simply disappear. I will do what I see as the better act (if I do it
at all) somewhat reluctantly, still feeling the pressure of my con¬
trary desire. This example can be made more directly relevant to
the present discussion as well. If I am told by someone who has
taken it upon himself to keep the book of which I desire a copy out
of the hands of the reading public that he will cause me serious
bodily harm if I go to the bookstore, and if I am certain that the
threat will be carried out if I do go, I will likely not go to the
know for certain that there is a God and in which whatever reasons
humans take themselves to have for doing good actions they con¬
sider themselves to certainly have. A situation in which the evidence
available is sufficient for belief (i.e., as we have seen, probabilify-
ing) is, however, not of this sort, and it is the latter situation that
must be shown to be problematic if the prima facie case of Part i is
to be rebutted. To assess the force of Swinburne’s argument in the
context of our discussion, therefore, we must take it to refer to
evidence sufficient for belief, and ask whether it is plausibly viewed
as sound when construed this way.
For the sake of argument, let us, for the moment, concede to
Swinburne the truth of (18). This leaves (16) and (17). Are these
premises plausibly viewed as true? Is it plausible to think of the
reasons in question as ones that humans would, given evidence
sufficient for belief, consider themselves to have (i.e., as pertinent)?
And are they plausibly viewed as strong enough to overwhelm
desires for bad actions (i.e., as efficacious)? The reasons in question
are, it seems, primarily reasons deriving from the belief that God
preserves human beings insofar as they do what is right, and more
specifically, that bad actions will be punished by God. Are these
reasons pertinent? And would they be efficacious? Let us begin
with the second question.
Unfortunately, Swinburne is less than clear (in the passages con¬
cerned) on how the relevant notion of punishment is to be under¬
stood. Does it, for example, imply punishment for each bad action
at the time at which it is performed, or only punishment in the
distant future, perhaps after death? And what is the nature of this
punishment? Bodily harm in the here and now or hellfire in the
hereafter or a progressively deteriorating quality of character lead¬
ing to eventual annihilation or. . . ?37 Clearly, to know whether the
reasons associated with punishment would be efficacious, we need
to know more about the form that punishment might be expected
to take. Swinburne comments: “whatever punishment is just.” But
this leaves the question wide open. ITuman beings, it seems, might
very well conceive of God as justly lenient in the moment of de-
37. This is the view Swinburne seems to support in more recent writing. See his
Responsiblity and Atonement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 180-184.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 123
that his desires are overpowering and so he is not responsible for his action. These
sorts of self-deception are possible even where there is certainty about God’s exis¬
tence and policies. Swinburne does not seem to me to take adequate account of
them.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 125
41. Swinburne has indicated in conversation that “think well of’ is the meaning
(of “value”) he intends.
42. I am grateful to Professor Swinburne for drawing this alternative construal
of his passages to my attention.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 127
43. Of course, not all of us find the same actions difficult, but all that is needed
here is the assumption that each of us finds some actions difficult.
Moral Freedom and Its Requirements [ 129
I. The “common claim” must, of course, be stated loosely to allow for differ¬
ent kinds and degrees of emphasis.
132 ] The Force of the Argument
He could not bear such great glory without falling into presump¬
tion. He wanted to make himself his own centre and do without my
help. He withdrew from my rule, setting himself up as my equal in
his desire to find happiness in himself, and I abandoned him to him¬
self. The creatures who were subject to him I incited to revolt and
made his enemies, so that today man has become like the beasts, and
is so far apart from me that a barely glimmering idea of his author
alone remains of all his dead or flickering knowledge. [Fragment
149, p. 77]
Pascal, then, accepts the historicity of the Fall. But there are two
aspects of his view which, for our purposes, need to be made more
explicit. First, humans did not initially fall away from the knowl¬
edge of God; only from a proper relation to it. On Pascal’s view, a
consciousness of God was at first retained; the Fall consisted in an
attempt to become equal with God. But the sequence of events that
followed took human beings ever farther away from God, until
today only a vestige of the original knowledge remains. Second, the
claim “God is hidden by sin,” where this is interpreted as “the
apparent weakness of theistic evidence is simply a matter of human
blindness,” would be criticized by Pascal as incomplete, for on his
view God himself contributed to the sequence of events just men¬
tioned by “inciting” the creatures to revolt: the harmony of the
created order (and, ipso facto, the evidence of its origin in God)
was intentionally weakened.3 Of course, humans have made things
worse for themselves by not responding appropriately to the signs
of God that remain in nature, and so there is a sense in which God’s
continuing hiddenness may be said to be (in part) the result of hu¬
man blindness; but it should be recognized that on Pascal’s view,
the relative weakness of the evidence provided by the created order
is fundamentally a function not of our blindness but of God’s in¬
tentional withdrawal.
The theme of Divine hiddenness can be traced not only in pas¬
sages of the Pensees which refer to the Fall but also in those dealing
with the Incarnation. In agreement with the Christian tradition,
Pascal held that God in the fullness of time responded to the Fall by
opening a “way of salvation” (fragment 149, p. 79). But he writes
that God’s wish to redeem humankind did not lead him to give a
clear revelation of himself—to attempt in this way an immediate
return to the pre-Fail state of affairs. God did make contact with
human beings, to be sure; but, in accordance with the policy of
restraint suggested by his immediate response to the Fall and its
repercussions on the created order, he came mildly—in a hidden
way:
3. Hence Pascal writes, “All creatures either distress or tempt him [i.e., man]
and dominate him either by forcibly subduing him or charming him with sweet¬
ness, which is a far more terrible and harmful yoke” (ibid.).
134 ] The Force of the Argument
they could not doubt the truth of his essence. . . . This is not the
way he wished to appear when he came in mildness, because so
many men had shown themselves unworthy of his clemency, that
he wished to deprive them of the good they did not desire. It was
therefore not right that he should appear in a manner manifestly
divine and absolutely capable of convincing all men, but neither was
it right that his coming should be so hidden that he could not be
recognized by those who sincerely sought him. He wished to make
himself perfectly recognizable to them. Thus wishing to appear
openly to those who seek him with all their heart and hidden from
those who shun him with all their heart, he has qualified our knowl¬
edge of him by giving signs which can be seen by those who seek
him and not by those who do not.
There is enough light for those who desire only to see, and
enough darkness for those of a contrary disposition. [Fragment 149,
pp. 79-8o]
4. As Pascal puts it, “all things combine to establish the point that God does
not manifest himself to men as obviously as he might” (ibid., fragment 449, p.
168).
The Importance of Inwardness [135
As for those who live without either knowing or seeking him, they
consider it so little worth while to take trouble over themselves that
they are not worth other people’s trouble, and it takes all the charity
of that religion they despise not to despise them to the point of
abandoning them to their folly. But as this religion obliges us al¬
ways to regard them, as long as they live, as beings capable of grace
which may enlighten them . . . we must do for them what we
would wish to be done for us in their place, and appeal to them to
have pity on themselves, and to take at least a few steps in an at¬
tempt to find some light. [Pensees, fragment 427, pp. 160-161]
5. In any event, I have provided reasons (in Chapter 5) for rejecting Hick’s
Autonomy Argument and so will not need to consider it any further here.
6. As another fragment puts it, “Religion is so great a thing that it is right that
those who will not take the trouble to look for it, if it is obscure, should be
deprived of it” (Pensees, fragment 472, p. 180).
7. It might seem that a less strident and more persuasive version of this argu¬
ment is also possible: “Humans have freely chosen to reject God, and it would be
inappropriate for God to overrule this decision. So they have been left to them¬
selves. God respects their freedom.” But this argument suggests no reason for God
to intentionally withdraw, to hide himself. It may be good for God to leave us in
our blindness if this results from free choices, but why should he make things even
more obscure? To this question, free will arguments do not seem to have an an¬
swer.
136 ] The Force of the Argument
There are other reasons as well for supposing that Pascal may
have had more in mind than is suggested by the Just Deserts Argu¬
ment. As Terence Penelhum points out (and as, more generally,
our discussion in the preceeding chapter should lead us to con¬
clude), God can be hidden from human eyes even when, objec¬
tively, the signs of his presence are clear:
As against the Just Deserts Argument, this point shows that if hu¬
mans are indeed corrupt, God would not necessarily get any better
revenge by hiding himself than by manifesting himself clearly. Of
course, perhaps in a situation of the sort Pascal describes, in which
God’s existence is overwhelmingly manifested, it would be more dif¬
ficult for us to keep God “at arm’s length” (although, as his discus¬
sion of the Fall suggests, it may be that humans could eventually
fall away from God even then). But why should such a situation be
thought to be the only alternative to hiddenness? For these reasons,
I conclude both that the Just Deserts Argument is inadequate and
that Pascal, brilliant and charitable thinker that he was, may well
have had some other explanation of hiddenness in mind. 9 But what
might this explanation be? It seems to me that an answer to this
question is latent in the following passages from the Pensees:
only right but useful for us that God should be partly concealed and
partly revealed, since it is equally dangerous for man to know God
without knowing his own wretchedness as to know his wretched¬
ness without knowing God. [Fragment 446, p. 167]
[Christianity] teaches men then these two truths alike: that there is a
God, of whom men are capable, and that there is a corruption in
nature which makes them unworthy. It is of equal importance for
men to know each of these points. . . . Knowing only one of these
points leads either to the arrogance of the philosophers, who have
known God but not known their own wretchedness, or to the de¬
spair of the atheists, who know their own wretchedness without
knowing their Redeemer. [Fragment 449, p. 168]
He [i.e., man] must not see nothing at all, nor must he see enough
to think that he possesses God, but he must see enough to know
that he has lost him. [Fragment 449, p. 170]
God wishes to move the will rather than the mind. Perfect clarity
would help the mind and harm the will.
Humble their pride. [Fragment 234, p. 101]
One needs no great sublimity of soul to realize that in this life there
is no true and solid satisfaction, that all our pleasures are mere van¬
ity, that our afflictions are infinite, and finally that death which
threatens us at every moment must in a few years infallibly face us
with the inescapable and appalling alternative of being annihilated or
wretched throughout eternity. . . .
Let us ponder these things, and then say whether it is not beyond
doubt that the only good thing in this life is the hope of another life,
that we become happy only as we come nearer to it. . . .
It is therefore certainly a great evil to have . . . doubts, but it is at
least an indispensable obligation to seek when one does thus doubt;
so the doubter who does not seek is at the same time very unhappy
and very wrong. [Fragment 427, p. 157]
not only right but useful for us that God should be partly concealed
and partly revealed” (my emphasis), and so take him beyond the
Just Deserts Argument.12
One of the virtues of the Presumption Argument, in particular,
is that it provides Pascal with a response to arguments such as Pe-
nelhum’s. Penelhum argues, as we saw, that God might very well
remain hidden from corrupt human beings in a situation of good
evidence, for, desiring to escape the knowledge of God, such indi¬
viduals would likely engage in various sorts of self-deception and
thus keep God at “arms length.” Pascal’s argument responds to
such claims by questioning the assumption on which they depend,
namely, that human beings would wish to escape the knowledge of
God. On his view, corrupt humans would not wish to be rid of
God, but rather would wish to compare themselves with him and
compete with him, or use him for their own selfish purposes. If
this view is correct, a situation of good evidence is not compatible
with Divine hiddenness. Thus Penelhum’s argument, although it
may point up a weakness in the Just Deserts Argument when that
argument is viewed in isolation, does not do so when it is taken
together with the Presumption Argument; nor does it have any
force against the Presumption Argument considered independ¬
ently.13
It must now be noted, however, that even if the Stimulus Argu¬
ment and the Presumption Argument, as so far developed, were to
be judged sound, no answer to our problem would be forthcom¬
ing. All these arguments suggest is that God has a reason for with¬
holding good evidence from those humans whose present actions
and motives are such as to prevent them from responding to it
appropriately. No reason is suggested for withholding evidence
from those who do not fall into this category—from those, for
example, who have felt their corruption and the emptiness of life
without God and who have begun to search for God with proper
motives. No reason is suggested, in short, for supposing that God
would permit the occurrence of reasonable nonbelief.
12. For a recent discussion of Pascal that seems to follow him here, see Thomas
V. Morris, “The Hidden God,” Philosophical Topics, 16 (1988), 5-21.
13. And this is of course how we must consider the Presumption Argument,
having rejected the Just Deserts Argument not only because of the force of Penel¬
hum’s criticism but also because of the implications of Christian charity.
The Importance of Inwardness [ 141
There are only two classes of people who can be called reasonable:
those who serve God with all their heart because they know him
and those who seek him with all their heart because they do not
know him. [Fragment 427, p. 160]
This is what I see and what troubles me. I look around in every
direction and all I see is darkness. Nature has nothing to offer me
that does not give rise to doubt and anxiety. If I saw no sign there of
a Divinity I should decide on a negative solution: if I saw signs of a
Creator everywhere I should peacefully settle down in the faith.
But, seeing too much to deny and not enough to affirm, I am in a
pitiful state, where I have wished a hundred times over that, if there
is a God supporting nature, she should unequivocally proclaim him,
and that, if the signs in nature are deceptive, they should be com¬
pletely erased; that nature should say all or nothing so that I could
see what course I ought to follow. Instead of that, in the state in
which I am, not knowing what I am or what I ought to do, I know
neither my condition nor my duty. My whole heart strains to know
what the true good is in order to pursue it: no price would be too
high to pay for eternity. [Fragment 429, pp. 162-163]14
the nonbeliever, namely, seeking, and so to contrast with indifference, which Pas¬
cal calls “monstrous” (fragment 427, p. 157). Whatever the case, it strongly sug¬
gests that Pascal considered “seeking without finding” to be part of the human
condition (although note the absence of any reference to the Christian revelation).
The Importance of Inwardness [ 143
It seems to me, however, that Pascal need not be faced with this
problem. For the phrase “with all their heart” is ambiguous. The
purity of desire, of motive, of intention (and perhaps depth of convic¬
tion on matters such as one’s wretchedness) to which it seems to
refer can be seen as instantiated in one who, upon recognizing her
unworthiness, is filled with remorse and, perhaps in prayer, ex¬
presses a desire to be properly related to God, even if she is subse¬
quently deterred from pursuing her search by pride or selfish de¬
sires; or as instantiated only in one who, through long, persistent,
unremitting searching, has a deeply ingrained attitude of humility
and desire for the life of faith, one who is no longer at all likely to
be deterred by lesser motives from pursuing a (proper) relationship
with God. If the phrase “with all their heart” is indeed ambiguous
in this way, Pascal can claim that the reasonable doubters to whom
he refers do not necessarily seek for God “with all their heart” in
the second, stronger sense of that phrase, and that it is this second
sense that is intended when it is said that God will reveal himself
clearly to those who seek with all their heart.
Whether Pascal saw this distinction or not, it is clearly one he
could employ. That he would be inclined to employ it (more specif¬
ically, that when he says God will be revealed to those who seek
with all their heart, he has in mind an attitude developed and ex¬
pressed in the course of a long and toilsome search) is suggested by
the following passage from the Pensees, in which it is said that ob¬
scurity can only provide the basis for an objection to Christian
theism if the one who complains of it has engaged in a very long
and very thorough search:
But even if we assume that Pascal does not necessarily face the
problem in question, and that he considers a long and thorough
search and a deeply ingrained attitude of humility to be necessary
for a clear revelation of God, we must still ask how this latter claim is
to be justified. It is only if we can find an argument for it that we will
have located the Pascalian answer to the problem of reasonable
nonbelief.
As I suggested earlier, such an argument, if it exists, is likely to
involve an extension of the Stimulus Argument or the Presump¬
tion Argument, or both. Do either of these arguments admit of
extension? It seems to me that, quite obviously, both do. For Pas¬
cal can claim the following: “The knowledge of God is a gift that
must be carefully given. Humans who have begun to search for
God (and, indeed, those who have honestly searched for some
time) may still be tempted, by virtue of their sinful nature, to fall
back into older and less worthy patterns of behavior; in particular,
they might very well relate externally and in a relationship-inhibit¬
ing way to any good evidence they were given. It is therefore im¬
portant that God remain hidden until they have persevered over a
long period and have developed a deeply ingrained attitude of humil¬
ity and a desire for a proper relationship with God strong enough
to overwhelm selfish desires. The hiddenness of God itself helps to
bring this development about by continually bringing home to hu¬
mans the poverty of a life without God and by continually
prompting them to seek God humbly. God’s hiddenness can there¬
fore be understood in terms of patience. Although he wishes to be
more deeply and intimately related to human beings (and, indeed,
because he wishes this), God is willing to wait until good evidence
will be religiously efficacious. It is only if he is patient that God can
ensure that those who come to be aware of his presence are those
willing to submit in the right way to what they see.”15
This, then, is the explanation of reasonable nonbelief to which
the arguments in the Pensees most naturally lead. Having got it out
15. One of the virtues of this interpretation is that it is able to make good sense
of Pascal’s repeated claim that in order to acquire a proper belief in God humans
need first to diminish their passions, and that to diminish passion we must resort to
habit (see fragments 119, p. 60; 125, p. 61; 418, p. 152; and 821, p. 274).
The Importance of Inwardness [ 145
that, for example, much evil exist—in other words, there remain
indirect methods of stimulating such an awareness which do not
require Divine hiddenness.16 I conclude therefore that the extended
Stimulus Argument does not succeed and that the success of the
Pascalian solution depends on the extended Presumption Argu¬
ment. For this reason, I will be focusing on the latter.
Pascal’s claim about the likelihood of a presumptuous response
to clear evidence of God’s existence may seem stronger than it oth¬
erwise would if we assume, as he does, that a historical “Fall” actu¬
ally took place. If we assume this, we are in effect assuming that
there is inductive evidence for the claim that, were God’s existence
to be revealed today, a presumptuous response would follow. But
in light of the findings of disciplines like evolutionary biology and
biblical criticism, it is hard to see how such an assumption could be
successfully defended. Thus it would seem that we do not have the
inductive evidence in question and, as a result, that Pascal’s argu¬
ment is deprived of (possibly) vital support from the very begin¬
ning.
But there is more that can be said on this score. For the pre-Fall
state of affairs—a state of absolute intellectual clarity and without
misery or death—seems to be, for Pascal, the paradigm of a situa¬
tion in which God is not hidden.17 Consequently (we may sur¬
mise), when he refers to Divine disclosure, he is inclined to think of,
inter alia, a world without evil, and the disastrous response o f the first
humans to life in such a world. This interpretation, whatever its other
merits, certainly helps explain why Pascal considered a presump¬
tuous response to Divine disclosure to be so likely. For it makes
some sense to suppose that if we knew of God’s existence and were
untroubled by evils which in the actual world bring home to us
our limitations, we might develop an inflated self-conception and
begin to respond to God in inappropriate ways. However, espe-
16. As I suggest immediately below, Pascal may assume that there is a necessary
connection between evil and hiddenness. But I will argue that this view is incor¬
rect.
17. This is perhaps to be expected since, as we have seen, God’s hiddenness is,
on his view, bound up with the corruption of nature and the introduction of mis¬
ery and death. It is only natural to think of the removal of hiddenness as involving
the removal of those phenomena that brought it about in the first place (cf. Pensees,
fragment 149, pp. 79-80; fragment 449, p. 170).
The Importance of Inwardness [ 147
The Christians’ God is a God who makes the soul aware that he is
its sole good: that in him alone can it find peace; that only in loving
him can it find joy; and who at the same time fills it with loathing
for the obstacles which hold it back and prevent it from loving God
with all its might. Self-love and concupiscence, which hold it back,
are intolerable. This God makes the soul aware of this underlying
self-love which is destroying it and which he alone can cure. [Frag¬
ment 460, p. 178]
What should we make of this? Why did Pascal not see these
claims as providing a counterexample to the Presumption Argu¬
ment? Why were they not seen as suggesting an alternative to theo¬
retical proof (and, for that matter, to the restoration of primeval
glory) and, hence, as rendering otiose the appeal to philosophical
arrogance? Whatever the reason may actually have been, it seems
clear that if religious experience can have the effects Pascal de¬
scribes, it could, if given, rule out a presumptuous response; and,
therefore, that God’s disclosure (in the relevant sense) need not at
all provoke such a response. That it can have these effects is
strongly suggested not only by Pascal’s own reports but also by
the testimony of many believers to experiences apparently of God
which brought home to them their corruption—experiences which
were unexpected and unsought, but which changed the direction
of their life and (on their interpretation) led to a deep and fulfilling
relationship with God. The critic of Pascal therefore has strong
inductive evidence of his own, evidence which seems to render
irrelevant the evidence adduced by the Pascalian in support of his
claim and, indeed, to positively establish the contrary claim.
I would suggest, therefore, that in focusing on the effects of
proofs on philosophers, Pascal has failed to take into account other
possible sources of evidence, in particular, the evidence of religious
experience, which, so far from provoking an arrogant response,
seems likely to produce its opposite. We could also vary the
emphasis and say that he is wrong to focus on the effects of any
evidence whatever on philosophers. If God were going to make
evidence sufficient for belief generally available, he would not
likely provide evidence of the sort that (sometimes) makes philoso¬
phers arrogant, namely, theoretical proofs, but rather evidence as¬
similable by anyone, no matter how sophisticated or lacking in
150 ] The Force of the Argument
19. Pascal himself offers support for the antecedent of this claim: “Do not be
astonished to see simple people believing without argument. God makes them love
him and hate themselves. He inclines their hearts to believe” (Petisees, fragment
380, p. 138).
The Importance of Inwardness [ i5 i
withdrawn. But I hope it will be obvious that this is not the case.2'1
Given all the considerations I have adduced, it seems unreasonable
to suppose that in the circumstances in question, anyone would
ever have more than an inclination to respond arrogantly or pre¬
sumptuously—an inclination, moreover, capable of being overrid¬
den. In other words, while some might be tempted to respond
inappropriately, everyone would be free not to. The most, there¬
fore, that a defender of Pascal could ever plausibly claim is that,
given good evidence, some might be inclined to respond presump¬
tuously, and it is the claim that God would remain withdrawn to
prevent humans from yielding to such an inclination that I reject.
My reasons for rejecting this claim are drawn from the discus¬
sion in Chapter 5. There I assumed, with Swinburne, that a loving
God would wish to give us a choice with respect to our own des¬
tiny, and that to do this, he must, inter alia, give us a range of
natural inclinations to act badly which it is up to us to yield to or
to suppress. He must leave us morally free. Now if God remained
withdrawn in the face of a possible presumptuous response to
theistic evidence, he would in effect be preventing us from choos¬
ing how to handle the gift of Divine disclosure; he would be ren¬
dering us morally unfree in this respect. And in preventing us from
choosing how to respond to Divine disclosure, he would be re¬
moving the possibility of an explicit choice with respect to our
relationship with himself—a choice which many theologians have
considered to be essential to a choice of destiny.
Perhaps it will be replied to this that there are other possible
choices one might make with respect to a relationship with God—
a choice to seek God, for example—and that it is not at all a bad
thing for God to be patient and to allow us to mature before per¬
mitting choices as significant as the one in question. But for this to
be plausible, the danger of a presumptuous response—and what is
more, a response with continuing relationship-inhibiting effects—
must be quite great indeed, and we have already noted the defects
of this view. Given the nature of human beings and the revelatory
20. Strangely, in order to suppose that it is the case, one must accept a claim
about human beings that is directly opposed to the claim advanced by Hick and
Swinburne (see Chapter 5): one must claim that humans would, in circumstances
of the sort in question, be morally unfree in respect of certain bad actions.
152 ] The Force of the Argument
works in which the author’s ideas are clearly stated. This is because
Kierkegaard preferred an indirect style. He wrote under pseudo¬
nyms and filled his books with parable, metaphor, irony, humor,
and poetry, hoping that by forcing his readers to toil for results, he
would cause them to become subjectively involved with the matters
discussed. Such involvement, he held, was necessary for the appre¬
hension of ethical and religious truths.23
I have more than one reason for noting here these features of
Kierkegaard’s writing style. For Kierkegaard’s most general inten¬
tions as a writer seem also to have been intentions he ascribed to
God, by reference to which he thought the hiddenness of God
could be explained. His (apparent) view was that God communi¬
cates with us indirectly in order to stimulate the proper sort of
subjective involvement in our existence as human beings, and in
order to prevent situations and states incompatible with such in¬
volvement. I will take it as my task to clarify and develop this view
and the reasons for Divine hiddenness it suggests, and to assess the
force of these reasons against the argument of Part i.24
27. For a good discussion of this notion, see Robert M. Adams, “Kierkegaard’s
Arguments against Objective Reasoning in Religion,” in Steven M. Cahn and
David Shatz, eds., Contemporary Philosophy of Religion (New York: Oxford Uni¬
versity Press, 1982), pp. 221-227.
156 ] The Force of the Argument
in God against all reason. In that moment one is closest to God: “It
is only momentarily that the particular individual is able to realize
existentially a unity of the infinite and the finite which transcends
existence. This unity is realized in the moment of passion” (p.
176). “God is a subject, and therefore exists only for subjectivity in
inwardness” (p. 178). The subjective individual, to realize her po¬
tential, must believe “against the understanding,” and feel “the
peril of lying upon the deep, the seventy thousand fathoms, in order
there to find God” (p. 208, my emphasis).
Kierkegaard’s notion of subjectivity is notoriously difficult, and
this account of it is doubtless incomplete in some respects. But it
conveys, I think, some of his most important emphases and will
suffice for our purposes. What now of the notion of God’s “hid¬
denness”? How is it understood?
Kierkegaard himself hardly ever uses the term, but it is clear that
what it is commonly taken to mean is expressed by him in other
ways. He speaks in the Postscript of the “objective uncertainty” of
God’s existence (by which he means, at the very least, the improb¬
ability of God’s existence) and of God’s “elusiveness” (pp. 218-
219). As the term “elusive” suggests, Kierkegaard apparently holds
that many of the epistemic difficulties we may face vis-a-vis God’s
existence are a result of God’s intentional withdrawal. It is sug¬
gested that God could (in some sense) reveal himself more clearly
but chooses not to.28 Since it is not just human blindness but God’s
intentional withdrawal that lies behind Divine hiddenness, the anx¬
iety and uncertainty humans may feel with respect to God’s exist¬
ence are not (at least not in the first instance) necessarily signs of
culpability.29 And so we may say that Kierkegaard’s understanding
28. This view is suggested most clearly in the famous parable of the king and
the humble maiden. In his application of this parable to theology, Kierkegaard
writes of God’s dilemma: “Who grasps the contradiction of this sorrow: not to
disclose itself is the death of love; to disclose itself is the death of the beloved. . . .
How grievous it is to have to deny the learner that to which he aspires with his
whole soul and to have to deny it precisely because he is the beloved” (Fragments,
p. 30). Here again we encounter the “patient God.”
29. I say “at least not in the first instance” because Kierkegaard suggests that a
failure to develop subjectively, and so a failure to come to believe that there is a
God, may be culpable (see Postscript, pp. 363, 379).
The Importance of Inwardness [ 157
of Divine hiddenness entails our own, that is, entails that God has
permitted the occurrence of reasonable nonbelief.30
Keeping these comments about “subjectivity” and “hiddenness”
in mind, we may now return to the sketch of Kierkegaard’s expla¬
nation given earlier and begin to fill in some of the detail. It was
suggested that he assigns to Divine hiddenness both a positive and
a negative function. I will begin with the former.
An argument for the view that divine hiddenness fulfills a posi¬
tive function is implicit in the following passage from the Postscript:
30. Of course, Kierkegaard would not say, as I would, that it follows that evi¬
dence sufficient for belief has not been provided, for this statement, as I have
defined it, presupposes that belief is involuntary, and Kierkegaard denies that this
is so.
31. Alastair Hannay has some helpful comments on this passage which relate
also to our emphasis: “Faith is being certain in spite of the objective uncertainty.
. . . In describing faith as the ‘contradiction’ . . . between the ‘infinite passion of
inwardness’ and the ‘objective uncertainty,’ Kierkegaard is referring to the conflict
between the subjective, or personal, certainty one seeks, and has found, on the one
hand, and the objective uncertainty, on the other, which has made the finding of
the former depend on a strenuous personal choice. The passion of inwardness is
the active passion of someone who has decided upon a risky course of action and
knows that the determination with which he pursues it would give way to despair
were he to fall back on the impersonal authority of reason. The objective uncer-
158 ] The Force of the Argument
32. Kierkegaard means “deceived by God”: God, fully aware of our disposition
to avoid subjective strain, would, in providing objective evidence, be knowingly
causing the formation of false beliefs.
33. Kierkegaard writes, “In general it is quite inconceivable how ingenious and
inventive human beings can be in evading an ultimate decision” (Postscript, p. 379).
160 ] The Force of the Argument
thinking that we had arrived when really there was still a lot to be
done, failing to recognize that the religious life, rightly pursued, is
subjectively demanding, and hence failing to pursue it rightly. Our
knowledge of God would be superficial, since the most that can be
known of God objectively is still radically incomplete: God is
Spirit and can only really be known through the activation of our
own spirit in inwardness. Our relationship with God would be
shallow, not deep, personal, and strenuous as befits a relationship
with the infinite Subject. We would remain happily within our fi¬
nite parameters, relating to God transactionally, not inwardly, and
hence not really relating to him at all. ”34 It is only a short step from
this argument (the Deception Argument, as I will call it) to the
claim that if God is hidden, the deception in question and its sub¬
jectivity-inhibiting corollaries will be prevented. Therefore, Kier¬
kegaard can claim that the hiddenness of God fulfills an important
negative function in relation to the life of faith.
It may be useful to note, before concluding this part of the dis¬
cussion, that the main emphasis of the Deception Argument seems
also to be traceable in the Philosophical Fragments.35 In chapter 2 of
that work, Kierkegaard presents his famous parable of the king and
the humble maiden. The main point of this parable is often taken
to be that God must come among us incognito if our freedom is to
be preserved.36 Kierkegaard, in other words, is often viewed as a
precursor of Hick. But while I do not wish to deny that such an
emphasis may be found in the Fragments, it is important to note
that it is not the only emphasis. In particular, the claim that, were
God to be openly revealed, we would be deceived and consequently
fail to reach a proper understanding of God, is also to be found:
comes unhappy and the instruction meaningless, for they are unable
to understand each other. . . .
The poet’s task is to find a solution, a point of unity where there
is in truth love’s understanding . . . for this is the unfathomable love
that is not satisfied with what the object of love might foolishly
consider himself blissfully happy to have. [Pp. 28-29]
all human beings at all times. Whether they provide at least one
actual rebuttal as well is the question to which I now turn.
(3) One can only choose to believe that there is a God in the
face of objective uncertainty if God is hidden.
I will assume here that God would indeed wish to facilitate the
exercise of subjectivity, even, if necessary, at the cost of permitting
reasonable nonbelief, meaning by this that some degree of risk and
sacrifice and commitment to the pursuit of genuinely religious
goals (including the goal of a relationship with God) are essential to
the most valuable kind of religious life. (I do not mean that God
would wish us to attempt to believe at will what we take to be
improbable propositions; we have already seen that the notion of
such “believing” is incoherent.) I will also assume that premises (7)
and (8) of the Deception Argument, as stated above, are true, for
their claims seem clearly correct. This leaves premise (6). What can
be said about it?
I would suggest that, whereas premise (6) must for our purposes
be taken as referring to evidence sufficient for belief, it is only
plausible when given the stronger interpretation that Kierkegaard
himself seems inclined to give it. If we think in terms of theoretical
proofs and striking displays of Divine power, as he seems to do,
we can begin to see how someone could come to assert it. For if
we were allowed access to such phenomena, we might indeed tend
to form false beliefs of the sort Kierkegaard mentions. If we wit¬
nessed an exhibition of Divine power, perhaps we would feel that
there was nothing left for us to do, that all that was required of us
was to stand back and watch God work, applauding at appropriate
moments, like observers at some celestial fireworks display. Per¬
haps if we were granted access to a successful theoretical proof, we
would be drawn away from the inner life and into a maze of argu¬
ments, thinking that this was the Divinely appointed way of ac-
i 66 ] The Force of the Argument
1. The full title is The Analogy of Religion, Natural and Revealed, to the Constitu¬
tion and Course of Nature. I have used thej. H. Bernard edition of Butler’s works
(The Works of Bishop Butler, 2 vols. [London: Macmillan, 1900]). Volume 2 con-
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [
many ways similar to our own, the problem posed for Christians
by the following skeptical claim: “If the evidence of revelation ap¬
pears doubtful, this itself turns into a positive argument against it,
because it cannot be supposed that, if it were true, it would be left
to subsist upon doubtful evidence.”* 2 Now, as his formulation of
this claim suggests, the problem to which Butler addresses himself
and the problem of reasonable nonbelief do differ in at least one
respect: the evidence Butler refers to as appearing “doubtful”
(whose apparent doubtfulness he attempts to explain) is evidence
adduced in support of Christian revelatory claims and not the evi¬
dence of theism (with which we have been concerned).3 Hence to
see what force Butler’s arguments have in the context of our dis¬
cussion, it will be necessary to adapt them for our purposes—to set
on one side the question of doubtfulness attaching to revelatory
claims, and focus instead on whether the explanations he offers
succeed as explanations of apparent doubtfulness in theistic evi¬
dence. I will accordingly assume hereafter that the evidence to
which Butler refers is evidence of this latter sort.4
A central claim of Butler’s Analogy is that we are subjected to
temptation in this life so that we may become fitted, through the
development of good moral character, for the life to come. Ours is
a “state of probation . . . intended for moral discipline and im¬
provement.” We have been placed in it so that we might “qualify
ourselves, by the practice of virtue, for another state, . . a future
state of security and happiness.”5
It will be noticed that this view in some ways parallels the claim
of Swinburne, discussed in Chapter 5, with respect to the relation
between temptation and a genuine choice of destiny. This may in-
tains the Analogy, and Butler’s fifteenth Rolls Sermon, to which I will also refer, is
to be found in volume 1. The numbers appearing in my references to the Analogy
are for the part, the chapter, and the paragraph, respectively. In references to Ser¬
mon 15, only the paragraph number appears.
2. Butler, Analogy, 2, 6, 1.
3. The reason for this difference is that the evidence for God’s existence did not
appear doubtful to either Butler or his opponents, the deists.
4. I will, however, return to the distinction between evidence for theism and
evidence for Christian revelatory claims at a later stage of the discussion. As we
will see, it is a distinction that the critic of (the adapted) Butler can exploit.
5. Butler, Analogy, 1, 5, 1.
170 ] The Force of the Argument
Now if the greatest pleasures and fains of the present life may be
overcome and suspended, as they manifestly may, by hope and fear,
and other passions and affections; then the evidence of religion, and
the sense of the consequences of virtue and vice, might have been
such, as entirely in all cases to prevail over . . . afflictions, diffi¬
culties and temptation; prevail over them so, as to render them ab¬
solutely none at all. But the very notion ... of a state of discipline
and improvement, necessarily excludes such sensible evidence and
conviction of religion, and of the consequences of virtue and vice.6
8. Buder, Analogy, 2, 6, 8.
9. Ibid., 2, 6, 12.
172 ] The Force of the Argument
10. Terence Penelhum, Butler (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985), pp.
195, 196. Penelhum is one of very few recent writers who give attention to But¬
ler’s philosophy of religion, and I have been greatly helped by his careful study.
11. Whether Butler considered this argument to be an extension of the other or a
narrower version of it depends on whether or not, in the final analysis, he endorsed
the latter. The first passage from Sermon 15 quoted above suggests that he did.
But it is important to note that the Analogy, which treats these matters at much
greater length, seems to favor a contrary view. There it is clearly implied that “real
immoral depravity and dissoluteness” is perfectly compatible with a “distinct con¬
viction” of the truth of religion (Analogy, 2, 6, 8), and from this it follows that
clear evidence would not necessarily remove moral temptation. For this reason, it
seems to me preferable to suppose that Butler viewed the second Probation Argu¬
ment as a narrower, more acceptable, version of the first.
12. Swinburne appears at times to recognize the possibility of extending his
“choice of destiny” argument to choices with respect to investigation of theistic
evidence (see, e.g., Faith and Reason [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981], p. 86). He
also suggests the possibility of construing as valuable the cooperative investigation
of theistic evidence (The Existence of God [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979], pp.
188-189). The arguments I deploy against Butler can, however, be applied to these
arguments with little adaptation. One possible response to the latter argument is
suggested by Swinburne himself when he notes that “men seem only to be begin¬
ning to take the opportunities which exist for co-operation for long-term practical
ends” (ibid., p. 189). There would appear to be endless opportunities for human
cooperation on important matters even if the question of God’s existence does not
need to be cooperatively investigated, and so—especially given that doing so
would preclude, in many cases, the great good of personal relationship with God
in this life—it seems unlikely that God would withdraw his presence on this ac¬
count.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 173
[There does not] appear any absurdity in supposing, that the spec¬
ulative difficulties, in which the evidence of religion is involved,
may make even the principal part of some persons’ trial. For as the
74 ] The Force of the Argument
13. Buder, Analogy, 2, 6, 13. It is interesting to note that this passage also sug¬
gests a reason for denying the (apparent) claim of Sermon 15 (viz., that a much
improved epistemic situation would rule out moral temptation and probation).
Butler suggests that many people, if provided with a proof of the truth of religion,
would still neglect it “from that frame of mind which renders many persons with¬
out feeling as to anything distant, or which is not the object of their senses.” This
is essentially the same point I made toward the end of Chapter 5, namely, that it is
often quite difficult to give up short-term pleasure for the sake of long-term goals.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 175
fulfillment, people who would not have any difficulty with the
practice of religion should a demonstration of its truth become
known to them. Therefore, if they also require a period of moral
probation (and Butler assumes they do), such individuals should
not be provided with a demonstration of religion, but should be
required to face the temptations attendant upon difficulties in the
evidence.14 In this way they too may be disciplined and provided
with an opportunity for the improvement of virtue.
What should we say in response to this argument? Does it make
plausible the view that a loving God would require at any rate
some individuals to investigate the question of his existence before
arriving at evidence sufficient for belief? As it seems to me, it does
not, for the following reasons.
First, individuals of the sort Butler describes must be exceed¬
ingly few in number, if they exist at all. No doubt there are per¬
sons of an intellectual bent who have a “deeper sense as to what is
invisible or future” and who recognize that things are “not less real
for their not being objects of sense.” But how many are also free
from the temptations to which objects of sense give rise? Suppose,
however, that there exist individuals who combine these qualities.
Now we must ask why Butler considers them to be in need of
discipline and improvement of virtue. If their virtue is apparent,
why should they be subjected to additional tests? Surely God
would only sacrifice personal relationships for the sake of intellec¬
tual probation, even for a short while, if there were individuals
who stood in need of it. Let us, however, also grant that the indi¬
viduals in question are in need of discipline. The question that then
arises is how intellectual probation could ever provide it if other
14. Note that Butler’s point here is not just a narrower version of Swinburne’s
prudential claim, that is, his point is not that this particular class of individuals
should not be provided with strong evidence because of their special sensitivity to
its prudential implications. His point is rather that clear evidence should not be
provided because the individuals in question stand in need of intellectual probation,
and this (logically) necessitates difficulties in the evidence. According to Butler,
these individuals would find religious practice easy in the circumstances described,
not for any reason directly associated with the availability of a demonstration of
religion, but because of their general rationality and freedom from sensual desire.
They are inclined to do what is right even if it goes against short-term interests and
so, seeing religious practice to be morally right, would not be tempted to do any¬
thing else.
76 ] The Force of the Argument
intrinsic value. There is value in free choices to pursue the good quite apart from
the value of the improved character to which such choices may lead. But to this we
must reply that the intrinsic value of such additional free choices surely does not
exceed the intrinsic value of personal relationship with God. And since, as we have
seen, God would value such relationship not only for the good—instrumental or
noninstrumental—it would produce in the life of the believer, but also for its own
sake, we must conclude that, all things considered, intellectual probation would
not be viewed by God as facilitating a good as great as the good that would (appar¬
ently) need to be sacrificed in order to make it possible.
78] The Force of the Argument
real possibility show that it could exist quite well, in all the forms
Butler suggests for it, if the signs of God’s presence were clear.16
18. Some may wonder whether we are not committed by the terms of the argu¬
ment developed in Part 1 to the claim that any evidence of revelation would also be
clear. They are referred to the end of Chapter 1, where a response to this sort of
objection is provided.
19. I assume that the evidence of revelation may remain open to reasonable
doubt. If, as I have argued, God’s existence may be reasonably doubted, this would
seem to be true a fortiori with respect to more specific claims about God’s action in
the world.
i 80 ] The Force of the Argument
20. In defense of this assessment, we may also call as witness the (unadapted)
Butler, for he and his opponents presupposed the existence of God, and yet the
difficulties in which the evidence of revelation is involved concerned them—in
particular, were taken by Butler as providing intellectual probation. The fact that
God’s existence was already (in his opinion) well-evidenced did not in his view in
any way lessen the value of the intellectual probation provided by doubtfulness in
the evidence of revelation.
21. It may be claimed that questions about God’s existence—about whether
there is a religious reality at all—are far deeper and more serious than questions
that presuppose the truth of the theistic claim, and so ones God would wish to be
among those we are given the opportunity of investigating. For this reason, it may
be said, it is a mistake to put both forms of investigation into the same category, as
I have done. Investigation of God’s existence would be viewed by God as the more
valuable of the two. But I suggest it is not at all obvious that the investigations
into religious matters we would be in a position to pursue were we in possession
of strong evidence for God’s existence and (perhaps) growing in relationship with
God would be any less interesting, deep, serious, and so on, than the investigation
of questions concerning God’s existence. If we suppose there to be a God who is
infinitely rich and inconceivably great, we may surmise that there is no limit to the
number of interesting and fruitful religious investigations it is possible to pursue
even after having satisfied ourselves that there is a God, and so that there is no way
to legitimately judge, from our perspective, that one such investigation is signifi¬
cantly “deeper,” more “serious,” and so on, than another. Even if there is such a
difference, however, I would claim that investigation of revelatory claims provides
a reasonable substitute for theistic investigation, and that since the former investiga¬
tion is compatible with theistic belief and the goods for which it is necessary,
whereas the latter is not, we must view a loving God as preferring it, all things
considered.
22. For an argument similar to Butler’s, which defends an understanding of
religious doubt as trial, seej. R. Lucas, “Doubt: A Sermon,” in Freedom and Grace
(London: SPCK, 1976), pp. 120-122. But Lucas also suggests an answer to this
argument, construed as an argument against the prima facie case I have developed,
namely, that the doubt in question may occur and have the desired effects within
the context of a relationship with God, and so need not occur prior to its develop¬
ment. I look more closely at suggestions of this sort in the penultimate section of
this chapter.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ i8i
23. I am grateful to Robert Adams for pointing out to me the possibility of such
a response. The formulation of it that appears here is, however, my own.
182] The Force of the Argument
24. I will assume here that (1") is true. Religious diversity in its sense can be
viewed as intrinsically valuable or as having value for the sort of reason discussed in
Chapter 5.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 183
cases. Indeed, disputes rage. This suggests that, were a strong epis-
temic situation in relation to theism to obtain, religious diversity
(in the sense in question) would not at all be ruled out. Quite the
contrary. If the object of the experiences in question were indeed
the inexhaustibly rich source of existence, we would expect tradi¬
tions that arose on the basis of such experiences to (potentially)
reflect this richness.25 While a certain direction might be given to
religious creativity, creativity could hardly be restricted in any im¬
portant sense. (And if such direction would not prevent diversity,
its presence should be seen as an advantage of the situation in ques¬
tion, rendering it preferable, all things considered, to the actual
situation; for creative chaos is surely not the religious ideal.) When
all of this is taken into account, it seems clear that where “religious
diversity” is understood as in (1") and (2"), the Diversity Argument
fails.
Can a more favorable judgment be rendered if the premises of
the Diversity Argument are (1') and (2') instead of (1") and (2")? It
seems to me that the answer must again be a negative one. Here
the problem is not the second premise but the first. It is not the
second because it is likely that any world in which a strong epis-
temic situation in relation to theism obtained would be one in
which the map of the religious traditions was different. If God had
always followed a policy of presenting himself to the experience of
individuals capable of recognizing him, then (it is likely) various
traditions now existing would not have arisen and/or various tradi¬
tions not now existing would have arisen (and/or various traditions
now existing would have existed in different form). Such an im¬
portant input into the religious life of humankind would surely
have had some effect.
Let us assume on the basis of this consideration that (2') is true.
What is to prevent us from accepting (C) as well and declaring the
argument sound? In response to this it can be argued, first of all,
that (1') would appear to derive any plausibility it has from (1"). If
the actual religious traditions have value, it is because they in some
way instantiate the free expression of religious imagination, cre-
25. In line with this point, we should recall what was mentioned in Chapter 2,
that in the situation in question there would be nothing preventing individuals
from having experiences apparently of God of other sorts.
4] The Force of the Argument
ativity, and so forth. But then, given that there are various possible
traditions that might have existed instead and that might also have
instantiated religious creativity, including religious traditions com¬
patible with a strong epistemic situation in relation to theism, and
given the extra value we must associate with traditions of the latter
sort, we must surely conclude that the existence of the actual reli¬
gious traditions is not as great a good as the good their existence
precludes, and so that (T) is false.
Perhaps it will be replied that Judaism, Christianity, and other
religious traditions are valuable not just in the sense of the preced¬
ing paragraph but also in an instrumental sense, constituting (to ap¬
propriate a Christian term) important “means of grace” for their
adherents. But surely we must answer, again, that many other
possible traditions, had they existed instead, would have per¬
formed the same function. In particular, if God exists and all expe¬
riences of grace are ultimately traceable to his benevolence, then, as
I have argued, possible situations in which the religious life of hu¬
mankind and explicit belief in God’s existence are more closely
linked than in ours must be ones in which the grace of God is more
readily appropriated. For these reasons and the reasons given
above, I conclude that (i'), which implies that God might wish the
religious life of humankind to be just as it is, is false. The argument
from (T) and (2') is therefore no more successful than the argu¬
ment from (1") and (2"), and so the Diversity Argument fails.
I could not have existed without past evils that have profoundly
affected the course of human history, and especially the “combina-
26. Robert Adams, “Existence, Self-Interest, and the Problem of Evil,” chap. 5
in The Virtue of Faith (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987).
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 185
Adams claims that it follows from this that “God has not wronged
us in causing or permitting those evils, if he is going to see to it
that we will have lives that are worth living on the whole. What
right could I have against satisfying the necessary conditions of my
coming to be, and how could I be injured by satisfying them, if
my life will be worth living?”28 On Adams’s view, this argument
makes a significant contribution to theodicy, for if all those who
claim they have been wronged by God in fact owe their existence to
the evils God has allowed (and live a reasonably good life), the
possibility of justified complaint would seem largely ruled out.
Critics of the case developed in Part 1 who are impressed by this
argument will wish to argue by analogy as follows: “If it were not
for the fact that God has not always followed a policy of presenting
himself to the experience of all human beings capable of recogniz¬
ing him, we—that is, the actually existing human beings, includ¬
ing those constructing and evaluating this argument—would very
likely not have come into existence. The absence of such an impor¬
tant input into the life of humankind, though it may seem regret¬
table, has in fact affected ‘the course of human history’ (including
especially the religious life of humankind) and (consequently) the
‘combinations of. . . people and marriages’; and we would almost
certainly not have existed had things been otherwise.” Since we are
referring here to an alleged evil of omission rather than an evil of
commission, this point is perhaps more naturally put the other way
around: “Had God always followed the policy in question, we
would likely not have come into existence. For such an important
input would have affected the ‘combinations of . . . people and
29. Adams suggests his acceptance of the coherence of this claim by arguing
against it at length.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 187
(4) If there were a God, all human beings would live a life
unblemished by evil e.
(5) If there were a God, all human beings (that is, all of the
human beings who actually exist) would live a life un¬
blemished by e.
I have suggested, however, that the arguer from evil need not
claim this much. What she may accept instead is the following de
dicto reading of the proposition in question:
(6) If there were a God, all human beings (that is, all existing
human beings, whoever they might be) would live a life
unblemished by e.
If (5) is true, then, if God exists, I exist. But the same need not be
said about (6), and so (6) is not subject to Adams’s criticism. Hav¬
ing noted this, we can now consider:
This proposition brings us back once more within the ambit of the
de re. But it is important to note that while it clearly follows from
(7) and (5) that there is no God, the same conclusion follows from
(7) and (6). That is, actual suffering can count against the existence
8] The Force of the Argument
and deriving
For although the human beings who actually exist need not exist
for God to exist, and so need not be among the human beings
mentioned by (10) who would come into being and benefit from a
strong epistemic situation if there were a God, if they do exist, it
follows from (10) that unless their epistemic situation is a strong
one, God does not exist. As (10) states, God and human beings in a
weak epistemic situation do not coexist, and so if actual human
beings exist in such a situation, God and actual human beings do not
coexist.
If this is correct, the Adams-type objection can be easily circum¬
vented. For then anyone can consistently claim both that the situa¬
tion of reasonable nonbelief in which she finds herself poses a
problem of evil, and that, had things been otherwise, she would
not have existed.
Perhaps it will be replied to my argument that I have missed the
point of the Adams article. Adams’s point, it may be said, is that if
we consider our existence to be on the whole a good thing, the fact
that conditions necessary for our existence have been satisfied must
also be viewed by us as a good thing, even if the satisfying of those
conditions can be seen by us to have involved the occurrence of
what is in itself evil. But to this it seems right to respond by saying
that the existence of individuals who would have come into being
had these evils not occurred and the necessary conditions of our
existence not been satisfied might also have been a great good. In¬
deed, where the evil in question is the existence of reasonable non¬
belief, the well-being achievable by them would have been much
greater than the well-being that actually existing individuals are in
a position to achieve. Would not God then have preferred their
existence to ours?
But a response to Adams need not rest on this point alone. (If it
did, it might be weakened by his claim that “God could be per¬
fectly good and . . . cause or permit evils that are necessary for
good ends that he loves, even if those goods are not the best states
90 ] The Force of the Argument
A world in which agents can benefit each other but not do each
other harm is one where they have only very limited responsibility
for each other. ... [If] I cannot harm you, you will be moderately
all right whatever I do. Your well-being will not then depend
greatly on me. God has reason for going beyond that. A God who
gave agents only such limited responsibility for their fellows would
not have given much.34
Taking these points into account, the critic may once again pro¬
ceed by analogy and suggest that there may well be opportunities
to harm or benefit which require for their existence that some indi¬
viduals for some period of time be (or possibly come to be) in a
state of reasonable nonbelief.35 We must now look at how such a
suggestion could be filled out.
(i) The most obvious development of this suggestion would in-
36. For surely, if God deprives A of evidence so that B can have the opportunity
of benefiting or harming A by bringing evidence to him or failing to do so, it is to
be expected that the evidence B is actually in a position to give A will be strong;
otherwise there is no sense in the supposition that B is in a position to benefit or
harm A.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 193
37. And given that God’s existence was well-evidenced, no one would be in a
position to claim that God should, for reasons of personal relationship, have made
this special information available to everyone. For as I have argued, personal rela¬
tionship with God is to be developmentally understood, and belief in God’s existence
is sufficient to enter upon such relationship.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 195
beings in contact with God. To put this point another way: there is
some reason to suppose that a loving God would wish to provide
evidence for belief in his existence directly, not through some hu¬
man intermediary; for otherwise the acceptance of evidence would
perhaps not be as likely to evoke a personal response, and further
information about God, however provided, would not be as
readily assimilated and spiritually appropriated. A second reason to
suppose that God would prefer to tie the spiritual responsibilities of
human beings to the dissemination of a special revelation is that it
is possible (some would say likely) that many human beings would
fail in their spiritual responsibilities, or that the fulfillment of these
responsibilities would be long delayed. Taking this into account, a
loving God would surely wish those for whom others had been
made spiritually responsible to be provided with some basis for
communion with himself in the interim—a more general knowl¬
edge of God’s existence and loving nature which would allow
them to experience at any rate some of the benefits associated with
a personal relationship with God.
Much of what I have said about general and special revelation
and human responsibility for dissemination of the latter matches
traditional Christian thinking about God’s self-revelation and the
nature of the missionary task. It will be noted, however, that on
the traditional view, the all-important message of God’s love and
forgiveness is not a part of the general revelation but is intimately
connected to the story of Christ. And so it may seem that my
distinction between the two notions is incorrectly drawn. Indeed,
it may seem that since the evidence for God’s existence I have been
mentioning is evidence for the existence of a perfectly loving God,
there is really no distinction left at all: what I am asking for includes
the special revelation of Christianity (or at least its major theme),
and so there is no “further revelation” for me to appeal to as an
alternative source of spiritual responsibility.
To this I would reply by saying that I have been describing what
seems to be the policy a perfectly loving God would pursue, and if
this conflicts with traditional Christian thinking, so be it: tradi¬
tional Christian thinking on these matters may be internally incon¬
sistent. The message of a God of love Christians have (in the actual
world) tried to convey has sometimes not taken root in the experi-
96 ] The Force of the Argument
38. This fact is the one we must emphasize in response to those who would
claim that the opportunity to prevent others from coming to believe that there is a
God constitutes a much deeper and therefore much more valuable form of respon¬
sibility than those here mentioned. It would be a great responsibility. But the harm
that might well—and I should say, would probably—result, would be commen-
surately great, and so I suggest a perfectly loving God, concerned not only to give
human beings responsibility, but also to enter into personal relationship with
them, would rest content with giving other responsibilities.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 199
them to reject him. But by the same token, it seems that a loving
God would not give anyone the opportunity to put others in a
position where neither explicit acceptance nor explicit rejection is
possible. God, if he exists, is concerned to make it possible for each
human being, at all times at which she or he exists and is capable,
to be personally related to himself, and will, other things being
equal, see to it that this is the case, unless that individual chooses
otherwise. Given the deep responsibilities humans could have even
given such a strong epistemic situation in relation to theism, the
second version of the Responsibility Argument does not seem to
me to be capable of adducing considerations strong enough to off¬
set this concern.
We may conclude this section with the following observation.
There is a tendency among some writers to value the giving of
freedom and responsibility almost limitlessly: their view seems to
be that if having some of these commodities is a good thing, then
more must always be better. But this is to forget that the context
for all theistic talk about these matters must be the love of God,
and that love not only grants freedom and responsibility, but de¬
sires personal relationship. A balanced view, it seems, must allow
for the realization of the relational aspirations of love, if their realiz¬
ation is compatible (as I believe it clearly is) with the giving of
much freedom and responsibility. Because of the nature of Divine
love, we may expect to find ourselves with freedom and respon¬
sibility, but by the same token, not in unlimited measure.
40. Such an interruption in the experience of God’s presence need not result in
inculpable doubt because it is not necessary to lose evidence sufficient for belief in
order to be so tested. Although it may seem that if the primary evidence of God’s
existence is experiential, I must always sense God’s presence in order always to
have evidence sufficient for belief, this is not the case. I may be forced to depend
on past experience, to remain true to it; and this past experience, together with the
past and present experience of others and nonexperiential evidence, may be per¬
fectly sufficient for some degree of belief.
41. Now perhaps the believer will come to doubt, unreasonably. Does this
mean that, contrary to the argument of Chapter 1, doubt is compatible with a
personal relationship with God? I would say no, for the believer, since she has
204 ] The Force of the Argument
responded presumptuously to her belief, may not have been in a personal relation¬
ship with God in the first place. But even if she was, if she doubts unreasonably
and so fails to believe or to experience the benefits of belief, the individual has
withdrawn herself from the relationship. (I assume here for the sake of discussion
that God exists.) It may seem that we should say she is still in the relationship, but
this, I think, is because the individual, while in doubt, is likely to be influenced in
various ways by her prior belief. Her life is still strongly affected by her having
been personally related to God, and indeed, she may once again become personally
related to God. We need not say that she still is so related to account for this.
42. The view I have been defending is well expressed, from the perspective of
theological commitment, by John Macquarrie: “As happens also in some of our
deepest human relationships, the lover reveals himself enough to awaken the love
of the beloved, yet veils himself enough to draw the beloved into an even deeper
exploration of that love. In the love affair with God (if we may so speak) there is
an alternation of consolation and desolation and it is in this way that the finite
being is constantly drawn beyond self into the depths of the divine” (In Search of
Deity [London: SCM Press, 1984], p. 198).
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 205
A Cumulative Argument
43. As I suggested earlier in this chapter, it seems less than plausible to suppose
that this state of affairs obtains, but for the sake of argument, I include it.
206 ] The Force of the Argument
44. Further support for this conclusion is to be found in the detailed arguments
of Chapter 6 and previous sections of Chapter 7.
Investigation, Diversity, and Responsibility [ 207
surely tips the balance decisively in favor of the second list. That is,
the conjunctive state of affairs represented by (vi)-(xf) (for the ex¬
istence of which the absence of reasonable nonbelief is necessary)
seems quite clearly the state of affairs we should (and a loving God
would) prefer. A perfectly loving God would not be deterred by
considerations of the sort the objector can marshal from bringing
about, as he would naturally be inclined to do, the state of affairs
represented by (xi), realizing that what would be sacrificed in so
doing could in large part be made up in other ways.
So it seems that a cumulative argument must also fail. Indeed, in
putting it forward, the objector helps bring the larger picture more
sharply into focus, enabling us to see more clearly the force of the
original claim.
Conclusion
vious day.1 Kim, if reasonable, will surely judge on the basis of her
total evidence that it was probably not Flo whom she saw. In this
case, there is no significant presumption for the new evidence to
defeat. And if Kim goes to the park again the next day and has the
same experience—that is, again has a fleeting glimpse of an indi¬
vidual resembling Flo—she, unlike Jim, who bumps into Joe and
sees him face to face, will judge, if reasonable (and if no other
evidence has come to light), that the individual she briefly sees is
probably not Flo. Although here too there are possible alternative
explanations of the witnesses’ testimony, given that her evidence
for believing that it was Flo she saw is not strong in the first place,
Kim has no reason to appeal to such possibilities. So too in the case
of S, if she finds herself without other reasons that clearly suggest
the existence of God. Without strong independent evidence for the
denial of my argument’s conclusion, S has no reason to appeal to
the possibility of an explanation unknown to her, perhaps beyond
her grasp. Without the indirect support for an appeal to the possi¬
bility of unknown explanations afforded by strong independent ev¬
idence of God’s existence, S must, if she agrees with this argu¬
ment, come to believe that there is no God.
My conclusion has important implications for a number of posi¬
tions and arguments in contemporary philosophy of religion. I will
mention two here—the positions of agnosticism and noneviden-
tialism.2 Nonevidentialism was originally and most famously en¬
dorsed by Pascal.3 On this view, one is pragmatically (as opposed
1. The analogy might be a closer one if we said that Kim is informed that had it
been Flo, she would have caught more than just a glimpse—that Flo likes to walk
out in the open where everyone can see her! But it is the point about independent
evidence I am emphasizing here, and for that, the present analogy will suffice.
2. The second of these positions, albeit familiar, does not seem to go by any one
name. I call it “nonevidentialism” to contrast it with a view popularly known as
“evidentialism”—the view that belief is rational only if based on adequate evi¬
dence.
3. I am of course referring to Pascal’s famous “wager” argument. See his Pen-
sees, A. J. Krailsheimer, trans. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1966), fragment 418.
William James, while disagreeing with Pascal on specifics, reaches a similar conclu¬
sion. See William James, The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy
(New York: Dover Publications, 1956). For more recent restatements of this view,
see Stephen T. Davis, Faith, Skepticism, and Evidence (Cranbury, N.J.: Associated
University Presses, 1978); Robert M. Adams, “Moral Arguments for Theistic Be-
212] Conclusion
lief,” in C. F. Delaney, ed., Rationality and Religious Belief (Notre Dame: Univer¬
sity of Notre Dame Press, 1979); and Nicholas Rescher, Pascal's Wager (Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1985).
Conclusion [213